Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Vol. 37, No. 3 (2017), pp. 588–617
doi:10.1093/ojls/gqw032
Published Advance Access February 4, 2017
What is Property Law?
Eveline Ramaekers*
Abstract—Property law scholars have been dealing with a number of key doctrinal
questions concerning property law since the first time someone pointed at
something and claimed: ‘This is mine!’ This scholarship has included questions
such as: What are property rights? What kind of things can we have property rights
in? What role can property law play in shaping our society? But one question that
seems to have drawn less attention than the others is: What is property law? This
article places the question of what property law is into the limelight. It tackles this
question in four steps: (i) it asks why the question is a valid one in the first
place; (ii) it presents an abstract model outlining the building blocks of property
law; (iii) it discusses how to separate property law from other, adjacent fields of
law; and (iv) it analyses the impact that developments in EU law have on the main
question of what property law is.
Keywords: property theory, EU property law, comparative property law
1. Introduction
Property law scholars have been dealing with a number of key doctrinal
questions concerning property law since the first time someone pointed at
something and claimed: ‘This is mine!’1 This scholarship has included
questions such as: What are property rights? What kind of things can we
claim property rights in? What do we expect from rules governing property, ie
what roles do property and property law play in shaping our society and what
roles do we want them to play? But one big question that seems to have drawn
less attention than the others is: What is property law? A deceivingly simple
question, the answer to which, however, is likely to be complex. It is a difficult
* Assistant Professor in Private Law, University of Amsterdam. Email: E.Ramaekers@uva.nl. I am grateful to
Bram Akkermans, Susan Bright, Sjef van Erp, Graham Reynolds, Jan Smits and André van der Walt for their
comments on earlier versions. Any errors remain my own.
Dedication: This paper is dedicated to the memory of Professor André van der Walt, who inspired me to write
it. He is sorely missed.
1
cf the words meum esse, used in Roman legal procedure by parties claiming that a certain object was theirs: G
Inst 4.16; M Kaser, ‘The Concept of Roman Ownership’ [1964] Tydskrif vir hedendaagse Romeins-Hollandse
reg 5, 7–8.
ß The Author 2017. Published by Oxford University Press. All rights reserved.
For permissions, please e-mail: journals.permissions@oup.com
AUTUMN 2017
What is Property Law?
589
question to demarcate. The other questions just mentioned are all closely
related and there is certainly some overlap between them. The question of what
property law is, however, would seem to overarch or encompass all of these
other questions, particularly the first two (ie what property rights are and what
kind of things we can claim them in).
With this article I wish to place the question of what property law is into the
limelight, but before I explain why, it is important to have a closer look at the
underlying premise of the question. By asking what property law is, we
presume that there is such a thing as property law, that it is a field of law that
can be separated from other areas of law, delimited and labelled ‘property law’.
Lawyers are used to the law being subdivided in a number of categories, eg
property law, criminal law, administrative law. Dividing the law into such
categories serves a number of practical and legal purposes: we use these
categories to structure legal education, when writing civil codes, when deciding
which judge, chamber or court to assign a case to and, in conflict of laws
situations, to decide what the appropriate connecting factor is to determine
which forum has jurisdiction and what the applicable law is. At the same time,
lawyers are aware that it is a bit of an illusion to try and draw hard lines
between various areas of law, that all areas of law connect to other areas of law.
The borders are clearly fluid and when we study law comparatively we see that
there is not just one way of drawing the lines either, because other legal systems
than our own draw the line between, say, property law and the law of
obligations differently. What is more, the influence of European law on our
national legal systems challenges the categories that we have created, since
European law does not use the same categories that national law uses.
Nevertheless, I would maintain that the question ‘What is property law?’
remains a valid one to ask because the categorisation of law is unavoidable for
the practical and legal reasons just mentioned.
So why do I want to investigate this question? First of all, this is an essential
question for all property law scholars, but so far it does not seem to have
received the attention it deserves, or at least not the same amount of attention
that some of the other ‘big questions’ just mentioned have received. Secondly,
it is a necessary and unavoidable question for anyone involved in creating or
reforming an area of law.2 I was first confronted with the question of what
property law is when trying to describe what European Union property law is.3
Systematising and developing EU property law is the primary aim of my
2
cf W Wiegand, ‘Sachenrecht im Obligationenrecht’ in P Caroni (ed), Das Obligationenrecht 1883–1983
(Haupt 1984) 109: ‘Ehe auf den Inhalt einzugehen ist, stellt sich die Frage, wieso diese heute im Sachenrecht
geregelten und auch materiell dem Sachenrecht zugeordneten Rechtsprobleme in eine Kodifikation des
Obligationenrechts aufgenommen wurden.’ (‘Before one can discuss the content, the question arises why these
legal concepts, which are presently regulated by the law of property and which are also substantively allocated to
the law of property, were included in a codification of the law of obligations’ translation ER.)
3
Similarly, Dr Wian Erlank was faced with this question when trying to describe what virtual property law is.
Both EU property law and virtual property law are new areas of law and for neither of them is it entirely clear
what ‘property law’ means. Researchers trying to develop these areas of law therefore inevitably find themselves
590
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies
VOL. 37
research. Because European law is competence driven it is not categorised
along the same lines as national law traditionally is, ie one would be hard
pressed to find legal bases in the Lisbon Treaties granting the EU the
competence to create criminal law, tort law, administrative law, property law
etc. Rather, the legal bases in the Treaties concern specific topics, such as the
creation and functioning of the internal market, competition, fisheries and
consumer protection. Therefore, providing a description of ‘European property
law’ meant searching all these different areas of EU law for rules regulating
proprietary relationships. That is only possible if you know what you are
looking for, ie you need to know what property law is before you can go look
for it within EU law. The needle needs to be defined before diving into the
haystack.
The question ‘what is property law?’ therefore constitutes one of the main
pillars on which my research is based. I have already touched on this question
specifically in the context of EU law.4 I now wish to expand on that work by
dealing with this question more generally. This will constitute the main part of
this article. Towards the end I will return to the EU law context and discuss
what my findings concerning the question ‘what is property law?’ mean for the
question ‘what is EU property law?’
An entire book could probably be written on this topic, so this article sets
out to provide only a big picture answer. It can therefore be seen as a research
agenda that can and will be expanded on in future, as the question of what
property law is will continue to resurface.
The article will first of all provide an abstract model of what property law is
and then apply the model to various examples drawn from national law.
Secondly, it will investigate how to draw the lines between property law and
other areas of law, particularly contract law.5 The relationship with contract law
will receive particular attention for three reasons: (i) express agreements
between parties seem to be the main instigator of property relationships; (ii)
the dividing line between property and contract is often used in comparative
legal debates to say that a certain jurisdiction’s property law is ‘narrower’ or
‘broader’ than that of another jurisdiction and it therefore pertains directly to
our primary question of what property law is; and (iii) the dividing line
between property and contract is often used by the European legislature to
demarcate its own legislative competences, which in turn provides an indication
of what the European legislature does and does not consider to be property
law. This could provide some inspiration in answering the question of what
property law is.
confronted with the question, what is property law? See W Erlank, Property in Virtual Worlds (Stellenbosch
University 2012) 211–308 <http://ssrn.com/abstract=2216481>.
4
E Ramaekers, European Union Property Law: From Fragments to a System (Intersentia 2013) ch 1, s 2.
5
The relationship between property law and other areas of law is the topic of section 3 of this article.
AUTUMN 2017
What is Property Law?
591
Thirdly, I will describe the characteristics of EU property law and discuss
how it is similar to or different from national property law. The conclusion will
provide an overview of my findings.
2. What is Property Law?
Every lawyer will have a conception of what property law is. They may have a
quite detailed definition in mind, or they may simply think ‘I will know it when
I see it’. Some may have extensively pondered the question,6 others may simply
have accepted the dichotomy between property law and adjacent areas of law,
such as contract or insolvency law, since their time as law students, because
these areas of law were presented to them as related but distinct fields
throughout their studies. Those who have studied comparative law will
understand that the borders of the field called property law are not drawn in
the same way by every jurisdiction. Some have tried to redraw the lines or even
to dispense with them altogether. Below follows an overview of definitions and
descriptions of property law that have been presented in both academic
literature and legislation. When looking at these descriptions it will become
clear that it can be difficult to separate the question ‘What is property law?’
from the question ‘What are property rights?’. The latter question has
produced a wide variety of answers, from Hohfeld’s description of property
rights as multital rights7 to Honoré’s bundle of rights8 to Smith’s characterisation of property rights as modules connected by interfaces.9 In addition,
there is a lot to be said in response to the question ‘What is property?’. Provided
that one interprets the word ‘property’ as pertaining to the ‘things’ (objects,
assets, etc) in which one can have property rights,10 answers to the question of
what property is could include that there is a difference between tangible and
intangible property,11 between personal and fungible property,12 between
property resting on one’s own labour and property resting on the labour of
6
See eg C von Bar and U Drobnig, ‘Study on Property Law and Non-contractual Liability Law as They
Relate to Contract Law’, European Commission, DG Health and Consumer Protection (2002) SANCO B51000/02/000574.
