Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

4 Two perspectives. Pars melior nostri. The Structure of Spinoza's Intellect. Chapter 4

In this chapter I will show that the perspective that came to light in the previous chapters – from which God is prior to the modes that follow from him – must be understood to be combined with a perspective from which t h e p a r t s a r e p r i o r t o t h e w h o l e t h e y c o n s t i t u t e. That is to say: the t o p-d o w n perspective in the previous chapters must be understood to be accompanied by a b o t t o m-u p perspective. This bottom-up perspective surfaces (inter alia) in Spinoza's important 'parallelism thesis'. As we shall see in the next chapter, recognition of the importance of these two perspectives in turn makes it clear how we must understand the two kinds of adequate knowledge that Spinoza discerns: r a t i o and s c i e n t i a i n t u i t i v a ....Read more
295 4. Two perspectives In this chapter I will show that the perspective that came to light in the previous chapters – from which God is prior to the modes that follow from him – must be understood to be combined with a perspective from which t h e p a r t s a r e p r i o r t o t h e w h o l e t h e y c o n s t i t u t e . That is to say: the t o p - d o w n perspective in the previous chapters must be understood to be accompanied by a b o t t o m - u p perspective. This bottom-up perspective surfaces (inter alia) in Spinoza’s important ‘parallelism thesis’. As we shall see in the next chapter, recognition of the importance of these two perspectives in turn makes it clear how we must understand the two kinds of adequate knowledge that Spinoza discerns: r a t i o and scientia intuitiva. 4.1 Introduction Spinoza has been called ‘the last of the mediaevals’ 1 – a title that is understandable given the priority that Spinoza allots the divine res. Even though Spinoza’s God is evidently very different from the scholastic conception of God, there is a clear traditional element recognizable his philosophy: the top-down direction of God’s power. The top-down perspective surfaces perhaps most explicitly in the proposition that starts off Spinoza’s creation narrative: EIp16. This Principle of Plenitude – that was treated extensively in Chapter 2 – leaves little doubt as to the direction proposed in it: in EIp16 Spinoza makes it clear that God qua God must be understood to be prior to the infinite modes (and all the things that fall under these infinite modes). Indeed, everything which can fall under an infinite intellect – i.e. omnes res – is claimed to follow from the divine nature. The agreement with his medieval predecessors concerning the causal priority 2 of God is made explicit in the third corollary of EIp16, where Spinoza states that ‘God is absolutely the first 1 Wolfson, The Philosophy of Spinoza I, vii. The relevant passage reads thus: ‘Then there is […] the implicit Spinoza, who lurks behind these definitions, axioms, and propositions, only occasionally revealing himself in the scholia; his mind is crammed with traditional philosophic lore and his thought turns along the beaten logical paths of mediaeval reasoning. Him we shall call Baruch. […] Baruch is the last of the mediaevals’. 2 The asserted equivalence of the designations ‘follow from’ and ‘is caused by’ is argued for in Chapter 2.
296 cause’. 3 This priority of the divine res is reiterated in various passages in part I of the Ethics, among which the claim in EIp25 that ‘God is the efficient cause, not only of the existence of things, but also of their essence’, 4 as well as Spinoza’s description of Natura naturans and Natura naturata in EIp29s. The assertions in this latter scholium – that round off the creation narrative that starts with EIp16 – are completely in line with the causal direction that surfaces in EIp16: it is from Natura naturans that all things in nature must be understood to follow. Even though Spinoza’s view differs considerably from the Thomistic conception of Natura naturans, 5 the causal direction he propagates is similar to the one his scholastic predecessors foster: in Spinoza’s philosophy too, Natura naturans is staged as the active principle from which Natura naturata follows. 6 So in the Ethics (as well as in Spinoza’s other philosophical works), God’s all-encompassing power is directed top- down. This can be rendered thus: Important as this top-down perspective may be for Spinoza’s philosophy, it is not the only perspective that can be recognized in it. His highly original (and non- medieval) claim that creator and creation are ontologically identical – and that the relation from EIp16 can thus be understood to be a relation of inherence (see 3 EIp16c3, (I) 425 (Deum esse absolutè causam primam). 4 EIp25, (I) 431 (Deus non tantùm est causa efficiens rerum existentiæ, sed etiam essentiæ). 5 In the KV, Spinoza refers explicitly to the Thomists when using the term ‘ Natura naturans’. KV I, Ch. VIII, (I), 91. To be sure, Spinoza may very well have gathered this term (and the accompanying ‘ Natura naturata’) from another source. Steenbakkers, ‘Een vijandige overname’, 43-45. 6 According to Steenbakkers, there is reason to suspect that Spinoza made use of these scholastic terms only during a relatively short span of time (1660-1663). Ibidem, 43. However, even though after EIp31 Spinoza does not employ the terms anymore in the Ethics (nor refers to the passages in which he does), the structural characteristic that is denoted with it – i.e. the conceptual distinction between an active and an ontologically identical passive aspect of nature – is clearly upheld in his mature philosophy. Natura naturans (a) God qua God ---------------------- (c) God Natura naturata (b) All the things that fall under an infinite intellect (table 1)
4. Two perspectives In this chapter I will show that the perspective that came to light in the previous chapters – from which God is prior to the modes that follow from him – must be understood to be combined with a perspective from which t h e p a r t s a r e p r i o r t o t h e w h o l e t h e y c o n s t i t u t e . That is to say: the t o p - d o w n perspective in the previous chapters must be understood to be accompanied by a b o t t o m - u p perspective. This bottom-up perspective surfaces (inter alia) in Spinoza’s important ‘parallelism thesis’. As we shall see in the next chapter, recognition of the importance of these two perspectives in turn makes it clear how we must understand the two kinds of adequate knowledge that Spinoza discerns: r a t i o and s c i e n t i a i n t u i t i v a . 4.1 Introduction Spinoza has been called ‘the last of the mediaevals’1 – a title that is understandable given the priority that Spinoza allots the divine res. Even though Spinoza’s God is evidently very different from the scholastic conception of God, there is a clear traditional element recognizable his philosophy: the top-down direction of God’s power. The top-down perspective surfaces perhaps most explicitly in the proposition that starts off Spinoza’s creation narrative: EIp16. This Principle of Plenitude – that was treated extensively in Chapter 2 – leaves little doubt as to the direction proposed in it: in EIp16 Spinoza makes it clear that God qua God must be understood to be prior to the infinite modes (and all the things that fall under these infinite modes). Indeed, everything which can fall under an infinite intellect – i.e. omnes res – is claimed to follow from the divine nature. The agreement with his medieval predecessors concerning the causal priority2 of God is made explicit in the third corollary of EIp16, where Spinoza states that ‘God is absolutely the first Wolfson, The Philosophy of Spinoza I, vii. The relevant passage reads thus: ‘Then there is […] the implicit Spinoza, who lurks behind these definitions, axioms, and propositions, only occasionally revealing himself in the scholia; his mind is crammed with traditional philosophic lore and his thought turns along the beaten logical paths of mediaeval reasoning. Him we shall call Baruch. […] Baruch is the last of the mediaevals’. 2 The asserted equivalence of the designations ‘follow from’ and ‘is caused by’ is argued for in Chapter 2. 1 295 cause’.3 This priority of the divine res is reiterated in various passages in part I of the Ethics, among which the claim in EIp25 that ‘God is the efficient cause, not only of the existence of things, but also of their essence’,4 as well as Spinoza’s description of Natura naturans and Natura naturata in EIp29s. The assertions in this latter scholium – that round off the creation narrative that starts with EIp16 – are completely in line with the causal direction that surfaces in EIp16: it is from Natura naturans that all things in nature must be understood to follow. Even though Spinoza’s view differs considerably from the Thomistic conception of Natura naturans,5 the causal direction he propagates is similar to the one his scholastic predecessors foster: in Spinoza’s philosophy too, Natura naturans is staged as the active principle from which Natura naturata follows.6 So in the Ethics (as well as in Spinoza’s other philosophical works), God’s all-encompassing power is directed topdown. This can be rendered thus: Natura naturans ---------------------Natura naturata (a) God qua God (c) God (b) All the things that fall under an infinite intellect (table 1) Important as this top-down perspective may be for Spinoza’s philosophy, it is not the only perspective that can be recognized in it. His highly original (and nonmedieval) claim that creator and creation are ontologically identical – and that the relation from EIp16 can thus be understood to be a relation of inherence (see EIp16c3, (I) 425 (Deum esse absolutè causam primam). EIp25, (I) 431 (Deus non tantùm est causa efficiens rerum existentiæ, sed etiam essentiæ). 5 In the KV, Spinoza refers explicitly to the Thomists when using the term ‘Natura naturans’. KV I, Ch. VIII, (I), 91. To be sure, Spinoza may very well have gathered this term (and the accompanying ‘Natura naturata’) from another source. Steenbakkers, ‘Een vijandige overname’, 43-45. 6 According to Steenbakkers, there is reason to suspect that Spinoza made use of these scholastic terms only during a relatively short span of time (1660-1663). Ibidem, 43. However, even though after EIp31 Spinoza does not employ the terms anymore in the Ethics (nor refers to the passages in which he does), the structural characteristic that is denoted with it – i.e. the conceptual distinction between an active and an ontologically identical passive aspect of nature – is clearly upheld in his mature philosophy. 3 4 296 Chapter 2)7 – accounts for yet another conceptual perspective in the Ethics.8 We have seen in the previous chapters that God knows himself (also) by way of the human mind, which is part of the infinite intellect of God. Combining these claims, we cannot evade the conclusion that God (c) knows himself (also) by way of the infinite intellect, that is: by way of (b). It seems that, whereas the causal direction from the divine res to all the things that follow from it must be conceived to be top-down, the conceptual direction can be understood to (also) be diametrically opposed to this causal flow.9 This can be rendered tentatively in the following way: Natura naturans ---------------------Natura naturata (a) God qua God (conceived cause) (b) The infinite intellect (conceiving effect) (c) God (table 2) This table suggests that God (c) can be understood to know himself in two ways. - Firstly, God (c) can be understood to know himself top-down, or from the knowledge of the cause to the knowledge of the effect, that is: from the absolute 7 The term ‘inherence’ itself does not surface often in Spinoza’s work. It can be found (in a relevant way) only in Letter 12, where Spinoza makes it clear that ‘some things are infinite […] by the force of the cause in which they inhere [emphasis added]’. Letter 12, (I) 205 (quaedam suâ naturâ esse infinita […]verò vi causæ, cui inhærent). In Chapter 2 we have seen that this clause can be understood to be applicable to the formal being of things (and by implication the objective being of things, as these are portrayed to be the very same things, albeit ‘conceived abstractly’. Ibidem, (I) 205 (abstractè concipiuntur)). This observation in turn is on a par with our claim in Chapter 2 that EIp16 must be understood to encompass intrinsic and extrinsic causation. 8 And thus we need not be surprised that Harry Wolfson does not only call Spinoza ‘the last of the mediaevals’, but also ‘the first of the moderns’. Wolfson, The Philosophy of Spinoza I, vii. 9 This is partly due to the mathematical model that Spinoza uses, a way of thinking that surfaces inter alia in his claim in the demonstration of EIp16 that ‘this Proposition must be plain to anyone, provided he attends to the fact that the intellect infers from the given definition of any thing a number of properties that really do follow necessarily from it’ and the elucidation in EIp17s that ‘all things [...] always follow, by the same necessity and in the same way as from the nature of a triangle it follows, from eternity to eternity, that its three angles are equal to two right angles’. These claims make it clear that, even though the causal direction – top-down – is distinctly medieval, the causal character is (early) modern. For an interesting account of the way this early modern character of Spinoza’s thought is related to (and radicalizes) Descartes’ mathematical perspective see: Valtteri Viljanen, Spinoza’s Geometry of Power (Cambridge 2011), 16-20. To be sure, in the passages of EIp16 and EIp17s the bottom-up perspective is not recognizable. The only claim I make here is that the mathematical character of the top-down cause that surfaces in it is distinctly non-medieval, and can be understood to give way to yet another conception of causal direction, which in turn surfaces in other propositions and scholiums (to be dealt with in subsequent sections). 297 - omnipotence of God qua God (a) – about whom it can be claimed that ‘the laws of his nature have been so ample that they sufficed for producing all things which can be conceived by an infinite intellect’10 – to all the things which can be conceived by an infinite intellect (b). Secondly, as ‘each idea […] of each singular thing that actually exists, necessarily involves an eternal and infinite essence of God’,11 God (c) can also be understood to know himself bottom-up, or from the knowledge of the effect to the knowledge of the cause, that is: from the infinite intellect (b) to God qua God (a).12 The implicit claim that the bottom-up perspective – i.e. the perspective that ‘starts with the parts’ at level (b) – is nothing but an aspect of God’s self-knowledge sets Spinoza apart from his medieval predecessors. It allows Spinoza to assert that an investigation of the order of nature (b) can somehow lead to true and adequate knowledge of (the ontologically identical) God qua God (a).13 Another way of saying this is that, even though Spinoza claims in EIIp10s that ‘the divine nature […] is prior both in knowledge and in nature’,14 there nevertheless appears to be a conceptual commitment with respect to the infinitely many individual things that constitute (b). It is the aim of this chapter to show how Spinoza’s view of the absolute causal and conceptual priority of God is combined with a conceptual commitment to the whole of nature (i.e. as argued for in Chapter 2, to the object of EI Appendix, (I) 446 (quia ipsius naturæ leges adeò amplæ fuerunt, ut sufficerent ad omnia, quæ ab aliquo infinito intellectu concipi possunt, producenda). 11 EIIp45, (I) 481 (Unaquæque cujuscunque corporis, vel rei singularis, actu existentis, idea Dei æternam, & infinitam essentiam necessariò involvit). 12 These are the two ways in which the (c)-variant of God can be understood to know himself. In Chapter 3 we have seen that the (a)-variant can be understood to know himself in an absolutely prior way, namely (so to speak) from knowledge of the cause to knowledge of the cause. Indeed, it became clear that God (a) is absolutely free from the duality that characterizes the intellect in the way we commonly understand it. 13 Indeed, however much Spinoza’s opponents (and, for that matter, many of his adherents) have claimed that Spinoza is an atheist, the claim that God is illusory must nevertheless be understood to be absurd in the context of Spinoza’s philosophy. To be sure, the claim that God is a person-like figure with a supreme intellect is equally absurd in the context of Spinoza’s philosophy. So iff ‘atheism’ is defined as ‘the denial of the realiter existence of a divine person-like figure who creates at will and who has a supreme intellect’, then Spinoza is an atheist. For Spinoza makes it very clear that this particular conception of God is illusory. 14 EIIp10S, (I) 455 (Nam naturam divinam […],quia tam cognitione, quàm naturâ prior est). 10 298 God’s idea), a commitment needed in the new mechanical worldview that ignited the philosophy of thinkers such as Bacon, Descartes, and Spinoza himself. 4.1.1 An idiosyncratic reading? Consider table 2 once more: Natura naturans ---------------------Natura naturata (a) God qua God (conceived cause) (b) The infinite intellect (conceiving effect) (c) God (table 2) We have just asserted that this table expresses the way in which the bottom-up perspective offers God a way to know himself. However, at this point it must be noted that table 2 is not as complete as we could wish for. The rendering of table 2 accounts for the way the bottom-up perspective can be understood insofar as God knows himself by way of the unspecified infinite intellect, that is: by way of the infinite intellect insofar as the distinction between the formal and the objective being of this infinite intellect is not yet made. However, in the previous chapters we have seen that an understanding of the functioning of the intellect must incorporate the conceptual distinction between the formal and the objective being of these things. And hence, apparently, the bottom-up variant of God’s self-knowledge that we are interested in must be rendered, not in the manner of table 2, but in the following way: Natura naturans (a) God qua God (top-down) --------------------------------------(b-i) The formal being of singular things Natura naturata (bottom-up) (b -ii) The objective being of singular things (c) God (table 3) Indeed, in Chapter 2 it has become clear that by way of our intellect we conceive singular things (i.e. modes that serve as the basis for the bottom-up perspective) in two ways: either insofar as we conceive them as to their objective being (b-ii), or insofar as we conceive them in to their formal being (b-i). It is this particular way of conceiving things that we have shown to be the structural characteristic of God’s self-knowledge insofar as he is expressed in the human mind (and indeed God’s 299 self-knowledge insofar as he is expressed in God’s idea). And hence this particular variant of God’s self-knowledge – that entails a trichotomy of modes, their objective being and it formal being15 – must somehow be integrated in our rendering of the bottom-up perspective. Table 3 evidently needs more elucidation. At least two things deserve attention: (I) (II) We are in need of closer insight into the exact relation between the formal (b-i) and the objective (b-ii) being of singular things We must illuminate how knowledge of the formal being of singular things (b-i) enables our intellect to attain knowledge of God qua God (a) (i.e. how God (c) is able to gather self-knowledge) We will return to point (II) in a subsequent section (and in the next chapter). First, it must be established how the levels (b-ii) and (b-i) are related. In order to provide an answer to point (I), I will turn to a treatment of one of the central aspects of Spinoza’s metaphysics: his so-called ‘parallelism thesis’ of EIIp7. In the next sections it will become clear that this proposition deals precisely with the relation between (b-ii) and (b-i) (and thus can be understood to shed further light on the trichotomous structure of the intellect that was uncovered in Chapter 2). Indeed, below I will argue for the claim that the famous assertion ‘the order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of things’ – on which Spinoza’s claim that a man’s body and his mind can be conceived to be ‘one and the same thing, but expressed in two ways’16 is based – must be understood to say the following: the order and connection of the objective being of things (b-ii) is the same as the order and connection of the formal being of things (b-i). Another way of saying this is that Spinoza’s parallelism thesis in EIIp7 can be conceived to be yet another expression of the constructive function of the intellect that can be discerned in the Ethics. 15 See section 2.5.3. 16 EIIp7s, (I) 451 (una, eademq́ue est res, sed duobus modis expressa). 300 Now, it must be admitted that prima facie this is a rather idiosyncratic rendering of Spinoza’s assertion in EIIp7. Generally, Spinoza’s parallelism thesis in EIIp7 is claimed to consist in an inter-attribute identity between modes of one attribute (say: human minds), and modes of another attribute (in casu: human bodies). That is to say: Spinoza’s parallelism is commonly understood to posit the following: Natura naturans Thought = Extension = R --------------------------------------------------------------(c) God Natura naturata idea x = body x = rx (table 4)17 Indeed, there appears to be consensus among scholars that with EIIp7 Spinoza aims to make it clear that for each extended thing – whether it be a stone, a tree, a man or a toaster – there is an idea (i.e. a ‘mind’) that is numerically identical to it. Yet, the rephrased version of EIIp7 provided above suggests that this ‘parallelism proposition’ must actually be understood to posit an intra-attribute parallelism i.e. a ‘vertical’ parallelism of things that are conceived within the realm of thought – in the following way: Natura naturans (a) God qua God ----------------------------------------------------------------(b-i) The formal being of singular things Natura naturata is identical to (b -ii) The objective being of singular things (c) God (table 5) Claiming that in EIIp7 Spinoza forwards an intra-attribute identity of the objective and the formal beings of things appears to deviate considerably from the communis opinio among Spinoza scholars. It must be stressed immediately that this deviation is partly illusory. I do not at all deny that Spinoza’s claim in EIIp7 entails an inter17 A few things must be noted with respect to this table. Firstly, it is important to make it clear the ‘R’ stand for ‘the remaining attributes’ and ‘r’ for ‘mode of the remaining attributes. Secondly, it must be stressed that this table only aims to express the identity relation that is entailed by Spinoza parallelism; the causal purport of his parallelism thesis will be addressed in the next chapter. Lastly, it must be added that in positioning Thought, Extension and R at the level of Natura naturans we have tacitly switched from the conceptual sense of the attributes (that surfaces in EID4) to the ontological (i.e. extra-intellectual) variant of the attributes (that is argued for in section 3.6). See also note 19. 301 attribute identity of ideas and their extended objects. There is little doubt that EIIp7 must be understood to imply that (as it is stated explicitly in the scholium of this proposition) ‘a mode of extension and the idea of that mode are one and the same thing, but expressed in two ways’.18 So I do not want to oppose the rendering of table 4. Rather, this chapter is aimed at showing that table 4 tells only part of the story.19 It will become clear that the horizontal identity of modes from table 4 can only be made intelligible on the basis of the specific vertical identity-relation that is posited in table 5. Indeed, below we will see that inter-attribute parallelism is merely an implication of Spinoza’s more comprehensive (what I have chosen to call) transitive parallelism that surfaces, not only in EIIp7, but also in EIIp21s.20 Treatment of this subject in turn enables us to understand how the top-down and the bottom-up perspective of God’s self-knowledge can be conceived. Or, to put the same point differently: treatment of the parallelism claim of EIIp7 makes it clear how Spinoza is able to reconcile a medieval perspective with a (very particular)21 early modern scientific view. 4.2 Two parallelisms? The ‘parallelism thesis’22 is one of the fundamental aspects of Spinoza’s philosophy. In previous chapters we have referred to this thesis various times. Up till this point EIIp7s, (I) 451 (Sic etiam modus extensionis, & idea illius modi una, eademq́ue est res, sed duobus modis expressa). This very insight enabled us to investigate the realm of extension in order to gather a better understanding of the way thought must be understood to be conceptually bifurcated. See section 1.3. 19 Attentive readers may have noticed that I have used the very same wording with respect to the elucidation of the intellect-dependent definition of ‘attribute’ (EID4) (see section 3.6). This is no coincidence. For in this chapter it will become clear that with respect to the intellectual grasping of singular things we encounter the very same structure as the one we encountered with respect to the attributes. Conceptually a man and the idea of that man are distinct in the same way the attributes are (this agrees with the claims in EIA4 and EIIp7s). Yet ontologically the formal being of a man and the formal being of the idea of the man are identical in the same way the attributes must be understood to express one and the same divine essence. More on this in a subsequent section. 20 The exact purport of the terms ‘vertical’ and ‘transitive’, as well as the relation with the term ‘intraattribute’, will be elucidated in the subsequent sections. 21 For in certain respects, Spinoza of course deviates as much from his early modern contemporaries as he does from his medieval predecessors. 22 I use quotation marks here because the term ‘parallelism’ is not actually used by Spinoza. The term seems to originate in the work of Leibniz, who in Considerations on the Doctrine of a Universal Spirit uses ‘parallelism’ to refer to the relation between soul and body: ‘And as to the complete separation between soul and body [...], I see no reason either in religion or in philosophy, which obliges me to give up the 18 302 we have more or less taken it for granted that according to Spinoza a body (or the all-encompassing collection of bodies: the whole of nature) and the idea of that body (or the all-encompassing collection of ideas of bodies: the whole of objective nature) are one and the same thing. At this point it must be shown how this claim is to be understood precisely, and how it functions within the structure of Spinoza’s metaphysics. 4.2.1 Inter-attribute parallelism Spinoza’s parallelism thesis is rooted in EIIp7, which famously states the following: The order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of things.23 (Ordo, & connexio idearum idem est, ac ordo, & connexio rerum) As already noted, this proposition is generally taken to posit a numerical identity between singular things that are understood to be operative under the attribute of thought (‘ideas’), and singular things that are conceived under the attribute of extension (‘bodies’).24 This reading of EIIp7 is underpinned by the following passage in EIIp7s: a mode of extension and the idea of that mode are one and the same thing, but expressed in two ways.25 (modus extensionis, & idea illius modi una, eademq́ue est res, sed duobus modis expressa) Spinoza’s explication in EIIp7s teaches us that the claim in EIIp7 must be understood to entail an identity relation between things that are conceived under different attributes that each express an essence of the very same substance. It is this doctrine of the parallelism of the soul and the body, and to admit a perfect separation [emphasis added]’ (je ne voy aucune raison ny de la religion ny de la philosophie, qui m’oblige de quitter la doctrine du parallelisme de l’ame et du corps, et d’admettre une parfaite separation). Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, ‘Considerations on the Doctrine of a Universal Spirit’ in: George Martin Duncan ed., The Philosophical Works of Leibnitz (New Haven 1890), 143. However, despite the somewhat problematic implications of the term when using it in the context of Spinoza’s philosophy, I will continue to use ‘parallelism’ anyway (while dropping the quotation marks), as it has become the standard term for Spinoza’s claim in EIIp7. 23 EIIp7, (I) 451. 24 See for instance: Wallace Matson, ‘Spinoza’s theory of mind’ in: The Monist, Vol. 55, No. 4 (1971), 573; Bennett, A Study of Spinoza’s Ethics, 127; Della Rocca, Representation,19. 25 EIIp7s, (I) 451. 303 very inter-attribute relation that enables Spinoza to assert that a man and the idea of that man are one and the same thing, yet conceived under another attribute (see table 4). Furthermore, the claim concerning the identity of things conceived under the attributes of thought and extension allows Spinoza to state that ‘the object of the idea constituting the human mind is the human body [...] and nothing else’ in EIIp13.26 The parallelism thesis enables him to posit that mind and body are one and the same thing, expressed in two ways. In this way, Spinoza claims, ‘we understand [...] what should be understood by the union of mind and body’. 27 Unlike René Descartes – who must allow causal interaction between the realms of thought and extension – Spinoza posits that these realms are causally closed. In Spinoza’s philosophy (say) the intended raising of an arm is not the result of an occurrence in thought, causing an action in the extended realm. Rather, the occurrence in thought causes some sort of process in the idea of the arm; and it is the extended parallel of the occurrence in thought that must be understood to cause the movement of the extended arm. This inter-attribute parallelism relation between ideas and their extended counterparts – one of the few things that Spinoza commentators agree upon completely – can be rendered in the way of table 4 (see above). 4.2.2 Intra-attribute parallelism To be sure, the Ethics appears to harbor yet another parallelism thesis. Apart from the inter-attribute parallelism that is asserted explicitly in the claim of EIIp7s, Spinoza also endorses a variant of parallelism that is operative within the attribute of thought. This latter intra-attribute parallelism surfaces in EIIp20 and EIIp21. In proposition 20 we read the following: EIIp13, (I) 457 (Objectum ideæ, humanam Mentem constituentis, est Corpus, sive certus Extensionis modus actu existens, & nihil aliud). 27 EIIp13s, (I) 457-458 (Ex his non tantùm intelligimus, Mentem humanam unitam esse Corpori, sed etiam, quid per Mentis, & Corporis unionem intelligendum sit). At this point it must be stressed that Spinoza’s term ‘idea’ is rather different from the way in which we commonly understand this term. The idea of my body in the sense in which Spinoza uses the term is not the idea that I have in my mind as ‘a picture on a tablet’ (EIIp43s) of my body. Rather, the idea of my body simply is my body, understood from the perspective of thought. More on this in the next chapter. 26 304 There is also in God an idea, or knowledge, of the human mind, which follows in God in the same way and is related to God in the same way as the idea, or knowledge, of the human body.28 (Mentis humanæ datur etiam in Deo idea, sive cognitio, quæ in Deo eodem modo sequitur, & ad Deum eodem modo refertur, ac idea sive cognitio Corporis humani) In the subsequent proposition Spinoza states: This idea [in God] of the [human] mind is united to the mind in the same way as the mind is united to the human body.29 (Hæc Mentis idea eodem modo unita est Menti, ac ipsa Mens unita est Corpori) These claims uncover an alternative variant of parallelism. The explicit reference to the union of the human mind and body teaches us that the identity relation that is referred to in EIIp7s and EIIp13 (i.e. the identity of the mind and its extended object) is applicable, not only to the conceiving of a thing under different attributes, but also to things that are understood to resort under the same attribute. For as we saw, the union of mind and body according to Spinoza consists in the fact that both are the same thing, expressed under different attributes. As EIIp21 reads that the idea of the human mind in God (that surfaces in EIIp20) is united to the human mind ‘in the same way’ (eodem modo) as this mind is united to the body, we are led to the conclusion that the idea of the human mind in God and the human mind itself are one and the same thing, conceived under the same attribute: thought. This puzzling relation between the idea of the mind and the mind itself is affirmed in EIIp21s: So the idea of the mind and the mind itself are one and the same thing, which is conceived under one and the same attribute, namely, thought. The idea of the mind, I say, and the mind itself follow in God from the same power of thinking and by the same necessity. For the idea of the mind, that is, the idea of the idea, is nothing but the form of the idea insofar as this is considered as a mode of thinking without relation to the object [emphasis added].30 (quare Mentis idea, & ipsa Mens una, eademq́ue est res, quæ sub uno, eodemq́ue attributo, nempe Cogitationis, concipitur. Mentis, inquam, idea, & ipsa Mens in Deo eâdem necessitate ex eâdem cogitandi potentiâ sequuntur dari. Nam reverâ idea Mentis, hoc est, idea ideæ nihil aliud est, quàm forma ideæ, quatenus hæc, ut modus cogitandi, absque relatione ad objectum consideratur) 28 EIIp20, (I) 467. EIIp21, (I) 467. 