Angelaki
Journal of the Theoretical Humanities
ISSN: (Print) (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cang20
MACHINE AND ECOLOGY
Yuk Hui
To cite this article: Yuk Hui (2020) MACHINE AND ECOLOGY, Angelaki, 25:4, 54-66, DOI:
10.1080/0969725X.2020.1790835
To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2020.1790835
Published online: 06 Aug 2020.
Submit your article to this journal
View related articles
View Crossmark data
Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at
https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=cang20
ANGELAKI
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 25 number 4 august 2020
1 introduction
It might very well still take a considerable
time to recognize that the “organism” and
the “organic” present themselves as the
mechanistic-technological “triumph” of
modernity over the domain of growth,
“nature.” (Martin Heidegger, Ponderings
XII–XV)
[…] We lack creation. We lack resistance to
the present. The creation of concepts in itself
calls for a future form, for a new earth and
people that do not yet exist. Europeanization
does not constitute a becoming but merely
the history of capitalism, which prevents
the becoming of subjected peoples.
(Deleuze and Guattari, What is Philosophy?)
The river is the locality of the locale of the
home. The river at the same time determines
the becoming of human beings as historical
in their being at home. The river is the wandering of that journey in which the becoming
of being at home has its essence. (Martin Heidegger, Hölderlin’s Hymne “Der Ister”)
T
his article titled “Machine and Ecology”
hopes to investigate the relation between
machine and ecology, and the philosophical
and historical questions concealed in these two
seemingly incompatible terms. First of all, I
want to problematize these two ambiguous
terms, “machine” and “ecology,” as a preparation to de-familiarize and de-romanticize
certain ideas about techno-ecology, and to
suggest a political ecology of machines, which
will center around what I term technodiversity.
This quest for technodiversity belongs to a systematic inquiry of my thesis on cosmotechnics
in The Question Concerning Technology in
China (2016), which argues against certain
yuk hui
MACHINE AND
ECOLOGY
traditions of philosophy, anthropology and
history of technology, and suggests that
instead of taking for granted an anthropologically universal concept of technics, one should
conceive a multiplicity of technics, characterized by different dynamics between the
cosmic, the moral and the technical.
Conventionally, one tends to think that
machines and ecology are opposed to one
another, because machines are artificial and
mechanical while ecology is natural and
organic. We may call this a dualism of critique
(instead of a critique of dualism), since its
mode of critique is based on the setting up of
binaries, which it fails to go beyond, like the
unhappy consciousness. This opposition has
ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/20/040054-13 © 2020 Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis
Group
https://doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2020.1790835
54
hui
resulted from some stereotypes concerning the
status of machines. Even today when people
talk about machines they tend to think of
mechanistic machines based on linear causality,
for example, the digesting duck designed by the
technician Jacques Vaucanson or the mechanical Turk by Wolfgang von Kempelen in the
eighteenth century; and when they talk about
ecology they tend to think of nature as a self-regulating system, which gives everything and
takes back everything.
2 after the overcoming of dualism
The above-mentioned notions of machine and
ecology undermine both the history of technology and the history of philosophy, therefore
they also ignore the technical reality which conditions the validity of such a criticism. Criticism
based on dualism fails to understand itself historically and critically. The mechanistic view
of machines was already completely surpassed
and rendered obsolete by cybernetics in the
mid-twentieth century; instead, we have witnessed the emergence of a mechano-organicism.
Today cybernetics becomes the modus operandi
in machines ranging from smartphones to
robotics and spacecraft. The rise of cybernetics
was one of the major events in the twentieth
century. Different from mechanism, which is
based on linear causality, e.g., A–B–C, it rests
on a circular causality, e.g., A–B–C–A′ ,
meaning that it is reflective in the basic sense
that it is able to determine itself in the form
of a recursive structure. By recursion we mean
a non-linear reflective movement which progressively moves towards its telos, be it predefined or auto-posited. Cybernetics belongs to
a larger paradigm in the sciences, namely,
organicism, which originated from the criticism
against mechanism as a fundamental ontological
understanding. Organicism also has to be distinguished from vitalism, which often relies on a
mysterious (separate, immaterial) “vital force”
to explain the existence of a living being;
instead, it finds its foundation in mathematics.