7
WN Hohfeld, ‘Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning’ (1916–1917) 26 Yale LJ
710–770.
8
AM Honoré, ‘Ownership’ in AG Guest (ed), Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence (OUP 1961) 107–47. The seeds
of the bundle of rights theory were already present in Hohfeld’s work, but he does not describe property rights in
so many words as bundles of rights. Rather, he regards them as aggregates of jural relations (Hohfeld, 96–97).
Honoré, in his work on ‘Ownership’, provided the meat to the bones of the bundle of rights theory: ‘[N]ot until
more than forty years later, when Honoré produced Ownership, was there a work that was widely recognized as
providing the elaboration which gave the bundle of rights thesis the substance it required’, JE Penner, ‘The
Bundle of Rights Picture of Property’ (1995–1996) 43 UCLA L Rev 711, 731.
9
HE Smith, ‘Property as the Law of Things’ (2012) 125 Harv L Rev 1691, 1691–726.
10
The term ‘property’ in a legal sense can be ambiguous and often its meaning needs to be discerned from the
context. It can mean things or objects, property rights or property law.
11
JHM van Erp and B Akkermans (eds), Cases, Materials and Text on Property Law (Hart Publishing 2012)
Chapter 1 S II.C Property Law.
12
MJ Radin, ‘Property and Personhood’ in MJ Radin, Reinterpreting Property (University of Chicago Press
1993) 37.
592
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies
VOL. 37
others,13 or between property for use and property for power.14 Yet the fact
that certain property is objectively treated differently, for instance because it
receives stronger than average protection,15 or is subjectively deemed to be
worthy of stronger protection than other kinds of property does not make the
rules that protect this property any more or less proprietary. What it does is tell
us something about the question of what property law should do, what we
expect it to do or want it to do.16 Nevertheless, although these questions of
what property is, what property rights are and what we feel property law
should do have resulted in a rich and interesting academic debate, they are not
immediately relevant to the present discussion and will not be dealt with
further. The emphasis of this article lies on the question stated in the title:
what is property law?
There are quite a few descriptions of what property law is, though they vary
in length and detail, and do not necessarily explain where the borders between
property law and other areas of law are or how to draw them.
Sagaert points out that the traditional dichotomy between property law and
the law of obligations is no longer sufficient intoday’s complex society, leading
to the appearance of ever more hybrid rights that have both personal and
proprietary characteristics.17 Based on this observation, he proposes to
dispense with the traditional in rem/in personam categories and to focus instead
on what he calls the active and passive sides of any ‘patrimonial right’
(vermogensrecht), the active side being the side of the right holder and the
passive side being that of the duty holder.18 If the right in question is accessory
to another thing or object, on either the active or passive side, any transfer of
that object automatically implies the transfer of the right as well under the
maxim accessorium sequitur principale. This leads Sagaert to conclude that there
are four types of patrimonial rights: (i) those which are not accessory to any
object at all, whether on the active or the passive side; (ii) those which are
accessory to an object on both sides; (iii) those which are accessory to an
object on the active side; and (iv) those which are accessory to an object on the
passive side.
Van Erp argues along similar lines, stating that the boundaries between
property law and contract law are becoming more and more fuzzy.19 Whereas
the distinction between property and contract could traditionally be seen as a
13
K Marx and F Engels, The Communist Manifesto (Penguin Books edn 1979) 96.
LT Hobhouse, ‘The Historical Evolution of Property, in Fact and in Idea’ in LT Hobhouse, Property: Its
Duties and Rights (2nd edn, Macmillan 1922) 9–11.
15
As is often the case with, eg, family homes.
16
A topic recently discussed in detail by JW Singer, ‘Property as the Law of Democracy’ (2014) 63 Duke LJ
1287. I answered the question of what I think property law should be as far as EU property law is concerned in
Ramaekers (n 4) ch 6, pt II.
17
V Sagaert, ‘Het goederenrecht als open systeem van verbintenissen? Poging tot een nieuwe kwalificatie van
de vermogensrechten’ (2005) 42(3) Tijdschrift voor Privaatrecht 983.
18
ibid s E.
19
JHM van Erp, ‘Contract and Property Law: Distinct, but not Separate’ (2013) 9(4) European Review of
Contract Law 307, 326.
14
AUTUMN 2017
What is Property Law?
593
binary one, with proprietary arrangements having binding force on third parties
but contractual arrangements not having such force, these two areas of law now
operate more on a sliding scale.20 At one end of the spectrum are rights with
no third party effects at all; at the other end are rights with full third party
effect. In between we find a number of arrangements with some, but not full,
third party effect. One example would be the security arrangements under
German law that accompany the Grundschuld, a non-accessory mortgage.21
Such security arrangements prevent the lender from enforcing his mortgage
right if there is no actual debt.22 German legislation has made these
arrangements enforceable against third party acquirers of the mortgage right.23
Gray writes that property is about control over access, that it is a power
relationship—namely, the power to exclude.24 The limits on property are
therefore not fixed by the ‘thinglikeness’ of particular resources, but by the
physical, legal and moral criteria of excludability.25 According to Gray, rooting
the concept of property in the test of excludability casts severe doubt on the
dichotomy between contract and property and, rather than trying to define the
quantum step that elevates contract to property, we should recognise that there
exists a spectrum of ‘propertiness’:26
[In this spectrum] obligations which derive their moral force from discrete acts of
affirmative consent shade gradually and almost imperceptibly into obligations whose
social persuasiveness rests upon the collective acceptance of sustained acts of assertive
control.27
Gretton, after a lengthy and impressively detailed discussion of the Gaian
Schema of corporeals and incorporeals and the questions of what our
relationship to each is and whether or not that relationship is one of ownership,
points out that there is a body of law that bridges both the law of things and
the law of obligations.28 In this area of law we find the law of limited rights, the
principle of numerus clausus and the law of ranking, all of which apply to both
limited personal rights and limited real rights (limited here in the sense of less
than full ownership).29 He refers to the Dutch civil code as an example of this
overlapping area of law: Book 3 of the Dutch civil code concerns the General
20
ibid.
The fact that the Grundschuld is non-accessory means that it is a security right which is not linked to the
underlying loan, meaning that it continues to exist even if the borrower has paid off their debt: § 1191 et seq of
the German civil code.
22
van Erp (n 19) 320.
23
The Limitation of Risks Statute, or Risikobegrenzungsgesetz.
24
K Gray, ‘Property in Thin Air’ (1991) 50/2 CLJ 252, 294.
25
ibid 299.
26
Gray (n 24) 302.
27
Gray (n 24) 303.
28
GL Gretton, ‘Ownership and its Objects’ (2007) 71(4) Rabels Zeitschrift für ausländisches und
internationales Privatrecht 802–51, 847.
29
ibid 847–848.
21
594
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies
VOL. 37
Principles of Patrimonial Law and applies as an overarching law to both Book 5
on the Law of Things and Book 6 on the Law of Obligations.
Henry Smith has described property law as the ‘law of modular things’.30 He
bases his ‘architectural theory of property’31 on information costs and explains
how ‘using modularity to manage complexity’32 can reduce information costs
for people trying to discover the existence and content of property rights. He
summarises his theory as follows:
Property organizes this world into lumpy packages of legal relations—legal things—by
setting boundaries around useful attributes that tend to be strong complements. The
law of property in effect encapsulates these lumpy packages, or modules,
semitransparently from other modules and the outside world generally [reference
omitted]. Thus, property defines things using an exclusion strategy of ‘keep off’ or
‘don’t touch’ and then enriches the system of domains of owner control with
interfaces using governance strategies [reference omitted]. These strategies zoom in
on relations between neighbors in the case of land, and between owners (and their
things) and other parties in the case of both land and personal property.33
The Ius Commune Casebook on Property Law states that ‘[i]n the most
general terms, the law of property is the law dealing with things. These things
may either be tangible (corporeal) or intangible (incorporeal)’.34 This general
description is then further elaborated and an explanation is provided as to why
property rights are different from other rights:
[T]hese . . . rights to objects [ie property rights] are different from other rights as they
are created in respect to an object and not vis-à-vis specific other persons. Property
rights, to put it differently, have effect against third parties by their nature. Personal
rights, which are rights arising from a contract, and even though they also concern an
object (the ‘performance’ of that contract), are generally only binding between two or
more specific parties. This is something that is shared universally between systems of
property law.35
This description focuses on a distinction between types of rights. Implicitly, it
suggests that the body of rules governing rights to objects (or things) is
property law and that rules governing other (personal) rights belong to the law
of obligations.