30 Ibidem, (I) 467. 29 305 Paraphrasing EIIp7s – which is validated by Spinoza’s remark that the present parallelism relation must be understood ‘in the same way’ as the union of mind and body – we can tentatively rephrase the claim of EIIp21s in the following way: a mode of thinking and the idea of that mode are one and the same thing, but expressed in two ways. Or in terms of EIIp13: the object of the idea of the human mind is the human mind and nothing else. Remarkable and counterintuitive as these claims may seem at first sight, they are actually confirmed by Spinoza in the demonstration of EIIp21, which reads: We have shown that the mind is united to the body from the fact that the body is the object of the mind (see P12 and 13); and so by the same reasoning the idea of the mind must be united with its own object, that is, with the mind itself, in the same way as the mind is united with the body.31 (Mentem unitam esse Corpori ex eo ostendimus, quòd scilicet Corpus Mentis sit objectum (vide Prop. 12. & 13. hujus): adeòque per eandem illam rationem idea Mentis cum suo objecto, hoc est, cum ipsâ Mente eodem modo unita esse debet, ac ipsa Mens unita est Corpori) These claims posit an aspect of duality within the attribute of thought that is in need of a closer scrutiny. For if the idea of the mind (viz. the idea of the idea, i.e. the idea God has of the mind) is identical to its object (viz. the idea that is the human mind, i.e. the idea God has of the body), and if both singular things32 are subsumed under thought, the question arises how they still can be conceived to be conceptually distinct. That is: how is it possible to distinguish between things if these things are claimed to be the very same thing, conceived under the same attribute? How must the intra–attribute relation between ideas and the ideas of these ideas be understood? 31 EIIp21, (I) 467. Spinoza defines ‘singular things’ as: ‘[…] things that are finite and have a determinate existence’. EIID7, (I) 447 (Per r e s s i n g u l a r e s intelligo res, quae finitae sunt et determinatam habent existentiam). As Spinoza in EIIp21s is arguing about the human mind insofar as it is united to the body (i.e. ‘insofar as it expresses the actual existence of the body, which is explained by duration’, EVp23d, (I) 607 (quatenus corporis actualem existentiam, quae per durationem explicatur)), in this context ‘idea’ and ‘idea of the idea’ both qualify as things that are finite and have a determinate existence, that is: they qualify as singular things. 32 306 4.2.2.1 Formality and objectivity revisited In order to show how an idea can be distinguished from the identical idea of that idea, it may be instructive to recapitulate how an idea can be distinguished from its extended object. As Spinoza claims in EIIp21 that the former relation must be understood in the same way as the latter, a summary of the things we have said concerning the status of ideas and their parallel bodies may provide us with a clue as to the way in which the distinction between an idea and the idea of that idea must be understood. Now, with respect to the inter-attribute relation between ideas and their parallel bodies (such as an idea of a raising arm and its parallel extended counterpart, or indeed the whole of objective nature – God’s idea – and its object: the whole of nature), Spinoza makes use of an internal characteristic of substance on the basis of which it is possible to conceive of substance in (at least) two ways: the very notion of ‘attribute’. It is by way of the attributes that our intellect has cognitive access to two ways – and two ways only33 – of understanding the essence of the one undividable substance: we grasp the essence of substance through thought, and we grasp it through extension. A singular thing can be understood to be mind and body, because a thing can be conceived to resort under two distinct attributes. In terms of Spinoza’s Principle of Plenitude (EIp16): ideas and bodies can both be understood to ‘fall under the infinite intellect’ (b) because a thing that follows from God qua God (a) can be understood (i) as an idea (that falls under the infinite intellect as it is part of this infinite mode of thought), and (ii) as a body (that falls under the infinite intellect because the whole it is conceived to be a part of – i.e. the infinite mode of extension – is perceived by the infinite intellect).34 We gathered Spinoza’s parallelism thesis in EIIp21 – the one I referred to using the term ‘intra-attribute parallelism’ – from the assertion that ‘the idea of the 33 This is stated explicitly for in Letter 64. ‘So I conclude that the human Mind cannot achieve knowledge of any other attribute of God beyond [Extension and Thought]’ (Atque adeò concludo Mentem humanam nullum Dei attributum præter hæc posse cognitione assequi, ut fuit propositum). Letter 64, (II) 438. An analysis of the arguments that Spinoza provides for this claim would take us too far afield. See also note 158. 34 This latter formulation is inspired by the version of the definition of attribute that Spinoza provides in EIIp7s. The definition of attribute (in both EID4 and EIIp7s) entails a claim about the representational nature of the intellect, which will be treated comprehensively in the next chapter. 307 mind and the mind itself are one and the same thing, which is conceived under one and the same attribute’. In this case too, some sort of internal characteristic must be supposed on the basis of which these two distinct descriptions are intelligible.35 So what could this internal characteristic be? At this point we must recall that in the previous chapters we have already uncovered an internal distinction that can be understood to be operative within the attributes, and that moreover is closely related to the distinction between ideas and their objects. We have seen that modes can be grasped in two ways. They can be considered: (1) insofar as we conceive them to exist in relation to a certain time and place, that is: in their objective being, representing their objects36 And the very same things can be grasped (2) insofar as we conceive them under a species of eternity, that is: in their formal being37 Indeed, in the previous chapters we have seen that any operation of the intellect (in the way we commonly understand it) must be understood to be characterized by a conceptual bifurcation between the objective and the formal being of the thing under scrutiny. Stated in terms of EVp29s: we conceive things as actual in two ways: either insofar as we conceive them in their o b j e c t i v e being, or insofar as we conceive them in their f o r m a l being. 35 Yitzhak Melamed made the same observation: ‘If the order of ideas is supposed to perfectly reflect the order of things, there must be an internal barrier within thought […] which reflects the barrier among the attributes’. Yitzhak Melamed, ‘Spinoza’s Metaphysics of Thought: Parallelisms and the Multifaceted Structure of Ideas’ in: Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 86:3 (May 2013), 674. 36 The next chapter will be dedicated to a scrutiny of the representational character of this relation. 37 Attentive readers may notice that I have changed the order of (1) and (2). In the previous chapters point (1) harbored the formal being of things, and point (2) the objective being of the same things. The present way of staging things is induced by the main subject of this chapter; the elucidation of the bottomup perspective. More on this in the subsequent sections. 308 Looking for an internal feature within the attributes that makes the intra-attribute parallelism of EIIp21s intelligible, the distinction between the formal and the objective being of things is very promising. The first thing that must be noted in this respect is that this very distinction plays a crucial role with respect to the perception of the multiple attributes (and thus with respect to inter-attribute parallelism). Indeed, in EID4 ‘attribute’ is defined as ‘what the intellect perceives of a substance [emphasis added]’. In the previous chapter it became clear that, insofar as the level of modes (b) is taken into account, the attributes must be taken in this intellect-dependent fashion. This in turn teaches us that the inter-attribute parallelism of EIIp7s must also be understood to be intellect-dependent. That is to say: we can only posit that the idea of a man (or of a raising arm) and the body of that man (or of the raising arm) are the very same thing if the intellectual distinction between the formal and the objective being of things is presupposed. For the attributes – the very internal feature of substance that allows us to distinguish between ideas and bodies – can only be grasped insofar as the divine res is conceived both as to its formal being (as God qua God (a)), and as to its objective being (as the (perceiving) infinite intellect (b)). In short: the recognition of inter-attribute parallelism is intellect-dependent. Now, as Spinoza’s claim in EIIp21 makes it clear that intra-attribute parallelism is to be understood in the same way as inter-attribute parallelism, we can draw the provisional conclusion that intra-attribute parallelism must be considered to be intellect-dependent as well (or to say it in a slightly different way: that both interand intra-attribute parallelism fall within the scope of the constructive function of the intellect that was uncovered in section 2.5). And hence, we have found an important indication that the internal feature that we are looking for is precisely the distinction between formality and objectivity that was treated in Chapter 2. The tentative suggestion that the distinction between the formal and objective being of things is precisely the feature that accounts for the intra-attribute parallelism of EIIp21 and its scholium is underpinned by the fact that the notion ‘form of the idea’ is used explicitly by Spinoza in EIIp21s. Consider the following claim from this scholium once again: 309 the idea of the Mind, that is, the idea of the idea, is nothing but the form of the idea insofar as this is considered a mode of thinking without relation to the object [emphasis added]’.38 (Nam reverâ idea Mentis, hoc est, idea ideæ nihil aliud est, quàm forma ideæ, quatenus hæc, ut modus cogitandi, absque relatione ad objectum consideratur) This formulation clearly corroborates our supposition that the bifurcation that surfaces in EIIp21s (i.e. the distinction between ideas and the ideas of these ideas) can be understood in terms of the very conceptual bifurcation that was treated in the previous chapters: the distinction between a finite idea that is conceived to exist in relation to a certain time and place (1), and that very same thing insofar as it is conceived in its eternal formal being (2). The assertion concerning forma ideae in this scholium reiterates that according to Spinoza an idea can be grasped in at least two ways: with and without relation to the object it is the idea of. It is hard to miss the similarity between these claims in EIIp21s and the things we have said in Chapter 2 with regard to the formal and objective being of ideas: - An idea that is claimed to be grasped insofar as it is considered with relation to its object is on a par with the objective being that surfaces in EIIp8c (and EIIp9). - The ‘form of the idea’ in EIIp21s is on a par with the formal being of EIIp5, that is: the being of the idea under scrutiny as it is in itself, viz. without relation to its object.39 So Spinoza’s formulation in the scholium of EIIp21 corroborates our tentative claim that the internal feature that enables him to distinguish between an idea and an identical mode under the very same attribute is grounded on the distinction between the objective and the formal status of that idea, i.e. the distinction between an idea insofar as it represents its object and that same idea as it is in itself. In terms of EIIp21s the distinction can be rendered thus: 38 EIIp21s, (I) 467-468. Here we take a tacit turn. Up till this point we were treating the question how the parallel relation between an idea and the idea of that idea can be understood. Henceforth we will be focusing on the parallel relation between the idea and the form of that idea. The important question how the form of an idea can in turn be understood to be the idea of an idea will be elucidated in a subsequent section. 39 310 A singular mind can be grasped in two ways: as the objective being of a body (i.e. as the idea with relation to its object) (1′) and (2′) as the formal being of the idea of a body (i.e. as the idea without relation to its object)40 These claims are very important when trying to understand Spinoza’s parallelism (and indeed pars melior nostri), as they suggest that the intra-attribute parallelism that surfaces in EIIp21 is an expression of the fact that ideas insofar as they are considered w i t h r e s p e c t t o t h e i r e x t e n d e d o b j e c t s must be understood to be paralleled by the very same ideas insofar as they are considered i n t h e m s e l v e s . And hence the claims in EIIp21 and its scholium can also be formulated thus: The order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of the formal being of these ideas. Or, as we have rendered it in table 5: Natura naturans (a) God qua God ----------------------------------------------------------------(b-i) The formal being of singular things is identical to Natura naturata (b -ii) The objective being of singular things (c) God (table 5) This particular way of staging the intra-attribute parallelism claim of EIIp21 and its scholium becomes even more important once it is acknowledged that according to Spinoza this intra-attribute parallelism must be understood in the very same way as inter-attribute parallelism. In order to test whether – and how – this claim can be upheld, we must return to EIIp7. In the next section I will show that this latter parallelism proposition can indeed be understood to make the very same claim that 40 It is precisely this particular dual structure that enables Spinoza to claim (in the demonstration of EIVp8) that it is clear from EIIp21s, that an idea is ‘not really distinguished’ but ‘only conceptually distinguished’ from its object. EIVp8d, (I) 551 (ab ideâ Corporis affectionis reverâ non distinguitur, nisi solo conceptu). 311 was uncovered with respect to EIIp21s (and hence that EIIp7 can also be rendered in the way of table 5). Below it will become clear that EIIp7 must be read thus: The order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of the formal being of these ideas Furthermore, I will argue that the assertions in EIIp7s concerning the identity of a body and the idea of that body are merely implied by proposition 7 (and in a subsequent section it will be shown that the identity of an idea and the idea of that idea can be understood to follow from the comprehensive parallelism claim of EIIp7 as well). Another way of saying this is that the present interpretation entails that, unlike some commentators have claimed,41 the variants of parallelism that we have treated in this section must be understood to be conceptual variants of one overriding parallelism claim. It will become clear that EIIp7 and EIIp21s posit the very same identity (and representation) relation, a relation that can be understood to be an expression of the very trichotomous structure of the intellect that was uncovered in Chapter 2. 4.2.3 One parallelism Recall that EIIp7 reads thus: The order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of things.42 (Ordo, & connexio idearum idem est, ac ordo, & connexio rerum) We have just asserted tentatively that this proposition can also be formulated thus: The order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of the formal being of these ideas. 41 Yitzhak Melamed claimed the following:‘E2p7 and its scholium assert two separate and distinct doctrines of parallelism. The former asserts a parallelism between the causal order of ideas and things, the latter a parallelism among the causal order of modes in each of the infinitely many attributes.’ Yitzhak Melamed, Spinoza’s Metaphysics. Substance and Thought, 142. I fully agree with his latter claim. However, I disagree with his claim that these two variants are ‘separate and distinct’, as will become clear below. 42 EIIp7, (I) 451. 312 This formulation of course needs further elucidation. For the claim that the term ‘things’ in EIIp7 can be understood to refer to the formal being of ideas is controversial. Various commentators have suggested that the term ‘things’ must be understood to refer to bodies. Jonathan Bennett is a case in point. He stated that the res in proposition 7 are to be seen as modes of extension.43 Michael Della Rocca ‘for convenience’ assumes the same.44 In other words: some leading Spinoza scholars have considered the term ‘things’ in the important EIIp7 to refer to something else than the formal being of ideas. This need not surprise us, as Spinoza himself appears to do the same. Consider the following assertions: If the human body is not affected by an external body in any way, then (by P7) the idea of the human body […] is also not affected in any way by the idea of the existence of that body45 (Si à corpore aliquo externo Corpus humanum nullo modo affectum est, ergo (per Prop. 7. hujus) nec idea Corporis humani, […] ideâ existentiæ illius corporis ullo etiam modo affecta est) P 11: The idea of any thing that increases or diminishes, aids or restrains, our body's power of acting, increases or diminishes, aids or restrains, our mind's power of thinking. Dem.: This proposition is evident from IIP7 […]46 (PROPOSITIO XI. Quicquid Corporis nostri agendi potentiam auget, vel minuit, juvat, vel coërcet, ejusdem rei idea Mentis nostræ cogitandi potentiam auget, vel minuit, juvat, vel coërcet. DEMONSTRATIO. Hæc Propositio patet ex Propositione 7. Partis 2) These two passages suggest that Spinoza himself chooses the same convenient route that Della Rocca has taken. Indeed, Spinoza’s position appears to be rendered correctly in table 4: Natura naturans Thought = Extension = R --------------------------------------------------------------(c) God Natura naturata idea x = body x = rx (table 4) 43 According to Bennett, Spinoza ‘advocates a doctrine of parallelism between the mental and physical realm’, and in this respect he refers to EIIp7. This appears to imply that according to Bennett, the distinction between thought and extension surfaces explicitly in the mentioned proposition. See: Bennett, A Study of Spinoza’s Ethics, 127. 44 Della Rocca, Representation, 18. 45 EIIp26d, (I) 469. 46 EIIIp11, (I) 500. 313 Table 4 makes it clear that things (and their causal connection) that are operative under the attribute of thought are numerically identical to the parallel things (and their causal connection) under the attribute of extension (or any of the remaining attributes). As already noted, this appears to be a fair description of Spinoza’s parallelism. That is to say: table 4 is fully corroborated by Spinoza’s explicit assertions in the scholium of EIIp7. However, if table 4 renders the purport of proposition 7 itself correctly – as is suggested by the passages adduced above – then how can we still uphold the supposition that Spinoza refers to the formal being of ideas – and not to modes of extension – when he uses the term ‘things’ in EIIp7? Our seemingly idiosyncratic reading of EIIp7 suggests that Spinoza in this proposition does not primarily forward an inter-attribute parallelism between ideas, bodies and r’s, but an intra-attribute parallelism between the objective and the formal being of a thing. How can this latter position (and hence table 5) be brought in line with table 4? Actually, there is considerable evidence for the claim that in EIIp7 Spinoza does indeed assert that the order and connection of ideas (b-i) is the same as the order and connection of the formal being of these ideas (b-ii). Below I will provide additional arguments for this controversial contention. Apart from our observation that both types of parallelism must be understood to be intellect-dependent – and must thus be conceived to be characterized by the distinction between the formal and the objective being of things – there are at least four more arguments that underpin our seemingly idiosyncratic assertion concerning the purport of EIIp7. After having provided these arguments, it will become clear how the present claim about the intra-attribute identity of ideas and their formal beings can be brought in line with the inter-attribute identity of ideas and their bodies (and, in a subsequent section, how this can be understood to be related to the bottom-up perspective in Spinoza’s philosophy). Argument 1: the context of EIIp7 EIIp7 is embedded in a series of propositions that deal explicitly with the formal (EIIp5 and EIIp6c) and the objective being of things (EIIp8 and EIIp9). In the claims preceding EIIp7 it is made clear how we must conceive the causal generation of the formal being of things. And the two subsequent propositions deal 314 respectively with the interrelation between the formal and the objective status of things (EIIp8, its corollary and its scholium), and the way in which the objective being of things must be conceived to be caused (EIIp9). This provides us with a first contextual indication that EIIp7 refers to the relation, not between objective beings (i.e. ideas) and their objects under extension (i.e. bodies), but between ideas and their formal being. Argument 2: the corollary of EIIp7 Consider the following claim in EIIp7c: From this it follows that God's power of thinking is equal to his actual power of acting. That is, whatever follows formally from God's infinite nature follows objectively in God from his idea in the same order and with the same connection.47 (Hinc sequitur, quòd Dei cogitandi potentia æqualis est ipsius actuali agendi potentiæ. Hoc est, quicquid ex infinitâ Dei naturâ sequitur formaliter, id omne ex Dei ideâ eodem ordine, eâdemq́ue connexione sequitur in Deo objectivè) It is hard to miss the fact that the very terms that I claim to be applicable to the assertion in EIIp7 – the formal and the objective being of things – are used explicitly in the very corollary of this parallelism proposition. Indeed: whatever follows formally from God’s infinite nature, is claimed to follow objectively in God insofar as the thing under scrutiny is considered under the attribute of thought. This underpins the assertion that the formal-objective distinction plays an important role in EIIp7, and that this proposition (and EIIp8)48 can in a certain sense be considered to be the crossroads of Spinoza’s claims about the formal being of ideas (in EIIp5 and EIIp6c) and the objective being of these same things (in EIIp8c and EIIp9) (see the previous argument). But this is not all. There is a further way in which Spinoza’s claims in EIIp7c can be understood to corroborate our present claim. For on the basis of EIIp7c it can be shown that – unlike what is commonly supposed (see above) – the term ‘things’ in EIIp7 does not refer to extended objects. The following reductio argument may be elucidative in this respect: 47 48 EIIp7c, (I) 451. More on this seemingly hermetic proposition shortly. 315 (i) (ii) (iii) (iv) (v) (vi) (vii) (viii) Suppose that the term ‘things’ in EIIp7 does refer to bodies The order and connection of ideas is identical to the order and connection of bodies (by EIIp7 and (i)) From this (ii) it follows that ‘whatever follows formally from God's infinite nature follows objectively in God from his idea’ (EIIp7c) The things that follow objectively in God from his idea must be the ideas from (ii) (by the causal barrier of EIIp6)49 So the things that follow formally from God’s infinite nature must be understood to be the bodies from (ii) (by (ii), (iii) and (iv). Bodies must be understood to be the formal being of ideas (by (iii), (iv) and (v)) It is absurd to claim (as (vi) does) that bodies are the formal being of ideas (by EIIp5) So the term ‘things’ does not refer to bodies The crucial steps in this argument can be elucidated in the following way: Ad. (i)-(iii). These claims are rather straightforward; (i) is the supposition that we are testing, (ii) is EIIp7 rendered in terms of the supposition in (i), and (iii) is the restatement of the part of EIIp7c in which the terms ‘formal’ and ‘objective’ are staged. Ad (iv). The claim that the things that follow objectively in God from his idea must be the ideas from (ii) perhaps needs some more elucidation. As noted under (iv), this assertion is corroborated by the causal barrier that is posited EIIp6, from which it can be inferred that if things follow in God from his idea, they must be modes of thought (and not modes of extension). That the things that follow ‘objectively’ from God’s idea indeed are modes of thought (i.e. ideas) is further underpinned by the fact that in the Ethics Spinoza uses the term ‘objective’ only with respect to the 49 EIIp6 reads thus: ‘The modes of each attribute have God for their cause only insofar as he is considered under the attribute of which they are modes, and not insofar as he is considered under any other attribute’. EIIp6, (I) 450 (Cujuscunque attributi modi Deum, quatenus tantùm sub illo attributo, cujus modi sunt, & non, quatenus sub ullo alio consideratur, pro causâ habent). To be sure, we have already referred to this ‘causal barrier’ various times in the preceding chapters. 316 representational nature of thought.50 So it appears to be rather uncontroversial that the claim about the things that follow objectively in God from his idea must be understood to refer to the order and connection of ideas. Ad. (v)-(vi). In EIIp7, Spinoza makes a distinction between two classes of things. On the present supposition these two classes consist of respectively ideas and bodies. Now, if things that ‘follow objectively in God from his idea’ must be understood to be ideas (as was established in (iv)), there appears to be only one candidate left for the things that according to EIIp7c ‘follow formally from God’s infinite nature’: bodies. Indeed, if it is granted that in EIIp7c Spinoza employs the terms ‘formal’ and ‘objective’ in order to refer to a duality of the objective being of things and their formal being,51 then the formal being of the things that follow ‘objectively in God from his idea’ must be understood to be bodies. Hence: bodies must be understood to be the formal being of ideas. Ad. (vii) and (viii). Point (vi) states that bodies must be understood to be the formal being of ideas. Yet, as we have seen in Chapter 2, EIIp5 reads that ‘the formal being of ideas admits God as a cause only insofar as he is a thinking thing […]’. And in the demonstration of this proposition Spinoza adds that ‘the formal being of ideas is a mode of thinking’ which ‘involves the concept of no other attribute of God’. This makes it abundantly clear that point (vi) is wrong: in the context of Spinoza’s mature thought it is absurd that bodies should be the formal being of ideas. And hence the initial supposition (i) must be rejected: the term ‘things’ does not refer to bodies (viii). This argument teaches us that EIIp7 cannot be understood to make a claim about ideas and bodies (nor about ideas and finite modes of any of the remaining 50 See EIp17s, EIp30, EIIp8c. Or as Della Rocca claims: the traditional term ‘objective’ clearly indicates that Spinoza posits a representational aspect in EIIp7c. Della Rocca, Representation, 19. As I will show in a the next chapter, this representational aspect is a characteristic aspect of modes insofar as they are conceived under the attribute of thought (just as (say) motion is a characteristic aspect of modes insofar as they are conceived under the attribute of extension). 51 A duality that, as we saw in Chapter 2, entails a trichotomy of formal being, objective being and object. More on the import of this structure for Spinoza’s parallelism claims will follow shortly. 317 attributes). Argument 3: The formulation of EIIp8 As already noted in Chapter 2, EIIp8 is generally considered to be a rather hermetic proposition. Consider this proposition and its demonstration once more: P8: The ideas of singular things, or of modes, that do not exist must be comprehended in God’s infinite idea in the same way as the formal essences of the singular things, or modes, are contained in God’s attributes. Dem.: This proposition is evident from the preceding one, but is understood more clearly from the preceding scholium.52 (PROPOSITIO VIII. Ideæ rerum singularium, sive modorum non existentium ità debent comprehendi in Dei infinitâ ideâ, ac rerum singularium, sive modorum essentiæ formales in Dei attributis continentur. DEMONSTRATIO. Hæc Propositio patet ex præcedenti, sed intelligitur clariùs ex præcedenti Scholio) One of the problems that needs solving is why Spinoza would say something here about modes that do not exist. In the propositions that precede EIIp8, Spinoza speaks about modes that do exist. And then all of a sudden he switches to nonexisting singular things. Why? This puzzle is solved once it is acknowledged that EIIp7 deals with the very distinction that was uncovered in section 2.5: the distinction between durational ideas (b-ii) and the eternal formal status of these ideas (b-i). It is crucial to recognize that the question how we must understand the metaphysical status of modes that do not exist arises precisely because in the preceding proposition it is claimed that ideas (that exist under duration) have the same order and connection as these very same things considered in their eternal formal state. For it is this remarkable assertion that leads to the problem how things that do not exist now (such as (say) king Louis XIV of France), can be conceived to have the same order and connection as something that must be understood to exist eternally. If EIIp7 would deal with bodies and ideas only, the reference to EIIp7 in the demonstration of EIIp8 would be incomprehensible. On our present reading, however, it is clear why Spinoza would treat the ideas of modes that do not exist, and why he would refer to the preceding proposition. Indeed, Spinoza’s claim that the ideas of non-existing modes must be comprehended in God’s infinite idea in 52 EIIp8, (I) 452. 318 the same way the formal essences of these modes are contained in God’s attributes can only be understood to follow from the preceding proposition and its scholium if it is acknowledged that in these passages the very same distinction between an eternal realm of formality and a durational realm of objective beings is posited.53 And hence, the seemingly hermetic formulation of EIIp8 fully underpins our suggestion that EIIp7 must be understood to deal with the isomorphic causal chains of durational ideas (b-ii) and their eternal formal beings (b-i). Argument 4: The attribute-neutral aspect of the formal being of things EIIp7 deals with the order and connection of things (res). Above we have argued that the term must be understood to refer, not to bodies, but to the formal being of things. In order to establish whether we are right in claiming that EIIp7 deals with things in their formal being we can take yet another route. Consider the following claim from the demonstration of EVp1: The order and connections of ideas is the same as the order and connection of things (by IIP7), and vice versa, the order and connection of things is the same as the order and connection of ideas (by IIP6C and P7).54 (Ordo, & connexio idearum idem est (per Prop. 7. p. 2.), ac ordo, & connexio rerum, & vice versâ, ordo, & connexio rerum idem est (per Coroll. Prop. 6. & 7. p. 2.), ac ordo, & connexio idearum) This passage makes it clear that the term ‘things’ in EIIp7 must be understood to refer to the ‘things’ that are treated in EIIp6c. This latter corollary reads thus: From this it follows that the formal being of things which are not modes of thinking does not follow from the divine nature because [God] has first known the things; rather the objects of ideas follow and are I use the epithet ‘formality’ here because the eternal status is applicable to both the formal essence and the formal being of things. 