Genre, Text
and Language
Mélanges Anne Freadman
Sous la direction de Véronique Duché,
Tess Do et Andrea Rizzi
PARIS
CLASSIQUES GARNIER
2015
Véronique Duché est professeur de langue et littérature françaises à l’université de
Melbourne. Spécialiste du roman à la Renaissance, elle s’intéresse tout particulièrement
à l’histoire de la traduction. Elle a publié Si du mont Pyrenée / N’eussent passé le haut
fait…, les romans sentimentaux traduits de l’espagnol en France au XVIe siècle (Paris, 2008).
Tess Do est maître de conférence en études françaises à l’université de Melbourne.
Spécialiste de littérature francophone et postcoloniale, elle s’intéresse aux rapports
entre exil et identité, guerre et mémoire, culture et alimentation dans les œuvres
des écrivains français d’origine vietnamienne. Elle a participé à l’ouvrage Exile
Cultures, Misplaced Identities (Leyde, 2008), dirigé par P. Allatson et J. McCormack.
Andrea Rizzi est maître de conférence en études italiennes à l’université de Melbourne.
Spécialiste d’histoire de la traduction, il a obtenu de l’agence de la recherche
australienne (ARC) la bourse de Future Fellowship. Il a publié « Living Well in
Renaissance Italy : The Virtues of Humanism and the Irony of Leon Battista Alberti »,
dans le no 119 de l’American Historical Review.
© 2015. Classiques Garnier, Paris.
Reproduction et traduction, même partielles, interdites.
Tous droits réservés pour tous les pays.
ISBN 978-2-8124-3794-6 (livre broché)
ISBN 978-2-8124-3795-3 (livre relié)
ISSN 2103-5636
CAN MATHEMATICS THINK GENRE?
Alain Badiou and Forcing
The mathematician and the logician
meet upon a common highway. But they
face in contrary directions
C.S. Peirce
GENRES OF BEING?
In her groundbreaking book on the American pragmatist C.S. Peirce,
The Machinery of Talk, Anne Freadman notes that: ‘Genre is a rhetorical
topic, and one in poetics; we take it for granted that it is a question
legitimately asked of film or literature, of sculpture and of television,
of painting and of journalism.’1 Is genre, however, a ‘question,’ let
alone a ‘concept,’ that can be applied to mathematics? Is mathematics a
genre? Are there genres in mathematics? Must the concept of genre be
transformed in its application to mathematics; or does genre encounter its limits with respect to mathematics? To advert once again to
Freadman’s thesis, part of the problem here is perhaps that ‘the major
differend besetting scholarship at present is what came to be known as
the “two cultures,”’2 and hence the ongoing inability of researchers to
find any adequate way of negotiating the “science”/“humanities” divide
without, it seems, privileging one side over the other, if not entirely
misrecognising the true stakes of the dissensus. Is it then possible — as
Alain Badiou has recently attempted—to rethink what “genre” is from
the point of mathematics itself? This essay takes up the above questions by
1
2
Freadman 2004, xxxvi
Freadman 2004, xxxi
204
JUSTIN CLÉMENS
way of an exegesis of Badiou’s metaphysical account in Being and Event
of Paul Cohen’s set-theoretical practice of ‘forcing.’
Surely an immediate objection will arise. How can “the genre” of
metaphysics take “the genre” of mathematics to provide the only good
account (read: “consistent concept”) of genre? Is this not the founding
gesture of metaphysics par excellence? In Freadman’s terms:
I take metaphysics to be a genre. This genre can be characterized in several
ways: it is the genre that denies its own generic specificity; it is the genre that
seeks its own foundations; it is the genre that stands outside experience in
order to account for the conditions of possibility of all knowledge, knowledge
of things, as well as knowledge of knowledge; it is the exercise of reason,
directed to a transcendental account of reason; it is the knowledge of the
essentially human, and so on1.
Significantly, however, Badiou’s own metaphysics conforms to none of
these restrictions, and does so by skewing the received acceptations
concerning all the key terms. Firstly, if metaphysics is a genre, it is a genre
that puts into question the very concept of genre itself. Second, metaphysics doesn’t therefore simply deny its generic specificity, but exposes,
analyses and affirms its genericity as a problem. Third, Badiou maintains
that the exception to genre of the genre of metaphysics is due to certain
anti-foundational requirements: indeed, metaphysics is dependent upon
its extra-philosophical conditions, that is, upon other genres. It is with
respect to one of these conditions in particular—that of science—that
Badiou seeks to rethink and reformulate what a genre is, in order to
rethink philosophy itself as not generic but trans-generic. Even at a glance,
the ‘doing ‘of philosophy cannot simply be said to be generic according to
most received understandings of the term. As Badiou succinctly puts it
in the ‘Author’s Preface’ to Theoretical Writings: ‘the philosophical corpus
seems to encompass every conceivable style of presentation.’2 Between
‘Socrates, he who does not write’ and the endlessly-rewritten treatises of
someone like Schopenhauer, philosophers are liable to produce dialogues,
seminars, playlets, novels, poems—and so on and on.
As we shall see, then, Badiou will hold mathematics generic, but
philosophy trans-generic. Mathematics will be that genre that enables
1
2
Freadman 2004, 6. See also such works as Frow 2006 and Ferrell 2002 which examine
this genre of claim in detail.
Badiou 2004, xiii
CAN MATHEMATICS THINK GENRE?