The Restatement (First) of Property (1936), produced by the American Law
Institute, provides the following description in its introductory note:
The word ‘property’ is used sometimes to denote the thing with respect to which legal
relations between persons exist and sometimes to denote the legal relations. The
30
31
32
33
34
35
HE Smith, ‘Property as the Law of Things’ (2012) 125 Harv L Rev 1691, 1694.
ibid.
ibid.
Smith (2012) Harv L Rev, 1693–1694.
van Erp and Akkermans (n 11) 31.
van Erp and Akkermans (n 11) 37–8.
AUTUMN 2017
What is Property Law?
595
former of these two usages . . . does not occur in this Restatement. When it is desired
to indicate the thing with regard to which legal relations exist, it will be referred to
either specifically as ‘the land,’ ‘the automobile,’ ‘the share of stock,’ or, generically, as
‘the subject matter of property’ or ‘the thing.’
The word ‘property’ is used in this Restatement to denote legal relations between
persons with respect to a thing. The thing may be an object having physical existence
or it may be any kind of an intangible such as a patent right or a chose in action. The
broader meanings of the word ‘property,’ which include any relationship having an
exchange value, are not used.
The Restatement then goes on to describe four types of legal relations between
persons with respect to a thing—right, privilege, power and immunity—
following the Hohfeldian classification.36 This description of ‘property’ (or
property law) is similar to that found in the Casebook in that it focuses on the
nature of the legal relation (or right), but it differs from the Casebook’s
definition in that it defines property as a legal relation between persons with
respect to a thing, whereas the Casebook describes property rights as legal
relations between a person and a thing.
German law separates property law from the law of obligations by focusing
more on the nature of objects (or things) than on the nature of various rights,
in contrast to the descriptions in the Casebook and the Restatement. It
employs the so-called Trennungsprinzip (principle of separation) to indicate a
strict separation between the law of obligations and property law and is
therefore one of the legal systems that most clearly and explicitly draws the line
between these two areas of law.37 German property law applies only to tangible
property,38 both movable and immovable, although it makes an exception for
the right of pledge (Pfandrecht), which can also be created in relation to a right
(Pfandrecht an Rechten),39 displaying a slightly inconsistent approach as to
whether or not intangibles belong to the realm of property law or contract law.
Spanish law provides a stark contrast to German law and its Trennungsprinzip,
and not just because it includes a far wider range of ‘things’ within property law
than German law does.40 Primarily, the contrast flows from the fact that Spanish
law operates a numerus apertus instead of a numerus clausus of property rights.41
36
See also JB Baron, ‘The Contested Commitments of Property’ (2009–2010) 61 Hastings LJ 917, 933.
van Erp and Akkermans (n 11) 34.
38
Ownership only includes ownership of Sachen (§903 German civil code), which according to §90 of the civil
code means ‘Sachen im Sinne des Gesetzes sind nur körperliche Gegenstände’ (‘Objects as it is used in this law
can only be corporeal objects’). Translation from N Kornet and S Hardt, Selected National, European and
International Provisions from Public and Private Law: The Maastricht Collection (3rd edn, Europa Law Publishing
2013).
39
§§1273–96 German civil code.
40
Both tangible and intangible things are governed by property law; see arts 334–7 of the Spanish civil code,
an English translation of which can be found at <http://www.elra.eu/wp-content/uploads/file/Spanish_Civil_
Code_(Código_Civil)%5B1%5D.pdf>.
41
B Akkermans, The Principle of Numerus Clausus in European Property Law (Intersentia 2008) 7; R Sánchez
Aristi and N Moralejo Imbernón, Property and Trust Law in Spain (2nd edn, Wolters Kluwer Law & Business
2014) 54.
37
596
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies
VOL. 37
This means that private individuals may create new property rights themselves,
provided they ‘satisfy an actual and socially valid need and that they respect the
characteristics of these kinds of rights’.42 For immovable property, it is the Land
Registry, in which property rights on immovables must be registered in order to
have third party effect, that applies this test to new types of property rights that
parties wish to create.
The law of England and Wales is not particularly straightforward on what it
considers to be property law. Some definitions focus on the nature of things to
define what property law is, similar to German law. Furthermore, what civil
lawyers might call property law is subdivided, in English law, into land law and
personal property law, evidencing the focus on the nature of various things.
McFarlane writes:
Property law is about rights to use things. ‘Things’ are objects that can be physically
located in a particular place: such as land, bikes . . . Property law deals with two very
common but impossibly difficult questions: (i) who is entitled to use a thing?; and (ii)
how are they entitled to use it?43
Lawson and Rudden present quite a different description of property law. It is
possibly also the most detailed description of what property law is that I have
encountered so far, focusing explicitly on what property law is, rather than on
what property (ie things/objects) is or what property rights are. They describe
property law as follows:
[T]he function of the law relating to private property is to provide us with a bag of
tools with which to achieve our wishes. [I]t says what counts as property, that is to say
what can be the object of its powers and protections. . . . The law of property also
determines the types of interests which will be treated as proprietary, that is as being
more than merely personal, familial, or contractual, and it spells out the
consequences of a finding that a particular interest is proprietary. It says what we
can do with these interests . . . [I]n conjunction with other branches of law—especially
the law of obligations—property law protects the rights of the holders of these
interests . . . [I]t deals with the transfer of property and the repackaging of proprietary
interests whether inter vivos or on death. . . . It is these formalities and structures
which most concern the law of property. . . . [O]ne of the main difficulties the student
of property law encounters at the very threshold is the presence of abstractions rather
than physical objects. . . . Property lawyers take surprisingly little interest in land or
ships or machinery or animals as such, but a great deal in abstract notions such as the
‘fee simple’ in land, trust funds, stocks and shares, security interests, title and
documents of title.44
My own previous research on the development of European property law led
me to develop an abstract model of property law that would fit the
42
43
44
Sánchez Aristi and Moralejo Imbernón (ibid) 54.
B McFarlane, The Structure of Property Law (Hart Publishing 2008) 4.
FH Lawson and B Rudden, The Law of Property (3rd rev edn, OUP 2002) 4–5.
AUTUMN 2017
What is Property Law?
597
characteristics of any property law system. This model of property law had to
be able to incorporate the elements that property law systems share in general,
without having to study the specifics of the property laws of each of the 28
Member States of the EU. In other words, the model had to be of a transsystemic nature.45 Such a model is presented in the next section. With this
model all the different elements that make up a system of property law can be
construed.
The model contains a description of what I believe to be the constitutive
elements of a system of property law and it provides a method of visualising
property rights that feature within a system of property law. I designed the
images that are presented in Figures 1–6 as a way to make this model of
property law visually accessible, as an alternative to a mere textual explanation
of the model. These images are not meant to say anything about the similarities
and differences between property law systems; their only purpose is to show
how different property rights can be visualised. They are intended to provide
additional clarity, but they are of course based on my personal preferences for
simplification through visualisation and may not appeal to everyone in the same
way. The underlying theory is therefore self-contained and not dependent on
the images. The textual explanation of the model is complete in and of itself,
though intended to be supported by the images shown below.
Once I have described the model, which shows what property law is, I will
continue with the question of how property law relates to and can be separated
from adjacent areas of law.
3. A Model of Property Law—The System-Cube
This model shows a standardised system of property law and is not dependent
upon a specific national definition.46 The model is not meant to explain where
property rights come from or what their function is, but only what they look
like, what their characteristics are. It is also intended to show which rules are
part of property law, but not what the content of those rules should be. In this
sense, the model is descriptive rather than normative. The model shows that
any system of property law can be opened up to reveal its constitutive
elements. Each separate property right that one encounters within the system is
made up of a particular assembly of building blocks and is governed by a
regulatory framework. The model visualises this internal structure of property
45
JHM van Erp, ‘Teaching Law in Europe: From an Intra-systemic, via a Trans-systemic to a Supra-systemic
Approach’ in AW Heringa and B Akkermans (eds), Educating European Lawyers (Intersentia 2011) 81: ‘Transsystemic analysis uses the functional method to discover how legal traditions solve particular problems,
discovering the underlying values, policy choices, leading principles, concepts, ground rules and more specific
technical rules. Through trans-systemic analysis the groundwork (perhaps one could say: the matrix) of legal
systems can be found.’ See also S van Praagh, ‘Preface—Navigating the Transsystemic: A Course Syllabus’
(2005) 50 McGill LJ 701.