54 EVp1d, (I) 597. The ‘vice versa’ deserves some attention: this term seems to imply that ‘ideas’ and ‘things’ operate at the same conceptual level, whereas my contention is that this is not the case (as I will claim that the relation is vertical). This problem disappears once we realise that Spinoza is reasoning specifically about the causal characteristics of these items. The claim that ‘Dutchmen are Europeans, and vice versa’ is untrue. However, it is completely sound to say that ‘the cause by way of which Dutchmen come into being is the same as the cause by way of which Europeans come into being, and vice versa’. The same applies to the present subject: the causation is applicable to both classes of things in the same way, even though there is a conceptual priority of one class over the other. 53 319 inferred from their attributes in the same way as that with which we have shown ideas to follow from the attribute of thought.55 (Hinc sequitur, quòd esse formale rerum, quæ modi non sunt cogitandi, non sequitur ideò ex divinâ naturâ, quia res priùs cognovit, sed eodém modo, eâdemq́ue necessitate res ideatæ ex suis attributis consequuntur, & concluduntur, ac ideas ex attributo Cogitationis consequi ostendimus) Now, it must be admitted that prima facie this reference suggests that the term ‘things’ does refer to bodies (or finite modes of any of the remaining attributes). For Spinoza clearly equates ‘things’ with ‘the objects of ideas’,56 which appears to imply that he is reasoning here about bodies (and modes of the remaining attributes). However, this leads to a problem. For above we have seen that the term ‘things’ in EIIp7 cannot be understood to refer to modes of any of the other attributes. Above it became clear that it is absurd that a body (or a finite mode from any of the remaining attributes) should be the formal being of an idea, as Spinoza claims in EIIp5d that the formal being of ideas is a mode of thinking. Is there a way out of this? I think there is. Knowing (i) that Spinoza states in EIIp6c that ‘the objects of ideas follow and are inferred from their attributes in the same way as that with which we have shown ideas to follow from the attribute of thought’, and (ii) that the only causal thread that is treated explicitly at this point in part II of the Ethics is the intrinsic causal thread of EIIp5,57 we seem to have gained enough ground to suppose that ‘the objects of ideas’ that ‘follow and are inferred from their attributes in the same way as’ the formal being of ideas can be understood to refer, not to the extrinsically caused finite modes of extension and the remaining attributes, but to the intrinsically caused formal being of these things. And hence we can proceed our investigation with the tentative claim that EIIp7 can be reformulated thus: The order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of the f o r m a l b e i n g of things which are not modes of thinking (i.e. the e s s e f o r m a l e rerum) 55 EIIp6c, (I) 450-451. In order to refer to the ‘object of ideas’, Spinoza uses the term ‘ideatum’ – instead of ‘objectum’. In Chapter 5 it will become clear why he would choose this term in this specific context. 57 As we have seen that the extrinsic causal thread of finite objective beings surfaces explicitly only in EIIp9; see section 2.5. 56 320 To be sure, with this reformulation we have not yet found a decisive answer to the question we aim to treat in this section. For one thing, the claim that the term ‘things’ refers to the esse formale rerum of EIIp6c needs more underpinning. Moreover, it was not our aim to establish that the order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of the formal being of things which are not modes of thinking. Rather, we intended to show that EIIp7 can be understood thus: The order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of the formal being o f t h e s e i d e a s So one of the questions we face now is whether there is a way to get from the claim concerning the formal being of things which are not modes of thinking to a claim that deals with the formal being of ideas. Now, I think there is such a way. In order to show this, I must adduce the reductio ad absurdum that was provided above once more, and substitute the term ‘bodies’ with ‘esse formale rerum’. If it is assumed that term ‘things’ in EIIp7 can be understood to refer to the esse formale rerum of EIIp6c, then the argument can be restated in the following way: (i′) (ii′) (iii′) (iv′) (v′) (vi′) The term ‘things’ in EIIp7 refers to the esse formale rerum of EIIp6c The order and connection of ideas is identical to the order and connection of the esse formale rerum (by EIIp7 and (i′)) From this (ii’) it follows that ‘whatever follows formally from God's infinite nature follows objectively in God from his idea’ (EIIp7c) The things that follow objectively from God’s idea must be the ideas from (ii′) (by the causal barrier of EIIp6) So the things that follow formally from God’s infinite nature must be understood to be the esse formale rerum from (ii′) (by (ii′), (iii′) and (iv′). The esse formale rerum must be understood to be the formal being of ideas (by (iii′), (iv′) and (v′)) Point (vi′) can count as a step forward in comparison with the reductio argument (i)-(viii) that was provided above. It neutralizes part of the incongruence that surfaced in the reductio ad absurdum from Argument 2. Whereas in the reductio 321 argument the (durational) extended body was staged as the (eternal) formal being of the idea under scrutiny, point (vi′) suggests that it is not the extended object of the idea (i.e. its body) that can be understood to serve as the formal being of the idea under scrutiny, but the formal being of this extended object. Indeed, whereas in the reductio variant of the argument the eternal and infinite formal being of an idea appeared to be a durational and finite thing (in casu: a body), point (vi′) safeguards that the eternal and infinite formal being of an idea is an eternal and infinite formal being. To be sure, this observation still does not fully corroborate the present supposition. For above we have seen that the formal being of an idea must be understood to be a mode of thinking (by EIIp5d). And hence we can only consider our claim to be validated (and argument (i′)-(viii′) not to be an incomplete rendering of yet another reductio argument) once we have shown that the horizontal conceptual distinction between the eternal formal being of ideas and the identical (by (vi′)) eternal formal being of non-mental modes (at level (b-i)) is less impermeable than the distinction between finite ideas and their identical finite bodies (at level b-ii)). Now, is it? Can the referential opacity58 that is applicable to modes insofar as they are considered objectively (i.e. the distinction between ideas and their extended objects) be understood to be neutralized if these singular things are considered in their formal being? I think it can be conjectured that this indeed is the case. That is to say: in a certain sense – and as opposed to modes insofar as they are conceived in their durational state – the formal being of modes can be understood to have an aspect of attribute-neutrality. Whereas durational things (such as ideas and bodies at level (b-ii)) can only be considered insofar as they are subsumed under a certain attribute, their eternal being at level (b-i) can (also) be understood insofar as it follows in an attribute-neutral way from God qua God. Prima facie, this solution may appear to rest on mere speculation. Indeed, it must be admitted that the concept of ‘attribute-neutrality’ does not surface explicitly in the Ethics. The existence of ‘attribute-neutral’ modes or features may have been forwarded by several scholars,59 but this sheer fact of course cannot serve 58 In this context, this term is inspired by Michael Della Rocca. See section 4.3.1 and note 95. Yitzhak Melamed calls these attribute-neutral modes ‘modes of God’. See: Melamed, Spinoza’s Metaphysics. Substance and Thought, 82-86. The same term is used by Gueroult. Gueroult, Spinoza. Dieu, 339. Jonathan Bennett calls them ‘attribute-neutral differentiae’. Bennett, A Study of Spinoza’s Ethics, 144145. Della Rocca stresses that the concept of ‘mode […] of no attribute whatsoever […] is Spinozistically 59 322 as an underpinning for our present claim; we are in need of additional textual evidence. That is to say: as I do not want to take refuge in an argumentum ad verecundiam, we must test whether there are indications in the Ethics that corroborate our claim (i) that Spinoza makes implicit use of the concept of attribute-neutrality, and (ii) that this attribute-neutrality can be understood to be applicable to the formal being of things. So is there any textual support for the assertion that the Ethics harbors the concept of attribute-neutrality? Perhaps unsurprisingly, I think there is. The first passage that must be adduced in this respect is EIIp7c. The already quoted claim that ‘whatever follows formally from God's infinite nature follows objectively in God from his idea’ provides us with an important indication that attributeneutrality is an implicit feature of Spinoza’s parallelism. For it is hard to see how the term ‘God’s infinite nature’ can be understood to be attribute-dependent; as God is defined in EID6 as ‘a substance consisting of an infinity of attributes’, the term ‘God’s infinite nature’ appears to denote the divine being, irrespective of the way its essence is perceived by the intellect, that is: God in his absolute, attributeneutral being. So far so good. It appears to be rather clear that the concept ‘God’ is prior to the concept ‘attribute’ and hence that attribute-neutrality is an implicit feature of Spinoza’s metaphysics. But this is of course not to say that modes can be conceived to be attribute-neutral as well. The question we must answer is not whether God is attribute-neutral, but whether the formal being of singular things can be understood as such; can the implicit attribute-neutrality of God qua God be understood to ‘contaminate’ the things that follow formally from the necessity of the divine nature? Indeed, we must answer the question whether the attribute-dependent modes that follow ‘objectively in God from his idea’ can be allotted an attributeneutral aspect insofar as they follow ‘formally from God’s infinite nature’. Now, with respect to this important question it is crucial to acknowledge that in fact we have already distinguished the ingredients on the basis of which the attributeneutral feature of modes in their formal state can be understood. For in the unacceptable’. Della Rocca, Representation, 121. However, at the same time he writes that ‘there is […] a small, but important class of extensional properties’. Ibidem 129. These are ‘properties […] that [do] not presuppose that the item with that property is of a particular attribute’. Ibidem 132. Samuel Newlands argued that the conceptual dependence relations in Spinoza’s philosophy must be understood to be attribute-neutral. Newlands, ‘Another Kind of Spinozistic Monism’, 472. 323 previous chapters it was shown that there is a close relation between extraintellectual formal essences in Natura Naturans and intra-intellectual formal beings in Natura naturata. It became clear that the absolute non-distinctiveness and ubiquity of the extra-intellectual formal essences of things at the level of God qua God (a) must be understood to be prolonged in the intra-intellectual formal being of these same things insofar as they are conceived to function as pervasive partswith-a-vista at the level of the immediate infinite modes (b-i). It is precisely here where we must locate the ‘contamination’ that we are looking for. I claim that the attribute-neutral aspect of things in their formal being must be understood to find its root in the attribute-neutrality of the formal essences of things at the level of God q u a God. That is to say: just as the formal beings of things can be attributed a certain species of eternity insofar as they are conceived to follow from the absolutely eternal formal essences, so also these formal beings can be ascribed a certain species of attribute-neutrality insofar as they are conceived to follow from the absolutely attribute-neutral formal essences. This can be rendered thus: (a) (b-i) Formal essences are attribute-neutral eo ipso, as they must be understood to be operative at the level of absolute identity (i.e. Natura naturans (a)).60 Formal beings can be conceived in two ways. Insofar as these partswith-a-vista are conceived in their part character, they can be subsumed under an attribute (namely the attribute of which the immediate infinite mode is the whole they are conceived to be a part of); and insofar as these parts-with-a-vista are conceived in their vistacharacter, they can be understood to express the absolute ubiquity of the formal essences they follow from, and hence transfer the attributeneutrality of their formal essences to the level of Natura naturata (b-i). This way of understanding the attribute-neutrality of the formal being of things finds corroboration in the already adduced claim of EIIp7c. Recall that this corollary reads thus: 60 More on the absolute identity and attribute-neutrality of the divine nature (a) in section 4.3.3.1. 324 From this it follows that God's power of thinking is equal to his actual power of acting. That is, whatever follows formally from God's infinite nature follows objectively in God from his idea in the same order and with the same connection.61 (Hinc sequitur, quòd Dei cogitandi potentia æqualis est ipsius actuali agendi potentiæ. Hoc est, quicquid ex infinitâ Dei naturâ sequitur formaliter, id omne ex Dei ideâ eodem ordine, eâdemq́ue connexione sequitur in Deo objectivè) With respect to this claim it is informative to recall what was said in section 3.6. There it was shown that God’s power of acting can be understood to encompass his power of thinking, his power of moving (and being at rest) and his power of r-ing. Indeed, as ‘God’s power is God’s essence itself’,62 there appears to be no ground at all to suppose that ‘God’s power of acting’ must be assigned to a specific attribute (and hence that EIIp7c and (by implication) EIIp7 deal with ideas and bodies). Rather, the adduced clause appears to state that everything that follows formally from God’s attribute-neutral infinite nature must be understood to fall within the scope of God’s all-encompassing power, and hence can (also) be understood irrespective of the attribute under which it is considered. This prolonged63 absolute identity of the extended and the mental being of a thing can be gathered from EIIp6c too. Recall that we have shown in Chapter 2 that the formal being of ideas must be understood to be caused intrinsically. Furthermore, as we saw above, in EIIp6c this variant of causation is deemed applicable to modes of any of the other attributes as well. If it is acknowledged that the clause ‘God’s infinite nature’ in EIIp7c indeed is attribute-neutral in the sense that it must be understood to encompass all the ways in which the essence of this nature can be perceived by an intellect (i.e. all the intellect-dependent attributes, including thought), then the claim in EIIp7c that ‘whatever follows formally from God's infinite nature follows objectively in God from his idea in the same order and with the same connection’ can be understood to say that whatever is caused intrinsically from God’s infinite nature follows objectively in God from his idea in 61 EIIp7c, (I) 451. EIp34, (I) 439 (Dei potentia est ipsa ipsius essentia). 63 This absolute identity is claimed to be ‘prolonged’ as in the present reading it is understood to cross the boundary between Natura naturans and Natura naturata. Recall that we used the same term with respect to the eternity and infinity of the formal being of things (see section 2.4.3). This is no coincidence. The present claim implies that the attribute-neutral character of God can be understood to follow from the divine res in the very same intrinsic way the eternity and infinity of the formal being of things can be conceived to proceed from the necessity of the divine nature (see section 2.7.2). 62 325 the same order and with the same connection. That is to say: as EIIp6c is aimed at stressing that as to the intrinsic causation of things there is no distinction whatsoever between the formal being of ideas and the formal being of modes of the other attributes,64 we are able to conclude once more that the things that follow intrinsically from God’s attribute-neutral infinite nature can be understood to have an attribute-neutral aspect (as well). As this point is crucial, I will provide yet another argument for it. Consider the following claim in EIIp9d, where Spinoza provides a paraphrase of EIIp7: But the order and connection of ideas (by P7) is the same as the order and connection of causes.65 (Atqui ordo, & connexio idearum (per Prop. 7. hujus) idem est, ac ordo, & connexio causarum) This assertion is important in the present context, as it makes it clear that the term ‘things’ in EIIp7 can be understood to be equivalent (or can at least be used salva veritate) to the attribute-neutral term ‘causarum’. Now, it appears to be fairly clear that this latter term must be considered to be attribute-neutral. For it is precisely because of this that the example of the raising arm (see above) can function at all. Spinoza can only foster a numerical identity of the order and connection of modes that resort under different attributes (which, as we saw, he forwards explicitly in EIIp7s) if the causal laws that are operative in these attributes are exactly the same. In order to prevent the possibility of a ‘representational mismatch’66 between (say) a raising arm and the idea of that raising arm, the causal power that can be recognized in nature must be understood to be attribute-neutral. The next thing that must be noted is that this attribute-neutrality of causes is not only applicable to the extrinsic causal thread of durational finite modes, but also the intrinsic causal thread of eternal infinite modes. As argued for in Chapter 2, EIIp5 posits an intrinsic top-down causal thread in the realm of thought. EIIp6c 64 It is because of this that Spinoza adds in EIIp6c that ‘the formal being of things which are not modes of thinking does not follow from the divine nature because God has first known the things [emphasis added]’. EIIp6c, (I) 450-451 (esse formale rerum, quæ modi non sunt cogitandi, non sequitur ideò ex divinâ naturâ, quia res priùs cognovit). The duality between knowing (in thought) and the thing that is known (in another attribute) is not applicable to God’s infinite nature. And hence the distinction between the attributes is not applicable to God qua God (a). 65 EIIp9d, (I) 453. 66 The term is Della Rocca’s. Della Rocca, Representation, 44-45. To be sure, Della Rocca understands the representational nature of Spinoza’s parallelism in a way that is different from mine, as will become clear in the next chapter. 326 makes it clear that the top-down causal thread that is staged in EIIp5 is not only applicable to the mental realm, but to the modes of the other attributes as well (see above). Just as the formal being of ideas follows ‘from the absolute nature of some attribute of God’ (EIp23d), so also the formal being of the modes of any other of the infinite attributes must be understood to ‘follow from the absolute nature of some attribute of God’, without God first knowing these things.67 Now, if it is acknowledged that the intrinsically caused formal beings of things are all subject to God’s causal power – that is (by EIp34): God’s attribute-neutral essence68 – in the very same way, it becomes clear once more that descriptions such as ‘the formal being of ideas’, ‘the formal being of bodies’ and ‘the formal being of r’s’ can all be considered to be members of the same class of attribute-neutral formal beings.69 As the ‘res’ are treated as to an aspect that is absolutely identical in each case (i.e. the fact that they follow immediately from God qua God), the ‘res’ in this context can be considered to be attribute-neutral in a certain respect. It is the very attributeneutrality of the causal claims in EIIp5 and EIIp6c that safeguards that the term ‘things’ in EIIp7 can be understood to fall without the scope of the referential opacity that is applicable to modes if they are considered to resort unconditionally under a certain attribute. Insofar as the formal beings of things are considered as to their causal order and connection, there is a perspective from which the fact that they must be understood to fall under one particular attribute can be ignored. Stated in terms of EIIp7c this is to say that the modes that are conceived to follow objectively as ideas in God from his idea, have an attribute-neutral aspect insofar as they are conceived to follow formally from God’s infinite nature.70 67 See note 64. It is precisely because of this that ‘God’s intellect insofar as it is understood to constitute his essence’ (EIp17s) must be understood to differ fundamentally from our intellect: God’s thinking essence is absolutely identical to his all-encompassing essence and hence, as opposed to noster intellectus, is not characterized by any duality. See the chapters 1 and 3. 68 ‘God’s power is his essence itself’ (Dei potentia est ipsa ipsius essentia). EIp34, (I) 439. 69 This can also be deduced from the demonstration of EVp1, which reads: ‘the order and connections of ideas is the same as the order and connection of things (by EIIp7), and vice versa, the order and connection of things is the same as the order and connection of ideas (by IIP6C and P7)’. EVp1d, (I) 597. See note 54. 70 Two things must be added. Firstly, one may object here that the extrinsic causal thread (that surfaces both in EIp28 and EIIp9) is attribute-neutral too (as it can be understood to be operative in any of the infinite attributes) and hence that the durational being of things can also be understood to have an aspect of attribute-neutrality (namely, insofar as they are conceived to be caused). Now, it is true that the extrinsic causal thread is attribute-neutral – this was actually stated above. But the crucial thing to note is that this attribute-neutrality cannot be understood to nullify the ‘referential opacity of causal contexts’ 327 With this we have made considerable progress in elucidating and corroborating our claim that the term ‘things’ can be understood to refer to the esse formale of EIIp5 and EIIp6c. The conceptual distinction between the formal being of ideas and the formal being of things that surfaced in point (vi′) indeed appears to be less impermeable than the conceptual distinction between ideas and their extended objects. For whereas in this latter case the absolute attribute-dependent context accounts for referential opacity, the identity of the formal beings from point (vi′) is not threatened by attribute-dependent referential opacity, as these formal beings can be understood insofar as they follow from the attribute-neutral necessity of the divine nature. To be sure, there still appears to be a problem with (Della Rocca, Representation, 166) as the things that are operative in the extrinsic causal thread do not follow from God in its absolute being. It is precisely the absolute being of the intrinsically causing prima causa that accounts for the specific attribute-neutral aspect of the formal being of things; insofar as things are conceived to be operative in an extrinsic causal thread only, there is no p r i m a c a u s a (and hence no prima cause that can be conceived in its absolute being, ‘contaminating’ the being of things with an aspect of attribute-neutrality). The second thing that can be noted here is that the close relation between EIIp7 and EIIp6c becomes evident also when considering the stunning brevity of Spinoza’s proof for EIIp7. The demonstration of this proposition reads thus: ‘This is clear from IA4. For the idea of each thing caused depends on the knowledge of the cause of which it is the effect.’ (Patet ex Ax. 4. p. 1. Nam cujuscunque causati idea à cognitione causæ, cujus est effectus, dependet), EIIp7d, (I) 451. EIA4 only states that ‘[t]he knowledge of an effect depends on, and involves, the knowledge of its cause’, EIA4, (I) 410. Understandably, various commentators have hinted at the meagerness of the demonstration of EIIp7. Jonathan Bennett rightfully states that ‘1a4 does not rule out mental items which do not match any physical items’ in: Bennett, A Study of Spinoza’s Ethics, 130. And Michael Della Rocca makes the same point when he says that ‘1ax4 does not by itself guarantee the thoroughgoing parallelism that Spinoza has in mind in 2p7.’ in: Della Rocca, Representation, 22. However, if it is acknowledged that the reference to EIA4 in EIIp7 is in fact connected closely to the reference to the same axiom in the preceding proposition EIIp6, things may become a bit clearer. Recall that EIIp6 reads that the modes of each attribute have God for their cause only insofar as he is considered under the attribute of which they are modes (see note 49). Now, it is crucial to recognize that Spinoza proves EIIp6 with the help of the very axiom EIA4 that is cited in EIIp7 (the very axiom, it can be added, by which – in the words of Della Rocca – ‘causation is […] made intelligible in terms of intelligibility itself’ – see Introduction, note 39). Spinoza posits in EIIp6 that the characteristic that is forwarded in it is applicable to the modes of any of the infinite attributes. In this sense the causal claim of EIIp6 (and EIA4) can be understood to be attribute-neutral. Furthermore, from EIIp6c it becomes clear that this attribute-neutrality is applicable to things that follow from God’s absolute nature as well. So on this account, EIA4 can be understood to imply that the knowledge of an effect, whether conceived to be caused intrinsically or extrinsically, depends on, and involves, the knowledge of its (intrinsic or extrinsic) cause. In this sense Spinoza is able to claim in EIIp7 that the order and connection of things that are considered insofar as they are caused extrinsically as objective beings, must be understood to be the same as the order and connection of these very same things insofar as they are conceived to be caused intrinsically as formal beings. And apparently he thinks that his treatment of the esse formale in EIIp5 and EIIp6c (as well as the purport of causal axiom EIA4) is so clear, that he does not even bother to mention it in the demonstration of EIIp7. 328 the present interpretation. For does Spinoza not state explicitly (in the demonstration of EIIp5) that the formal being of an idea must be understood, not to be attribute-neutral, but to be a mode of thinking? Indeed, we have used this very argument ourselves in our rejection of the horizontal reading of EIIp7 (see the reductio ad absurdum (i)-(viii), point (vii)). So how can we nevertheless uphold the claim that the formal being of an idea can be understood to have an attributeneutral aspect? Precisely here the importance of the distinction that was mentioned in the introduction to this chapter – i.e. the distinction between the top-down and the bottom-up perspectives – and its relation with Spinoza’s parallelism comes to light. Although this subject will be treated comprehensively only in a subsequent section, it must be noted here that the formal being of an idea, which can be conceived as to an a t t r i b u t e - n e u t r a l a s p e c t if it is conceived to follow t o p - d o w n f r o m God’s infinite (and attribute-neutral) nature, must be understood to be an attribute-d e p e n d e n t mode of thinking if it is conceived from the b o t t o m - u p perspective of thought.71 This claim – that actually is a restatement of our assertion that the formal being of a thing can be conceived both in its part- and in its vista-character (see above) – may sound all too hermetic. Therefore I will provide a preliminary example that may elucidate things a bit (even though it is hard to provide an example which adequately explains what we speak of here).72 Suppose we have two glasses. One is filled with water and the other is filled with milk. So now we have a glass of water and a glass of milk. Two children enter the room, they both take a glass and drink it until virtually no liquid is left. Thus we are left with two almost empty glasses: an almost empty glass of water and an almost empty glass of milk. As This same distinction surfaces in Martial Gueroult’s claim that there can be considered to be three parallelisms in Spinoza’s philosophy. Apart from the inter-attribute parallelism between ideas and bodies, Gueroult discerns two intra-attribute parallelisms: in one case the idea is taken in its ‘formal essence, as mode of thinking, a cause in the infinite chain of causes in Thought’ (L’idée considérée comme e s s e n c e f o r m e l l e (ou être formelle), mode de la Pensée, cause comprise dans la chaîne infinie des causes dans la pensée), and in the other case the idea is taken ‘in its form or nature as idea of idea’ (L’idée considérée dans sa f o r m e ou n a t u r e , comme idée de l’idée). Gueroult, Spinoza. L’Ame, 70. These two variants correspond with the two ways of understanding the formal being of ideas that will be presented in this section. To be sure, I claim that these two variants – as well as the inter-attribute parallelism of EIIp7s – must be considered to be variants of the one overriding variant of parallelism that is posited in EIIp7. 72 Attentive readers will have noticed that this formulation is inspired by a remark from Spinoza himself in EIIp8c. This is no coincidence, as the present example treats the same subject: the distinct conceptual states of the very same thing. 71 329 the father of the two children is thirsty himself, he decides to really empty the glasses. He does so, and empties both glasses till the last molecule; not a single trace of milk or water can be found in the two glasses. Reasoning from the perspective of the father and the children we are left with a totally empty glass of milk and a totally empty glass of water. Of course the glasses can also be described differently: they are just two empty glasses. When the mother enters the room after a day’s work and notices that the father did not tidy up the room as promised, she may get angry about the two empty glasses that are still standing on the table. However, it is nonsensical for her to say to her husband that he should have cleared away the ‘empty glass of milk and the empty glass of water’. She will refer to the objects simply as ‘the empty glasses’. As the milk-water information is not available to her, she only considers the glasses qua glasses.73 Now, a similar thing seems to happen with respect to the formal being of things. From a top-down perspective, the formal being of an idea must be considered to be an esse formale that does not belong to a certain ‘preferred attribute’; in this sense this formal being can be understood to proceed from an adequate idea of the formal essence of God’s attributes74 (i.e. topdown), and can be called a ‘mode of God’ (to use a phrase from Yitzhak 73 One may object that considered in this way, God’s position (which is represented by the mother) is less powerful then our position (which is represented by the father) as the father has knowledge (i.e. the milkwater information) that is not available to the mother. And hence the example appears to state that we have knowledge that is not available to God. However, once we realize that the milk-water information is a representation of the intellect-dependent attributes, the claim that the father is more powerful than the mother boils down to the claim that something with an intellect (such as the human animal) is more powerful than God, who according to Spinoza does not have an intellect. Now, this is evidently absurd in the context of Spinoza’s philosophy. Another way of saying this is that it must be granted that we have knowledge that is not available to God insofar as God is considered in his (a)-variant that (as opposed to God (c)) is absolutely free from an intellect in the way we commonly understand it. Claiming that God qua God has an intellect in the way we commonly understand it (i.e. claiming that the milk-water information is available to God qua God) implies a diminution of his power. The suggestion that God qua God must also be understood to have access to the milk-water-information is on a par with the claim that God qua God must have three angles, just because the triangle that is in him has three angles. As must be clear from these remarks – and from the things that were said in the previous chapter – these claims can only be made with respect to the coalescent concept of God (i.e. God (c)). In terms of the milk-water information: this information can only be understood to be available to the mother insofar as the mother is considered to be a coalescent aspect of the family she forms with her husband and children. See also Chapter 3, note 153. 74 Attentive readers will doubtlessly have noticed that I use a part the very formulation with which Spinoza elucidates his ‘third kind of knowledge’. Evidently, this is no coincidence. The ratio behind the use of this formulation will become clear in the next chapter. 