Cybernetics, as one form of organicism,
mobilizes two key concepts, feedback and information, to analyze the behavior of all beings,
55
both animate (living) and inanimate (lifeless),
and both nature and society. In the first
chapter of his Cybernetics: Or Control and
Communication in the Animal and the
Machine (1948), the founder of cybernetics,
Norbert Wiener, first reiterated an opposition
between Newtonian time and Bergsonian time.
Newtonian motion is mechanistic, and timesymmetric, hence reversible, while Bergsonian
time is organic, biological, creative and irreversible. It is not until the Second Law of Thermodynamics, proposed by the French physicist
Sadi Carnot in 1824 (almost a century after
Newton’s death in 1727), that we recognize the
“arrow of time” in being and the fact that the
so-called entropy of a system increases with
time and is irreversible. Already in his first
book Essai sur les donné es immé diates de la
conscience (1889), Bergson launched a fierce
attack on the way in which time was conceptualized in Western science and philosophy. Time is
here understood in terms of space, for example,
in terms of intervals which can be represented in
space. Therefore, the time that was thus conceptualized is actually timeless according to
Bergson. It is also homogenuous, like the intervals marked on a clock. Instead, organic time or
duré e, Bergson suggested, cannot be fully
understood as extension ordered in spatial
terms, rather it contains heterogeneity or qualitative multiplicity in organic forms. Time is a
force which is singular in every instant, like
Heraclitus’s river; it doesn’t repeat itself twice
like a mechanical clock. Indeed, mechanical or
linear causality doesn’t exist in correct duration.
Bergsonian “organic” time also provides a new
way to understand human consciousness and
experience.
Wiener proposed that such opposition was
already surpassed by the discovery of statistical
mechanics in physics. For example, considering
a container of particles, with statistical mechanics it is possible to communicate between
the macrostate and the microstates, therefore,
to control the behavior of the system. In other
words, cybernetics endeavors to eliminate
dualism, it wants to create a connection
between different orders of magnitude, macro
and micro, mind and body, like what Hans
machine and ecology
Jonas says in his Phenomenon of Life regarding
cybernetics, “an overcoming of the dualism
which classical materials had left in possession
by default: for the first time since Aristotelianism we would have a unified doctrine, or at
least a unified conceptual scheme, for the representation of reality” (111). The same observation was made in Gilbert Simondon’s On the
Mode of Existence of Technical Objects
(2012), where he considers the reflexive thinking of cybernetics (characterized by feedback
and information) as key to the resolution of
the dualism intrinsic in culture: traditional
and modern, rural and urban, major (adult)
and minor (child) modes of technology education, etc. In Recursivity and Contingency
(2019), I put feedback under a more general category: recursivity. Recursion in general designates a non-linear operation which constantly
returns to itself in order to know and determine
itself. There are different modalities of recursions, but they all share the overcoming of
dualism. Information is the measurement of
the degree of organization, feedback is a recursive or circular causality which allows auto-regulation to take place. For example, when reaching
my arm to grasp a bottle of water, many feedback processes are taking place, which allows
me to adjust the attention of my eyes and the
muscles of my arms until I reach the destination, or the telos. Therefore, towards the end
of this chapter, Wiener was able to claim that:
The modern automation exists in the same
sort of Bergsonian time as the living organism, and here there is no reason in Bergson’s
considerations why the essential mode of
functioning of the living organism should
not be the same as that of the automation
of this type […] In fact, the whole mechanist–vitalist controversy has been relegated
to the limbo of badly posed questions. (44)
Whether the claim of Norbert Wiener can be
completely justified has to be scrutinized
under the light of history. However, it remains
significant for us to reconceptualize what is happening today regarding the relation between
machine and organism, human and environment, technology and nature, departing from
Wiener’s cybernetics. Wiener’s bold statement
suggests a radical revaluation of the humanist
values which oppose the organic and the inorganic, and it also renders the humanist critique
ineffective. Different from what, for example,
André Leroi-Gourhan and Bernard Stiegler
might call “organized inorganic,” Wiener’s
focus was not the man–machine or man–tool
hybrid, but rather the possibility of assimilating
both the organic and the inorganic by cybernetic
machines. Modern machines are all cybernetic
machines: they all employ circular causality as
their principle of operation. In this sense, a
cybernetic machine is no longer merely mechanistic, but rather assimilates certain behaviors of
organisms. It is important to bear in mind that
resemblance doesn’t mean equivalence, and it is
this misunderstanding that dominates our contemporary politics of machines today.