46
This model was first developed in Ramaekers (n 4) 20–38.
598
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies
VOL. 37
law. It consists of a core and a regulatory framework surrounding that core.
The core represents the building blocks that make up property rights. The
regulatory framework around it—which I have called the operating system—
consists of the rules governing these property rights. Together, these two
component parts (ie core and surrounding framework) represent property law.
The core by itself only depicts property rights. The examples below focus on
the core only (without the surrounding framework of operating rules) because
they depict various property rights and their characteristics.
The core visualises the three dimensions of property rights. The first
dimension consists of the objects, the things that can be the object of property
rights. Depending on the legal system, these may be only tangible or may
include intangibles as well. The second dimension consists of the content of
the various property rights, ie ownership, title or fee simple, and other, limited,
property rights which one can have in relation to the objects. Whereas
ownership is unlimited in content, in that an owner can in principle do
whatever she wishes with her object unless it is contrary to the law, other
property rights are more limited. A leaseholder in English law is allowed to use
the freeholder’s land, but not to sell the freehold to a third party. The third
dimension of property rights is the dimension of time. Property rights, as well
as the objects on which they rest, can be unlimited or limited in time. For
instance, ownership is unlimited in time, but a security right is usually limited
to the time during which the underlying claim that it secures is being repaid.47
There is a constant interplay between the three dimensions of property rights.
Under German law, one can only have a right of ownership in tangible objects,
yet intangibles (eg a claim on a debtor) can be transferred and be burdened
with limited property rights, such as a usufruct.48 Under Dutch law, emission
rights cannot be pledged, even though other intangible objects usually can.49
The core of the model, consisting of property rights, is governed by a set of
operating rules. Previously, I concluded that the operating system contains
rules on creation, transfer, registration and destruction.50 These rules are part
of the operating system because they each regulate a different stage in the life
of a property right. Any time you want to do anything with a property right you
will need rules from one or more of these categories to do so. In other words,
without an operating system, property rights would exist in a vacuum. The
rules in these four categories inform people how particular property rights can
be acquired or passed on to someone else and what these rights can and cannot
47
cf Birks’s description of estates in land (in English law) as slices of time: P Birks, ‘Before we Begin: Five
Keys to Land Law’ in S Bright and J Dewar (eds), Land Law: Themes and Perspectives (OUP 1998) 457–86.
48
§ 1068(1) German civil code.
49
See art 16.42(3) of the Dutch Wet Milieubeheer (Law on Environmental Management). Emission rights
are a new kind of object, introduced by European law: Directive 2003/87/EC Establishing a Scheme for
Greenhouse Gas Emission Allowance Trading [2003] OJ L275/32.
50
Ramaekers (n 4) 22–23.
AUTUMN 2017
What is Property Law?
599
be used for. They also tell us how a property right may be lost or brought to an
end.
This initial description of the operating system can, however, be elaborated.
The creation and transfer of property rights are just two ways in which
property rights can be acquired. Although they are the primary means and
therefore essential elements of the operating system, there are other modes of
acquisition. Acquisition can be either original or derivative. Original acquisition
means that someone receives ‘a right which did not previously exist, which
originates in the hands of the new owner or holder of the right’.51 Derivative
acquisition means that someone receives ‘a right which previously belonged to
someone else’.52 Each type of acquisition—original and derivative—contains
further subtypes. Original acquisition can occur through creation or through
occupatio, where someone takes possession of an abandoned, ownerless object
(ie a res nullius), thereby becoming its owner. Cases where rights arise as of
necessity—for instance, easements of necessity53—also concern original acquisition. Derivative acquisition occurs primarily through the transfer of property
rights, either through an ordinary transfer or through gift or succession.
Acquisitive prescription (or adverse possession) could also be seen as a type of
derivative acquisition, in that the adverse possessor acquires the title previously
held by the now dispossessed owner. There is, however, some discussion as to
whether adverse possession is really a form of derivative acquisition or whether
it is actually a form of original acquisition in that the title previously held by
the dispossessed owner is extinguished and a new title arises in the hands of the
adverse possessor.54
If we elaborate on the operating system in this way, we can see that it
contains rules on acquisition (with its subcategories of original and derivative
acquisition), registration and destruction. Although registration requirements
are sometimes constitutive for the valid creation or transfer of property rights,
in which case they would be part of the rules on acquisition, this is not always
the case.55 It is therefore appropriate to treat them as a separate category.
The operating system also contains rules relating to the third party effect of
property rights. One of the distinguishing features of property rights is that
they can be invoked erga omnes,56 whereas personal rights can only be invoked
against one or several specific persons, based on contract or tort law. Operating
51
van Erp and Akkermans (n 11) 617.
van Erp and Akkermans (n 11) 617.
53
B McFarlane, N Hopkins and S Nield, Land Law: Text, Cases and Materials (OUP 2012) ch 25, s 3.2.1.
54
van Erp and Akkermans (n 11) 738.
55
That registration is not always constitutive for the valid creation and transfer of property rights can be seen,
eg, in ch 1 of the English Land Registration Act 2002, which distinguishes between voluntary registration and
compulsory registration. It can also be seen in French law, where registration is necessary to ensure a third party
effect of the creation or transfer of a property right, but it is not constitutive for the valid creation or transfer of a
property right as such—without registration, the creation or transfer still has effet relatif (relative effect, ie as
between the parties only); see van Erp and Akkermans (n 11) 900–2.
56
van Erp and Akkermans (n 11) 39.
52
600
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies
VOL. 37
Figure 1. The System-Cube, Visualising the System of Property Law
rules concerning the third party effect of property rights are therefore, for
instance, rules that determine if and when a property right can be invoked
against a third party or whether a third party transferee is protected against the
invalidity of a previous transfer.
These four categories (acquisition, registration, destruction and third party
effect) constitute the absolute minimum of operating rules necessary to
regulate the core of the system of property law, ie the property rights. Beyond
these four categories lies a large grey area of rules that could be part of the
operating system, but do not necessarily have to be part of it. These are, for
instance, rules of insolvency law, succession law or constitutional law. How
property law relates to these adjacent areas of law forms the topic of the next
section.
The core of the model plus the operating system together form the system of
property law. This model shows the building blocks out of which property
rights are made. The full model, ie the core of property rights and the
operating system that governs those rights, are visualised in Figure 1.
The model follows the démembrement (or subtraction) theory of limited
property rights. This method stems from the French legal tradition and takes
as a starting point that the right of ownership contains a number of powers,
AUTUMN 2017
What is Property Law?
601
which can be divided into specific parts. These parts can be transferred to
another person, in whose hands they form a limited property right. The limited
property right thus consists of fragments of the right of ownership out of which
it was created.57
A few examples will serve to show how this model can be applied to various
national property rights. The whole cube will hereafter be called the SystemCube, whereas the individual smaller cubes of which it is made up will be
called the minor cubes. Each of the minor cubes will be given its own
designation. The three minor cubs in the bottom front row represent various
kinds of objects (immovable, movable, intangible; or land, choses in possession,
choses in action). The cubes behind each of these three (forming the
dimension of depth) represent the content of a property right: the more
cubes there are in this dimension, the more extensive the property right is (ie
the more rights and powers it grants). On top of each minor cube at the
bottom of the System-Cube are stacked two more minor cubes, representing
the dimension of time. Two minor cubes on top of the rights cubes indicate
that the right is in principle unlimited in time. Take one away from the top and
the right is limited in time. The same is true for the time cubes placed on top
of the objects cubes: take one away from the top and the object is limited in
time. By taking away, or leaving in place, one or more of the minor cubes in
any of the three dimensions, it is possible to visualise what the characteristics of
a given property right are.
It is irrelevant how many minor cubes one starts with to make up the whole
System-Cube: the principal idea always remains the same. The images in
Figures 1–6 make use of a System-Cube of 3 33 minor cubes, because I
believe this provides a clear but not overly complex visualisation of the building
blocks that make up property rights. It would, however, be perfectly possible to
use more (or fewer), depending on how detailed a visualisation the user would
like.
A. Security Rights in Relation to Tangible Objects
A security right created in relation to a tangible object reduces the width of the
System-Cube, because intangibles are left out; it reduces the depth of the cube,
because a security right is less extensive than full ownership; and the height
above the rights cubes is reduced, because security rights only exist for the
duration of the claim that they are meant to secure. A security right in relation
to a tangible object can therefore be visualised by the System-Cube as in
Figure 2.