330 Melamed).75 Yet, if the formal being of this idea is grasped on the basis of an idea (i.e. bottom-up), this very same formal being somehow ‘belongs to’ the attribute it is comprehended in, in pretty much the same way the glasses from the perspective of the father and the children ‘belong to’ the fluids that were in them. We will return to the distinction between the top-down and the bottom-up perspective in a subsequent section (and will provide textual support for (i) this distinction, and (ii) the close relation with Spinoza’s parallelism claims as well as his view on the structure of the intellect). The thing to note here is that the distinction between these two perspectives makes it clear that Spinoza’s claim in EIIp5d that the formal being of an idea is a mode of thinking, does not counteract our claim that the formal being of an idea can be grasped as to an attribute-neutral aspect as well. And hence we are in a position to draw an important conclusion with respect to the way in which we must understand the term ‘things’ in EIIp7. In the context of the present argument it was already established tentatively that EIIp7 can be rendered thus: The order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of the formal being of things which are not modes of thinking (i.e. the e s s e f o r m a l e r e r u m ) As we have seen that considered top-down the esse formale rerum in EIIp6c can be understood from an attribute-neutral perspective, and that ‘the formal being of ideas’ can be conceived to be a subcategory of the esse formale, we are able to conclude that EIIp7 can also be rendered in the following way: the order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of the formal being of ideas (and modes of the other attributes) * 75 See note 59. One more thing must be added. At this point it may appear that we are actually speaking here about the very formal essences that were referred to in Chapter 2. However, it must be stressed that this is not the case. The crucial thing to note in this respect is that we are dealing here with things that are claimed to follow from God, which makes it clear that the attribute-neutrality that is treated here is the attribute-neutrality of the formal beings at Natura naturata, and not of the (ontologically identical) formal essences at Natura naturans. To be sure, the attribute-neutrality of pervasive formal beings is evidently closely connected with the absolute attribute-neutrality of the ubiquitous formal essences they must be conceived to follow from. 331 In this section I have treated four arguments for the claim that EIIp7 must be understood to posit a parallelism relation, not between ideas and bodies, but between ideas and the formal being of these ideas. We have seen (i) that EIIp7 is embedded in a series of propositions that deal with the formal and the objective being of things, (ii) that EIIp7c implies that ‘things’ in EIIp7 cannot be understood to refer to finite modes of extension, (iii) that the hermetic EIIp8 makes it clear that EIIp7 must be understood to deal with the eternal and the durational being of things, and (iv) that considered top-down the esse formale that surface in EIIp5 and EIIp6c can be conceived as to an attribute-neutral aspect that nullifies the ‘referential opacity of causal contexts’ and hence that the formal being of ideas and the formal being of modes of the other attributes can be understood to be absolutely identical. Thus, we are in a position to state that EIIp7 claims that the order and connection of the objective being of things is the same as the order and connection of the formal being of things. Idiosyncratic as this reading of EIIp7 may have seemed at first sight, I have provided considerable evidence for the claim that Spinoza’s ‘parallelism proposition’ must be read in this particular way. To be sure, not all the problems that this reading gives rise to are solved yet. One of the pressing questions that is in need of an answer is how this ‘vertical’76 reading of EIIp7 can be brought in line with the inter-attribute reading that – as we saw – surfaces explicitly in various passages from the Ethics. For the present interpretation can only be considered to do justice to Spinoza’s claims if it also provides a way to understand the ‘horizontal’ inter-attribute relation between ideas and their parallel bodies. This is the subject to which we will turn now. 76 I use the term ‘vertical’ here because on the present reading there is posited a relation between the levels (b-i) and (b-ii), that stand in some sort of hierarchical relation (as in Spinoza’s philosophy the eternity of (b-i) appears to have a more ‘real’ status than the duration of b-ii)). To be sure, it is important to stress that this ‘vertical’ relation is not on a par with intra-attribute parallelism. Firstly it must be noted that the vertical relation is between modes of a certain attribute (at (b-ii)) and their identity with modes that are attribute-neutral (at (b-i)) – which of course implies that the vertical relation does not stay within the boundaries of a certain attribute. Secondly, it is important to stress that a horizontal relation (i.e. an identity relation between two modes that both are operative at level (b-ii)) does not necessarily cross the boundaries between the attributes. Indeed, the very relation between an idea and the idea of that idea must be understood to be a horizontal relation that nevertheless stays within the boundaries of the attribute of thought. A subsequent section will be dedicated to the question how this idea of the idea (at (b-ii)), that is related horizontally to its idea (at (b-ii)), is related vertically to the formal being of its idea (at (b-i)). 332 4.2.3.1 Two parallelisms reconciled So far we have been focusing mainly on the vertical ontological identity and conceptual distinction of things. For we concluded that EIIp7, with its reference to ‘the order and connection of ideas’ and ‘the order and connection of things’, actually establishes an identity relation, not between finite things, but between (b-i) the eternal and infinite formal being of a thing and (b-ii) its durational and finite objective being. The horizontal relation between durational finite things that are conceived under different attributes – i.e. ideas and bodies – (and indeed the relation between ideas and ideas of these ideas),77 remained (mostly) out of sight. However, Spinoza explicitly posits such a horizontal relation (i.e. an identityrelation between things that both are operative at the level of duration (b-ii)) in EIIp7s, where it is stated that ‘a mode of extension and the idea of that mode are one and the same thing, but expressed in two ways’.78 This claim clearly posits the identity of singular modes of different attributes. As we have seen that in other propositions not EIIp7s but EIIp7 itself is staged as the foundation for the parallelism between ideas and bodies, we face the question in what way this interattribute parallelism can be understood to be grounded in the intrinsic distinction between the formality and objectivity of things that was uncovered in the previous section. Indeed: how can our tables 4 and 5 can be reconciled? Recall that these two tables provided the following – apparently opposing – renderings of Spinoza’s parallelism thesis: Natura naturans Thought = Extension = R --------------------------------------------------------------(c) God Natura naturata idea x = body x = rx (table 4) And: 77 78 This identity relation between ideas and the ideas of these ideas will be treated in section 4.3.2. EIIp7s, (I) 451. 333 Natura naturans (a) God qua God ---------------------------------------------------------------(b-i) The formal being of singular things is identical to Natura naturata (b-ii) The objective being of singular things (c) God (table 5) At first glance, these tables appear to state something different. Yet, given what we have seen above, we are in a position to see how table 4 and 5 can be brought in line. The first thing to stress in this respect is that the attributes in table 4 are staged in their ontological variant (see section 3.6). In this particular state, the attributes must be understood to be ontologically and conceptually identical to the very infinite nature of God (i.e. God qua God (a)).79 Another way of saying this is that God’s essence is absolutely attribute-neutral, that is: his essence must be understood to exist irrespective of the way it is perceived via an intellect.80 Indeed, as (by EIIp7c) ‘God's power of thinking is equal to his actual power of acting’ – and as there is no reason to attach the designation ‘power of acting’ to a ‘preferred attribute’ – the designations ‘Thought’, ‘Extension’ and ‘R’ from table 4 can all be captured under the one designation ‘God qua God (a)’ that surfaces in table 5. Hence table 4 can also be rendered thus: Natura naturans (a) God qua God --------------------------------------------------------------(c) God Natura naturata idea x = body x = rx (table 4′) Secondly, we have seen in Chapter 2 that modes of the infinite attributes can be understood in two ways: objectively as finite durational modes, and formally as infinite eternal modes. This can be rendered thus: Natura naturans (a) God qua God --------------------------------------------------------------(b-i) form x form x form x Natura naturata - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - is identical to - - - - - - - - - - - - (b-ii) idea x = body x = rx (c) God (table 4″) 79 80 For a further elucidation of this claim, see section 4.3.3.1. The extra-intellectual ‘existence’ of God’s essence was treated in Chapter 3. 334 Thirdly, it became clear that the absolute identity of the attributes at the level of Natura naturans can be understood to be mirrored in the formal beings of things insofar as these are conceived to follow top-down from God’s absolutely infinite nature. That is to say: these formal beings can be considered to be attributeneutral in the very same way God qua God (and indeed the formal essences that are contained ubiquitously in God qua God) is. Insofar as the formal being of things is considered to follow top-down from God qua God, the absolute divine attributeneutrality is transferred to the level of Natura naturata (or, as we have formulated it somewhat awkwardly above: the formal being of things can be understood to be ‘contaminated’ by the absolute attribute-neutrality of God’s infinite nature). This observation allows us to adjust table 4″ in the following way: Natura naturans (a) God qua God --------------------------------------------------------------(b-i) the formal being of singular things Natura naturata - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - is identical to - - - - - - - - - - - - (b-ii) idea x = body x = rx (c) God (table 4‴) In the previous section we have asserted that considered top-down – that is: insofar as the formal being of a thing is conceived to follow intrinsically from God’s infinite nature – the distinction between the attributes is not applicable to level (bi) (indeed in the same way the designations ‘milk’ and ‘water’ were not applicable to the perspective of the mother). And so from this top-down perspective the schematic distinction between the attributes is only operative at level (b-ii), in the way rendered in table 4‴. The next thing that must be incorporated in the schematic rendering of Spinoza’s parallelism is the representational nature of thought,81 that also surfaces in our claim concerning the trichotomy that is entailed by the formal-objective distinction (see section 2.5.3). As thought was shown to be characterized by the fact that modes of this attribute have objects that resort under other attributes, table 4‴ can also be rendered thus: 81 This representational nature of thought will be elucidated further in the next chapter. 335 Natura naturans (a) God qua God --------------------------------------------------------------(b-i) the formal being of singular things Natura naturata - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - is identical to - - - - - - - - - - - - (b-ii) the objective being of singular things (c) God (table 4*) Now, it cannot escape our notice that table 4* is virtually identical to table 5 (see above). There is only one difference: in table 4* the distinction between the attributes (i.e. between the objective being in thought and its object in another attribute) is still recognizable at level (b-ii) (namely in the grey vertical lines). This is informative, as it makes it clear that things insofar as they are grasped objectively in thought (and which as such surface as a durational idea), must be understood to be durational in their own attributes as well. Indeed, the parallel extended object of a durational idea must be understood to be a durational body (which is of course precisely what we have claimed in section 2.5.3, when we introduced the concept of trichotomy). If this is kept in mind, table 4* can also be rendered thus: Natura naturans (a) God qua God --------------------------------------------------------------(b-i) the formal being of singular things Natura naturata - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - is identical to - - - - - - - - - - - - (b-ii) the objective being of singular things (c) God (table 5) The upshot of the arguments in this section is that it is possible to reconcile both renderings of Spinoza’s parallelism thesis. The present reading of EIIp7 provides us with a way to understand how Spinoza’s vertical parallelism claim of EIIp7 (and EIp21s) can be conceived to encompass the inter-attribute parallelism of EIIp7s. For our findings allow us to make the following claim: A singular idea and its parallel mode (or object) under extension b o t h a r e f i n i t e and durational expressions in their own attribute of the v e r y s a m e a t t r i b u t e - n e u t r a l a n d e t e r n a l f o r m a l b e i n g .82 82 I use the term ‘singular idea’ instead of ‘idea’ because there is one important exception (which we could call a ‘borderline case’): the whole of objective nature (i.e. the all-encompassing totality of singular ideas, 336 And hence we can draw the important conclusion that the inter-attribute parallelism of EIIp7s can be understood to be an i m p l i c a t i o n of the vertical parallelism of EIIp7. Indeed, because of the fact that the attribute-neutral and infinite esse formale are expressed within each of the infinite attributes, there also is an inter-attribute parallel relation between the finite modes that are conceived under different attributes. Table 5 implies that idea x, body x and rx are identical, precisely because they are finite expressions under their own intellect-dependent attribute of the very same attribute-neutral formal being. In this sense, inter-attribute parallelism can be understood to be an implication of vertical parallelism. According to Spinoza, a man and the idea of that man can be considered to be one and the same thing because the order and connection of things is expressed in the same way in any of God’s attributes (thus including extension and thought). Every extended mode is identical to the parallel mental one because an idea and its object both are finite expressions (w i t h i n their respective attributes) o f t h e v e r y s a m e t h i n g : the attribute-neutral esse formale that follows from God’s infinite nature (and that, unlike the formal essences, must be positioned at the level of Natura naturata). This transitive structure of Spinoza’s parallelism – that we recognize as yet another expression of the trichotomous structure of pars melior nostri – can be elucidated with the following example. The German poet Heinrich Heine once wrote that ‘thought precedes action as lightning precedes thunder’.83 Whatever Heine’s poetic or political purpose may have been with this remark,84 in a certain sense the claim is imprecise. For as is well known, lightning and thunder are distinct manifestations of one and the same phenomenon: the discharge of huge amounts of electricity in the sky. Insofar as this discharge is considered in itself, lighting does not precede thunder. The respective manifestations of this single phenomenon can only be perceived to be distinct because the discharge is expressed in two separate ways: in light waves (in which case it is called ‘lightning’), and in which due to its infinity is not a singular idea). It is an exception because it is must be understood to be an infinite expression of an eternal formal being. Indeed, the whole of objective nature and its parallel modes under the remaining attributes can be understood to be the only modes that combine infinity with duration. The durational nature of the whole of objective nature was treated in section 3.3. 83 In: Zur Geschichte der Religion und Philosophie in Deutschland (1835). In: Heinrich Heine, Heines Werke in fünf Bänden 5 (Berlin 1964), 141 (Der Gedanke geht der Tat voraus wie der Blitz dem Donner [my translation JHH.)). 84 Heine uses this metaphor in order to make it clear that according to him revolution is due in nineteenth century Germany, as at that point there is a rich corpus of revolutionary philosophy in Germany. 337 sound waves (in which case it is called ‘thunder’). Even though this distinction between lightning and thunder is real enough – especially when the electrical discharge is considered from a certain distance – the perceived preceding of the manifestation insofar as it is expressed in light waves should not lead one to the conclusion that lightning and thunder refer to separate events. The difference between the speed of light and the speed with which sound waves travel through air makes these two separate manifestations only seem to indicate separate events. But in fact they have one and the same reference: the ‘light-and-sound-neutral’ discharge of electricity. Indeed: (3) (4) (5) Lightning is a manifestation of an electrical discharge Thunder is a manifestation of the same electrical discharge Hence: The phenomenon ‘lightning’ refers to = the phenomenon ‘thunder’ refers to Or, to state it in yet another way: lightning and thunder have the same reference but a different meaning. Now, the very same applies to the way in which according to Spinoza a mind and a body must be understood to be related. Even though their distinction is real enough, the mind and body of (say) the present president of France must be understood to refer to the very same thing: their attribute-neutral formal being. Indeed: (6) (7) (8) The mind of the present president of France is an expression of the attribute-neutral formal being of the present president of France The body of the present president of France is an expression of the attribute-neutral formal being of the present president of France Hence: The thing ‘the mind of the present president of France’ refers to = the thing ‘the body of the present president of France’ refers to It is due to the intrinsic identity of a finite mode and its infinite attribute-neutral being that a mode of thinking and its parallel extended object can be understood to 338 be the very same thing, even though the manifestation of the thing – as a body or as an idea – is quite different.85 On the basis of the things we have seen above, we can conclude that God qua God (a) can be conceived to create infinitely many attribute-neutral and eternal formal beings (top-down) that in turn can be understood to be expressed in infinitely many attribute-dependent durational modes. It appears to be precisely because of this that Spinoza is able to state in EIp16 that ‘infinitely many things’ follow from the divine nature ‘in infinitely many modes’: the infinitely many formal beings of things that follow from the divine nature can in turn be conceived to be expressed as modes of the infinitely many attributes.86 Or, as Spinoza repeats in the concluding remark of EIIp7s: ‘So of things as they are in themselves, God is really the cause insofar as he consists of infinitely many attributes’87 – a further clear indication that things in their formal being can be conceived irrespective of their attribute (as well). Yet another way of saying this is that the parallelism of modes mirrors the absolute identity of the ontological attributes that was treated in section 3.6, and that surfaces explicitly in the claim in EIIp7s that ‘the thinking substance and the extended substance are one and the same’. As the attributes must be understood to be absolutely identical in their ontological status, so also the eternally existing formal beings of the modes (that follow immediately from the attributeneutral essence of God), and the finite expressions of these forms in objective beings and their objects (under duration) must be understood to have the very same 85 Furthermore, from EIIp8 we can gather that this relation is not only applicable to things that exist at this moment under duration (such as the present president of France), but also to things that do not exist at this moment under duration, but that do have an ‘external cause which has been determined to produce such a thing’ (EIp33s1, (I) 436 (causa externa datur, ad talem rem producendam determinata)) at a certain moment under duration (such as (say) king Louis XIV). Indeed: (9) The mind of Louis XIV is an expression of the attribute-neutral formal being of Louis XIV (10) The body of Louis XIV is an expression of the attribute-neutral formal being of Louis XIV Hence: (11) The thing ‘mind of Louis XIV’ refers to = the thing ‘the body of Louis XIV’ refers to. 86 Yitzhak Melamed made more or less the same observation. He states with respect to EIp16 that ‘the things that follow from God’s nature are the infinitely faceted units that I call ‘modes of God’ (i.e. modes under the infinitely many attributes), and the infinitely many ways by which each mode of God follows from God’s nature are the infinitely many modes of the attributes that are aspects of the same mode of God.’ Melamed, Spinoza’s Metaphysics, 150. However, there is one crucial difference between Melamed’s interpretation and the present one: Melamed does not equate the ‘things’ that surface in EIp16 with the ‘things’ from EIIp7 (and EIIp6c). 87 EIIp7s, (I) 452 (Quare rerum, ut in se sunt, Deus reverâ est causa, quatenus infinitis constat attributis). 339 reference. Hence they can be conceived to parallel each other insofar as they are grasped as to their meaning. In this sense, the claim in EIIp7 posits a transitive parallelism relation:88 mode of thought xt can be understood to be identical to mode of extension xe because mode of thought xt is identical to attribute-neutral mode xf, and attribute-neutral mode xf in turn is identical to mode of extension xe. With this we encounter the very same trichotomy relation that was treated in section 2.5.3. Our claim in that section that the constructive function of the intellect entails a trichotomy of eternal formal beings, durational objective beings and their durational objects is fully corroborated by the present way of understanding Spinoza’s parallelism. It has become clear that transitive parallelism is nothing but an expression of the very trichotomy that characterizes the intellect in the way we commonly understand it: an idea is numerically identical to its object because idea and parallel object both are durational expressions of the very same formal being. 89 * In sum: EIIp7 does n o t primarily posit a parallelism relation between ideas and bodies. This important parallelism proposition must be understood to assert that t h e order and connections of things insofar as they are considered with respect to their objects is the same as the order and connection of things insofar as they are c o n s i d e r e d i n t h e m s e l v e s . As due to the absolute identity of the attributes at the level of N a t u r a n a t u r a n s the formal being of ideas and the formal being of 88 There is some controversy concerning the use of the term ‘parallelism’ with respect to the aspect of Spinoza’s metaphysics that was treated in this section. Chantal Jacquet argued that ‘equality’ is a better term than the Leibnizian term ‘parallelism’ (see note 22). Yet, given the indicated importance of the esse formale for Spinoza’s parallelism thesis, the term ‘conformity’ (which can also be found in Leibniz’ work, namely in the following claim: ‘C'est qu'il faut donc dire que Dieu a créé d'abord l'âme, ou toute autre unité réelle de telle sorte, que tout lui doit naître de son propre fonds, par une parfaite spontanéité à l'égard d'ellemême, et pour tant avec une parfaite c o n f o r m i t é aux choses de dehors [emphasis added]’ in: G.W. Leibniz, Neues System der Natur in: Fünf Schriften zur Logik und Metaphysik (Stuttgart 1966), 30 (note)) actually seems more appropriate. Indeed, this term accounts both for the transitive identity (‘con’) and the referential aspect (‘form’) of this relation. However, not to disorient the reader too much, I will stick to the term ‘parallelism’ in this study, as this term is firmly rooted in mainstream Spinoza-scholarship. 89 The question in what way transitive parallelism is related to the truth and adequacy of ideas will be treated in the next chapter. 340 bodies must be understood to be absolutely identical as well, this ‘vertical’ parallelism of the formal and the objective being of things entails the ‘horizontal’ inter-attribute parallelism between ideas and bodies. A singular idea is identical to the body it is the idea of because both can be considered to be f i n i t e a n d d u r a t i o n a l expressions of the very same infinite and eternal formal b e i n g . In this sense Spinoza’s parallelism thesis can be understood to be an expression of the trichotomy that characterizes the intellect in the way we commonly understand it. 4.3 The bottom-up perspective In the previous section we have seen that (and how) EIIp7, its corollary and its scholium can be understood via EIIp5 and EIIp6c, which both are rooted in the top-down causal thread put forward in the Principle of Plenitude of EIp16.90 It was shown that Spinoza’s parallelism entails a vertical identity of the top-down generated infinite and eternal formal being of things and the finite and durational expressions of these same things in each of the infinitely many attributes. This was rendered thus: Natura naturans (a) God qua God ----------------------------------------------------------------(b-i) The formal being of singular things Natura naturata - - - - - - - - - - - - - is identical to - - - - - - - - - - - (b-ii) The objective being of singular things (c) God (table 5) In this section I will argue for the claim that the formal being of things can also be grasped bottom-up in the way of the following table: Natura naturans (a) God qua God ----------------------------------------------------------------(b-i) The formal being of singular things Natura naturata - - - - - - - - - - - - - is identical to - - - - - - - - - - - (b-ii) The objective being of singular things (c) God (table 5′) 90 As will become clear below, EIIp5d shelters an aspect of the bottom-up perspective as well. 341 An important reason for taking this turn is the fact that we have not treated Spinoza’s parallelism exhaustively yet. In the previous section we may have established that EIIp7 can be understood thus: the order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of the formal being of things which was shown to imply that the order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of bodies However, as of yet it is not clear at all how this parallelism can account for the identity relation that surfaces in EIIp21s, namely the relation between ideas and ideas of ideas, a variant of parallelism that in turn can be rendered thus: the order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of ideas of these ideas Indeed, it is important to acknowledge that up till this point we have been arguing mainly about the way in which ideas can be understood to be identical to their formal being and their extended objects; the question how these forma ideae can in turn be understood to be idea ideae was not addressed yet. This is the subject that we will turn to now. In this section I will argue that (and how) ideas of ideas are related horizontally to their ideas in the same way ideas are related to their body. The bottom-up perspective will be shown to play an important role in this horizontal intra-attribute parallelism; it will become clear that this particular perspective accounts for the way in which this variant of parallelism can be fitted in the encompassing transitive parallelism that was elucidated above. Moreover, a treatment of the bottom-up perspective will also provide us with an answer to the question that induced our investigation of Spinoza’s parallelism claims in EIIp7 and EIIp21: the way in which we must understand God’s self-knowledge (and hence the knowledge of pars melior nostri). 342 4.3.1 Similar passages We already caught a first glimpse of the bottom-up perspective in the example of the glass of water and the glass of milk. It was argued in the previous section that in the context of Spinoza’s philosophy the formal being of things can be conceived in two ways: top-down these things can be conceived to have an attribute-neutral aspect, and considered bottom-up they must be understood to ‘belong’ to a specific attribute. In order to provide a more comprehensive argument for the claim that the Ethics harbors two perspectives – and that the formal being of things can also be grasped bottom-up in the way suggested in table 5′ – we must turn to the passage that spurred our interest in intra-attribute parallelism (i.e. EIIp21 and its scholium) once more. For, as will become clear below, Spinoza’s claim in EIIp21s that ‘as soon as someone knows something, he thereby knows that he knows it, and at the same time knows that he knows that he knows, and so on to infinity’91 can count as an important manifestation of the bottom-up perspective in the Ethics, a manifestation that is on a par with (inter alia) a remarkable claim in EIIp7s that was not treated yet. Elucidating the way in which the bottom-up perspective can be understood, we must start by pointing out once more that in EIIp21s ideas are asserted to be conceivable in two ways: an idea can be grasped with and without respect to its object. Furthermore we have learned that when an idea is understood in this latter way, Spinoza uses the term ‘form of the idea’. At this point it is important to note that in order to underpin this important claim, Spinoza does not refer to EIIp5 (nor to EIIp7 or EIIp7c) – as we might expect on the basis of the things we have ascertained above – but to EIIp7s. The scholium of EIIp21 starts with the remark that ‘this proposition is understood far more clearly from what is said in P7S’.92 So if we want to gain a full understanding of the claims that are made in EIIp21 and its scholium, we must turn to a closer scrutiny of EIIp7s. As was shown above, EIIp7s appears to be dedicated first and foremost to the horizontal inter-attribute variant of parallelism (i.e. to the parallel relation between finite ideas and their extended finite objects at level (b-ii)). Hence it is not EIIp21s, (I) 467-468 (simulac enim quis aliquid scit, eo ipso scit, se id scire, & simul scit, se scire, quòd scit, & sic in infinitum). 92 EIIp21s, (I) 467 (Hæc Propositio longè clariùs intelligitur ex dictis in Schol. Prop. 7. hujus). 91 343 immediately evident how EIIp7s can be understood to underpin Spinoza’s claims in EIIp21 and its scholium, which assert an intra-attribute variant of parallelism. Consider the following remark in EIIp21s: [in EIIp7s] we have shown that the idea of the body and the body […] are one and the same individual, which is conceived now under the attribute of thought, now under the attribute of extension. So the idea of the mind and the mind itself are one and the same thing, which is conceived under one and the same attribute, namely, thought’93 (ibi enim ostendimus Corporis ideam, & Corpus, hoc est (per Prop. 13. hujus) Mentem, & Corpus unum, & idem esse Individuum, quod jam sub Cogitationis, jam sub Extensionis attributo concipitur; quare Mentis idea, & ipsa Mens una, eademq́ue est res, quæ sub uno, eodemq́ue attributo, nempe Cogitationis, concipitur) True, from this assertion it becomes clear that, according to Spinoza, the parallelism between ideas and ideas of ideas put forward EIIp21 must be understood in the same way as the variant of parallelism that is staged in EIIp7s. But at the same the adduced claim is hardly illuminating as to how EIIp7s can be understood to provide a basis for the parallelism of EIIp21s (or for the bottom-up perspective that I aim to elucidate in this section). In order to understand this, we must turn to a closer scrutiny of the things that are claimed in EIIp7s. Consider the following important passage from this scholium: When I said that God is the cause of the idea, say of a circle, only insofar as he is a thinking thing, and the cause of the circle, only insofar as he is an extended thing, this was for no other reason than because the formal being of the idea of the circle can be perceived only through another mode of thinking, as its proximate cause, and that mode again through another, and so on, to infinity.94 (Nec ullâ aliâ de causâ [te voren] dixi, quòd Deus sit causa ideæ ex. gr. circuli, quatenus tantùm est res cogitans, & circuli, quatenus tantùm est res extensa, nisi quia esse formale ideæ circuli non, nisi per alium cogitandi modum, tanquam causam proximam, & ille iterùm per alium, & sic in infinitum, potest percipi) These remarks may indeed shelter the key for understanding the parallelism – and the bottom-up perspective – of EIIp21 and its scholium. In this respect, the following two aspects are promising. Firstly, the assertion in EIIp7s clearly deals with the relation between modes insofar as they are operative under the same attribute. Secondly, in this passage the very term that can be understood to ground Spinoza’s transitive parallelism – ‘esse formale’ – is used explicitly. 