205
a true knowledge of genre. Yet Badiou does not for all this think that
genres are themselves mathematical, nor that they need to know what
they are doing to be genres. On the contrary. But only mathematics is
able to rigorously thematise and identify the points at which rationality
is divided between consistency and inconsistency, and it does so as an
integral part of its practice. It’s not that maths is the only acceptable
form of rationality or of thought—on the contrary, Badiou is obsessed
with demonstrating that love, politics and art are also rigorous forms
of thinking—but that, without mathematics, one will not even know at
which point one has fallen into an inconsistency which freights irrational
forces, nor the real points where the real leaps of reason and unreason
must be taken. To put this another way, mathematics as system is not
truth, but it is the only acceptable paradigm of “true knowledge” for
metaphysics (so to speak). It is to a discussion of Badiou’s account of
mathematics that we therefore now turn.
MATHEMATICS = ONTOLOGY
or, Set-Theory as the Constrained Exposition of Being;
or, Letter, Formalization, Affirmation
In Being and Event, his magnum opus, Badiou makes a strong claim
that is clear but which has proven extraordinarily controversial. It is that
mathematics = ontology1. This claim is not, as it has very often been
misread, a “Pythagorean” claim, which would treat existence itself as
integrally mathematical, governed by proportion and harmony, reason
and necessity2. On the contrary, as Badiou explains:
1
2
The secondary material to date has evidently been much concerned with this claim, albeit
with ambiguous or unsatisfactory results. There is certainly understandable resistance to
it, but it is at least necessary to get it right before responding. For helpful introductory
English-language accounts, see Barker 2002; Clemens and Feltham 2003; Feltham 2008;
Hallward 2003; Norris 2009; Pluth 2010. For various reasons—not least the narcissism
of proximity—the French reception to Badiou has generally been less exegetical and more
polemical. See, inter alia, Kacem 2011 and Laruelle 2011, but also Tarby 2005, and the
collection Ramond 2002.
On this point, see the polemic between Nirenberg and Nirenberg 2011; Badiou 2011;
Bartlett and Clemens 2012; and Nirenberg and Nirenberg 2012.
206
JUSTIN CLÉMENS
The thesis that I support does not in any way declare that being is mathematical, which is to say composed of mathematical objectivities. It is not
a thesis about the world but about discourse. It affirms that mathematics,
throughout the entirety of its historical becoming, pronounces what is
expressible of being qua being1.
It is rather to the extent that “being” can be properly thought at all,
it must be thought mathematically. Why? What does this mean? First,
mathematical thought must be extracted from linguistics and from
all and any theory of natural signs, whether these are supposedly truly
“natural” (à la ‘bio-signs’) or ‘natural languages.’ This is an unpopular
position to take in a philosophical universe still dominated by rival
versions of the linguistic turn. As Badiou himself notes of what he sees
as the three major philosophical orientations active today—the hermeneutic, analytic and postmodern—they, despite the misunderstandings,
polemics, and real differences, nonetheless all render “language” as ‘the
great historical transcendental of our times.’2 Whether we think of Peirce,
Nietzsche, Wittgenstein or Heidegger, the continentals or the analytics,
the literary or scientifically-minded, the problematic of language qua
logic of sense remains primary. The effect of this for Badiou is double:
philosophy in the grand style is declared to be essentially over, and
truth is subordinated to meaning. Badiou will maintain, quite to the
contrary, that contemporary philosophy qua metaphysics must begin as
a kind of rupture with the dominance of language. Yet it cannot do this
in a naïve manner: there is no sense to simply reasserting the privilege
of the real against the language that discloses it. Hence Badiou will
agree with his enemies that ‘there are only bodies and languages’—but he
adds ‘except that there are truths.’3 This assertion evidently necessitates a
reconstruction of the notion of “truth” on Badiou’s part, and, as we shall
see, he does this by returning to mathematics as giving a new, rigorous,
consistent formal account of how to think genre itself.
The power of exposing the exception of truths as generic is exactly
the determining role that Badiou wishes to assign to mathematics and
logic. But several distinctions then need to be made and justified. The
relevant divisions here include: philosophy and its conditions; mathematics
1
2
3
Badiou 2005, 8
Badiou 2003, 46
Badiou 2009, 4. Italics Badiou’s.
CAN MATHEMATICS THINK GENRE?
207
and language; being and formalization; consistency and inconsistency;
knowledge and truth. These divisions are not simple oppositions; they
are not directly aligned with each other; they do not totalise the field.
What they do do, as we shall see, is enable a reconstruction of the ways
in which metaphysics essentially relies on different genres to think at
all, as it separates thinking from the dominance of any one genre in
particular. Above all, the “exposure” of which I just spoke is not in the
slightest reductionist, for reasons that I will try to elaborate. In order to
do this, however, Badiou must essay to separate mathematics and logic
from the dominance of language. These practices can hence no longer
be considered subsets of language in general or to be understood on
the model of language, even if they are de facto always and everywhere
implicated with one or another natural language. As he responds to a
question on precisely this point in an interview with Lauren Sedofsky:
LS: Here’s the inevitable question: Isn’t logic a language?
AB: My thesis is that it’s not reducible to a language. From the point of view
of logic, you always have to make linguistic suppositions; there’s a linguistic
manipulation. What I try to demonstrate philosophically, though, is that the
essence of logic is not linguistic, no more so than that of mathematics or a
scientific discipline. Like any discipline of thought, logic must finally settle
in a language, but its essence concerns what the general form of a world is,
which is the question I pose1.