57
The other possibility is to see limited property rights not so much as derived from the powers of the
owner but as a limitation of those powers. Such a limitation entails that those powers that accumulate in the
limited property right are not taken away from the person with the more extensive property right, but that
this person can, temporarily, simply not make use of those powers. This is the so-called limitation model. See
Akkermans (n 41) 116 and 415.
602
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies
VOL. 37
Figure 2. A Security Right in Relation to a Tangible Object
B. Right of Ownership of Emission Rights
Emission rights are new objects of property rights introduced through
European legislation.58 Directive 2003/78/EC59 establishes a Union-wide
trading scheme in so-called greenhouse gas emission allowances. Article 3
defines an emission allowance as ‘an allowance to emit one tonne of carbon
dioxide equivalent during a specified period, which . . . shall be transferable in
accordance with the provisions of this Directive’. Emission rights differ
somewhat from other intangible objects in that they are used up: once the
greenhouse gasses have been emitted, the rights expire. Visualising ownership
of emission rights through the System-Cube is therefore done in the following
way: the width is reduced, because emission rights constitute an intangible
object; the depth is not reduced, because we are talking about the right of
ownership, the most extensive property right; the height is reduced, but not
above the rights cubes as in the previous examples, because the right of
ownership is unlimited in time. The height is reduced above the object cube,
since emission rights are inherently limited in time. They are depleted, used up.
This provides Figure 3.
58
Dutch law, for instance, treats them as vermogensrechten (patrimonial rights) because they represent a
certain value and are transferable; see B Akkermans, ‘The European Union Development of European Property
Law’ (2011) Maastricht European Private Law Institute (M-EPLI) Working Paper 27/2011, 8; JS Kortmann, ‘De
overdracht van CO2-emissierechten nader beschouwd’ (2005) 8 Nederlands Juristenblad 392, 393.
59
[2003] OJ L275/32.
AUTUMN 2017
What is Property Law?
603
Figure 3. Right of Ownership of Emission Rights
This example may raise the question how it is possible to have ownership
(which is thought of as ‘for eternity’ or ‘perpetual’) of an intangible thing with
a limited lifespan. This question essentially comes down to whether the nature
of the thing can affect the nature of the right in the thing. There is no definitive
answer to this question, only theories going in various directions. As we have
already seen,60 some legal systems accept that one can have ownership of both
tangible and intangible objects (eg the French droit de propriété). Others state
that one can only have ownership of tangible objects (eg the German Eigentum
and the Dutch eigendom). These jurisdictions have a unified system of property
law in that there is a single set of rules that applies to everything deemed to be
property. Then there are jurisdictions, such as English law, which have a
fragmented system of property law in that there are separate sets of rules for
different kinds of property, eg land law for land (ie tangible immovable
property) and personal property law for choses in possession and choses in
action (ie tangible and intangible movable property). The more you move from
one end of the spectrum (eg French law) to the other (eg English law), the
60
See section 3.
604
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies
VOL. 37
more likely you will find the view that the nature of the thing does affect the
nature of the right in the thing.
I find myself more on the ‘French’ end of the spectrum, ie that the nature of
the thing has only a very limited, if any, effect on the nature of the right in the
thing. First of all, as we will see below,61 EU law is very similar to French law
in that it accepts that all things, whether tangible or intangible, movable or
immovable, can be the object of ‘perpetual’ rights (ownership, in EU law) as
long as they represent some economic value.62 EU law has thus bypassed the
international debate on whether or not intangibles can be owned. Secondly, if
the nature of the thing had such an immediate impact on the nature of the
right in the thing, it would lead to the conclusion that there could never be a
perpetual or eternal right, since nothing exists in perpetuity. Objects perish all
the time: as you are reading this article, you may be holding a sandwich that
may not make it until the end of the article, but that does not mean that you
do not, at present, consider yourself the owner of your sandwich. Even land
has a limited life, to which the residents near the cliffs of Dover or the coast of
Norfolk can surely attest. Nevertheless, someone holding a fee simple absolute
in possession in a plot of land in these areas would be considered to be holding
a perpetual right in land.
To return to the original example of emission rights: it is perfectly possible for
someone owning an emission right to think of themselves as holding a perpetual
right to an intangible thing which has a limited life. The lifespan of the right is a
separate issue from the lifespan of the object. Often, the right does not last as
long as the object. With emission rights, the opposite happens to be true.
C. Restrictive Covenants
As a result of historical developments, English law consists of two subsystems:
common law and equity.63 A consequence of this division is the existence of
legal as well as of equitable property rights.64 This division into subsystems
does not prevent the application of the System-Cube. The depth of the Cube
represents the range of property rights. The content of the right determines just
how deep that dimension is. There is no reason why this range of property
rights cannot contain both the legal and the equitable rights. Whether a person
holds a property right at law or in equity does not change the content of the
right as such, although it may mean that different operating rules apply to the
property right.65 Rules on third party effects, for instance, may apply
61
See below, section 5.
Ramaekers (n 4) ch 4, ss 4.2, 5.7 and 5.8.
PS Davies and G Virgo, Equity & Trusts—Text, Cases and Materials (OUP 2013) 3–23; Lawson and Rudden
(n 44) 10–11.
64
M Dixon, Modern Land Law (9th edn, Routledge 2014) 10; Akkermans (n 41) 336; A Clarke and P
Kohler, Property Law—Commentary and Materials (CUP 2005) 403 et seq.
65
Dixon (n 64) 10–26.
62
63
AUTUMN 2017
What is Property Law?
605
differently depending on whether a person holds a property right at law or in
equity. Equitable property rights cannot generally be invoked against a bona
fide purchaser for value without notice, whereas legal property rights usually
can, although certain registration requirements may have to be met. However,
a change in the operating rules does not change the parameters of the SystemCube. English property rights, regardless of whether they are legal or equitable
property rights, can therefore be visualised through the System-Cube like any
other property right.
There is one exception, however, and that is restrictive covenants.66
These only exist in equity.67 A restrictive covenant is an agreement between
parties that restricts the holder of an estate in land in his use of the land. 68
The most important aspect for present purposes is that restrictive covenants
must be negative in the sense that they can only entail an obligation for the
holder of the servient tenement not to use his property in a certain way.69 It
cannot contain a positive obligation for the holder of the servient tenement
to do something with or on the property, 70 nor can it contain a right for the
holder of the dominant tenement to do something with or on the servient
tenement.
This makes it somewhat difficult to visualise a restrictive covenant
through the System-Cube, because it has no content for the ‘active side’, ie
the right holder of the dominant tenement, in the sense that the latter can
do something with or on the servient tenement. Restrictive covenants do not
grant a right to the freeholder of the dominant tenement to use or take
something from the servient tenement and therefore have a ‘negative’
content for the freeholder of the dominant tenement. They do, however,
make an addition to the freehold of the dominant tenement.71 For instance,
if a restrictive covenant is created to prevent the owner of the servient
tenement from developing the land, then that essentially adds the development value of the servient tenement to the dominant tenement.72 Therefore,
while the System-Cube cannot visualise the content of a restrictive covenant
as such—since it has only a negative content—it can visualise the fact that a
restrictive covenant forms an addition to the freehold of the dominant
tenement. The result would be as in Figure 4.
The minor cube in the front, marked with horizontal stripes, represents the
dominant tenement, which is an immovable object. The two minor cubes
behind it marked with an ? represent the freehold of the dominant tenement.
66
This section pertains only to freehold covenants, not to leasehold covenants.
Law of Property Act 1925, s 1; Dixon (n 64) 340.
Tulk v Moxhay (1848) 2 Ph 774.
69
Rhone v Stephens [1994] UKHL 3. See also McFarlane, Hopkins and Nield
(n 53) 928–32.
70
Unless it is made as part of a lease: Akkermans
(n 41) 364.
71
cf McFarlane, Hopkins and Nield (n 53) 923 and 926.
72
Lawson and Rudden (n 44) 156–7.
67
68
606
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies
VOL. 37
Figure 4. A Restrictive Covenant on Land
Neither the object nor the freehold is limited in time, which is why no time
cubes have been removed. The column of minor cubes at the back represents
the restrictive covenant that is attached to the freehold of the dominant
tenement. It is also unlimited in time.