93 94 Ibidem, (I) 467. EIIp7s, (I) 451-452. 344 Michael Della Rocca claimed that EIIp7s uncovers the ‘referential opacity of causal contexts’95 as the quoted assertion from this scholium makes it clear that ‘the truth of causal claims is description-dependent’:96 due to the conceptual distinction between the attributes, the formal being of an idea can be understood to be causally related to another mental thing only, and not to a mode of another attribute. This appears to be correct (just as it is correct to state that lightning cannot be described in terms of sound-waves). As a matter of fact, I have used more or less the same argument in the reductio ad absurdum above. There I have claimed that the term ‘things’ that is used in EIIp7 cannot be understood to be bodies due to the causal barrier between the attributes. So in this respect Della Rocca’s remark provides a reading of EIIp7s that is in line with the present interpretation. Yet, at the same time it must be noted that the ‘referential opacity of causal contexts’ does not account for the parallelism relation that is suggested by the reference to EIIp7s in EIp21s. The fact that a mental thing can only be conceived to be connected causally to another mental thing (and not to an extended or an r-ed thing) – and hence that the causal thread that is mentioned in EIIp7s has an intra-attribute character – does not at all imply that (mental) cause and (mental) effect must be understood to be the very same thing. Yet, precisely this identity claim between ideas and their formal being is made in the very passage from EIIp21s that is claimed to find its ground in EIIp7s. As we saw above, Spinoza states explicitly in EIIp21s that the form of the idea and the idea itself (and indeed the idea and the idea of that idea) ‘are one and the same thing’. And thus the reference to EIIp7s in EIIp21s firmly suggests that the quoted passage from EIIp7s actually entails something more than merely the referential opacity of causal contexts; it seems that it must also harbor information with which the identity of ideas and their formal being can be understood. This supposition is underpinned by the things we have seen in Chapter 2. Recall that we have established there that Spinoza’s assertions in EIIp5 – the very proposition that treats the causal generation of the formal being of ideas – have more to it than merely the causal barrier Della Rocca refers to. We have seen that ideas in their formal being (EIIp5) must be understood to follow intrinsically from God as a ‘thinking thing absolutely’, whereas things in their objective being (i.e. the 95 96 Della Rocca, Representation, 166. Ibidem, 166. 345 ideas in the way they are staged in EIIp9) follow extrinsically from God as a res cogitans.97 That is to say: we have established that a thing in its objective being (i.e. its idea) and in its formal being must be understood to diverge in the conceptual nature of the intra-attribute causal thread it is conceived to follow from; the formal being of ideas from EIIp5 follow vertically (i.e. from (a) to (b-i)) from God as a ‘thinking thing absolutely’, and the ideas from EIIp9 follow horizontally (i.e. from (b-ii) to (b-ii)) from God as a res cogitans insofar as he is conceived to be expressed in another finite mode of thinking, and that mode again in another finite mode of thinking, and so on to infinity. Now, it does not seem to be an outrageous claim to suppose that this very distinction between ideas and their formal being may apply to the assertion in EIIp7s as well. Indeed, on the basis of the things we have said in section 2.5 and the reference to EIIp7s in the scholium of EIIp21 we can conclude tentatively that the quoted passage of EIIp7s must be understood posit, not only the referential opacity of causal contexts, but also the conceptual distinction between the formal and the objective being of things. To be sure, even though this observation provides us with a firm indication that the claim concerning the formal being of a circle in EIIp7s has more to it than merely the reiteration of the causal barrier between the attributes, our remarks in section 2.5 are not particularly illuminating with respect to the subject that we are treating presently: the identity relation that is posited in EIIp21 (and the way this relation is connected with a bottom-up perspective). In order to clarify these aspects of Spinoza’s philosophy, we must turn to a scrutiny of a passage that can be found in §33 of the TdIE. For this section contains elements that are remarkably similar to some of the assertions that surface in EIIp7s and EIIp21s. This similarity may provide us with an alternative angle with which the assertions concerning ideas and their formal beings in EIIp7s and EIIp21s – and hence the relation between ideas and ideas of ideas (and the bottom-up perspective) – can be understood. Consider the following claims from §33 of the TdIE: A true idea (for we have a true idea) is something different from its object. For a circle is one thing and an idea of the circle another – the idea of the circle is not something which has a circumference and a centre, as the circle does. Nor is an idea of the body the body itself. And since it is something different from its object, it will also be something intelligible through itself; that is, the idea, as far as its formal essence is 97 See section 2.5. 346 concerned, can be the object of another objective essence, and this objective essence in turn will also be, considered in itself, something real and intelligible, and so on, indefinitely.98 (Idea vera (habemus enim ideam veram) est diversum quid à suo ideato: Nam aliud est circulus, aliud idea circuli. Idea enim circuli non est aliquid, habens peripheriam, & centrum, uti circulus, nec idea corporis est ipsum corpus: & cùm sit quid diversum à suo ideato, erit etiam per se aliquid intelligibile; hoc est, idea, quoad suam essentiam formalem, potest esse objectum alterius essentiæ objectivæ, & rursus hæc altera essentia objectiva erit etiam in se spectata quid reale, & intelligibile, & sic indefinitè) And then Spinoza gives the following example: Peter, for example, is something real; but a true idea of Peter is an objective essence of Peter, and something real in itself, and altogether different from Peter himself. So since an idea of Peter is something real, having its own particular essence, it will also be something intelligible, i.e., the object of second idea, which will have in itself, objectively, whatever the idea of Peter has formally; and in turn, the idea which is the idea of the idea of Peter has again its essence, which can also be the object of another idea, and so on indefinitely. Everyone can experience this, when he sees that he knows what Peter is, and also knows that he knows, and again, knows that he knows that he knows, etc.99 (Petrus ex. gr. est quid reale; vera autem idea Petri est essentia Petri objectiva, & in se quid reale, & omninò diversum ab ipso Petro. Cùm itaque idea Petri sit quid reale, habens suam essentiam peculiarem, erit etiam quid intelligibile, id est, objectum alterius ideæ, quæ idea habebit in se objectivè omne id, quod idea Petri habet formaliter, & rursus idea, quæ est ideæ Petri, habet iterum suam essentiam, quæ etiam potest esse objectum alterius ideæ, & sic indefinitè. Quod quisque potest experiri, dum videt se scire, quid sit Petrus, & etiam scire se scire, & rursùs scit se scire, quòd scit, &c) There is a clear similarity between these passages and the things that are being said in both EIIp7s and EIIp21s. In this respect we must notice, firstly, that in these passages Spinoza treats precisely the subject that is hinted at in EIIp21s: the idea without relation to the object. A true idea is described as ‘something different from its object’ and the true idea of Peter is called ‘altogether different from Peter’. An idea considered apart from its object is called the formal essence of the idea, which in turn firmly underpins our supposition that the adduced passage treats the very same subject as EIIp21s: the difference between the objective and the formal status of a thing. Secondly, it must be noted that the quoted passages from the TdIE and EIIp7s both deal with the formal status of a circle, and hence appear to be the result 98 TdIE §33-35, (I) 17. To be sure, the status of the term ‘formal essence’ in this early work of Spinoza must be understood differently than the status that is attributed to the term in the present interpretation (i.e. as affection that must be understood to be located extra-intellectum (EIp4d)). A detailed philological scrutiny of the genealogy of this particular term in Spinoza’s work would take us too far afield. 99 Ibidem, (I) 17-18. 347 of a copy-paste operation. To be sure, the remarkable analogy between the passages in the TdIE and EIIp7s does not end with the observation (i) that both deal with the formal and objective status of things and (ii) that both passages are formulated in more or less the same way. Yet another striking similarity surfaces when considering the line in EIIp7s that ‘the formal being of the idea of the circle can be perceived only through another mode of thinking, […] and that mode again through another, and so on, to infinity [emphasis added]’. This claim is strongly reminiscent of Spinoza’s assertion in the TdIE that ‘the idea, as far as its formal essence is concerned, can be the object of another objective essence, and this objective essence in turn will also be, considered in itself, something real and intelligible, and so on, indefinitely [emphasis added]’. In both passages there seems to be posited an infinite chain of objective expressions of formal beings that surface as ideas, as ideas of ideas, and so on. This very infinite chain is recognizable in EIIp21s too, namely in Spinoza’s assertion that ‘as soon as someone knows something, he thereby knows that he knows it, and at the same time knows that he knows that he knows, and so on, to infinity’. Indeed, the latter claim from EIIp21s is virtually identical to something that is asserted in the passage from the TdIE (as an example for the very infinite chain referred to above): ‘the idea of the idea of Peter has again its essence, which can also be the object of another idea, and so on indefinitely. Everyone can experience this, when he sees that he knows what Peter is, and also knows that he knows, and again, knows that he knows that he knows, etc. [emphasis added]’. The similarity of the claims in the TdIE, EIIp7s and EIIp21s suggests that the assertions in the two latter passages can both be considered to be a concise reformulation of Spinoza’s rendering of the working of the intellect in the important passage from the TdIE.100 For in all three passages we encounter the following key features: 100 This similarity of course has been noted by other scholars too. Alexandre Matheron is a case in point. He identified a series of apparent differences between the quoted passages from the TdIE and EIIp21s. However, Matheron concludes that these differences do not forestall the important similarity concerning the status of the ideas of ideas in both works: ‘Donc, finalement, il n’y a pas de contradiction entre le TIE at l’Éthique’. Alexandre Matheron, Études sur Spinoza et les philosophies de l’age classique (Lyon 2011), 540. To be sure, even though I agree with Matheron insofar as the structure of the argument is concerned, I do not think there is no relevant difference at all. Perhaps the most important difference concerns the use of the terms ‘formal’’ and ‘objective essence’ in the TdIE. In the Ethics, Spinoza switches to ‘formal’ and ‘active’ essence. The reason for this change of terms will be elucidated in the next chapter. 348 (i) (ii) (iii) A situating of the formal status of things and the objective expression of these things within the attribute of thought101 An infinite chain of perceptions A conceptual exclusivity of formality and objectivity Ad (i). The situating of the formal status of things and the objective expression of these things within the attribute of thought surfaces in the remark in EIIp7s that ‘the formal being of the idea of the circle can be perceived only through another mode of thinking [emphasis added]’ (which as we saw mirrors the assertion in the TdIE that ‘the idea can be the object of another objective essence [emphasis added]’). With this remark Spinoza makes it clear that the interplay between formality and the objective modus in which this formality is expressed must be positioned within the mental realm. The interplay between formal and objective being of things can be understood to be operative entirely in the attribute of thought. Ad (ii). As we saw, the formal being of the idea can be perceived only through another mode of thinking (i). This other mode of thinking in turn can only be perceived only per alium cogitandi modum (EIIp7s). And the resulting mode of thinking again can only be perceived through another mode of thinking. And so on indefinitely. Now, this very same structure of infinite perceptions is recognizable in the claim in the TdIE that ‘the idea, as far as its formal essence is concerned, can be the object of another objective essence, and this objective essence in turn will also be, considered in itself, something real and intelligible, and so on, indefinitely’, which as we saw is explicated by Spinoza – both in the TdIE and in EIIp21s – with a reference to ideas of ideas, and to knowledge of knowledge (of knowledge of knowledge, and so on). 101 One important thing must be added: the ‘real Peter’ that gives rise to the first objective essence (‘the true idea of Peter’) may be understood to be the extended Peter in the quoted example. However, in a note Spinoza remarks that ‘we are not asking how the first objective essence is inborn in us’. TdIE §34, note n, (I) 18. That is to say: Spinoza at this point neither confirms nor denies that the original thing is an extended thing. In this sense, Bennett’s remark that ‘for Spinoza the body calls the tune’ is misguided. See: Bennett, A Study of Spinoza’s Ethics, 81 and 186. In the next chapter we will say something more about the way in which Spinoza conceives the ‘first adequate idea’. 349 Ad (iii). The conceptual exclusivity of ‘the formal being of the idea of the circle’ and ‘the [objective] idea of the circle’ can be explicated thus: as according to EIIp7s this formal being can be perceived only through another mode of thinking (non nisi per alium cogitandi modum), the idea (or objective being (EIIp8c)) of the circle thus is asserted to differ necessarily (in a certain respect) from the formal being of that same idea. This implies that (from the present perspective) the formality and objectivity of a thing are conceptually exclusive. When ideas are grasped in the way staged in the passages quoted above, they fall apart in an objective aspect (i.e. the idea insofar as it represents its object), and a formal aspect (i.e. the same idea insofar as it is considered without relation to its object). This need not surprise us, as this fully corroborates our claim that with respect to Spinoza’s parallelism we encounter the very constructive function of the intellect that was elucidated in section 2.5. And as we have seen in Chapter 1 and 2 that (firstly) pars melior nostri is characterized by a necessary duality as by EVp29s ‘we conceive things as actual in two ways [emphasis added]’, that (secondly) this duality must be understood to be the very duality between the (eternal) formal and the (durational) objective being of things, and that (thirdly) Spinoza states in EVp29d that ‘eternity cannot be explained by duration’,102 it is clear why the formal and objective being of things are staged as conceptually exclusive. These similarities, combined with Spinoza’s explicit claim that EIIp21 must be understood to find corroboration in EIIp7s, underpin our supposition that the assertions in this latter scholium refer, not only to the causal isolation of the attributes, but also to the very vertical relation between (durational) ideas and their ontologically identical but conceptually distinct (eternal) formal beings that surfaced in our treatment of EIIp5 and EIIp9. That is to say: the quoted claims from EIIp7s can only be understood to provide an elucidation of EIIp21 – which as we saw is explicitly claimed to be the case by Spinoza – when the assertions in EIIp7s are considered to posit a v e r t i c a l relation between the eternal forms and their expression in durational modes within the same attribute. Spinoza’s claim in EIIp21s that his intra-attribute variant of parallelism is corroborated by EIIp7s only makes sense if it is granted that both scholiums deal with the two ways in which we 102 EVp29d, (I) 609 (At æternitas per durationem explicari nequit). 350 conceive singular things: objectively (i.e. as durational finite modes) and formally (i.e. as eternal infinite modes). Yet another way of saying this is that, even though Della Rocca is right in his claim that in the passage from EIIp7s Spinoza forwards the causal isolation of the attributes, this assertion is not complete. This passage must be understood to say still something more: it also posits the vertical relation between the objective and the formal being of things. This is of course precisely what we would expect on the basis of the things we encountered in the previous sections (and in section 2.5). For above we have seen that Spinoza’s claim from the corollary of EIIp7 (namely that ‘whatever follows formally from God's infinite nature follows objectively in God from his idea in the same order and with the same connection’) establishes a vertical identity relation between eternal formal beings and durational ideas. It would go vehemently against the geometrical rigour with which Spinoza aimed to devise his philosophy to suppose that in the scholium of the very same proposition and corollary in which the vertical identity relation of formal beings (at (b-i)) and their objective expressions (at (b-ii)) is posited, he would forget about this important characteristic and claim that the relation between (say) the formal being of the idea of a circle and the durational mode of thinking that expresses this formal being (i.e. the idea of the circle) is to be understood as a horizontal causal relation in which the identity claim (as well as the constructive importance of the intellect) has mysteriously disappeared from view (only to rear its ugly head again in EIIp21s). 4.3.1.1 Horizontal intra-attribute parallelism Our elaborations so far teach us that the relation between ideas and their formal beings must be understood to disclose an intra-attribute variant of parallelism (in the sense that these things can be conceived to be operative under the same attribute), and a vertical variant of parallelism (in the sense that they must be understood to express the distinction between items under duration (b-ii) and the very same items in their eternal being (b-i)). To be sure, as of yet it is unclear (i) how we must understand the intricate relation between the formal being of an idea (‘forma ideae’) and the idea of that idea (‘idea ideae’) – and the way in which this latter notion must be understood to be parallel to its idea, and (ii) how the perspective that is forwarded in the claims from EIIp7s and EIIp21s can be 351 understood to be bottom-up. In this section we will treat point (i); the bottom-up character of this perspective will be the subject of the subsequent section. In order to elucidate the way in which an idea can be understood to be parallel to the idea of that idea, it is instructive to adduce the schematic rendering of the conceptual duality that is forwarded in (inter alia) EVp29s once more. We have seen that a singular thing can be conceived as to: the objective being of a thing (i.e. the idea with relation to its object, in which case the object is the parallel body) and as to (2″) the formal being of that idea (i.e. the idea without relation to its object) (1″) This dual structure was recognizable in the passages from the TdIE, EIIp7s and EIIp21s as well: in all three passages we encountered the vertical distinction between durational ideas and their eternal formal beings. To be sure, it is important to note that the mentioned passages tell us still something more. The close similarity between the quoted passages from the TdIE, EIIp7s and EIIp21s teaches us that the formal being of an idea (2″) can in turn be the object of another idea. That is: the formal being of an idea in itself (i.e. the formal being qua formal being) can be conceived as actual in two ways, and can thus be conceived as: the objective being of (the formal being of the idea), i.e. (by EIIp21s) the idea of the idea103 considered with relation to its object (in which case the object is the idea (1″)) (2″i) and as 103 Both Edwin Curley and Jonathan Bennett remarked that this structure of ideas of ideas’ may very well be called a propositional structure. Curley says the following: “Since I am identifying the possession of an idea of an idea with consciousness, it seems natural to say that an idea of an idea is a special kind of proposition about a proposition, namely, one expressing what is sometimes called a propositional attitude […].’ Edwin Curley, Spinoza’s Metaphysics, 129. Bennett writes: ‘We translate [Spinoza’s Latin word idea] by ‘idea’, and think of it as mental […]. But there is a way of taking ‘idea’ in which ideas are not mental at all. […] Much of the time Spinoza takes ideas to be propositionally structured […]. [O]n the psychological reading an ‘idea’ is a state or episode of believing that P or the like, while on the logical reading it is just the proposition that P’. Jonathan Bennett, A Study of Spinoza’s Ethics (Cambridge 1984) 50-51. 352 (2″ii) the formal being of (the idea of the idea),104 i.e. the idea of the idea considered without relation to its object And (2″ii) itself can in turn be conceived as actual in two ways (or, in the wording of EIIp7s, ‘be perceived only through another mode of thinking’), resulting in: (2″ii-i) the objective being of (the formal being of (the idea of the idea)), i.e. the idea of (the idea of the idea) considered with relation to its object (in which case the object is the idea of the idea) (2″i)) and (2″ii-ii) the formal being of (the idea of (the idea of the idea)) and so on to infinity.105 It is precisely this important addition to the structure of EVp29s that provides the basis for Spinoza’s statement in EIIp21s that ‘as soon as someone knows something, he thereby knows that he knows it, and at the same time knows that he knows that he knows, and so on to infinity’. Indeed: it is the objective being of something (i.e. the idea) that accounts for the knowledge of the thing under scrutiny106 (say: a circle), it is the objective being of the idea of the circle (i.e. the idea of the idea) that accounts for the knowledge of the knowledge of the circle, it is the objective being of the idea of the idea (i.e. the idea of the idea of the idea) that accounts for the knowledge of the knowledge of the knowledge of the circle, and so on, to infinity. 104 These parentheses are ‘mathematical’ in the sense that they aim to make it clear that the terms between the parentheses function as a (in linguistic terms) unit of meaning. 105 That this intricate structure – in fact expressing the infinite applicability of the constructive function of the intellect – is a recurring theme in Spinoza’s philosophy became clear already in our treatment of the distinction between the absolute infinite intellect and the whole of (objective) nature (see Chapter 2). Indeed, it was precisely the recognition of the constructive function of the intellect that made it clear how the absolutely infinite intellect and the whole of objective nature can be understood to be conceptually distinct. They can be grasped in this way because the unspecified infinite intellect can be grasped as to (1‴) the objective being of the infinite mode of extension (i.e. as the infinite idea with relation to its object, that is: as the whole of objective nature having the whole of extended nature as its perceived object), and as to (2″) the formal being of the infinite intellect (i.e. the infinite idea without relation to its object, that is: as the absolutely infinite intellect). 106 Or, as Spinoza says in the TdIE: ‘From this it is clear that certainty is nothing but the objective essence itself, i.e., the mode by which we are aware of the formal essence is certainty itself’ (Hinc patet, quòd certitudo nihil sit præter ipsam essentiam objectivam; id est, modus, quo sentimus essentiam formalem, est ipsa certitudo). TdIE §35, (I) 18. 353 This way of understanding the functioning of pars melior nostri provides us with an answer to the question we aimed to answer in this section. For the enumeration above gives us additional insight with respect to the exact nature of the parallelism relation between ideas and the ideas of these ideas. Consider table 5 once more: Natura naturans (a) God qua God -----------------------------------------------------------------(b-i) The formal being of singular things Natura naturata - - - - - - - - - - - - is identical to - - - - - - - - - - - - - (b-ii) The objective being of singular things (c) God (table 5) Above we have stated with respect to this table that an idea (say: of a circle) and its body (the circle) are numerically identical because they can both be conceived to be objective expressions at level (b-ii) of the same res: the formal being of the circle at level (b-i). Given what we have seen in this section, it becomes clear that according to Spinoza the representational nature of thought is so thoroughgoing, that the formal being of an idea is not only expressed in an idea (see point (1″)) that can be understood to be a representation of its parallel extended object, but that this idea can also be understood to be grasped objectively itself (see point (2″i)), in which case it appears as the idea of the idea, that is: as a representation of itself. As soon as the eternal forma ideae is perceived by another mode of thinking, this eternal form – due to the conceptual exclusivity of the formal and objective being of things – turns into the durational objective being of the idea it is the form of, and hence surfaces as the idea ideae at level (b-ii). In Chapter 5 we will see how the selfrepresentation that is expressed in the notion idea ideae can be understood to account for the consciousness that must be attributed to ideas. The thing to note in the context of the present section is that it is precisely the possibility to form an idea of the formal being of a thing qua formal being that accounts for the claim that the order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of i d e a s o f i d e a s . For on the basis of the things we have seen in this section we can conclude that transitive parallelism is applicable to ideas and their mental objects in the same way it is applicable to ideas and their extended objects. Indeed: 354 the order and connection of the objective being of bodies is the same as the order and connection of the objective being of the ideas of these bodies This in turn makes it clear that the horizontal relation at level (b-ii) can be understood to be of the intra-attribute variant as well: a mode of thinking cannot only be understood to be numerically identical to its finite object in extension (in which case the horizontal parallelism is of the inter-attribute variant), but also to its finite object in thought (in which case the horizontal parallelism is of the intraattribute variant)). Before turning to the second important subject that was announced above – an elucidation of the bottom-up perspective – it may be informative to provide yet another argument for the horizontal intra-attribute parallelism that was uncovered just now. This additional argument takes off from the acknowledgement that Spinoza’s Principle of Plenitude implies that ideas and bodies can both be understood to ‘fall under the infinite intellect’. They fall under the unspecified infinite mode of thought in the following way: a thing that follows from the necessity of the divine nature can be understood (i) as an idea that is part of the infinite intellect, and (ii) as a body that is a part of the whole that is perceived by the infinite intellect. Considered in this way there appears to be a difference between an idea and a body. For the idea – i.e. the objective being (or the idea with respect to its object) – that represents its body, appears to fall under the infinite intellect, not insofar as it is represented in thought (as is the case with its body), but insofar as it is an unrepresented part of the infinite intellect. This of course leads to the question whether this idea cannot be understood to have a representational feature as well, not insofar as it is related to its extended object, but insofar as it is considered in itself. Now, on the basis of EIIp20 and EIIp21 (and the passages from the TdIE and EIIp7s quoted earlier), this question can be answered affirmatively. That is to say: it is precisely here where the notion ‘idea ideae’ comes into play. Insofar as the intellect directs its representational powers at itself, its formal being is not expressed in an extended thing, but in a finite mental thing: the idea of the idea. Another way of saying this is that in the context of Spinoza’s philosophy the inherent representational nature of thought107 is so thoroughgoing that this This inherent representational nature of ideas is also recognizable in Descartes’ philosophy. With respect to this latter subject, Richard Fields has stated the following: ‘An idea, then, has objective being, and is the 107 355 particular attribute offers a window on all the other attributes including itself (which of course is corroborated by the definition of attribute in EID4).108 Once God, insofar as he is expressed in the human mind, has an idea of an idea that is in him, that idea must be understood to fall apart in (i) the finite idea of the idea, and (ii) the parallel finite object that is represented (or perceived) by this idea ideae: the idea it is numerically identical to. 4.3.2 The objective being as ground floor Having established how the parallel relation between an idea and the idea of that idea must be conceived, we can turn to the second subject that was announced above: the bottom-up perspective. Now, it is important to note that the way in which a forma ideae is shown to turn into an identical idea ideae (namely by way of the infinite grasping operation that surfaces inter alia in EIIp7s and EIIp21s) also tells us something about the way in which the ‘bottom-up’ perspective must be understood. In order to see this, we must adduce structure (1″)-(2″ii-ii) once more. We have seen that a singular idea can be conceived as to: the objective being of a thing (i.e. the idea with relation to its object, in which case the object is the parallel body) and as to (2″) the formal being of that idea (i.e. the idea without relation to its object) (1″) representation of something, quite apart from any relation, whether actual or hypothetical, it might have to a thing. In other words, the idea is in itself, or essentially, representative. [...] Ideas, considered apart from the actual existence of their objects, represent the natures or essences of things having determinate character independently of the act of thought itself. [...] If the possible existent that is represented in this manner by an idea actually does exist, then the idea can be said to represent something in a second way by virtue of the conformity of the objective being of the idea to the actualized nature, or what Descartes calls the "formal being" of an existing object. [...] Unlike the previous manner of representation, which is nonrelational and essential to the character of ideas, representation in this second manner does require a relation between an idea and an existing object.’ Richard W. Field, ‘Descartes on the Material Falsity of Ideas’ in: The Philosophical Review, Vol. 102, No. 3 (1993), 310-312. More on the way in which Spinoza underpins this representational nature of thought in Chapter 5. 