Difficult as it may be to accept the classical terms in which Badiou phrases
his position here—“essence”, “form”, “discipline”—we cannot take this
terms as if they were terms we already recognise and understand. On
the contrary, part of Badiou’s import is that he rigorously re-establishes
their significance so as to evade all existing critiques. This doesn’t of
course mean that they cannot be criticised in their turn—only that
existing criticisms will not be up to the task.
For Badiou, there are a number of levels at which pure mathematics and pure logic function. Let us begin at the “lowest” level, that
of the material sign itself. For if mathematics-logic are, like all other
discourses, necessarily imbricated with materiality, one of their peculiarities is that they are, strictly speaking, indifferent to their materials.
This feature, this power of indifference, derives from a triple knot, of
1
Badiou and Sedofsky 2006, 246-53
208
JUSTIN CLÉMENS
material literalisation, epistemic formalization, and existential assertion. In
what follows, I will restrict myself to outlining what I believe to be
Badiou’s arguments, without always being able to argue fully for their
veracity; nonetheless, I will also attempt to give some indications of how
and why he supports these arguments, as well as how they depart from
several currently still-dominant interpretations of mathematical practice.
The triple of which I speak is not all that is important in Badiou’s work
on mathematics—far from it—but for the present context it provides
the necessary background features to the rethinking of the problem of
genre that is at stake here.
Regarding the interpretation of the status of the materiality of
letters, Badiou has been strongly influenced by the work of the French
psychoanalyst Jacques Lacan and his school, whose propositions have
been perhaps most thoroughly developed and justified by the linguist
Jean-Claude Milner1. However, Badiou also contests the general Lacanian
approach at certain points2. For Badiou, a letter is not a signifier or a
sign; it has in itself neither sense nor reference; it marks nothing in
particular3. It is simply and primarily a mark of any kind, and any sort
of mark will do. A letter is at once eminently material, yet, in being so,
requires the necessity of a difference between itself and its ground. If
this difference is undeniably a form of suture, it is also the case that the
logical or mathematical mark precisely deploys itself as independent of
all and any empirical grounds4. Why? Because a logical or mathematical
mark can in principle take any form whatsoever without loss of function; it can
1
2
3
4
For the key texts of J.-C. Milner, see Milner 1995a and 1995b. Today, the influence of
the Lacanians upon Badiou has literally blossomed into controversy: see Badiou, Milner
and Petit 2012.
Although the scholarship on this point remains minimal to date, see Bartlett et al.
2013. See also Bartlett and Clemens 2012, as well as the entry on “Lacan” in Bartlett
and Clemens 2010; Ronen 2010; Hoens and Pluth 2004; Grigg 2005; Chiesa 2006. For
the most part, card-carrying Lacanians have responded critically to Badiou’s work, e.g.,
MacCannell 2009. The same goes, a fortiori, for Deleuzians: in addition to the essays in
the aforementioned Badiou and Philosophy, the summa of such attempts would have to
be Roffe 2011.
On this point, see Clemens 2003; for a radical post-Badiouan take on the problematic of
the letter, see Meillassoux 2012. For a different account of the role of formalization, see
Livingston 2011.
If there are of course many different types of mathematical signs (e.g., variables, connectors,
quantifiers, relations, punctuations, etc.), it is not necessary to go into the arcane complexities
of their differentiation here: all that is necessary is to show that such “signs” share a
CAN MATHEMATICS THINK GENRE?
209
take on any function without predetermining any form. This is one integral
aspect of the Lacanian insistence on the priority of the matheme: letters
that are integrally transmissible beyond any particular meaning, and
indeed beyond any particular language, precisely to the extent that they
are expressly contingent in the form of their materialization. This precisely
distinguishes them from all other kinds of expression, which otherwise
continue to partake of ‘the machinery of talk,’ in Peirce’s expression. The
inscriptions of mathematics have nothing whatsoever to do with such
machinery, insofar as their patent formal contingency is explicitly and
integrally directed against any substance, meaning or reference inhering
in their empirical apparition. Letters in this sense, and this sense alone,
are “transmaterial” entities.
One can denominate a variable a or a variable x: the forms of inscription remain indifferent to this formalization. Whether one uses a, b and
c or x, y, and z or, indeed, É, ®, or Þ (for material implication)—again,
the indifference of the mark to what it “is” or “designates”—the manipulations of these letters must sustain and exemplify their own consistent
deployment throughout a demonstration. Formalization, as opposed to
form, requires the indifference of all or any particular set of letters to
what they can be deployed to demonstrate. Yet it is precisely for this
reason that the principles of their deployment must be explicitly and essentially
manifested in and by their deployment itself. Moreover, this must be done
immanently to the demonstration: at every point of a mathematical
demonstration the linkages between steps of a proof and the principles
of such linkages must be practically shown as inseparable. Indeed, formalization can be considered the immanent rendering-consistent of the
ramshackle indifference of its own contingent materials. In mathematical
and logical systems, this rendering-consistent — at least in classical and
intuitionist logics — is equivalent to the impossibility of producing any
contradiction within that system. So consistency is what mathematics
and logic inseparably do and what they think in and by this doing. To
put this yet another way, the difference between appearing and doing
or between showing and proving is itself indifferent in mathematical
practice — and only in this practice. This is equivalent to what Brian
Rotman, from an essentially Peircean perspective, derisively refers to
peculiar feature and are the only signs that do so: their material contingency qua patent
indifference to their own materiality.
210
JUSTIN CLÉMENS
in mathematical formalization as being ‘completely without indexical
expressions.’1 Mathematical indifference to empirical criteria is ensured precisely through the effective suppression of any markers of the
taking-place of the ‘utterance,’ which is therefore not an utterance in any
existing semiotic sense.