D. A Few Words on Limitations
Property rights are subject to a variety of limitations. Some of these are internal
to the operating system, in the sense that the operating system itself limits
rather than facilitates the use of property rights. Rules on third party effects
can limit the use of property rights in that they prohibit their exigibility against
certain parties in certain circumstances. Other limitations are external to the
operating system in that they flow from another area of law, are self-imposed,
or are factual or physical. One example of a limitation flowing from another
area of law would be environmental law restricting the use of land for certain
purposes. Leasehold covenants agreed upon between landlord and tenant could
constitute self-imposed limitations, limiting the landlord in her use of her fee
simple estate and/or limiting the tenant in her use of her lease. Factual or
physical limitations could arise, for instance, from the nature of an object itself.
An owner of emission trading rights is not allowed, under Dutch law, to pledge
them.73 This is a result of the nature of emission rights: once they are used
73
At art16.42(3), the Dutch law implementing the Directive states: ‘In derogation from article 228 of book 3
of the Civil Code a right of pledge cannot be created on an emission right’ [translation ER].
AUTUMN 2017
What is Property Law?
607
they dissipate and can no longer be used as collateral for a security right. All
these limitations, both those that are internal to the operating system and those
that are external to it, are to be separated from limitations that are inherent to
the property right itself. For instance, the holder of a right of pledge or a
charge is allowed to seize the pledged or charged object and sell it, but she is
not allowed to use it for herself. This is because a pledge or charge is inherently
limited to these powers—it is in the nature of a pledge or charge that it only
conveys the powers of possession and sale. Similarly with a right of way: it
grants the holder the right to cross over another person’s land, but it does not
include the right to plant a tree on that person’s land, or to walk into that
person’s home and watch television on their sofa.
4. The Border between Property Law and Adjacent Areas of Law
Having set out what property law is and how it might be represented visually,
the next question to be addressed is how to define the border between property
law and adjacent areas of law. As indicated previously,74 the rules currently
included in the operating system are the bare minimum necessary to allow
property rights to function. Without rules on acquisition, we would be unable
to create or transfer property rights; without rules on extinction or destruction,
we might be stuck with property rights which no longer serve any useful
purpose; and without rules on third party effects, the whole point of property
rights—that we can rely on them erga omne—would be negated. These
operating rules are therefore without a doubt part of property law. Then there
are various areas of law, the rules of which are undoubtedly not part of property
law, such as criminal law or immigration law. However, in between the heart of
property law and these clearly non-property law rules lies a large grey area of
rules that could be, but do not necessarily have to be, part of property law.
These rules are found in areas of law that are closely adjacent to property law
but are nevertheless considered to be separate. These are primarily contract
law, tort law, certain areas of public law—particularly environmental law and
zoning law—constitutional law, insolvency law and succession law. Each of
these areas of law has a specific relationship to property law:
(a) contract law is the generator or enabler of property law—the majority of
proprietary relationships are founded on a contractual agreement: for
instance, a usufruct, easement or charge will exist because parties have
decided to create one, and every time a sale of goods takes place (which
is likely to be billions of times a day) ownership passes from one person
to the next;75
74
Section 2.
This is, of course, not to say that proprietary relationships cannot arise outside the realm of contracts, such
as through necessity, adverse possession, marriage or succession, but those will be in the minority.
75
608
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies
VOL. 37
(b) tort law is the enforcer of property law, for instance through the tort of
trespass; this is not to say that property law is without enforcement
mechanisms of its own—we only need to point out the reivindicatio—but
tort law adds to property law’s arsenal for enforcement of property rights;76
(c) insolvency law is the mediator of property law—it attempts to achieve a
balance between various property (and contractual) rights in case the
party against whom these rights are claimed has gone insolvent and
possesses insufficient property to satisfy all claims;
(d) succession law is a facilitator of property law—it provides a mechanism
through which property can be transferred either automatically or in
accordance with someone’s last will in the very specific case of
distribution of property upon death;
(e) public law (environmental law, zoning law . . .) often acts as a limiter or
constrainer—it places limits on what people may do with their property
rights in order to protect other interests than merely those of the right
holder, such as clean air or soil, or the even distribution of businesses
and private homes within a given area;
(f) constitutional law functions on the one hand as a protector of property
rights, but it also shapes property rights. It protects property rights
through provisions such as article 1 of Protocol 1 to the European
Convention on Human Rights and through various national constitutions.77 It shapes property rights through, for instance, article 17 of the
Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union78 which defines
the right to property as ‘the right to own, use, dispose of and bequeath
his or her lawfully acquired possessions’.79
These relationships between property law and adjacent areas of law can be
depicted as in Figure 5.
This image is property-law-centric for the purposes of this article, but it
would of course be possible to centre a different area of law and draw a similar
image depicting its interactions with other areas of law.80
76
It might be said that criminal law can also act as an enforcer of property law, but that would not be entirely
correct since a criminal procedure could only lead to a fine or a prison sentence. It would not deal with the
return, replacement or repair of any property stolen and/or damaged.
77
Eg art 14 of the German Constitution, s 25 of the South African Constitution, the Takings Clause of the
Fifth Amendment of the US Constitution.
78
[2000] OJ C364/01.
79
cf national definitions of ownership: art 544 of the French civil code: ‘La propriété est le droit de jouir et
disposer des choses de la manière la plus absolue, pourvu qu’on n’en fasse pas un usage prohibé par les lois ou
par les règlements’ (‘Ownership is the right to enjoy and dispose of objects [choses] in the most absolute manner,
provided they are not used in a way prohibited by statutes or regulations’); §903 of the German civil code: ‘Der
Eigentümer einer Sache kann, soweit nicht das Gesetz oder Rechte Dritter entgegenstehen, mit der Sache nach
Belieben verfahren und andere von jeder Einriwking ausschließen’ (‘The owner of an object can, when this is not
contrary to the law or the rights of third parties, do with the object what he wishes and exclude others from
exercising influence’). Both translations from Kornet and Hardt (n 38).
80
If one were to do so, then of course the role of those areas of law would be more than that of, say, mediator or
facilitator, but in the present context they have been given those descriptions from a property-law-centric point of
view.
AUTUMN 2017
What is Property Law?
609
Figure 5. Property Law and Adjacent Areas of Law
Now that we have seen how property law interacts with adjacent areas of law,
we can consider the question of how to draw the line between property law and
other areas. Of particular contention has always been the separation between
property law and contract law. It is often said that, for instance, German
property law is ‘narrower’ than French property law because German property
law only applies to physical tangible objects,81 whereas French property law
also applies to intangibles.82 It is said that, in German law, intangibles fall
solely within the realm of contract law. It is then concluded that German law
and French law draw the border between property law and contract law
81
See n 38.
French civil code, art 516: ‘Tous les biens sont meubles ou immeubles’ (‘All things are movable or
immovable’); art 526: ‘Sont immeubles, par l’objet auquel ils s’appliquent: L’usufruit des choses immobilières;
Les servitudes ou services fonciers; Les actions qui tendent à revendiquer un immeuble’ (‘Immovable are,
through the object to which they apply: the right of usufruct of immovable objects; servitudes or easements;
actions to revindicate an immovable’), translations from Kornet and Hardt (n 38); art 529: ‘Sont meubles par la
détermination de la loi les obligations et actions qui ont pour objet des sommes exigibles ou des effets mobiliers,
les actions ou intérêts dans les compagnies de finance, de commerce ou d’industrie, encore que des immeubles
dépendant de ces entreprises appartiennent aux compagnies. Ces actions ou intérêts sont réputés meubles à
l’égard de chaque associé seulement, tant que dure la société. Sont aussi meubles par la détermination de la loi
les rentes perpétuelles ou viagères, soit sur l’Etat, soit sur des particuliers’ (‘Obligations and actions having as
their object sums due or movable effects, shares, or interests in financial, commercial, or industrial concerns,
even where immovables depending on these enterprises belong to the concerns, are movables by operation of law.
Those shares or interests shall be deemed movables with regard to each shareholder only, as long as the concern
lasts. Perpetual or life annuities, either from the State or private individuals, are also movables by operation of
law’), translation from <http://legifrance.gouv.fr/Traductions/en-English/Legifrance-translations>.
82
610
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies
VOL. 37
differently.83 This conclusion is, however, questionable, and not just because
there is an internal inconsistency in German law in that ownership of
intangibles is rejected, though it is possible to hold other property rights, such
as a right of pledge, in an intangible.84 If the abstract description of these two
areas of law is that property law is the ‘law of things’ and contract law is the
‘law of persons’, meaning that property law governs person–thing relationships
and contract law governs person–person relationships, then allocation of a
specific rule to either the realm of property law or the realm of contract law
depends on whether that rule regulates a person–thing relationship or a
person–person relationship. Tinkering with the term ‘things’ so as to include or
exclude intangibles does not mean that person–thing rules are suddenly no
longer person–thing rules but have become person–person rules; all it means is
that the scope of application of the person–thing rules is perhaps more limited in
legal systems that exclude intangibles from the definition of things than it is in
legal systems that include intangibles in the definition of things. A rule stating
how an easement can be extinguished is still a rule of property law (or a
person–thing rule), even though it is limited to a certain category of property
or ‘thing’, namely land, and does not apply to cars or shares. In other words,
the only difference caused by the (partial) removal of intangibles from the
realm of property law is that, to refer back to the System-Cube model, there is
one type of object fewer in relation to which (some) property rights can be
held. This does not, however, make the property rights or the operating rules
within the system as such any less proprietary.