108 As already noted in section 3.6, the definition of attribute (EID4) reads thus: ‘By attribute I understand what the intellect perceives of a substance, as constituting its essence’. As this definition must also be understood to be applicable to the attribute of thought, and as the intellect that does the ‘perceiving of substance’ must be understood to fall under this very attribute, EID4 implies that in the case of the attribute of thought the perceiving operation is to be seen as self-representational. 356 And then we saw that the formal being of an idea in itself (i.e. the formal being qua formal being) can be conceived as actual in two ways, and can thus be conceived as: the objective being of (the formal being of the idea), i.e. (by EIIp21s) the idea of the idea considered with relation to its object (in which case the object is the idea (1″)) (2″i) and as (2″ii) the formal being of (the idea of the idea), i.e. the idea of the idea considered without relation to its object Furthermore it became clear that (2″ii) itself can in turn be conceived as actual in two ways (or, in the wording of EIIp7s, ‘be perceived only through another mode of thinking’), resulting in: (2″ii-i) the objective being of (the formal being of (the idea of the idea)), i.e. the idea of (the idea of the idea) considered with relation to its object (in which case the object is the idea of the idea) (2″i)) and (2″ii-ii) the formal being of (the idea of (the idea of the idea)) and so on to infinity. At this point it is crucial to acknowledge that this structure not only makes it clear how formal beings of ideas can be understood to be expressed in durational ideas of ideas, but also that at each successive step of this intellectual structure the objective being of a thing serves as the ground floor for the inference.109 At every stage, the formal being is conceptually dependent on its objective being (in more or less the same way the time between thunder and lightning – or the designation ‘glass of milk’ and ‘glass of water’ – is depending on the position of the knowing agent). The enumeration that was provided above is based on the concept of a singular idea that is captured in (1″). Point (1″) must be understood to serve as the foundation for (2″); and as soon as (2″) is grasped objectively in (2″i), the resulting ‘idea of the idea’ serves as the foundation for (2″ii); and again, as soon as (2″ii) is grasped 109 See note 101. 357 objectively in (2″ii-i), the resulting ‘idea of (the idea of the idea)’ grounds (2″ii-ii), and so on indefinitely. In other words, in this particular intellectual operation the conceptual direction must be understood thus: (1″) ⟶ (2″) ⟶ (2″i) ⟶ (2″ii) ⟶ (2″ii-i) ⟶ (2″ii-ii) ⟶ ad infinitum. It is hard to overestimate the importance of this observation. For it teaches us (or rather: it underpins our assertion) that in the context of Spinoza’s metaphysics the knowledge of a formal being qua formal being – even though it must be understood to follow top-down from God (by EIp16, EIIp5 and EIIp6c) – can be considered from yet another perspective: it can also be conceived to be the result of an act of inferring: from the objective being of a thing (i.e. from an idea with respect to its durational object) an eternal formal being qua formal being is inferred on the basis of a conceptually prior objective being.110 That is to say: the formal being of an idea, although shown to follow immediately from God as a ‘thinking thing absolutely’ – and as such to be logically prior to its objective expression – can be considered to be psychologically posterior to the objective being that serves as the basis for the inference of this formal being. It is precisely this conceptual priority of an objective being that grounds the rhetorical question ‘who can know that he understands something unless he first understands it?’ in EIIp43s.111 According to Spinoza a true idea must be understood to serve as the basis of the idea of that idea (which by EIIp21s of course is nothing but the forma ideae). As already noted, this bottom-up perspective emerges clearly in the assertion in EIIp21s concerning the knowledge of knowledge of knowledge of things. The close connection between EIIp21s and EIIp7s (see above) suggests that this perspective is also recognizable in this latter scholium. Indeed, our claims concerning the similarity between the claims from EIIp21s and EIIp7s can only be upheld if the very same bottom-up perspective is recognizable in EIIp7s as well. Now, is it? Can this scholium be understood to encompass the perspective that has ideas with respect to their objects as its ground floor? On closer scrutiny this indeed appears to be the case. In order to see this, it is crucial to focus on the remarkable causal relation that is posited in EIIp7s. Consider the following claim once more: For as soon as the formal being is grasped objectively (or as EIIp7s states, per alium cogitandi modum), it loses the precise characteristic that warrants the use of the predicate ‘formal’. When turning into an objective being, the grasped thing can only be described as a (by TdIE §33-35) modus, quo sentimus essentiam formalem. However, the formal being can be inferred to exist in itself. 111 EIIp43a, (I) 479. 110 358 the formal being of the idea of the circle can be perceived only through another mode of thinking, as its proximate cause, and that mode again through another, and so on, to infinity.112 (esse formale ideæ circuli non, nisi per alium cogitandi modum, tanquam causam proximam, & ille iterùm per alium, & sic in infinitum, potest percipi) With regard to the causal claim that is being made in this passage, we cannot fail to notice that there is something funny with Spinoza’s assertion. For the quoted claim appears to state that the formal being of an idea is caused by the mode of thinking it is perceived through. When it is acknowledged that in this assertion from EIIp7s the intra-attribute distinction between the formal and the objective being of the circle is posited, the clause ‘as its proximate cause’ suggests that the formal being of an idea is claimed to be caused proximately by the objective being it is the form of. That is to say: the quoted passage suggests that the logically prior formal being of an idea is merely the proximate result of the objective being of that same thing. Prima facie, this appears to go against the causal thread posited in EIIp5 (see section 2.5). For with respect to this important proposition we have established that the formal being of ideas follows immediately from God as a ‘thinking thing absolutely’. However, given what we have seen, the assertion that the formal being of ideas can be understood to be caused proximately by their objective expressions is not too surprising. For in the causal claim of EIIp7s that was cited just now we encounter the very bottom-up structure that was elucidated above. Indeed, this formulation in EIIp7s makes it clear that this scholium corroborates our claims concerning the alternative perspective that can be recognized in the Ethics. In the quoted passage from EIIp7s, the idea of a circle is staged insofar as it has a certain conceptual priority over its identical formal being. The objective being of the circle (i.e. idea of the circle with respect to its object) is portrayed as the proximate cause of the formal being of the idea of the circle (i.e. of the idea of the circle without respect to its object). This is completely in line with the assertion in EIIp21s that ‘as soon as someone knows something, he thereby knows that he knows, and at the same time knows that he knows that he knows, and so on, to infinity’. In other words: the intra-attribute bottom-up perspective is clearly recognizable in EIIp7s too. Just as the passages from the TdIE and EIIp21s, EIIp7s fosters a perspective from which the objective being of things is conceptually prior to their formal beings. This 112 EIIp7s, (I) 451-452. 359 firmly underpins our claims that (i) the these passages all express a vertical relation between ideas and their formal beings, and that (ii) apart from the vertical topdown perspective that is advanced in the Principle of Plenitude of EIp16, Spinoza also puts forward a vertical bottom-up perspective. The vertical top-down perspective runs from Natura naturans (a) to Natura naturata (b); the vertical bottom-up perspective that was uncovered in this section must be located within Natura naturata and runs from the objective and durational (b-ii) to the formal and eternal (b-i) being of things. 4.3.2.1 Some more examples The elucidations so far have shown us that Spinoza’s philosophy must be understood to shelter a bottom-up perspective that expresses the ability of pars melior nostri to infer the formal being of things on the basis of the objective being of things. This bottom-up perspective can be rendered thus: Natura naturans (a) God qua God ----------------------------------------------------------------(b-i) The formal being of singular things Natura naturata - - - - - - - - - - - - - is identical to - - - - - - - - - - - (b-ii) The objective being of singular things (c) God (table 5′) Indeed, we have seen that in (inter alia) EIIp7s and EIIp21s the objective being of a thing (b-ii) is presented as the foundation for the grasping of the formal being of the same thing (b-i). To be sure, in order to erase all doubt as to whether the Ethics harbors this bottom-up perspective, I will provide five more examples of passages that underpin this important claim. Example 1: EIIp5d A first additional indication that the bottom-up perspective that was elucidated above must be understood to be endorsed fully by Spinoza can be found in the demonstration of EIIp5. In Chapter 2 we have argued that this proposition posits an intrinsic top-down causal thread, as it is based – via EIIp3 – on the ‘medieval’ Principle of Plenitude of EIp16. However, at this point it must be added that in the 360 demonstration of EIIp5 Spinoza proposes yet ‘another way of demonstrating this’.113 In this second demonstration he forwards the claim that the formal being of an idea is a mode of thinking. Now, if the formal being of an idea is staged as the formal being of an idea, it is quite evident – or as Spinoza formulates it: ‘ut per se notum’ – that the recognition of the formal status of the thing under scrutiny is based on its objective being (i.e. on the idea of the thing) and not on the absolute attribute neutral divine essence it follows from. Hence it is clear that EIIp5d can be understood to shelter two perspectives from which the very same formal being of ideas can be grasped. Whereas the first part of the demonstration is based on the top-down perspective that is put forward in EIp16, the second part of the demonstration fosters the bottom-up perspective. Example 2: EIIp6c A closely related indication can be found in EIIp6c. Consider the following passage: the objects of ideas follow and are inferred from their attributes in the same way as that with which we have shown ideas to follow from the attribute of thought [emphasis added].114 (eodém modo, eâdemq́ue necessitate res ideatæ ex suis attributis consequuntur, & concluduntur, ac ideas ex attributo Cogitationis consequi ostendimus) The thing to note here is that Spinoza uses two different terms to explicate the way in which things can be understood to resort under their attributes. Things are asserted to follow (consequuntur) from their attributes, and they are claimed to be inferred (concluduntur) from their attributes. Given what we have seen above, we can conjecture that with the term ‘consequuntur’ Spinoza refers to the top-down perspective from which the formal being of a thing is prior to its objective being (as this formal being must be understood (by EIIp6c) to follow immediately from God (a)), whereas the term ‘concluduntur’ expresses the bottom-up perspective from which the objective being of a thing is perceived to be prior to the formal being of the same thing (as the formal being is understood (by EIIp7s) to be caused proximately by its objective being, and hence to be a mode of thinking (by EIIp5d)). On the present interpretation it becomes clear why Spinoza in EIIp6c would use 113 114 EIIp5d, (I) 450 (aliter hoc modo demonstratur). EIIp6c, (I) 450-451. 361 the two terms in order to refer to the very same operation: the formal being of things can be understood to be grasped in two conceptually distinct ways: topdown and bottom-up. Example 3: The ‘physical excursion’ The same bottom-up perspective is also recognizable in the ‘physical excursion’ that can be found after EIIp13s. In this respect an already quoted claim from EIIL7s – part of this ‘physical excursion’ – is very informative. Spinoza states the following in this scholium: So far we have conceived an individual which is composed only of bodies which […] are composed of the simplest bodies. But if we should now conceive of another, composed of a number of individuals of a different nature, we shall find that it can be affected in a great many other ways, and still preserve its nature. […] [E]ach part of it is composed of a number of bodies […]. But if we should further conceive a third kind of individual, composed of this second kind, we shall find that it can be affected in many other ways, without any change of its form. And if we proceed in this way to infinity, we shall easily conceive that the whole of nature is one individual, whose parts, that is, all bodies, vary in infinite ways, without any change of the whole individual.115 (Atque hucusque Individuum concepimus, quod non, nisi […] ex corporibus simplicissimis componitur. Quòd si jam aliud concipiamus, ex pluribus diversæ naturæ Individuis compositum, idem pluribus aliis modis posse affici, reperiemus, ipsius nihilominùs naturâ servatâ. Nam quandoquidem ejus unaquæque pars ex pluribus corporibus est composita […].Quòd si præterea tertium Individuorum genus, ex his secundis compositum, concipiamus, idem multis aliis modis affici posse, reperiemus, absque ullâ ejus formæ mutatione. Et si sic porrò in infinitum pergamus, facilè concipiemus, totam naturam unum esse Individuum, cujus partes, hoc est, omnia corpora infinitis modis variant, absque ullâ totius Individui mutatione) From this passage we learn that Spinoza offers a perspective that (so to speak) starts with the parts. In EIIL7 the whole of nature is clearly claimed to be an aggregate whole constituted by infinitely many bodies. And insofar as the whole of nature is conceived objectively as the whole of objective nature (i.e. as God’s idea), it can be understood to be constituted by infinitely many ideas. Indeed, there is a perspective – i.e. the bottom-up perspective – from which a body (and its idea) is a prior and constituting part of the whole of (objective) nature, even though these parts cannot in any way be understood to be prior to, or constitutive of, the whole they are in insofar as this whole is considered as to its reference. 115 EIIL7s, (I) 461-462. 362 The next thing that must be noted is that in section 2.6 we have established that this whole of nature (EIIL7s) can be understood to be related to its formal being in the same way a part of the whole of nature can be understood to be related to the formal being of that part. Indeed: The whole of nature can be conceived as actual in two ways. It can be conceived as to the objective being of the whole of nature, i.e. as God’s idea with relation to the (extended) whole of nature, (viz. (b-ii) the whole of objective nature that exists sempiternally) and as to (2*) the formal being of God’s idea, i.e. God’s idea without relation to the (extended) whole of nature, (viz. (b-i) the absolutely infinite intellect that exists eternally) (1*) The thing to note with respect to these assertions is (i) that in the intellectual structure that surfaces in this particular enumeration, the objective being of a thing must once again be understood to serve as the ground floor for the formal being of that same thing, and (ii) that the relation between the whole of objective nature (1*) and the absolutely infinite intellect (2*) is completely on a par with our mereological contentions from Chapter 2. Recall that we have asserted there that if the unspecified infinite intellect is considered in itself, the whole of objective nature (1*) can be understood to be an exhaustive part of the absolutely infinite intellect (2*). It must be noted now that the claim that (from the bottom-up perspective) the part is prior to its whole is just another way of formulating the claim that the objective being of a thing serves as the foundation for the inference of its formal being: in both cases the whole of objective nature is staged as conceptually prior to the absolutely infinite intellect. And hence from this perspective the (exhaustive) part is staged as prior to its whole. Or stated in terms of the present chapter: from a certain perspective, an objective being (b-ii) can be considered to be prior to its formal being (b-i). If it is acknowledged furthermore that according to Spinoza both the whole of objective nature and the absolutely infinite intellect have God qua God as their reference, it becomes clear that the priority of the parts that 363 surfaces in this example can actually be understood to be a manifestation of the early modern conceptual commitment to the whole of nature that Spinoza fosters. For on his account, investigating the durational parts of nature means nothing less than investigating God.116 Example 4: EIIp43s The claim in the TdIE that ‘there is no idea of an idea unless there is first an idea’,117 is reiterated in the Ethics, not only in the claim in EIIp21s about knowledge of knowledge, but also in EIIp43s. In this scholium, in which Spinoza refers explicitly to the notion ‘idea of an idea’ in EIIp21s, he asks the following: who can know that he understands some thing unless he first understands it? That is, who can know that he is certain about something unless he is first certain about it? What can there be which is clearer and more certain than a true idea, to serve as standard of truth?118 (quis scire potest, se rem aliquam intelligere, nisi priùs rem intelligat? hoc est, quis potest scire, se de aliquâ re certum esse, nisi priùs de eâ re certus sit? Deinde quid ideâ verâ clarius, & certius dari Potest, quod norma sit veritatis?) This passages corroborates our claim that the bottom-up perspective – i.e. the proximate causal relation between the objective being and the resulting formal being of ideas – is endorsed by Spinoza. In this passage the idea is portrayed to be conceptually prior to the form of the idea (see EIIp21s). And thus, on the basis of this claim as well, we can posit a priority of (b-ii) over (b-i). Example 5: EVp29s and EVp30 In EVp29s – the very scholium that also served as a basis for our claim concerning the vertical duality of our intellect – Spinoza asserts explicitly that modes are ‘real’ insofar as they are conceived ‘under a species of eternity’ and their ideas thus To be sure, the way in which the knowledge can be understood to ‘cross the boundary’ between Natura naturata and Natura naturans will only be elucidated in the next section. 117 TdIE §38, (I) 19. 118 EIIp43s, (I) 479. 116 364 ‘involve the eternal and infinite essence of God’.119 Indeed, as he stresses once more in the demonstration of EVp30: To conceive things under a species of eternity, therefore, is to conceive things insofar as they are conceived through God's essence, as real beings, or insofar as through God's essence they involve existence.120 (Res igitur sub specie æternitatis concipere, est res concipere, quatenus per Dei essentiam, ut entia realia, concipiuntur, sive quatenus per Dei essentiam involvunt existentiam) Now, it crucial to recognize that the very conception of ‘things under a species of eternity’ can only to take place when these things q u a things are conceived as given. One can only conceive a thing under a species of eternity (i.e. in its formal being at (b-i)), if that very same thing surfaces under duration (i.e. in its objective being at (b-ii)) first.121 And hence, taken in this way, the objective being serves as the basis for the inference of the formal being of that same thing; the objective being of ideas can indeed be perceived as the proximate cause of their formal beings. * These examples make it clear that from a certain perspective the ‘direction of fit’122 between the being of things insofar as these are conceived to represent their objects, and the same things insofar as they are considered in themselves, must be understood to be bottom-up in the way of table 5′. We have seen, firstly, that Spinoza’s philosophy also harbors a bottom-up perspective from which the objective being of things serves as ground floor, and, secondly, that considered from this bottom-up perspective the formal being of an idea ‘belongs’ to the attribute of thought (in the same way the glasses in our example in a previous section were claimed to ‘belong’ to the liquids that were in it). Consequently, table 5′ can be understood to provide an accurate rendering of an important aspect of Spinoza’s 119 EVp29s, (I) 610. EVp30d, (I) 610. 121 As we shall see in the next chapter, this must be understood to be a qualified remark. In the case of knowledge of the third kind one is actually able to grasp the eternal essence of things, not bottom-up (starting from the durational being of a thing), but top-down (proceeding from the formal essence of the attributes). 122 This term is not entirely adequate, as it appears to suppose an extrinsic fit (i.e. between the mind and something that is external to the mind), whereas in the present case the fit must be understood to be intrinsic (i.e. a bottom-up conception within the mind vs. a top-down conception within the mind). 120 365 metaphysics. On closer scrutiny, this is not too surprising. Actually, the bottom-up perspective appears to express a rather commonsensical view on the way human minds attain knowledge. For human mental behavior in the way we commonly understand it indeed appears to deal primarily with the external ‘parts of nature’ that are somehow represented in a human mind. The way in which this representation of external things can be understood to be related to the intellectual structure that we have uncovered will only be elucidated in the next chapter. First we will have to treat yet another important aspect of the bottom-up perspective: the way in which knowledge of the formal being of things can be understood to entail divine self-knowledge. 4.3.3 God’s bottom-up self-knowledge There is ample evidence for the claim that Spinoza fosters a bottom-up perspective between the objective (b-ii) and the formal being of things (b-i). Yet, at the same time it must be acknowledged that an understanding of this particular bottom-up perspective does not suffice for an understanding of the way in which God (c) can be conceived to know himself. For the bottom-up perspective that accounts for a full-blown version of God’s self-knowledge by way of our intellect needs to cross the conceptual boundary between Natura naturata and Natura naturans (i.e. between (b) and (a)). God can only be understood to know himself by way of a human mind if this perspective offers the divine r e s cognitive access to his own essence. It is precisely because of this that the variant of the bottom-up perspective provided in the introduction of this chapter did not halt at level (b), but was claimed to progress to level (a). This was rendered schematically in the following way: Natura naturans (a) God qua God (top-down) --------------------------------------(b-i) The formal being of singular things Natura naturata (bottom-up) (b-ii) The objective being of singular things (c) God (table 3) With respect to this table, we formulated the following questions: 366 (I) (II) We are in need of closer insight into the exact relation between the formal (b-i) and the objective (b-ii) being of singular things We must illuminate how knowledge of the formal being of singular things (b-i) enables our intellect to attain knowledge of God qua God (a) (i.e. how God (c) is able to gather self-knowledge) In the previous sections I have provided an answer to point (I). A scrutiny of Spinoza’s parallelism-claims in EIIp7 and EIIp21 has made it clear that the order and connection of the objective being of singular things (at (b-ii)) can be understood to be the same as the order and connection of the formal being of things (at (b-i)). This identity is rooted in the fact that the formal and objective being of things, although conceptually exclusive, must be understood to have the very same reference. Just as the whole of objective nature is ontologically identical to (yet conceptually distinct from) the absolutely infinite intellect (see Chapter 2), so also the finite parts that constitute the whole of objective nature must be understood to be ontologically identical to, yet conceptually distinct from the infinite parts-with-a-vista that constitute the absolutely infinite intellect. This is all but surprising, as we have seen that the formal and objective being of things – whether it be of the whole of nature or of singular things that merely constitute the whole of nature – must be understood to be the two ways in which pars melior nostri is asserted (in EVp29s) to conceive the very same things (namely: insofar as the thing under scrutiny is conceived (i) under a species of eternity, and (ii) in relation to a certain time and place). Having given an answer to the question that was captured under point (I) (and having shown that Spinoza’s parallelism can be understood to be yet another expression of the constructive function of the intellect, harboring the trichotomy of objects, their horizontally parallel objective beings, and their vertically parallel formal beings), we can turn to point (II). Below I will provide an123 answer to the question how God can be understood to know himself bottom-up (i.e. from effect to cause). However, before elucidating how this variant of divine self-knowledge can be understood, it may be instructive to first adduce a few passages that make it clear that Spinoza indeed fosters a bottom-up perspective that crosses the boundary 123 I claim that I will provide ‘an’ answer because a more comprehensive answer will be given in the next chapter, which deals with Spinoza’s claims concerning adequate knowledge 367 between Natura naturata and Natura naturans. I will provide five examples of statements from the Ethics that underpin this supposition. Example 1: The definition of attribute A first example of a passage that corroborates our claim that Spinoza puts forward a perspective that runs from (b) to (a) can be found in the notorious definition of ‘attribute’, which must be adduced once more: By attribute I understand what the intellect perceives of a substance, as constituting its essence. 124 (Per attributum intelligo id, quod intellectus de substantiâ percipit, tanquam ejusdem essentiam constituens) A lot has already been said concerning this important definition. The thing that must be stressed once more is that in EID4 Spinoza posits a conceptual operation with which the intellect (which is claimed (in EIp31) to be operative on the level of Natura naturata) attains knowledge of substance (which is claimed (in EIp29s) to be operative on the level of Natura naturans). So the conceptual operation that is forwarded in one of the most seminal definitions of the Ethics entails a conceptual operation that runs from (b) to (a). Example 2: EIp11d In the demonstration of EIp11, Spinoza gives various proofs for the existence of God. In the previous chapter we have seen that the first proof can be understood to underpin our claim concerning the conceptual distinction between the (a)- and the (c)-variant of the divine res.125 That EIp11d also provides evidence for the observation that the Ethics harbors a bottom-up perspective that runs from level (b) to level (a) becomes clear in the third proof that is provided in this demonstration: either nothing exists or an absolutely infinite Being also exists. But we exist [...]. Therefore an absolutely infinite Being – that is [...], God – necessarily exists, q.e.d. 124 125 EID4, (I) 408. See section 3.7. 368 Schol.: In this last demonstration I wanted to show God’s existence a posteriori, so that the demonstration would be perceived more easily – but not because God’s existence does not follow a priori from the same foundation.126 (ergo vel nihil existit, vel Ens absolutè infinitum necessariò etiam existit. Atqui nos [...] existimus [...]. Ergo ens absolutè infinitum, hoc est […] Deus necessariò existit. Q. E. D. SCHOLIUM. In hâc ultimâ demonstratione Dei existentiam à posteriori ostendere volui, ut demonstratio faciliùs perciperetur; non autem propterea, quòd ex hoc eodem fundamento Dei existentia à priori non sequatur) In this passage, Spinoza evidently makes use of an argument in which the boundary between the levels (b) and (a) is crossed. For he infers from the durational existence of modes (i.e. singular parts of the infinite modes of the attributes) – which clearly must be positioned at level (b) (see table 2 and 3) – that there is an absolutely infinite being (i.e. an absolutely indivisible substance) – at level (a). And although Spinoza’s remark in EIp11s indicates that he agrees with Descartes that such a bottom-up argument is ‘not so satisfactory as the other’,127 he evidently does make use of bottom-up reasoning in the adduced passage. Example 3: EIIp1 This way of reasoning surfaces in EIIp1 and its demonstration too: P1: Thought is an attribute of God, or God is a thinking thing Dem: Singular thoughts [...] are modes which express God’s nature in a certain and determinate way (by IP25C). Therefore (by ID5) there belongs to God an attribute whose concept all singular thoughts involve, and through which they are also conceived. Therefore, thought is one of God’s infinite attributes, which expresses an eternal and infinite essence of God (see ID6), or God is a thinking thing, q.e.d.128 (PROPOSITIO I. Cogitatio attributum Dei est, sive Deus est res cogitans. DEMONSTRATIO. Singulares cogitationes, sive hæc, & illa cogitatio modi sunt, qui Dei naturam certo, & determinato modo exprimunt (per Coroll. Prop. 25. p. 1.). Competit ergo Deo (per Defin. 5. p. 1.) attributum, cujus conceptum singulares omnes cogitationes involvunt, per quod etiam concipiuntur. Est igitur Cogitatio unum ex infinitis Dei attributis, quod Dei æternam, & infinitam essentiam exprimit (vid. Defin. 6. p. 1.), sive Deus est res cogitans. Q. E. D.) 126 EIp11-EIp11s, (I) 418. Descartes, Reply to Objections II, 49. 128 EIIp1, (I) 448. 127 369 It cannot fail to escape our notice that in this demonstration, Spinoza again starts with singular thoughts. Although singular thoughts – i.e. ‘those things that flow from external causes’ as opposed to ‘substances that [...] can be produced by no external cause’129 – must be considered to be caused by God, they nevertheless ‘come first’ in a certain respect. That is to say: it may be obvious that Spinoza takes God to be prior in nature, but the priority in knowledge (that is asserted in EIIp10s)130 is somewhat less obvious in the quoted passage from EIIp1. Apparently, in this latter proposition Spinoza cannot do without the bottom-up perspective that starts with singular things (at level (b)) in order to reach the conclusion that there can be conceived to be a res cogitans. And as we have seen in section 3.6 that the intellect-dependent attributes of EID4 must be understood to have an ontological counterpart at Natura naturans, this implies that EIIp1 posits a conceptual operation that runs from (b) to (a). EIIp1 provides us with yet another indication that Spinoza fosters a conceptual commitment with respect to Natura naturata, a commitment that enables the intellect to achieve knowledge of God’s eternal and infinite essence. Example 4: EIIp47 Consider EIIp47 and its demonstration: P47: The human mind has an adequate knowledge of God's eternal and infinite essence. Dem.: The human Mind has ideas (by P22) from which it perceives (byP23) itself, (by P19) its own Body, and (by P16Cl and P17) external bodies as actually existing. And so (by P45 and P46) it has an adequate knowledge of God's eternal and infinite essence, q.e.d.131 (PROPOSITIO XLVII. Mens humana adæquatam habet cognitionem æternæ, & infinitæ essentiæ Dei. DEMONSTRATIO. Mens humana ideas habet (per Prop. 22. hujus), ex quibus (per Prop. 23. hujus) se, suumq́ue Corpus (per Prop. 19. hujus), & (per Coroll. 1. Prop. 16. & per Prop. 17. hujus) corpora externa, ut actu existentia, percipit; adeóque (per Prop. 45. & 46. hujus) cognitionem æternæ, & infinitæ essentiæ Dei habet adæquatam. Q. E. D.) This claim clearly posits the very same conceptual commitment with respect to singular ideas, a commitment that in turn is asserted to provide a way to adequate 129 EIp11s, (I) 418. See the reference to this scholium in the introduction of this chapter. 131 EIIp47, (I) 482. 