If, at the turn of the twentieth century, Gottlob Frege could still
maintain that the three required properties for any mathematical
theory were consistency, completeness and decidability, it is now the
case that at least the latter two have been demonstrated to be, strictly
speaking, external to mathematics or, rather, that mathematics must
mathematically limit the extension of its own claims with respect
to them: Gödel’s incompleteness theorems show that there is any
sufficiently powerful axiomatized system can only be consistent if
incomplete, and that any such system will produce at least one undecidable proposition. Twentieth-century developments have therefore
pared-away the various inessential mathematical elements that inhered
in prior mathematics, to expose the problem of consistency itself as the
singular domain of mathematics and mathematical logics. I say ‘the
problem of consistency,’ since consistency is therefore identified and
isolated as such, as the fundamental concern of all mathematical/
logical thinking, yet without its own status being thereby able to
be resolved in general by such thinking. Otherwise put, this is one
reason why mathematics is the paradigm of knowledge for Badiou:
not because it knows more or better than anything else, but because
it alone apodictically knows the points that it doesn’t know in order to give
a new knowledge of what it does.
Hence, as Badiou puts it in Briefings on Existence: ‘Mathematics….
forges a fiction of intelligible consistency.’2 I underline Badiou’s careful
use of the term “fiction” here, not because it is thereby intended to link
or equate the fictions of mathematics with the fictions, say, of literary
1
2
Rotman 1993, 7. Rotman’s very interesting book nonetheless suffers from a number of
serious problems, evident in the current context. Above all, his understanding of what
constitutes “Platonism” is quite naïve, and certainly unable to account for Badiou’s peculiar
interpretation. Another problem is that, despite Rotman’s emphasis on the materiality of
mathematical signification, he doesn’t quite separate—as the French thinkers in Lacan’s
wake have—the “signifier” and the ‘letter,’ such a distinction enabling a more detailed,
materialist and persuasive account of the issues.
Badiou 2006, 48
CAN MATHEMATICS THINK GENRE?
211
writing, but quite the reverse. It is rather to qualify the particular discursive powers and problems of mathematics: its operations establish
and model the pure limits of reason, without thereby claiming they
are the final take on the question. After all, subsequent developments
in mathematics might pinpoint hitherto-inseparated differences within the field (hence the “fictionality” of maths insofar as it is always in
principle susceptible to radical new formalizations). In fact, the exposure
of pure consistency as the essential problem of mathematical system
is confirmed by the recent development of paraconsistent logics which
contravene the principle of non-contradiction, and for which consistency
no longer simply means the impossibility of deriving a contradiction
within the system: for such logics, “true contradictions” are sometimes
possible. What this shows is that contemporary mathematics and logic
negatively limn inconsistency as such, exposing with the most rigorous clarity and distinctness the contested points on the borders between pure
consistency and the inconsistent. This “consistency” is outlined without
recourse to any unifying figure of unity or totality as such, since it is a
trans-arithmetical program. It rigorously theorizes its own limits, and
is thus also a radical program of self-restraint. Yet the consequences of
the exposure of the problem of in-consistency itself as restrictively yet
essentially mathematical does not render mathematics simply a formalism, that is, a rule-governed game with letters for which there is no
particular meaning or reference.
Mathematics as pure formalization is therefore not a metaphor. It is
not a metaphor, because it is a literalisation of the consistent without
possible figure: the little letters and lines of mathematical formalisation
have no inherent apparition-value. Rather, we find there a formal inscription of the limits of reason, of pure reason at and as its limits. Given
then that form ≠ formalism ≠ formalization for Badiou, the problematic
of mathematical formalization necessarily requires a rethinking of the
terms and conditions of reference1. If in-consistency becomes the problem
for mathematical practice, then a new double question emerges as a
result: i) what is the relation between logic and mathematics? ii) what
1
Note that, “while mathematical and logical formalization is a paradigm for formalization,
formalization is not identical with this,” Badiou, Fraser, and Tho, 2007, 89. As we shall
see, different kinds of formalization— generic!—can be accomplished in the domains of
love, politics and art as well.
212
JUSTIN CLÉMENS
is the relation between mathematics and “being” and mathematics and
“the world”?
The classical problems of metaphysics, of philosophical ontology, can
therefore be rephrased as: how can letters discern and inscribe the status
of the relation between letters themselves and their ground? This is
where mathematical axiomatics become crucial: it is at once the point at
which mathematics can be separated from logic, and the point at which
mathematics can return to the world. If both mathematics and logic
share an indifference to the contingent form of their materiality, and
both deploy this indifference in the service of a pure becoming-consistent
that is also their raison d’être (the stringent elaboration or practice of
laws of thought as the rendering of materiality to the absolute limits
of consistency), unlike logic—which ultimately deals with regulating
the consistency of thinking, delimiting, defining and describing what
can and cannot count as such—mathematical axioms also make fundamental declarations about what is and is not1. There is an ‘originary
belonging of mathematical deductive fidelity to ontological concerns.’2
Mathematics enacts consistency in inscribing “some” extra-mathematical
reference at its heart, albeit inscribing it as foreclosed; logic formalizes
the laws of possible consistencies, without necessarily making any actual
referential claims. Mathematics inscribes rational actuality, logic rational
virtuality. Paradoxically, this means that mathematics has something
1
2
This is perhaps the central and most radical position elaborated in the opening sections
of Being and Event. For a different, but in my opinion, quite wrong-headed account of
the role of mathematics and logic for Badiou, see Plotnitsky 2012, 351-68. Although
there is obviously not the space to respond to Plotnitsky adequately here, the points of
his confusion hinge on his complete failure to understand the particular role Badiou
assigns to axiomatization in mathematics (as opposed to the constructive establishment
of logical spaces), to the difference he sees regarding classical compared to post-classical
logics in the assignation of existence, to the non-mathematical status of the event (which
Plotnitsky doesn’t seem to get at all), and to Plotnitsky’s failure to separate the concept
of the generic provided by mathematics from Badiou’s generically political claims. Even
Plotnitsky’s claim that topos theory ‘inscribes the plurality of possible ontologies’ as if it
were a rebuke to Badiou at once repeats Badiou’s own position without understanding
its import. Other, more rigorous critical accounts of Badiou’s mathematics can be found
in Brassier 2007; Mount 2005; Fraser 2006. It is, however, symptomatic that this latter
crew, Livingstone op. cit. included, are essentially launching their critiques on the basis
of their own speculative improvisations upon an unconfessed intuitionist decision of
their own. Hence their positions ultimately remain finitist, realist, and analytic, in the
pejorative senses of these terms—and hence, in Badiou’s account, pre-Cantorian.