5. What is EU Property Law?
Having discussed the broader question of what property law is, I will now focus
on the more specific question of what EU property law is. The following
sections will discuss how the nature of EU law affects its definition of property
law and how it draws the line between property and contract law. They will
also explain how EU (property) law impacts our national conceptions of
property law. We will see that EU property law is not only generated very
differently from national property law, but also that its fragmented state can
cause difficulties for the more systematised national property laws.
A. Competing Conceptions of Property Law
The premise of the question ‘What is property law?’ is that there is an area of
law called property law or that such an area of law can be distinguished from
83
JHM van Erp, ‘DCFR and Property Law: The Need for Consistency and Coherence’ in R Schulze (ed),
Common Frame of Reference and Existing EC Contract Law (2nd rev edn, Sellier. European Law Publishers 2009)
262–3.
84
The same inconsistency is present in Dutch law: van Erp and Akkermans (n 11) 382.
AUTUMN 2017
What is Property Law?
611
other areas of law.85 If one accepts this premise, it is entirely appropriate to ask
the question of what property law is. Within our own domestic systems of law
we are very much used to categorising the law along the lines of public and
private law, with further subdivisions such as constitutional and administrative
law, and property, tort and contract law. At the same time, a comparison of
national private law systems shows that these categories are not set in stone:
English law distinguishes between land law, trusts and personal property,
whereas civil law systems would generally treat all of these under the single
heading of property law. The Dutch civil code, although it contains separate
books on property law (goederenrecht) and the law of obligations
(verbintenissenrecht), also contains a book on ‘patrimonial law’ (vermogensrecht),
which acts as an overarching structure for the books on property and
obligations. Hence, all property law is patrimonial law, but not all patrimonial
law is property law. Similarly the German civil code: Book 1 is called General
Part (Allgemeiner Teil) and provides an overarching structure. It is followed by
Book 2 on the Law of Obligation Relationships (Recht der Schuldverhältnisse)
and Book 3 on Property Law (Sachenrecht). Still, despite these variations in the
traditional categories of private law, they are still recognisable as property law,
contract law, etc.
Not so with EU law. EU law is unique in the sense that it does not follow
these national categories of law. It is competence-driven, meaning that it
regulates certain topics, such as competition, agriculture or free movement.
The only legal basis to be found in the Treaties that explicitly refers to a
category of law that we would recognise from the perspective of national law is
article 81(2)(c) of the Treaty on the Functioning of the European Union
(TFEU), which gives the European legislature the competence to regulate
matters concerning conflict of laws. There are no legal bases for property law,
contract law, tort law, etc. There would also be no point in defining the EU’s
legal bases in this way, because each Member State has a different conception
of what these areas of law entail.
The consequence of this competence-driven legislation is that it produces
rules which some national lawyers might call property law, whereas others
might call them contract law, insolvency law or environmental law. Therefore,
while the question ‘What is property law?’ may be a valid one in a domestic
context, it is in a way irrelevant in the European context. The fact that national
conceptions of property law vary does not really pose a problem for EU law
given that it is generally not concerned with such categorisation. Conversely,
the nature of EU law may cause problems for national conceptions of property
law. EU law takes supremacy over national law in case the two conflict.86
What, then, would happen to the national conceptions of property law if there
85
86
See the introduction.
Case 6/64 Costa v ENEL ECLI:EU:C:1964:66.
612
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies
VOL. 37
were an EU conception of property law? The answer to this question depends
on how a European-autonomous definition of property law (and of property
concepts such as ownership, transfer, immovable) were to be formed. It might
be formed completely independently of the national conceptions, in which case
there might be more of a discrepancy between the European and national
definitions. However, the CJEU often draws inspiration from a comparison of
the national legal systems in order to form a European definition.87 Where this
is the case, there may be more overlap with national definitions and therefore
fewer problems. It must be pointed out, though, that the CJEU will not
necessarily adopt the highest common denominator amongst the legal systems
of the Member States. If a definition is found among a minority of Member
States that fits better within the overall framework of EU law, the CJEU might
adopt that one.88 After all, the EU’s raison d’être is different from that of a state
and it will adopt concepts in line with its aims. The extent of the impact of EU
law on national property law is therefore not necessarily different for civil law
systems than for common law systems, even though common law systems are
in the minority within the EU.
B. Drawing the Line between EU Property Law and Other Areas of EU
Private Law
Occasionally, the European legislature has tried to press its laws into the
moulds of national categories of law, but with dubious consequences. It has
been very active in the development of European contract law, particularly
contracts for the sale of goods and consumer contracts. Two measures that
have resulted from this process should be mentioned: the Consumer Credit
Directive89 and the Consumer Rights Directive.90 It was decided for each that
they should only regulate contractual aspects and not proprietary aspects.91 For
the Consumer Credit Directive, this means that any aspects of a credit
agreement for residential property that are governed by property law and land
registration are not covered by the directive and remain to be regulated by
national law.92 For the Consumer Rights Directive, this means that it has
chosen for the passing of risk to occur upon delivery of the goods and not upon
the time of conclusion of the contract,93 which seems to be in line with a
traditional system of transfer rather than a consensual one and may cause
difficulties for those national legal systems that follow a consensual system and
87
Ramaekers (n 4) ch 1, s 2.1.1.
Ramaekers (n 4) ch 1, s 2.1.1.
Directive 2014/17/EU on credit agreements for consumers relating to residential immovable property
[2014] OJ L60/34.
90
Directive 2011/83/EU on consumer rights [2011] OJ L304/64.
91
Preamble to Directive 2014/17/EU on consumer credit agreements, Recital 9; Preamble to Directive 2011/
83/EU on consumer rights, Recital 51.
92
Preamble to Directive 2014/17/EU, Recital 9.
93
Directive 2011/83/EU on consumer rights, art 20.
88
89
AUTUMN 2017
What is Property Law?
613
do not make this distinction between delivery and transfer.94 At the same time,
and seemingly contradictorily, the Consumer Rights Directive also purports to
leave the determination of the conditions for the transfer of the ownership of
the goods subject to national law.95 Both these measures seem to be
unsuccessful attempts to fit European law into national categories of law. As
with all other European legislation—to the extent that it requires implementing
measures by the Member States—the Member States will decide themselves
whether the European measure is incorporated into what they consider to be
property law or contract law. There therefore does not seem to be much point
in European law trying to label itself along the lines of national categories,
other than trying to make it look more recognisable to national lawyers,
perhaps.
C. Changes to National Property Law
Even when European law is not trying to market itself as, for example, contract
or property law, it can nevertheless cause the boundaries between various areas
of law to fade and it may change the nature of what we think property law (or
any other area of law) is. The application of internal market law may mean that
certain rules of property law will have to be altered or will no longer be allowed
to exist whenever they directly or indirectly, actually or potentially hinder free
movement within the internal market.96 Directives may be implemented in
such a way that their various elements are dispersed throughout different parts
of national civil codes, making them ever more interconnected on the one
hand, but also blurring the lines between the various parts of the civil codes on
the other hand. If we were to express this impact that EU (property) law has
on national property law through the System-Cube model presented in section
2 of this article, we would see that almost all aspects of property law are
touched upon in some way.
To start with, EU law maintains its own, European-autonomous definition of
‘rights in rem’. It held in Lieber v Göbel that ‘[t]he difference between a right in
rem and a right in personam is that the former, existing in an item of property,
has effect against the whole world, whereas the latter can only be claimed
against the debtor’.97 Furthermore, it has developed its own classification of
objects.98 It distinguishes between immovable, movable and intangible
94
LPW van Vliet, Transfer of Movables in German, French, English and Dutch Law (Ars Aequi Libri 2000) 23.
Preamble to Directive 2011/83/EU on consumer rights, Recital 51.
Case 8/74 Procureur du Roi v Dassonville [1974] ECR 837, [5]; B Akkermans and E Ramaekers, ‘Free
Movement of Goods and Property Law’ (2013) 19 European Law Journal 237, 240–8.