130 370 knowledge of God. According to Spinoza, the human mind has adequate knowledge of God’s essence because it has ideas; in this demonstration singular ideas serve as the ground floor for knowledge of God’s essence. Hence the perspective that is championed in the quoted passage can be understood (i) to be directed bottom-up, and (ii) to cross the boundary between Natura naturata and Natura naturans. In other words: this passage makes it abundantly clear that God, insofar as he is expressed in a human mind, does have cognitive access to his own essence. Example 5: The dictates of reason In part IV of the Ethics, Spinoza provides a series of propositions that are aimed at an elucidation of what he calls ‘the dictates of reasons’.132 In these propositions (EIVp18s-EIVp37s) Spinoza clearly heralds a bottom-up perspective, which surfaces (inter alia) in the following claim in EIVp18s: if we consider our Mind, our intellect would of course be more imperfect if the Mind were alone and did not understand anything except itself. There are, therefore, many things outside us which are useful to us, and on that account to be sought [emphasis added].133 (&, si præterea nostram Mentem spectemus, sanè noster intellectus imperfectior esset, si Mens sola esset, nec quicquam præter se ipsam intelligeret. Multa igitur extra nos dantur, quæ nobis utilia, quæq́ue propterea appetenda sunt) From this passage – and from various other passages from Spinoza’s elucidation of the dictates of reason – it becomes clear once more that the perspective from which there must be conceived to be multiple finite things outside our mind provides a way to knowledge of God. Indeed: The absolute virtue of the Mind, then, is understanding. But the greatest thing the Mind can understand is God.134 (Est igitur Mentis absoluta virtus intelligere. At summum, quod Mens intelligere potest, Deus est) Again, the conceptual commitment with respect to the whole of nature (at level (b)) can be understood to provide a way to knowledge of God (at level (a)). 132 EIVp18s, (I) 556. Ibidem, (I) 556. 134 EIVp28d, (I) 560. 133 371 * Having established that Spinoza can be understood to foster a bottom-up perspective that crosses the boundary between the conceptual levels (b) and (a), we can turn to the question how this proceeding functions precisely. With respect to the question how pars melior nostri is able to grasp the divine res adequately135 (or, what is the same, how God is able to attain genuine self-knowledge by way of a human mind), it is crucial to acknowledge that we have actually already isolated the ingredients with which an answer can be provided. That is to say: the things we have uncovered concerning the structure of Spinoza’s intellect provide us with a way to understand the variant of the bottom-up perspective that is the subject of the present section. Recall that with respect to pars melior nostri we have established the following: - we conceive things as actual in two ways things can be conceived in their objective and in their formal being the formal being of things can be understood to be equally in the part and in the whole as these are parts-with-a-vista of its immediate infinite mode these parts-with-a-vista must in turn be understood to be contained ubiquitously as a formal essence in their attributes these parts-with-a-vista thus involve an eternal and infinite essence of God These observations enable us to see how God can be understood to have cognitive access to his own essence via a human mind. Consider the following enumeration, in which it is shown how knowledge of a singular thing (in casu: a circle) enables God, (only)136 insofar as he is expressed in a human mind, to gather knowledge of his own essence: In the next chapter we will see that grasping something adequately means grasping something in its formal being. So this makes it very clear that the adequate grasping of the divine res entails the having of knowledge of the (a)-variant of the divine being: God considered in itself, or God qua God. 136 The term ‘only’ is added here because of a claim in EIIp11c that makes it clear that this ‘only’ is an important condition for the adequacy of an idea. In the enumeration (I)-(V) (see below) this ‘only’ is dropped because here the truth and adequacy of the idea that is staged in it (i.e. the idea of a circle) is already accounted for in the claim in EVp29s that ‘we conceive things as actual in two ways’. More on the way in which EVp29s is related to EIIp11c, and hence on the way in which the ‘adequacy’ of ideas must be understood precisely, in the next chapter. 135 372 (I) God, insofar as he is expressed in a human mind, conceives a circle in two ways. (II) God, insofar as he is expressed in a human mind, conceives a circle in its objective being (i.e. the idea of the circle) and in its formal being (i.e. the formal being of the idea of the circle).137 (III) This formal being of the idea of a circle, which is conceived by God insofar as he is expressed in a human mind, is a part-with-a-vista of the absolutely infinite intellect. (IV) This formal being of the idea of a circle, which is conceived by God insofar as he is expressed in a human mind, must in turn be understood to be the counterpart at Natura naturata of the formal essence of that circle that is contained ubiquitously in God as a res cogitans at Natura naturans (V) The formal being of the idea of a circle, which is conceived by God insofar as he is expressed in a human mind, thus involves an eternal and infinite essence of God From this we learn that (God, insofar as he is expressed in) a human mind indeed is able to grasp God’s eternal and infinite essence by way of the bottom-up perspective. On the basis of the things we have seen in this and the previous chapters, we can conclude that according to Spinoza knowledge that starts with a part (i.e. with the objective being of a thing) provides a way to knowledge of an eternal and infinite essence of God. Or, as Spinoza states it himself in EIIp45: ‘Each idea of each body, or of each singular thing which actually exists, necessarily involves an eternal and infinite essence of God.138 As already noted above, it is precisely this conceptual commitment to the parts of nature that accounts for the early-modern character of Spinoza’s philosophy. 137 As we are investigating the bottom-up perspective, this formal being surfaces here as the formal being of an idea (viz. as a mode of thinking), and not in its attribute-neutral guise. The same argument is applicable to the subsequent points. 138 EIIp45, (I) 481 (Unaquæque cujuscunque corporis, vel rei singularis, actu existentis, idea Dei æternam, & infinitam essentiam necessariò involvit). 373 4.3.3.1 An essence or the essence? Enumeration (I)-(IV) is not complete yet. One problem with it, is that it does not make it clear how the human mind is able to gather true and adequate knowledge of (say) a circle that actually exists under duration (i.e. how the horizontal representation of external things in the human mind functions precisely). As already noted, this important subject will be treated in the next chapter. First we have to address yet another problem. It is this: enumeration (I)-(IV) only shows how the human mind can be understood to have cognitive access to an eternal essence of God (in casu: God’s thinking essence); we must still answer the question whether cognitive access to an eternal essence of God implies knowledge of the eternal essence of God. Now, our claims so far certainly suggest that this is the case. In section 4.2.3.1 it was asserted that ‘the attributes must be understood to be ontologically and conceptually identical to the very infinite nature of […] God qua God’. However, we must not proceed too quickly here. For with respect to this subject it is crucial to note that some eminent scholars have claimed that knowledge by way of singular ideas does not offer a way to knowledge of the eternal divine essence. Edwin Curley is a case in point. He stated that ‘the idea [...] involves God’s essence only insofar as that essence is expressed through the attribute under which the idea’s object is conceived, not insofar as God’s essence is expressed in infinitely many attributes’.139 This claim is based on the following assertion by Martial Gueroult:140 it is clear as daylight that each attribute does not through itself provide knowledge of the essence of the infinitely infinite substance, but only [of the essence] of a certain substance, that is to say: of one of the perfections by which God is constituted141 So Gueroult and Curley both hold that knowledge that takes off from a singular idea (say: of a circle) only involves partial knowledge of God’s all-encompassing essence. Even though the thinking substance and the extended substance are 139 EIIp45 note 68, (I) 481. Curley refers explicitly to the claim of Gueroult that will be treated shortly. Ibidem, (I) 481. 141 Gueroult, Spinoza. Dieu, 54 (il résulte, clair comme le jour, que chaque attribut ne fait pas connaitre par lui seul l’essence de la substance infiniment infinie, mais seulement celle d’une certain substance, c'est-à-dire d’une des perfections dont Dieu est constitué) [my translation JHH]. 140 374 asserted by Spinoza to be ‘one and the same substance’ (in EIIp7s), these scholars suggest that the referential opacity that is applicable to modal contexts must be understood to be transferred to God’s absolute essence. On their reading Spinoza’s horizontal conceptual dualism142 (that is expressed in his claim in Letter 64 that the human animal has cognitive access to God’s essence via two attributes, and two attributes only)143 must be understood to reach all the way up to substance itself. Can these claims be upheld? Is it correct to state that knowledge of an idea only provides cognitive access to God’s thinking essence (and knowledge of a body only to God’s extended essence), and not to God’s essence sui generis? I think it is not. It can be shown that Gueroult cum suis ‘did not observe the proper order of Philosophizing’ as ‘they believe that the divine nature, which they should have contemplated before all else (because it is prior both in knowledge and in nature) is last in the order of knowledge, and that the things which are called objects of the senses are prior to all’.144 The crucial point in this respect is that – as argued for in section 3.6 – in Spinoza’s philosophy the attributes can be understood in two ways: in their intellect-dependent and in their intellect-independent variant. Recognition of this important conceptual duality with respect to the term ‘attribute’ provides a way to understand the ‘conceived real distinction’145 between the attributes, and the fact that from this conceived distinction ‘we still cannot infer that they constitute two beings, or two different substances’.146 Below I will provide three arguments for the claim that according to Spinoza the conceptual distinction between the intellect- This dualism of two attributes is called ‘horizontal’ as there is also a vertical conceptual dualism at work in Spinoza’s philosophy, namely between the (ontological) attributes and their (unspecified) infinite modes (and indeed between the formal and the objective being of singular things). 143 Letter 64, (II) 438. 144 EIIp10s, (I) 455 (Cujus rei causam fuisse credo, quòd ordinem Philosophandi non tenuerint. Nam naturam divinam, quam ante omnia contemplari debebant, quia tam cognitione, quàm naturâ prior est, ordine cognitionis ultimam, & res, quæ sensuum objecta vocantur, omnibus priores esse crediderunt). 145 In EIp10s Spinoza claims that ‘two attributes may be conceived to be really distinct’. EIp10s, (I) 416 (duo attributa realiter distincta concipiantur). 146 Ibidem, (I) 416 (non possumus tamen inde concludere, ipsa duo entia, sive duas diversas substantias constituere). Here we encounter the very same contradiction Alan Donagan refers to when he claims that ‘we are now in a deadlock. On the one hand, it has been established that Wolfson was mistaken in denying that the divine attributes are really distinct […]; on the other, Gueroult’s proposal has also been found wanting, that the divine attributes each constitute the essence of a distinct substance of one attribute, so that the essence of the divine substance is constituted by an infinity of essences of substances each infinite in its kind. Spinoza’s position is both that the divine attributes are really distinct, and that they each express the same essence’. Alan Donagan, ‘Essence and the Distinction of Attributes’, 62. 142 375 dependent attributes – that accounts for their causal and explanatory isolation at the level of Natura naturata – must be understood to dissolve into an absolute conceptual and ontological unity of the intellect-independent attributes at the level of Natura naturans. It will become clear that, as soon as the intellect-dependent attributes (which, as we saw in the previous chapter, must be located at the level of God (c)) are grasped as to their referential features, knowledge of the allencompassing essence of God qua God (a) is attained. Argument 1: God’s true and adequate ideas In EIIp32, Spinoza claims the following: All ideas, insofar as they are related to God, are true.147 (Omnes ideæ, quatenus ad Deum referuntur, veræ sunt) And in the demonstration of EIIp36 he states this: All ideas are in God (by IP15); and, insofar as they are related to God, are true (by P32), and (by P7C) adequate148 (Ideæ omnes in Deo sunt (per Prop. 15. p. 1.); &, quatenus ad Deum referuntur, sunt veræ (per Prop. 32. hujus), & (per Coroll. Prop. 7. hujus) adæquatæ) As all ideas in God are true and adequate, so also the idea of the circle that is had by God, only149 insofar as he is expressed in a human mind, can be understood to be true and adequate. It can be understood as such as soon as the objective being of the circle is grasped under a species of eternity, i.e. if the idea of the circle is grasped in its formal being.150 Now, the claims by Gueroult and Curley imply that the 147 EIIp32, (I) 472. EIIp36d, (I), 474. 149 See note 136. 150 At this point it may be elucidative to remark that the close connection between the adequacy of an idea and its formal being surfaces clearly in the claim in EIIp36d. For indeed, it cannot escape our notice that in the corollary Spinoza refers to – EIIp7c – the very distinction is made (as we already saw above) between ‘whatever follows formally from God’s infinite nature’ and the same things that follow ‘objectively in God from his idea’ [emphasis added]. The exact way in which the adequacy of an idea must be understood, and the way in which the formal being of a circle can be understood to be adequate in the human mind will be elucidated in the next chapter. 148 376 adequate idea of the circle that is had by God, insofar as he is expressed in a human mind, only accounts for partial divine self-knowledge. On their reading, in the case of the example of the idea of the circle, God can be understood to have cognitive access only to his own thinking (insofar as the idea is considered in itself) and extended essence (insofar as the idea is considered as to its extended object). The access to his r-ed essence and to his essence sui generis is claimed to be barred. This is a surprising limit to ‘a Being absolutely infinite and supremely perfect’,151 the more so as several assertions in the Ethics claim the exact opposite. Consider the following clause in EVp30: Insofar as our mind knows itself and its body under a species of eternity, it necessarily has knowledge of God’152 (Mens nostra, quatenus se, & Corpus sub æternitatis specie cognoscit, eatenus Dei cognitionem necessariò habet) In the demonstration of this proposition the following is added: to conceive things under a species of eternity [...] is to conceive things insofar as they are conceived through God’s essence […]’.153 (Res igitur sub specie æternitatis concipere, est res concipere, quatenus per Dei essentiam […] concipiuntur) Spinoza’s claim in EIIp46 is perhaps even clearer in this respect: The knowledge of God’s eternal and infinite essence which each idea involves is adequate and perfect. 154 (Cognitio æternæ, & infinitæ essentiæ Dei, quam unaquæque idea involvit, est adæquata, & perfecta) In these claims there is no indication at all that knowledge of mind and body by way of pars melior nostri (and hence God’s self-knowledge insofar as he is expressed in a human mind) leads to partial knowledge of God only. Knowledge of things under a species of eternity – i.e. knowledge of things in their formal being155 – is EIp11, (I), 417 (Ente absolutè infinito, & summè perfecto). EVp30, (I) 610. 153 EVp30d, (I) 610. 154 EIIp46, (I) 482. 155 In the next chapter we will see that the adequacy of ideas consists precisely in grasping the formal being of ideas. Another way of saying this is that in Spinoza’s philosophy there must be understood to be two variants of adequate knowledge: a bottom-up and a top-down variant (as we have shown that the formal being of ideas can be grasped in two ways). In Chapter 5 we will see (i) that Spinoza indeed distinguishes 151 152 377 claimed to entail ‘perfect’ knowledge of God’s essence. Surely, if it was Spinoza’s intention to assert that knowledge of mind and body leads to knowledge of God’s essence insofar as he is expressed in thought and extension only, he would have added this important restriction (and would have abstained from using the word ‘perfecta’). We cannot fail to notice that the assertions in EIIp46 and EVp30, that must be understood to be strangely incomplete on the reading of Gueroult and Curley, say exactly what they are supposed to say on the present interpretation: knowledge of an eternal essence of God implies knowledge of the eternal essence of God. According to Spinoza, God, insofar as he is expressed in a human mind (i.e. God (c)), has cognitive access to his own all-encompassing essence (i.e. God qua God (a)). And really: what else can we expect from a being that is claimed to be absolutely perfect and supreme, and that is asserted to have adequate and true ideas only? Argument 2: Two attributes only? Gueroult’s remarks concerning the (in my terms) merely partial self-knowledge of God are motivated by a problem that is real enough. It is the problem of the (apparent) infinity of the number of attributes, and the fact that the human mind is explicitly claimed (in Letter 64) to have access to only two of them: thought and extension.156 This leads to the following question: if the adequate ideas in our intellect are nothing but adequate ideas of God himself, then how is it possible that we have cognitive access to two attributes only? Does not the fact that we are capable of ‘logging in’ to God’s adequate self-knowledge imply that we must be able to attain knowledge of each of the infinite attributes? And does not the fact that human knowledge of the remaining attributes is explicitly denied by Spinoza in Letter 64 imply that God’s self-knowledge by way of the human mind must thus be understood to be partial after all? As already noted, the problem that is addressed two variants of adequate knowledge, and (ii) that these can be mapped on the two perspectives that were discerned in this chapter. 156 I use the term ‘apparent’ because it is absolutely unclear how these remaining attributes must be understood. At the same time, Spinoza’s formulations in (inter alia) Letter 64 make it clear that there must be understood to be more attributes than thought and extension, even though the human mind is claimed to ‘involve’ and ‘express’ the latter two only. Letter 64, (II) 438. 378 by Gueroult is real enough. Moreover, it must be admitted that Spinoza’s answers in Letters 64 and 66 to G.H. Schuller’s and Ehrenfried Walther von Tschirnhaus’s questions157 about the very same subject are unconvincing, or hermetic at best.158 Still, even though it is hard to find support for the present interpretation (nor, it must be added, for Gueroult’s view) in the only passages in Spinoza’s work in which the present problem is addressed explicitly, the remaining ‘circumstantial’ textual support is clearly in favour of an interpretation that upholds the claim that knowledge of a certain essence of substance implies knowledge of the essence of substance. In this respect it is crucial to note that any suggestion that God should be constituted by referentially opaque multiple essences defies the explicit claim in EIp13 that ‘a substance which is absolutely infinite is indivisible’.159 It is hard to see how this assertion can be upheld while at the same time advancing a conception of substance that is constituted by multiple essences. True, Spinoza’s definition of attribute (EID4) makes a suggestion in this latter direction; it is hard to deny that according to Spinoza the essence of substance can be perceived in (to put it conservatively) more than one way. But this does not imply that the perceived aspects of the essence of substance must be understood to have a constituting function at the level of God qua God. EID4 provides two clear indications that the implicit distinction between ‘constituting’ essences is intellect-dependent (and applicable to God (c)) and hence cannot be understood to be operative at the level of Natura naturans (God qua God (a)) insofar as this level can be inferred to exist 157 Actually, they are all Tschirnhaus’s questions, For as Schuller remarks in Letter 63, just before mentioning the problem concerning the knowledge of only two attributes: ‘[Mr. von Tschirnhaus] asked me repeatedly to propose a solution to the following doubts’ ([Tschirnhausen] me iterato rogans, ut sequentium dubiorum solutionem tibi proponerem). Letter 63, (II) 426. 158 In Letter 64 Spinoza says that ‘the human Mind can achieve knowledge only of the things which the idea of an actually existing body involves’ (Mentem humanam illa tantummodò posse cognitione assequi, quæ idea corporis actu existentis involvit). Letter 64, (II), 438. And in Letter 66, replying to Tschirnhaus’s question in Letter 65, he claims: ‘I say that although each thing is expressed in infinite ways in the infinite intellect of God, nevertheless those infinite ideas by which it is expressed cannot constitute one and the same Mind of a singular thing, but infinity many minds, since each of the infinite ideas has no connection with any other, as I’ve explained in the Scholium to E II P7, and as is evident from I P10.’. Letter 66, (II) 440-441 (quòd quàmvis unaquæque res infinitis modis expressa sit in infinito Dei intellectu, illæ tamen infinitæ ideæ, quibus exprimitur, unam eandemque rei singularis Mentem constituere nequeunt; sed infinitas: quandoquidem unaquæque harum infinitarum idearum nullam connexionem cum invicem habent, ut in eodem Scholio Propositionis 7. Part. 2. Ethic. explicui, & ex Prop. 10. Part. 1. patet). This answer is claimed to be ‘hermetic’ as it is not easy to see how EIp10 and EIIp7 provide the answer to Tschirnhaus’s question. See also note 163. 159 EIp13, (I) 420 (Substantia absolutè infinita est indivisibilis). 379 absolutely outside the intellect. For in his notorious definition of ‘attribute’ Spinoza not only claims that an attribute is what the intellect perceives (instead of ‘conceives’), but moreover he adds that an attribute is what the intellect perceives as (tamquam) constituting an essence of substance. If it is acknowledged (i) that the verb ‘perceives’ indicates that this particular way of grasping substance is inferior to another (un-indicated) way of grasping the same thing (i.e. ‘conceiving’),160 (ii) that the term ‘tamquam’ can also be read as ‘as if’, and (iii) that this very ‘as if’ refers to the verb ‘constituting’ (and not to the noun ‘essence’), we encounter an alternative way of understanding EID4, a reading that is completely in line with Spinoza’s other claims about God’s essence. For now we can provide the following comprehensive definition of ‘attribute’, a definition in which both the ontological and the conceptual variants of ‘attribute’ are captured: An attribute is (i) what expresses a c e r t a i n e s s e n c e o f s u b s t a n c e , and (ii) what the (infinite) intellect g r a s p s b o t t o m - u p of a substance a s i f this certain essence is constituting the all-encompassing essence of substance Indeed, even though each attribute expresses a certain essence of substance (by EIp10s) that must be understood to have an ontological status at Natura naturans (by EIp29s), and even though the perceiving of this essence by way of our intellect – i.e. bottom-up from Natura naturata – suggests that substance is thus constituted by the infinite attributes, the relation between substance and its attributes can in no way be understood to be a relation of parts and wholes. Rather, it is clear that according to Spinoza the very horizontal conceptual duality between the intellectdependent attributes that is recognizable at the level of Natura naturata must be understood to be grounded in an absolute extra-intellectual unity of the intellectindependent attributes at the level of Natura naturans, somewhat in the same way the distinct manifestations ‘thunder’ and ‘lightning’ can be understood to be expressions of one phenomenon (or ‘milk’ and ‘water’ can both be understood to be contained in a fluid-neutral glass). 160 In the Explication of EIID3, Spinoza says that ‘the word perception seems to indicate that the Mind is acted on by the object. But concept seems to express an action of the Mind’. EIID3, (I) 447 (quia perceptionis nomen indicare videtur, Mentem ab objecto pati. At conceptus actionem Mentis exprimere videtur). 380 This point can be elucidated further adducing an argument that was used in section 3.6. Consider the following table once more: Natura naturans ---------------------Natura naturata (a) Substance qua substance intrinsically causing (bt) The infinite intellect (ct) Thinking substance (table 6) The thing to recall with respect to this table is that (ct) can only be called thinking substance when the infinite intellect is produced by (a). The very thinking essence that is expressed objectively in (bt) (by the Principle of Plenitude EIp16), and that comes to light conceptually (or intellect-dependently) in (ct) (by EID4), must be understood to be rooted ontologically in (a). As already noted in section 3.6, this is completely in line with Spinoza’s claim that ‘God’s power is God’s essence itself’:161 Spinoza’s God is absolutely omnipotent because ‘everything which can fall under an infinite intellect’ (bt) follows from the necessity of God’s essence (a). It is also precisely because of this that Spinoza is able to state in EIIp7c that ‘God’s power of thinking is equal to his actual power of acting’:162 the divine essence that can be grasped intellectually via an attribute (in casu: thought) must be understood to be absolutely identical to the extra-intellectual divine essence sui generis. There is yet another way of showing this. Consider the following tables: (a) Electrical discharge expressed in (b) Light waves (c) Lightning (table 7) Or: (a) Glass containing (c) Glass of milk (b) Milk (table 8) Or: 161 162 EIp34, (I) 439 (Dei potentia est ipsa ipsius essentia). EIIp7c, (I) 451 (Dei cogitandi potentia aequalis est ipsius actuali agendi potentiae). 381 (a) The third patriarch In his capacity of (b) The person who was so-called because he seized his brother’s heel (c) Jacob (table 9) Now, with respect to these tables the following is noteworthy: - as soon as someone acquires knowledge of a violent electrical discharge insofar as it is an electrical discharge by way of a study of the lightning that is an expression of it, one has acquired knowledge of the underlying phenomenon (a) sui generis (and not only of this discharge insofar as it is expressed in lightning (c)) - as soon as one has acquired knowledge about a glass insofar as it is a glass by way of an investigation of a glass that contained milk, one has acquired knowledge of a glass (a) sui generis (and not only of a glass insofar as it contains milk (c)). - as soon as one establishes that (say) Jacob was buried in the cave of Machpelah, one has also acquired knowledge about the burial place of the third patriarch insofar as he is referred to by any other name (and not only of the burial place of the third patriarch insofar as he is called ‘Jacob’). Furthermore it must be noted that knowledge of an electrical discharge, a glass or the third patriarch via the proposed bottom-up route does imply nor require that the knowing agent has acquired knowledge of respectively all (c)-manifestations of the electrical discharge, all the infinitely many fluids that can be understood to be contained in the glass, and all the names that can be used in order to designate the third patriarch. Now, the very same appears to apply to Spinoza’s view on the relation between substance and its attributes: as soon as adequate knowledge is acquired by way of the intellect-dependent attribute of thought (ct), one has also acquired knowledge concerning God’s essence sui generis (a), without the necessary implication that knowledge of this all-encompassing essence at level (a) entails knowledge of all the aspects of this essence that must be understood to be somehow 382 conceivable with an intellect. Admittedly, this solution is not as strong as one may wish for.163 But at the same time it seems to be the only way in which Spinoza’s statements in Letter 64 and 66 can be squared with his explicit claim in EIp12 and EIp13 that a substance is indivisible, whilst at the same time upholding the assertion in EIIp47 that ‘the human mind has an adequate knowledge of God’s eternal and infinite essence’. With respect to this latter contention it must be added that, if Spinoza would have intended to make it clear that the human mind must be understood to have knowledge of certain constitutive aspects of God’s eternal and infinite essence only, then surely he would have added this important restriction here. But again, this addition lacks. On the basis of the comprehensive rendering of EID4 it is clear why: Spinoza does not need to add the restriction as in the context of his philosophy the knowledge of an eternal essence of God (c) implies knowledge of the eternal essence of God qua God (a). 163 It seems that the problem is rooted in the notorious EID4. Spinoza’s choice to render the definition of attributes in conceptual terms (i.e. in terms of ‘what the intellect perceives) – a choice that appears to be inspired by his need to combine a medieval top-down perspective with the very bottom-up perspective that is the subject of this chapter, and of which (as we saw above) EID4 can be understood to be an important expression – provides him with the problem that the remaining attributes (i.e. the attributes apart from though and extension) seem to fall without the scope of EID4. For even though these remaining attributes must be understood to be ontological aspects of substance, it seems that they cannot be perceived by an intellect. Spinoza’s hermetic solution to this problem in Letter 66 to Tschirnhaus is hardly illuminating. He states here that ‘although each thing is expressed in infinite ways in the infinite intellect of God, nevertheless those infinite ideas by which it is expressed cannot constitute one and the same Mind of a singular thing, but infinitely many minds, since each of the infinite ideas has no connection with any other, as I’ve explained in the Scholium to EIIP7, and as is evident from IP10’. Letter 66, (II) 440-441 (quòd quàmvis unaquæque res infinitis modis expressa sit in infinito Dei intellectu, illæ tamen infinitæ ideæ, quibus exprimitur, unam eandemque rei singularis Mentem constituere nequeunt; sed infinitas: quandoquidem unaquæque harum infinitarum idearum nullam connexionem cum invicem habent, ut in eodem Scholio Propositionis 7. Part. 2. Ethic. explicui, & ex Prop. 10. Part. 1. patet). It is hard to see how the mentioned passages can be understood to corroborate the claim that in nature there must (apparently) be infinitely many parallel minds that (apparently) each have access to one of the remaining attributes. For the only thing that Spinoza asserts in EIp10 and EIIp7s is that (i) attributes must be conceived through themselves, (ii) that we must suppose one and the same connection of causes in any of the attributes. However, in these passages little is said concerning the representational nature of thought and the way it provides cognitive access to the other attributes. And it is precisely this that Tschirnhaus’s (and indeed our) question demands. 