Badiou 2005, 250
CAN MATHEMATICS THINK GENRE?
213
extra-logical about it: the practice of inventive mathematics can embody
forms of reason that go beyond the contemporaneous closure of reason
acceptable to logic.
Mathematical axioms do this for Badiou—quite to the contrary
of the usual claims and presuppositions about their status—not
by defining basic terms, but by refusing to define what they affirm. If
received interpretations about the status of axioms usually hold the
axioms themselves to constitute “indubitable” ‘clear,’ “distinct” and/
or ‘self-evident’ “truths” — a position that could be (relatively) plausibly assigned to mathematicians and logicians from Euclid through
Descartes to Frege — there is also a lineage that sees the axioms
as fundamentally game-like presuppositions, without necessitating
any absolute grounding. For example, the independence of Euclid’s
parallel postulate became clear in the 19th century, when radically
new-yet-consistent forms of geometry were developed by tampering
with this axiom: a development which naturally founded another
intense spurt of interrogations of the foundations of mathematics.
Hence there developed plausible pragmatic interpretations of the status
of axioms, whether as what’s good in the way of belief, as evidence
of unplumbable ‘ontological relativity,’ or under other descriptions.
None of this conforms to Badiou’s position. Axioms rather constitute
decisions about what exists, but without having any grounding in the
incontrovertible. On the contrary, they declare the basic constituents
of existence, but without providing definitions of what they declare
to be the case; they prescribe connections, but without defining what
it is they are working with. As such, they comprise what Badiou
calls in Platonizing vein ‘the grand Ideas of the multiple.’1 In doing
so, axioms pinpoint the ways in which they are themselves decisions
which cannot ever be fully rationalised. A new account of the dialectic
between freedom and necessity is broached.
If mathematics has undergone many fundamental transformations,
the development of set-theory in the late nineteenth century is of
crucial significance in Badiou’s account, precisely because in it the
practice of axiomatization is from the first an explicit problem for
that work of axiomization itself. On the basis of his interpretation
1
Ibid., 60
214
JUSTIN CLÉMENS
of set-theory, Badiou at once wants to account for the fact that there
are rationally many different, even incommensurable systems able to
be constructed by mathematic reason — in fact, there are several
different rival axiomatizations of set-theory itself — but what all the
different systems share is an agreement as to which points are the ones
one can rationally differ in regards to. Axioms designate the points at
which extra-rational decisions about rationality have had to be made,
and every axiom is thus necessarily polemical, in an extra-rhetorical
(i.e., extra-linguistic) sense. Rather than an axiom simply being or
stating an incontrovertible principle of reason, then, it is a statement
which, in its very declarativeness and prescriptiveness, shows that it
is rationally incontrovertible that a decision about what will have to count
as rational has had to be made at and about a particular point. This is
one reason why Badiou’s thought is at once righteously unbending
and authentically pluralist: it demonstrates that there is a rational
necessity for incommensurable decisions about how reason must proceed. There must be axioms for systematic rational knowledge to be
able to practice self-knowing consistency as such; but those axioms
are themselves the outcomes of (necessarily) extra-rational decisions;
as such, their very elaboration affects something new at the limits
of reason itself.
But this is only one, very general consequence of Badiou’s stunning
interpretation of set theory1. There are very many aspects of interest,
which I can only list here, but which provide the necessary terms for
the account of genre that follows. Perhaps the most important of these
is the thinking of the infinite, and the concomitant development of
mathematics’ self-grasping of its own systematic destiny. Indeed, Georg
Cantor, the inventor of set-theory, indexes the moment for Badiou
at which mathematical thought shifts from a restricted to a general
economy. Why? Because for the first time, a rigorous mathematical
concept was given of the infinite, as opposed to it simply functioning
as the unthinkable exception to the finite, as totality, or as unique.
Cantor demonstrated that “infinity” was not only not an ultimate limit
of mathematical thinking, but that there were infinite infinities, that
is, sets that could not be put into one-to-one correspondence with each
1
In addition to the works already cited, see the brilliant little volume Badiou 2008.
CAN MATHEMATICS THINK GENRE?
215
other (e.g., the infinity of natural numbers is demonstrably smaller than
the continuum of all the numbers between 0 and 1).
In doing this, Cantor inspired enormous resistance among even the
greatest mathematicians, and very quickly certain paradoxes started
to show up in his and related programs. Perhaps the most famous of
these is Russell’s paradox, which showed that the concept of a set of all
sets—an ultimate or total set which contains all others—is inconsistent.