Ecology is equally a concept charged with
ambiguity. If ecology is rooted in an attempt
to understand the relation between the living
being and its milieu, as it is in the case of
Ernst Haeckel in the nineteenth century and is
continued in the early twentieth century by
Jakob von Uexkü ll, we have to bear in mind
that this discourse remains important but insufficient to understand the complexity which
belongs to human societies. Jacob von Uexkü ll
has furthered Haeckel’s concept of ecology to
show that the environment is not only that
which selects according to its physicality (in
this respect Haeckel remains a Darwinian),
but also that which is selected and internalized
by the living being. The first type of selection
may be called adaptation, meaning that the
living being has to adapt itself to the milieu
according to the available resources and physical
conditions; the second type of selection may be
called adoption, meaning that the living being
has to select and to construct contexts from
what is available to it as means of survival.
The tick, an arachnid without eyes, remains
inactive from its position on a tree, and only
by detecting the smell of butyric acid (sweat),
wind and warmth – which signify the approaching of a mammal – it falls down in order to
attach to the animal’s body, to reach the skin
and then to suck its blood. There is a semiotics
56
hui
in the process of selection of information, based
on the Bauplan, the sensorium and the central
nervous system of the animal, which in turn
defines its Umwelt (von Uexkü ll 50–51).
However, human beings are not ticks, they
invent tools and change the environment.
They are beings talented not only with adapting
to the external environment but also with changing and adopting that environment itself
through technical means. In these processes of
adaptation and adoption, we see that there is a
reciprocity between the living being and its
environment, which we can also call its organicity, namely, the fact that they do not only
exchange information, energy and matter but
also constitute a community. A human community is far beyond the sum of the human actors
that constitute it, it also includes their environment and other non-human beings.
The intervention of human beings in the
environment defines the process of hominization, the evolutionary and historical becominghuman and its politics. It is beyond our capacity
to outline this process, however, human civilization could be seen as an intimate and complicit
relation between humans and their environment, which gives rise to what is called mesology since Plato (according to Augustin
Berque’s historiography). However, to cut it
short to the subject at hand, let us interrupt
with a verdict from Marshall McLuhan, who
said in an interview from 1974 that:
Sputnik created a new environment for the
planet. For the first time the natural world
was completely enclosed in a man-made container. At the moment that the Earth went
inside this new artifact, Nature ended and
Ecology was born. “Ecological” thinking
became inevitable as soon as the planet
moved up into the status of a work of art. (49)
This verdict of McLuhan has to be further analyzed. The 1957 event, namely, the launch of
Sputnik by the Soviet Union, is the first time
that human beings were able to ponder upon
the earth from the outside, and in this respect,
the earth is now principally viewed as an artifact
with the aid of space technology. In The Human
Condition, Hanna Arendt also describes the
57
1957 launch of Sputnik as “second in importance to no other, not even to the splitting of
the atom,” because it suggests, like what Konstantin Tsiolkovsky said, that “mankind will
not remain bound to the earth forever.” This
liberation from the earth directly confronts
humankind with the infinite universe and prepares for a cosmic nihilism. It is the moment
that nature ended and ecology was born. In contrast to the meaning that Ernst Haeckel gave to
the term ecology towards the end of the nineteenth century meaning the totality of relations
between a living being and its environment (2:
286–87; see also Richards 8), as well as to von
Uexkü ll’s definition of it as the selection
process from the Umgebung (physical environment) to the Umwelt (the “interpretation” of
the world by the living being), what McLuhan
meant by ecology is no longer a biological
concept. According to McLuhan, the earth is
considered to be a cybernetic system monitored
and governed by the machines upon it and in
outer space. What we witness is the disappearance of the earth, since it is continuously
absorbed into a plane of immanence constructed
by the recursive thinking of cybernetics.