383 Argument 3: Absolute unity Gueroult and Curly hold that Spinoza’s horizontal conceptual dualism between thought and extension must be understood to reach all the way up to the essence of substance itself. Just as an idea (at Natura naturata) must be conceived to be conceptually distinct from (even though ontologically identical to) its body, so also (Gueroult and Curley claim) thinking substance (which they both locate at Natura naturans)164 is conceptually distinct from (even though ontologically identical to) extended and r-ed substance. We have already provided two arguments that suggest that this is not a correct way of understanding the structure of Spinoza’s metaphysics. But there is yet another way of showing that the suggested variant of referential opacity cannot be understood to be operative at the level of Natura naturans (a). In this respect it is important to note that we have shown above that the horizontal distinction between an idea and its body is an implication of the vertical distinction between the objective and the formal being of the thing under scrutiny. Indeed, concerning Spinoza’s important parallelism claim in EIIp7 we have established that the idea of (say) a circle and the extended circle itself can be understood to be the very same thing because they must both be conceived to be finite expressions in their own attribute of their attribute-neutral formal being (see section 4.2.3.1). Now, with respect to the claim of Gueroult cum suis it is crucial to note that the horizontal conceptual distinction between thinking, extended and red substance can only be made if there is also asserted a vertical conceptual distinction between these infinitely many certain essences and the all-encompassing essence of God. That is to say: the horizontal distinction can only be made when apart from the formal being of an attribute (say: of thought), a prior layer of the divine res is posited. If two concepts are claimed to be ontologically identical, then the absolute ontological identity of the thing these concepts refer to – and hence a conceptual layer that is prior to the conceptual duality under scrutiny– is posited eo ipso. To be sure, Gueroult made the same observation; he makes the distinction between ‘a certain substance’ and a prior ‘infinitely infinite substance’.165 In this sense his interpretation runs parallel with the present one, as we have also made a conceptual distinction between God and God qua God. However, as Gueroult does 164 165 More on this shortly. See note 141. 384 not distinguish between the two concepts of God that were uncovered in Chapter 3, his position must be understood to entail that the horizontal and vertical duality are operative at the level of God’s absolute essence, i.e. at the level of God qua God (a). Yet, it has become clear in the previous chapter that a prior – or eminent – layer of the divine res at level (a) goes against anything Spinoza is willing to admit. In section 3.5 we have seen that God’s essence (a) must be understood to be an absolute unity that is self-causing as a one place predicate. Anyone who would claim on the basis of the multiplicity in nature that God’s essence is constituted by multiple essences166 turns nature upside down. From what we have seen in the previous chapters, it is clear that God’s infinite power of thinking at level (a) must be understood to differ from our intellect precisely in the fact that there is no duality whatsoever (i.e. neither vertical nor horizontal) that can be attributed to it; whereas the intellect, whether finite or infinite, is at most simultaneous with the things understood, in God qua God (a) thought, extension and r must be understood to be absolutely identical. * On the present interpretation the horizontal distinction between the attributes is safeguarded without the unwelcome implication that God must be understood to be constituted by infinitely many essences. That is to say: as we have shown that Spinoza distinguishes between two concepts of God, we can see how he is able to state that God’s essence admits of no duality or multiplicity whatsoever, while at the same time upholding that God can be perceived to be constituted by his attributes. The distinction between God qua God (a) and God (c) safeguards that the intellect-dependent variant of God (c) can be conceived to express the vertical coalescence of God’s absolute essence (a) and the infinite modes that follow from this essence (b). Another way of saying this is that the very conceptual distinction 166 As must be clear from the present context, the ‘multiple essences’ that we speak of here are the essences that are intellectually expressed in the infinite attributes, i.e. God’s absolute thinking, extended and r-ed essence. To be sure, our interpretation implies that there is yet another category of essences that must be understood to be operative at the level of Natura naturans: the formal essences of the infinitely many things that follow from the necessity of the divine nature. As these formal essences of things were shown to be contained pervasively in the attributes, the absolute unity of substance is also not threatened by this particular multiplicity of essences. 385 between God qua God (a) and God (c) accounts for the fact that our intellect can at the same time be understood to be a part of a divine intellect (namely of the infinite intellect of God (c) that surfaces in (inter alia) EIIp11c), and to be fundamentally different from a divine ‘intellect’ (namely from the absolute thinking essence of God qua God (a) that surfaces in EIp17s). With respect to this important observation it may be informative to add that both Gueroult and Curley team up with Alexandre Koyré (see Chapter 1) and claim that ‘God’s intellect’ (EIp17s) and our intellect do not stand to each other like a constellation of stars and a barking animal. As already noted before, this assertion is understandable. For prima facie it is hard to see how Spinoza is able to claim that ‘God’s intellect’ and our intellect have nothing in common with each other, whilst at the same time holding that our intellect is part of the infinite intellect of God. However, this apparent contradiction is solved once it is acknowledged that, whereas the term ‘God’s intellect’ insofar as it is conceived to refer to the coalescent thinking substance (c) certainly has a close connection with our intellect (as our intellect is a part of the infinite intellect that must be understood to be a coalescent aspect of God (c)), ‘God’s intellect’ insofar as it refers to God’s absolute thinking essence (a) – as is conditionally proposed in EIp17s – is fundamentally different from our intellect. The problem that Gueroult encounters finds its root in the fact that he does not distinguish between the two concepts of ‘God’ (and hence between the intellectdependent and the intellect-independent variants of God’s attributes) that can be detected in the Ethics. Gueroult cum suis erroneously transfer the intellectdependent duality between thought and extension (or in terms of EIp10s: the real distinction of the attributes that finds its ground in the fact that one can ‘be conceived without the aid of the other’)167 from God (c) to God qua God (a).168 Yet, this operation finds no warrant in Spinoza’s work. For Spinoza makes it very clear that anyone who would claim that, because our intellect is characterized by a duality, so also God’s infinite power of thinking must be understood to be characterized by a prior – or eminent – duality (that can account for a horizontal or 167 EIp10s, (I) 416. Remark that the ‘real distinction’ is staged in terms of ‘conception’, which indeed suggests that the real distinction takes place (and takes place only) insofar as substance appears in it coalescent variant. 168 Or as Alan Donagan stated it: ‘[Gueroult] has overlooked that if there is only one causal act by which all the attributes of God exist, then there is only one essence which involves their existence’. Donagan, ‘Essence and the Distinction of Attributes’, 61. 386 vertical duality at level (a)), reasons in exactly the same way a triangle would reason when it would claim that God must be understood to be characterized by a prior – or eminent – layer of triangularity. Anyone who transfers the conceptual commitment with respect to the infinite intellect at level (b) to God’s absolute thinking essence (a), ‘did not observe the proper order of Philosophizing’. 169 For whereas the ‘objects of the senses’170 are grasped at most ‘simultaneous with the things understood’, God’s essence – encompassing absolute thought – must be understood as an absolute unity. To Spinoza, this is as clear as the fact that stars do not bark. 4.3.3.2 Extra-intellectual? Above I aimed to show that God, insofar as he is expressed in a human mind, has cognitive access to his own essence sui generis. I have provided various arguments for the claim that this bottom-up perspective that crosses the boundary between Natura naturata and Natura naturans must indeed be understood to play an important role in Spinoza’s mature philosophy. To be sure, we are not there yet. There still appears to be one important lacuna with respect to the present interpretation. It is the tension between the absolute extra-intellectual status of God’s essence (a) that was argued for in the previous chapter, and the present claim that the human mind has cognitive access to the eternal and infinite essence of God. Indeed: how can our claim from Chapter 3 that God qua God (a) is outside the reach of the intellect be squared with the assertions in the present section? Does not the claim that the human mind has cognitive access to God qua God (a) imply that God qua God is not absolutely extra-intellectual? The first way to corroborate our claim that God qua God, even though this variant of the divine being must be understood to exist and be self-conceiving absolutely outside the intellect, can still be understood to come within the scope of the intellect in the way we commonly understand it, is by stressing that it is (i) the conceptual direction and (ii) the conceptual structure that dictates whether knowledge can be understood to be knowledge of an intellect or not. With respect to the 169 170 EIIp10s, (I) 455 (ordinem Philosophandi non tenuerint). Ibidem, (I) 455 (sensuum objecta). 387 absolute self-conception of God qua God (a) that was elucidated in Chapter 3, we can establish the following: (i) the absolute self-knowledge of God qua God (a) was shown to take place entirely at level (a) and hence to (somehow) proceed from level (a) to level (a) (i.e. to cause a cause q u a cause). This makes it clear that the conceptual (and causal) direction is different from the variant of the divine selfknowledge that was elucidated above. For this bottom-up variant of God’s self-knowledge was shown to proceed from level (b) to level (a); (ii) it was shown that the self-knowledge of God qua God (a) cannot in any way be understood to be bifurcated in the way the knowledge of an intellect (in the way we commonly understand it) is. This makes it clear that the conceptual structure of the absolute extra-intellectual self-knowledge differs from our bottom-up knowledge of God in the same way a constellation of stars differs from a barking dog. These two points make it clear that God qua God can be understood to come within the reach of the intellect, without the implication that the bottom-up perspective entails absolute extra-intellectual self-knowledge of the divine res. For it is clear now that, even though the bottom-up perspective entails cognitive access to the eternal essence of God qua God, it has (i) the wrong conceptual direction and (ii) the wrong conceptual structure to count as God’s absolute self-knowledge (or ‘absolute thought’). Another way of saying this that the bottom-up perspective accounts for self-knowledge of God (c), not for self-knowledge of God qua God (a). There is a second way of corroborating the claim that the extra-intellectual character of the absolute self-knowledge of the divine res can be squared with the claim that it is possible to gather knowledge of this variant of God. In this respect it is crucial to note that insofar as God’s essence is grasped with an intellect – and hence insofar as the divine thing that is contained objectively in the intellect is understood to be necessarily in nature (to paraphrase a claim from EIp30d) – the divine essence is known insofar as it is mediated by the intellect that grasps it. Now of course, this very divine essence must also be understood to exist apart from any intellectual operation; if this would not be the case, the objective knowledge of this 388 essence would have to count as ‘a conclusion without a premise’,171 which is absurd on the basis of the claim from EIp30d. A substance can only be grasped with an intellect – and hence fall apart conceptually in a formal and an objective aspect – if this substance also exists absolutely outside the intellect, i.e. in a realm where the distinction between its formal and objective being is absolutely senseless. In short: God’s essence as it is absolutely in itself must be understood to ‘escape’ the intellect; it is essentially impossible to use the intellect to grasp something in its absolute extraintellectual status. Indeed, God’s essence, which surfaces objectively as the infinite intellect, and formally as the (ontological variant of the) attribute of thought, must be understood to ‘exist’ in itself absolutely extra-intellectually. This of course is precisely the point that was already made in Chapter 3. Having elucidated this last important subject, we can conclude that when God (insofar as he is expressed in a human mind) has objective knowledge of a thing, he has cognitive access to his own essence; knowledge of an eternal and infinite essence of God (c) (starting from an idea (b-ii), via the formal being of that idea (b-i), reaching knowledge of the formal essence of that idea (a)) implies knowledge of the eternal and infinite essence of God (a). Given what we have seen above, we can enhance points (IV) and (V) in the following way: (IV′) This formal being of the idea of a circle, which is conceived by God, insofar as he is expressed in a human mind, must in turn be understood to be the counterpart at Natura naturata of the formal essence of that circle, which is contained ubiquitously in God sui generis at Natura naturans (V′) The formal being of the idea of a circle, which is in God (c) insofar as he is expressed in a human mind, thus expresses the eternal and infinite essence of God qua God (a) God, insofar as he is expressed in a human mind, has bottom-up cognitive access to his own essence. 171 This clause is inspired by Spinoza’s claim in EIIp28d that ‘ideas of the affections, insofar as they are related only to the human mind, are like conclusions without premises’. EIIp28d, (I) 470 (Sunt ergo hæ affectionum ideæ, quatenus ad solam humanam Mentem referuntur, veluti consequentiæ absque præmissis). 389 Now that it has become clear that Spinoza not only fosters a variant of bottom-up knowledge that halts at Natura naturata, but that the conceptual operation in table 3 can genuinely be called (bottom up) self-knowledge of God (c) (as God (c) encompasses the knowledge with which (b) conceives (a)),172 we can provide the following comprehensive rendering of the structure of the selfknowledge of God (c):173 Natura naturans (a) God qua God -------------------------------------------------(b-i) The formal being of singular things Natura naturata - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - (b -ii) The objective being of singular things (c) God (table 10) This table expresses the very way in which Spinoza can be understood to depart from the medieval philosophical tradition, whilst at the same time upholding the medieval view of the absolute priority of God. With the perspective that surfaces in (inter alia) EIIp7s and EIIp21, Spinoza provides a way for attaining true selfknowledge of God – and hence of nature – via the level of modes. The bottom-up perspective in the way uncovered in this chapter must be understood to be a highly idiosyncratic expression of the (early) modern scientific character of Spinoza’s philosophy. Spinoza’s claim that God and nature refer to the very same thing, combined with his assertion – elucidated in this chapter – that is it possible to acquire true knowledge of Deus sive Natura by investigating the objective being of singular things, differs considerably from the claims of his medieval predecessors (and contemporary opponents), and provides a philosophical basis for a scientific view of nature. To be sure, this is not to say that Spinoza’s philosophy is devoid of medieval aspects. Quite the opposite. Table 10 clearly shows that Spinoza also upholds a certain ‘medieval perspective’ from which God is prior to the things that follow from him. It is important to note that these two perspectives correspond Remark that this claim concerning God (c)’s bottom-up self-conception mirrors the claim from section 3.4.1 concerning his top-down self-causation as a two-place predicate. There we have said that (c) is the cause of itself as (a) causes (b). In this section we claim that (c) conceives itself as (b) conceives (a). 173 The extra-intellectual self-knowledge of God (a) that must be understood to proceed from (a) to (a), is not captured in this table, not only because it is very hard to find a proper way to render this particular variant of God’s self-knowledge, but also because in this study we are primarily interested in the knowledge of the intellect. 172 390 with the two kinds of adequate knowledge that Spinoza discerns. Indeed, perhaps the best argument for the claim that he distinguishes two variants of God’s selfknowledge has not been provided yet. It is the fact that in the important second scholium of EIIp40 Spinoza forwards two kinds of adequate knowledge that can be had by our intellect (and hence by God insofar as he is expressed in a human mind): reason (ratio) and intuitive knowledge (scientia intuitiva). In the next chapter it will become clear that the two perspectives referred to in this chapter must be understood to express these two variants of knowing things adequately. 4.4 Conclusion Spinoza occupies on intriguing position in the history of philosophy. For on the one hand this ‘God-intoxicated man’ champions a medieval way of understanding the causal generation of nature: according to Spinoza the whole of nature can be understood to be created by God; considered realiter, God is prior to everything that follows from him. Yet on the other hand the ‘righteous atheist’ fosters a perspective from which the all-encompassing totality of modes that constitute God’s creation are (i) identical with God, (ii) conceptually prior to God, and (iii) offer a way to gather knowledge of God’s essence. This chapter was aimed at elucidating this latter early modern perspective as well as the way in which it is related to the medieval thread that can be discerned in Spinoza’s philosophy. Whereas the previous chapters dealt mainly with the way omnes res must be understood to follow from (and to inhere in) God, in the present chapter we have seen how the top-down causal (and conceptual) perspective can be understood to be teamed up with a bottom-up conceptual (and causal) stance. The scrutiny of this bottom-up perspective was invoked by way of an analysis of one of the central tenets of Spinoza’s metaphysics: his so called ‘parallelism thesis, which surfaces in EIIp7. This proposition reads thus: The order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of things.174 (Ordo, & connexio idearum idem est, ac ordo, & connexio rerum) 174 EIIp7, (I) 451. 391 This claim is generally understood to posit an identity relation between things conceived under the attribute of thought, and things conceived under the attribute of extension. In Spinoza’s own words: ‘a mode of extension and the idea of that mode are one and the same thing, but expressed in two ways’.175 This can be rendered schematically in the following way: Natura naturans Thought = Extension = R --------------------------------------------------------------(c) God Natura naturata idea x = body x = rx (table 4) In this chapter it has become clear that this rendering of the horizontal numerical identity of ideas and bodies (and r’s) does justice to Spinoza’s claims in the Ethics. Various passages underpin the claim that horizontal inter-attribute parallelism is endorsed by Spinoza. Yet, we have seen that EIIp7 entails something more. A scrutiny of EIIp7 and its connection with an alternative parallelism claim in EIIp21 and its scholium taught us that the horizontal parallelism of table 4 is to be seen as a mere implication of the comprehensive vertical parallelism claim that surfaces in the following rendering: Natura naturans (a) God qua God ----------------------------------------------------------------(b-i) The formal being of singular things Natura naturata is identical to (b-ii) The objective being of singular things (c) God (table 5) The assertion in EIIp21 that the ‘idea [in God] of the [human] mind is united to the mind in the same way as the mind is united to the human body’,176 and the explication in EIIp21s that ‘the idea of the mind and the mind itself are one and the same thing, which is conceived under one and the same attribute, namely, thought’177 led us to the observation that the horizontal inter-attribute and vertical parallelism must be understood to be manifestations of the very same transitive parallelism. EIIp7s, (I) 451 (modus extensionis, & idea illius modi una, eademq́ue est res, sed duobus modis expressa). EIIp21, (I) 467 (Hæc Mentis idea eodem modo unita est Menti, ac ipsa Mens unita est Corpori). 177 EIIp21s, (I) 467 (quare Mentis idea, & ipsa Mens una, eademq́ue est res, quæ sub uno, eodemq́ue attributo, nempe Cogitationis, concipitur). 175 176 392 Indeed, a scrutiny of some key passages in the Ethics led us to the following comprehensive formulation of the parallelism claim of EIIp7: the order and connection of the objective being of things (b-ii) is the same as the order and connection of the formal being of things (b-i). The relation between the ‘horizontal’ (i.e. operating at the same conceptual level) and the ‘vertical’ (i.e. operating at different conceptual levels) aspects of Spinoza’s parallelism claim can be formulated succinctly in the following way: A singular idea and its parallel mode (or object) under extension both are finite and durational expressions (b-ii) in their own attribute of the very same eternal formal being (b-i). Just as a bolt of lightning and the accompanying thunder are one and the same thing insofar as they both are manifestations of one and the same phenomenon, so also a man and the idea of that man are the same thing insofar as they both are finite expressions of the very same formal being. In other words: because the formal and objective being of a thing is (vertically) identical under the same attribute (table 5), the objective expression of that same thing is (horizontally) identical under different attributes (table 4). Vertical parallelism encompasses horizontal parallelism. To be sure, it became clear that this horizontal parallelism is not only recognizable in an inter-attribute variant, but also in an intra-attribute variant. For the following claim can be made as well: an idea and its parallel mode (or object) under the same attribute (i.e. the i d e a i d e a e ) both are finite and durational expressions (b-ii) in their own attribute of the very same eternal formal being (b-i). And hence it became clear that Spinoza’s transitive parallelism manifests itself in three conceptually distinct ways: - as vertical parallelism, that is: as the identity of the infinite and eternal formal and the finite and durational objective being of things 393 - as horizontal inter-attribute parallelism, that is: as the identity of finite and durational ideas and their finite and durational objects in other attributes as horizontal intra-attribute parallelism, that is: as the identity of finite and durational ideas and their finite and durational objects in the same attribute This latter variant of intra-attribute parallelism is based on the bottom-up perspective that was discerned in Spinoza’s philosophy. The thing to note in this respect is that we turned to an investigation of Spinoza’s parallelism claim because we were interested in the precise relation between the formal (b-i) and the objective (b-ii) being of things. Now, a scrutiny of this relation has not only given us insight in the way Spinoza’s parallelism thesis must be understood, but has also taught us more about the relation between the formal (b-i) and the objective (b-ii) being of things. In this respect a claim in EIIp7s can hardly be overestimated. In this important scholium, Spinoza asserts that (b-ii) serves as the proximate cause for (b-i). In EIIp7s – in which we can also find the most explicit formulation of Spinoza’s horizontal inter-attribute parallelism – we encounter the remarkable claim that ‘the formal being of the idea of the circle can be perceived only through another mode of thinking, as its proximate cause’. And this in turn makes it clear that a bottomup perspective, that is: a perspective from which the objective being of things serves as the ground floor, must be understood to form an integral part of Spinoza’s metaphysics. That the surprising assertion in EIIp7s cannot be understood to be ‘a slip of the pen’ becomes clear once it is acknowledged that the bottom-up perspective is recognizable in various other passages in the Ethics also, including the very scholium in which the most evident manifestation of Spinoza’s vertical and horizontal intra-attribute parallelism can be found: EIIp21s. The claim that ‘as soon as someone knows something, he thereby knows that he knows it, and at the same time knows that he knows that he knows it, and so on, to infinity’ is one of the most evident claims in the Ethics in which a thing that is grasped objectively is portrayed to serve as the ground floor for the idea of that idea (which by EIIp21s is nothing but the form of that idea), which in turn serves as the basis for the idea of the idea of that idea (which is nothing but the form of the idea of the idea), and so on, to infinity. Yet another way of saying this is that the perspective that came to light in the previous chapters – from which the whole is in a certain sense prior to the parts – 394 must be understood to be combined with a perspective from which the parts are conceptually prior to the whole they constitute. That is to say: the top-down perspective treated the previous chapters is accompanied by a bottom-up perspective. Recognition of this bottom-up perspective in the Ethics in turn enables us to solve a problem that was brought up in the concluding section of the previous chapter. Recall that in section 3.8 we have stated that the fact that we are able to attain knowledge of God’s essence (i.e. the eternal and infinite power of acting that must be positioned at Natura naturans) – by way of our intellect (i.e. an expression of this power which must be positioned at Natura naturata), implies that God’s self-knowledge insofar as God is expressed in a human mind (i.e. in the objective being of a human body) must be understood to be directed bottom-up. In this chapter we have seen that this way of understanding the causal and conceptual flow can be validated. Apart from the reasoning from cause to effect (i.e. from (a) to (b)), Spinoza also discerns a conceptual direction from effect to cause (i.e. from (b) to (a)). This cognitive access of (God, insofar as he is expressed in) a human mind to the essence of the divine res can be rendered thus: Natura naturans (a) God qua God -------------------------------------------------(b-i) The formal being of singular things Natura naturata - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - - (b-ii) The objective being of singular things (c) God (table 10) This table makes it clear that Spinoza can be called ‘‘the last of the mediaevals’ – namely insofar as he propagates a top-down perspective – whilst at the same time forwarding an early modern conception – namely insofar as the identification of God and nature is claimed to offer the human mind bottom-up cognitive access to God’s essence by way of a study of the whole of nature. In this way, Spinoza’s ‘righteous atheism’ can indeed be understood to be ‘God-intoxicated’. 4.4.1 Pars melior nostri In the previous chapters we have made considerable progress in determining how pars melior nostri must be understood in the context of Spinoza’s philosophy. So far 395 we were able to make the following claims with respect to the intellect (in the way we commonly understand it): - - - - - The intellect is a mode The intellect can be conceived to be a part of the infinite mode of thought The intellect is by nature either posterior to or simultaneous with the things understood, which in turn implies that the intellect is characterized by a conceptual duality The intellect is characterized by a conceptual distinction in the following way: our intellect grasps things either insofar as it conceives them to exist as extrinsically caused finite modes (i.e. in their objective being under duration, representing their durational objects), or insofar it conceives them as intrinsically caused infinite modes (i.e. considered in themselves, in their eternal formal being). This distinction entails yet another distinction, which accounts for a certain trichotomy: the distinction between the durational object of an idea, the objective being of this object (i.e. the idea of the object), and the formal being of this idea. The things that function in this structure must in turn be understood to have an ubiquitous counterpart that must be located absolutely outside the intellect: the formal essences of things. The intellect is a coalescent feature of God (c) In the present chapter we have focused some more on the precise relation between the two aspects that must be understood to be characteristic for the ideas that constitute the intellect (whether finite or infinite): the formal and the objective being of things. In this respect it has become clear that Spinoza’s transitive parallelism can be understood to fall within the scope of the constructive function of the intellect: Spinoza’s three conceptual variants of this parallelism can all be understood to be grounded in the fact that we conceive things as actual in two ways: in their formal eternal being and in their objective durational being (this latter being in turn falling apart in the representing (durational) objective being and the represented (durational) object). Furthermore the following has become clear: 396 - The eternal and infinite formal being of things can be conceived in two ways: top-down (i.e. proceeding from God’s essence (a)) and bottom-up (i.e. inferring it on the basis the objective being of things) Whereas the previous chapters were (mainly) concerned with the top-down perspective that surfaces most explicitly in Spinoza’s Principle of Plenitude (EIp16), in the present chapter it was claimed that God’s self-knowledge cannot only be understood to be (i) absolutely outside the intellect (i.e. proceeding from (a) to (a)), and (ii) proceeding from God’s essence to the infinitely many things that follow from this essence (i.e. proceeding from (a) to (b)), but also from the (infinite) intellect to God’s essence (i.e. proceeding from (b) to (a)). This latter perspective was rendered schematically in the following way: (I) God, insofar as he is expressed in a human mind, conceives (say) a circle in two ways. (II) God, insofar as he is expressed in a human mind, conceives a circle in its objective being (i.e. the idea of the circle) and in its formal being (i.e. the formal being of the idea of the circle). (III) This formal being of the idea of a circle, which is conceived by God insofar as he is expressed in a human mind, is a part-with-a-vista of the absolutely infinite intellect. (IV) This formal being of the idea of a circle, which is conceived by God insofar as he is expressed in a human mind, must in turn be understood to be the counterpart at Natura naturata of the formal essence of that circle which is contained ubiquitously in God as a res cogitans at Natura naturans (V) The formal being of the idea of a circle, which is conceived by God insofar as he is expressed in a human mind, thus involves an eternal and infinite essence of God And as God qua God (a) must be understood to be an absolute identity, this implies that: (IV′) This formal being of the idea of a circle, which is conceived by God insofar as he is expressed in a human mind, must in turn be understood to be the 397 counterpart at Natura naturata of the formal essence of that circle which is contained ubiquitously in God s u i g e n e r i s at Natura naturans (V′) The formal being of the idea of a circle, which is conceived by God insofar as he is expressed in a human mind, thus involves t h e eternal and infinite essence of God In the next chapter we will argue for the claim that the bifurcation in topdown and bottom-up perspective marks the distinction between the two types of adequate knowledge that Spinoza discerns: ratio and scientia intuitive. Moreover, we will treat an important aspect of the intellect that was not addressed yet: the way in which the human mind is able to gather knowledge of external things in nature by way of horizontal representation. In Chapter 5 we will see how the top-down and bottom-up perspectives must be understood to be related to the specific phenomena that we would commonly associate with human mentality. 398