(Notoriously, this set belongs to itself if it doesn’t and doesn’t if it does)1.
As Badiou notes, the two major effects of these paradoxes was: i) ‘to
abandon all hope of explicitly defining the notion of set’; ii) “to prohibit
paradoxical multiples.”2 This led to the work of axiomatization over
the next 40 or so years, which produced various rival systems. Badiou’s
own decision is to run with the standard Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) system
of nine axioms, which, he declares “concentrate the greatest effort of
thought ever accomplished to this day by humanity.”3
To give one reviewer’s useful general summary:
ZF is a mainstream focus of modern set theory and principally used to study
varieties of the mathematical infinite. Additionally, most “ordinary” mathematics (calculus, algebra, probability, number theory, geometry, etc.) can be
thought of as codified as sets, sets of sets, and so on. In this way, ZF (defined
formally in standard predicate logic) may be thought of as a foundation for
all types of mathematical representation. Intuitively, ZF starts with nothing,
the empty set, Ø. From that, you can form a new set consisting of all of the
subsets of Ø; since the only subset of Ø is Ø itself, this new set of subsets is
just {Ø}. Then you can take that set’s subsets (i.e. {Ø, {Ø}}), and so inductively generate partial universes of sets Vn, each mini-universe Vn defined as all
subsets of Vn-1. That only leads to finite sets, so a further axiom is needed to
guarantee the existence of infinite sets. With that, additional ZF axioms for
collecting and redefining sets allow construction of transfinite ordinal numbers
α which continue the natural, or counting, numbers into the infinite, and
hence the process of set formation in further collections Vα4.
Badiou gives an extraordinary interpretation of each of ZF’s axioms
and their philosophical import: picking up on what I have said above,
1
2
3
4
See Badiou’s various discussions of this, e.g., in Badiou 2009, 109-11, 153-5.
Badiou 2005, 43
Ibid., 499
Kadvany 2013. The review, unfortunately, concludes in error by imputing several theses
to Badiou that he does not hold, including the incomprehensible claim that Badiou thinks
that there is a set-theoretical foundation for natural science.
216
JUSTIN CLÉMENS
and as I have shown more extensively elsewhere, he literally reads these
axioms literally1.
To give a single example, crucial to Badiou: among the nine axioms
of standard ZF set theory, ‘one alone, strictly speaking, is existential;
that is, its task is to directly inscribe an existence, and not to regulate
a construction which presupposes there already being a presented
multiple.’2 This axiom is usually called ‘the axiom of the empty-set,’ and
its canonical formulation is ‘there exists a set which has no members’:
to advert to the terms provided just above, this axiom decides that
something exists; it declares that this something is a set that is empty;
it prescribes that all (mathematical) existence be thought on the basis
of this vacuity.
Since we are dealing with pure mathematics here (i.e., “pure” in the
sense of the above-noted indifference to all empirical content), what sort
of referent can be given to such an axiom? This is one great metaphysical
moment within Badiou’s work: set theoretical mathematics thinks being
as void. Not only does this evade the problems of substance that have
always haunted ontology, but it gives a basis to mathematics that is quite
extraordinary. The empty set is the most rigorous possible formulation
of the place at which thought (in this case, mathematical thinking) is
sutured to being (in this case, the void). Or, to be even more precise,
the empty set for Badiou becomes “the proper name of being.” Axioms
are thus ultimately formalisations of pure reference. Not only are they pure
because non-empirical in a general sense, but because what they refer
to is without any possible definition, substance or meaning. Yet this is also
precisely what gives them their stringently rational character, their
“extimate” bond to a foreclosed interior.
There are three further points to make first about this triplet of
literalisation, formalization, and existentialisation. First, it’s crucial that,
for Badiou, these are not strictly mathematical, but meta-mathematical
theses. As such, they are metaphysical, external to mathematical practice proper. Yet they are entirely dependent upon such a practice. As
I’ve already flagged, Badiou’s metaphysics therefore does not conform
to the charges levelled by Freadman above. Precisely because metaphysics relies on mathematics for its ontology, metaphysics cannot be a
1
2
See Clemens 2005, 21-35.
Badiou 2005, 60
CAN MATHEMATICS THINK GENRE?
217
self-grounding genre. But there is more. Mathematics is not the only
practice upon which metaphysics is dependent for its own ‘grounds.’ For,
second, Badiou wants to claim that there are four (if only four!) kinds
of genre: science, art, politics and love. He explicitly nominates these
genres ‘truths,’ and therefore considers truths to be essentially generic.
If this is the case, then, philosophy cannot itself simply be generic: its
“genre” is to be trans-generic insofar as it relies upon all four fundamental genres simultaneously. Why is “generic” the appropriate name for
truth? Because something generic is precisely something that belongs as
such, but without any particularities to compromise the belonging; the
generic is something that exemplifies a kind of universal pure belonging.
But, then, third, what enables us to think genre as such? Nothing but
mathematics has the necessary rigour to provide a consistent formalization of the concept of genre. The paradoxical essence of the genre
of mathematics is truly knowing what it doesn’t know about the thing it
declares to be nothing—even or especially since that “thing” is literally
‘nothing.’ Yet things are more complicated still, for the mathematical
genre formalises how it necessarily exceeds its own knowledge in its
self-elaboration.