97
Case C-292/93 Norbert Lieber v Willi S Göbel and Siegrid Göbel [1994] ECR I-2535, [14]. This definition
was repeated in Case C-115/88 Reichert [1990] ECR I-27, [11] and in Case C-294/92 Webb v Webb [1994] ECR
I-1733, [15].
98
On CJEU case law concerning the classification of objects, see E Ramaekers, ‘Classification of Objects by
the European Court of Justice’ (2014) 39(4) European Law Review 447.
95
96
614
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies
VOL. 37
property,99 and accepts that all three are capable of forming the subject of
property rights. It has even introduced a number of intangible objects that can
be the subject of ‘rights in rem’ itself, such as the Community Trade Mark,100
the Community Design101 and the Greenhouse Gas Emission Allowance.102 It
has also dealt elaborately with the question of what an immovable is in the
context of the VAT Directive103 in cases on, amongst others, caravans and
mobile homes,104 prefabricated buildings105 and houseboats.106
EU law’s influence on what I have called the operating system of property
law has been less extensive. It does not really provide any rules on how
property rights might be created or transferred, although it does recognise that
a power to dispose is a prerequisite for the creation and transfer of property
rights.107 The Regulation on the Community Trade Mark provides one—and
to my knowledge the only—example where registration plays a crucial role, in
that a Community Trade Mark cannot be invoked against third parties unless it
has been registered.108 Rules concerning third party effects of property rights
feature a bit more prominently. The Community Trade Mark Regulation
establishes a ranking.109 The Insolvency Regulation grants property effect to
retention of title clauses—they can be invoked against third parties.110 The
Directive on the return of stolen cultural objects restricts the scope of national
third party protection rules.111 Under this directive stolen cultural objects can
be retrieved from parties who acquired them in good faith where otherwise
those parties would be protected exactly because they were in good faith.
Finally, several CJEU judgments on mortgage enforcement procedures have
altered the balance between debtor and creditor, weakening the powers of the
mortgagee.112 According to the Court, national courts must be able to provide
interim measures that will suspend mortgage enforcement proceedings while
the (un)fairness of clauses in the mortgage loan agreement is assessed, thereby
allowing the debtor to retain ownership of the property in the meantime.
Enabling national courts to assess the fairness of terms in the loan agreement
in turn allows them to strike out these terms if they find them to be in violation
99
See eg art 3 of Directive 2005/60/EC on the prevention of terrorist financing [2005] OJ L309/15: ‘(3)
‘‘property’’ means assets of every kind, whether corporeal or incorporeal, movable or immovable, tangible or
intangible, and legal documents or instruments in any form including electronic or digital, evidencing title to or
an interest in such assets’.
100
Regulation 207/2009/EC on the Community Trade Mark (codified version) [2009] OJ L78/1, art 19.
101
Regulation 6/2002/EC on Community Designs [2002] OJ L3/1, art 29.
102
Directive 2003/87/EC Establishing a Scheme for Greenhouse Gas Emission [2003] OJ L275/32, art 3.
103
Directive 2006/112/EC on Value Added Tax [2006] OJ L347/1.
104
Case C-60/96 Commission v France [1997] ECR I-3827.
105
Case C-315/00 Maierhofer [2003] ECR I-586.
106
Case C-532/11 Leichenich v Peffekoven [2012] ECR I-720.
107
Case C-117/06 Möllendorf [2007] ECR I-8361; Ramaekers (n 4) 159–60.
108
Regulation 207/2009/EC on the Community Trade Mark, arts 17(6) and 23(1).
109
art 29(2).
110
Regulation 1346/2000/EC on insolvency proceedings, art 7(1) and (2).
111
Directive 93/7/EEC on the return of stolen cultural objects, art 5.
112
See Case C-415/11 Mohamed Aziz v Catalunyacaixa EU:C:2013:164; Case C-169/14 Morcillo & Garcı́a
EU:C:2014:1388; Case C-34/13 Kušionová EU:C:2014:2189.
AUTUMN 2017
What is Property Law?
615
of the directive, thereby altering the relationship between debtor and creditor.
Consequently, rights in the property held by the debtor, creditor and possibly
third parties such as a tenant are directly affected by the CJEU’s intervention
in national mortgage enforcement proceedings.
It is unfortunate that there is hardly any sort of operating system to be found
in European law. If European-autonomous property rights were to be (further)
developed through legislation or case law, they would exist in a vacuum
because there would be no rules telling us how to create them, transfer them,
etc.113 That vacuum would be filled by the Member States’ own operating
systems. This could mean that a European property right created according to
the law of one Member State might not be recognised by another Member
State that applies a different set of criteria to the creation of property rights.
This, in turn, would make the existence of European-autonomous property
rights,114 which ought to operate in the same way in all Member States, rather
pointless.
In light of the above, the European version of the core of the System-Cube,
depicting the European system of property rights, looks like Figure 6.
The dotted lines indicate the areas that have not yet been filled in or are
insufficiently defined by the European acquis to draw any definite conclusions.
All in all, the impact of EU law on national property law has so far been
modest, although the CJEU’s case law on the VAT Directive has already led to
situations in which an object had to be considered immovable for the purposes
of EU law, even though it would have been considered movable under national
property law.115 The fact that Member States can no longer always determine
Figure 6. EU Property Law
113
See section 3.
I drafted a proposal for the creation of European-autonomous property rights previously: Ramaekers (n 4)
ch 6, s 5.
115
Ramaekers (n 98) 464.
114
616
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies
VOL. 37
whether an object is movable or immovable solely on the basis of their own
national law if a given situation falls within the scope of EU law seems
remarkable.
6. Conclusion
So what, in the end, is property law? And what is European property law? EU
law itself does not present us with an answer to that question that would be
similar to the definitions of property law described in section 1. EU property
law is currently not a mature, coherent system, nor is it based on any clear
policy.116 It is therefore too soon to be able to discuss its theoretical
underpinnings in the same way as we can with national systems of property
law. As the System-Cube showed, there are still quite a few holes to fill in. The
only part of EU property law that is quite well established is that concerning
the definition of ‘things’. European legislation adopts a wide definition of
things (objects, assets, etc) in which one can have property rights. As we saw
earlier,117 immovable, movable and intangible objects are all included, the
determining factor being that they need to have some economic value. What is
less clear and needs more research is the extent to which EU law has adopted
its own definitions of individual property rights, eg ownership or lease. A
European-autonomous operating system is still mostly lacking. Furthermore,
the competence-driven nature of EU law makes attempts to draw the line
between EU property law and other areas of EU private law rather futile, since
categories such as property law, contract law and tort law are national
categories that are not generally employed in EU law.118
To return, then, to the primary question of this article, property law is a
system consisting of a core of property rights surrounded by a framework of
rules—the operating system—that regulate the acquisition, registration, destruction and third party effects of those property rights. These rules are
essential to a system of property law; without them, property rights would exist
in a vacuum in that it would not be possible to use them in any way. The
operating rules are to property rights what the operating system on your tablet
is to your apps. Beyond these four categories of operating rules there is a grey
area of rules that could be, but do not necessarily have to be, part of property
law, such as contract law, succession or insolvency law. It is within this grey
area that we see the differences between national systems of property law
emerge, with some systems, for example, relegating intangibles to the realm of
contract law whereas others include them within property law.
116
For a more detailed description of the current state of EU property law, see E Ramaekers, ‘The
Development of EU Property Law’ (2015) 23(3) European Review of Private Law 433.
117
See above section 3.B.
118
And as we have seen, when the European legislature does try to press EU law into these categories the
results can be dubious—see above, section 4.B.
AUTUMN 2017
What is Property Law?
617
Within this grey area we also find rules that limit property law pur sang:
environmental law and zoning law, for instance, may limit us in our use of our
property. In addition, limitations are inherent to the system of property law
itself. Sometimes they flow from the operating system, eg where a property
right is only exigible between parties to a transfer but not against a third party
without registration. Limitations are often also part of a property right itself. A
usufruct, for instance, gives its holder the right to use and enjoy the property,
but not to transfer ownership of the property to a third party.
The System-Cube model of property law presented in this article was
originally developed in order to research the existence and content of EU
property law. It is therefore primarily based on comparative research into
European legal systems. Future research will investigate to what extent it can
be applied to non-European systems of property law and to property
‘entitlements’119 that have developed outside the realm of private law.120
119
As opposed to the traditional property rights a private lawyer would expect to find within the numerus
clausus.
120
eg rights to land or to intangibles such as pensions, which have been developed in constitutional and
human rights law.
Copyright of Oxford Journal of Legal Studies is the property of Oxford University Press /
USA and its content may not be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv
without the copyright holder's express written permission. However, users may print,
download, or email articles for individual use.