COHEN’S FORCING AS THE FORMALIZATION
OF THE THOUGHT OF THE BECOMING-GENERIC OF BEING
Having established mathematics as the “knowing genre” qua paradigm of knowledge-of-being—what Nick Heron has called, in a private
communication to me, Badiou’s ‘onto-mathesis’—we can now turn to
the problem of how Badiou holds set-theoretical mathematics thinks
genre. I mentioned above that the distinction between “knowledge”
and “truth” is crucial to Badiou, and it is precisely here that it has its
most fiendish impact. For if mathematics is the paradigm of knowing, it
also, as I have explained, knows by not knowing in a very specific sense.
Moreover, it can formalize the ways in which thought can proceed rigorously in and by its own not-knowing. But it must do so by foreclosing
inconsistency in its theory and practice. This opens onto the problem
218
JUSTIN CLÉMENS
for Badiou of the “generic” or, as he will also nominate it for reasons
to be discussed, the ‘indiscernible.’ To give a coherent formalization
of the generic, Badiou picks up the work of Paul Cohen on ‘forcing,’
which deals with, to begin as simply as possible, a process that, while
conforming absolutely to the strictures regarding consistency required
by mathematics, produces something new, something “impossible” in
the terms of the initial situation into which it intervenes. And while any
actual such process cannot be mathematically captured (by definition), it
turns out that there is indeed a way to think the in-principle compatibility
of the existence of such a process with mathematical knowledge.
If one imagines an infinite situation established by the most stringent mathematical procedures, it is possible to say that everything in
this situation is known, or knowable: nothing goes unaccounted for;
everything is necessary. Every element in a situation can be mixedand-matched with others, “represented” by classifying different kinds
of subsets of the basic situation. Badiou will even term this aspect of
knowledge “encyclopedic”; the knowledge of a situation “discerns” and
“classifies” everything that can appear within it. The problem of nomination and reference arises again with a vengeance. The generic, to be truly
generic, must therefore evade the language of the situation—otherwise
it will be named and localised in an incontrovertible frame. But even if
naming is evaded altogether (and it is very uncertain whether such an
eventuality is possible), then the subsequent “unnameable” could not,
strictly speaking, be said to exist, since existence is, as we have seen,
established axiomatically, at the most fundamental level. But what if
a name might be able to refer to something that has no name-being
in the situation as such, or nomination might be able to be separated
from predication and linked to a pure existence without identity? We
are clearly in the realm of impossibility and paradox.
Can this paradox be resolved? Abstractly speaking, one can immediately see that this can be done if one can find a way to separate and
re-stratify the intra-mathematical relationships between nomination,
predication and existence. For every particularity in mathematics must
be able to be named as such, i.e., can be given a predicate. To be generic,
then, predication must be evaded insofar as predication is equivalent to
particularization. But surely evading predication is precisely impossible
in the mathematical environment? In set theory, such an impossibility
CAN MATHEMATICS THINK GENRE?
219
would require that something be able to be designated without being
discernible; it would mean finding a way to identify an existence without
any certification of that existence; it would certainly mean contravening
the Leibnizian principle of the identity of indiscernibles. As Badiou
puts it, ‘it all comes down to this: can ontology produce the concept of
a generic multiple, which is to say an unnameable, un-constructible,
indiscernible multiple? The revolution introduced by Cohen in 1963
responds in the affirmative.’1
As one might expect, the details of Cohen’s forcing are of a stunning
complexity2. I will try to avoid as far as possible any recourse to technical
language here; the aim is merely to give an ordinary language translation that points to the key intellectual operations and consequences at
stake. Cohen forged his new techniques in his attempt to resolve some
fundamental questions that emerged very early in the set-theoretical
enterprise. If, as Cantor showed, there can be infinite infinities of different
“sizes”—which he denominated as ‘cardinality,’ to distinguish the pure
multiplicity of infinity from ‘ordinality,’ an ordered sequence—how are
these infinities to be ordered? Designating the sequence of infinities by
the Hebrew aleph, À, and their increasing order by subscripts, that is, À0,
À1, À2…, Cantor, having demonstrated that the cardinality of the real
numbers (the numbers on a real line) was “larger” than the cardinality
of the natural numbers (the infinity 1, 2, 3…), he wanted to propose an
ordering of these massive sets. As he had also shown that the “power
set” of a set is always “larger” than the initial set, Cantor’s so-called
“continuum hypothesis” posited that the cardinality of the power set of
the natural numbers was equal to the cardinality of the real numbers.
This would, in essence, give a nice, orderly reordering to the hallucinatory
consequences opened up by the demonstration that there were indeed
infinite infinities that were mathematically thinkable. Cantor, however,
could not prove his continuum hypothesis; Kurt Gödel showed that, at
least, it cannot be disproved given the presumption of the consistency
1
2
Ibid., 355
In his excellent presentation “A beginner’s guide to forcing,” T.Y. Chow proposes the concept
of “an open exposition problem”: given the difficulty of forcing even for mathematicians,
the problem of teaching what’s going on becomes paramount. Paper downloaded from
<http://arxiv.org/abs/0712.1320> 8 April 2013. Paul Cohen’s own report of his findings
is Cohen 1966; English readers of Badiou should, first and foremost, refer to the short
account in Hallward 2003.
220
JUSTIN CLÉMENS
of the axioms of set theory; Cohen’s demonstration, however, showed
that neither can the continuum hypothesis be proved from those axioms.
Cohen had in fact shown the independence of the continuum hypothesis.
But to do so, he had had to invent a new mathematical technique, the
aforementioned ‘forcing.’
The key operations of forcing require, first, the establishment of
what is known as a ‘quasi-complete situation’ or ‘ground-model’ that
is “countably infinite” (that is, it has the cardinality, the size, of the
infinity of natural numbers, À0). What Cohen calls a “generic extension”
will be a subset of this situation, i.e., it will be included in a situation.
Note that in set-theory, there is a distinction between elements, which
“belong” to sets (belonging being the fundamental relation of set theory),
and subsets, which are “included” in sets, insofar as every element that
belongs to the subset also belongs to the set in question (inclusion being
therefore a derivative relation).
This generic extension will necessarily be an unnameable subset in a
very particular sense. The elements of the generic extension (this special
subset of our initial set) are given a double aspect: first, they constitute
the material of this subset; second, they also provide information about
this subset. These elements are called the “conditions” of the generic
set. As Badiou so brilliantly summarizes: a ‘generic subset is identical
to the whole situation in the following sense: the elements of this subset—the components of a truth—have their being, or their belonging
to the situation, as their only assignable property.’1 The elements have
to be able to be grouped together in such a way that, even though every
particular condition will have to be able to be named in the language
of the existing situation, taken together, there will always be at least
one element in any grouping of conditions that prevents that grouping
from falling under a name already available in and for that situation.
In other words, any grouping of conditions (an ordered set of elements
of the generic subset) cannot permit the “next” element in the string
to be able to be predicted no matter how long or large that grouping
has become.
Badiou is blunt: ‘The striking paradox of our undertaking is that
we are going to try to name the very thing which is impossible to
1
Badiou 2009, 36, translation slightly modified.
CAN MATHEMATICS THINK GENRE?
221
discern. We are searching for a language for the unnameable. It will
have to name the latter without naming it, it will instruct its vague
existence without specifying anything whatsoever within it.’1 To do so,
requires enriching the language of the situation by reconstructing a
hierarchy of names already available within that situation, but whose
referent will no longer be directly tied to this or that element of the
situation. A linguistic paradox is thereby to be avoided—how does one
define the name “name” without circularity?—and set theory does so
by reference to the above-discussed ‘empty set.’ The technique involves
defining names as pairs, built upon a coupling of the empty set (the
minimal condition) and another mark (designating an indeterminate
condition). The definitional circle can thus be cut by reinscribing names
as indices of a hierarchy all built up on the basis of the void, the most
minimal and universal of conditions (it is “absolute”); this means that
every name can be constructed on the basis of an already-established
definition. As Bartlett puts it, this project depends ‘on establishing a
form of nomination which allowed Cohen to talk about the elements of
this non-constructible thus unknowable set, before knowing them. In
short, the referent for this name (a name including within it conditions
(terms) and statements that are part of the original set), which counts
out the elements that belong to the “generic set” without knowing them,
is contained in the supposed or quasi-complete “generic extension.”’2
Technical as this necessarily is, the import is hopefully perspicuous.
The hierarchy of names becomes literally hypothetical or conditional,
whereby we can repurpose names drawn from our existing ground-model
that now name elements that belong, not to the original ground-model,
but to the generic extension. In doing so, these names have a referent,
but an indeterminate one, a referent which may exist but cannot be
picked-out as such by their nomination.
Moreover, in Badiou’s own words:
the force of a generic extension is to obtain models that validate propositions
other than those that validate the ground model and not to conserve the same
semantics!! For this, it is necessary that what supplements the ground model
is generic and therefore, in a precise sense, not constructible on the basis of
1
2
Badiou 2005, 376
Bartlett 2011, 211-2
222
JUSTIN CLÉMENS
that model. Otherwise one remains in the same semantics. It is precisely this
characteristic, at once supplementary and nonconstructible, that makes the
generic the formal schema of truths; they are added to the situation without
being able to be directly deduced from it, and their deployment thus unveils
unknown possibilities of the primitive situation. This attests that they aim
at, in the situation, what the language of this situation cannot separate in it
before the supplementation1.
Mathematics thus formalizes the rational compatibility of knowledge
and truth, though the latter by definition transforms established
knowledges (all we could know from and about the ground model differs after forcing) and therefore cannot be captured by these knowledges.
Truth is generic (universal) because it escapes being known (particularism), and it escapes being known by nominating something that
could not previously be recognised in and by any knowledge within its
situation. Yet it can be named, even if this name cannot identify any
particular element as such: hence, mathematics enables the rigorous
demonstration of the possibility of reference without identification. The
nominated indiscernible novelty: the hallmark of genre.
CONCLUSION
What I have sought to elucidate in this presentation is how Badiou
uses mathematics to give a rigorous formalization of the generic. If
such an elucidation has been, by necessity, truncated and abstract, I
nonetheless hope that the basic waystations of Badiou’s itinerary have
been at least somewhat clarified. In short, mathematics is a genre whose
own generic singularity is bound up with its rigorous elaboration of
the disjunctive syntheses between consistency and inconsistency, truth
and knowledge. In doing this, mathematics is the only genre that can
consistently formalise ‘the concept of genre’ itself, as a particular relation
between truth, knowledge and praxis. As a result of its deployment of
mathematics in this fashion, metaphysics is not so much itself a genre as
at once meta—and trans-generic—not in the sense of being a superior
1
Badiou 2012, 363
CAN MATHEMATICS THINK GENRE?
223
or higher form of genre, or something external to or beyond genre, but
as entirely dependent upon genre, and upon more than one genre. What, in
the end, is exceptional about the generic is that the generic is exceptional in its rigorous evasion of particularity—and that metaphysics must
deploy mathematics to truly know this.
Justin Clémens
University of Melbourne