The hybridism between the natural environment and machines constitutes a gigantic
system, and it is in this conceptualization that
nature ended and ecology began. Ecology,
beyond its strict use in biology,1 is not a
concept of nature but rather a concept of cybernetics. This is more evident when we refer to the
notion of Gaia coined by James Lovelock to
describe the ecological system of the earth: “a
cybernetic system with homeostatic tendencies
as detected by chemical anomalies in the
Earth’s atmosphere” (142). So we quickly
arrived here at the position that the modern
machine is no longer mechanistic and ecology
is nothing natural; in fact, modern machines
and ecology are two discourses adhering to the
same principle, namely, cybernetics. The difference being, if we insist, that we have moved
from individual machines, for example, those
automatic machines in the factories of nineteenth-century Manchester described by Marx,
to technical systems which connect different
machines and establish recursivity between
machine and ecology
them. These systems can take different scales,
from a local network to a planetary system
such as the earth’s technosphere. Now we
want to ask what could be the implications of
this redefinition of (the relation between)
machine and ecology.
3 technological becoming of
geophilosophy
We are more than ever in an epoch of cybernetics, since cybernetics was not a discipline
parallel to other disciplines such as philosophy
and psychology, but rather it aimed to be a universal discipline, able to unite all other disciplines, therefore, we could say, a universal
(mode of) thinking par excellence. Cybernetics
as a universal reflexive thinking has displaced
the role formerly always played by philosophy
as reflexive thinking. This displacement is not
a rejection of philosophy, but rather, in the parlance of Martin Heidegger, the completion or
end of philosophy (the German word Ende signifies both completion and end). What does
this end mean? Does it mean that Western philosophy has no more role to play in the technological age, since it is already completed in it
as its destiny? Or does it mean that philosophy
in order to survive will have to reinvent itself,
namely, to become a post-European (or postmetaphysical, post-ontological as you like) philosophy, and this is also no exception for Europe
itself? I do not want to open a Pandora’s box
here, but I simply want to point out that cybernetic thinking as an alleged universal and ecological thinking is that which sublates, or at
least pretends to sublate, the traditional metaphysical dualisms in ontology and epistemology,
and it is in this respect that it calls forward a
new condition of philosophizing, and therefore
a new inquiry into the question of ecology.
Here is the postulation: maybe it is no longer
a dualism which is the source of danger in our
epoch, but rather a non-dualistic totalizing
power present in modern technology, which
ironically resonates with the anti-dualist ideology (e.g., rejection of any comparison between
the East and the West). Ironically, because the
anti-dualist ideology still believes that the
main danger is dualism, without realizing that
this duality is no longer the foundation of
modern science and technology. In other
words, without having examined this intimate
relation between philosophy and technology, it
will be difficult, if not impossible, to develop a
philosophical thinking contemporary to our
situation.
Now, let’s bring our skepticism to the fore
and pursue the argument further: will cybernetics be the solution to the ecological problems
that we face today? Will the organismic model at
the heart of cybernetics be able to overcome the
shadow that European modernity has cast on us
for centuries? If the early moderns provide us a
mechanistic view of the world through geometrization (Kepler, Galileo, Newton, Descartes
among others) and experimental science
(Bacon and Boyles), now with cybernetics as
the realization and concretization of organismic
thought which started culminating since the end
of the eighteenth century, can we finally terminate modernity with cybernetics? Don’t we
already find in cybernetics, and its planetary
version, the Gaia theory, a generic logic that
rests on the recognition of the relation
between the living being and its milieu, that
which the philosopher and orientalist Augustin
Berque has emphasized in many places?
To overcome the modern alternative is to
recognize that the structural moment of our
existence – our mediance – is such that
each of us is split: “half” (in Latin, medietas,
hence mediance) in one’s individual animal
body, while the other “half” consists of the
eco-technical-symbolic system that is our
life milieu. (Berque 60)
Berque has been endeavoring to propose a
non-binary thinking that he found in Japanese
thought or Eastern thought in general, and
opposed it to the modern thought of which Cartesian dualism is the spokesperson. However, let
us not rush to an answer because we may fall
victim to the dualism of critique that we discussed above. Instead, let’s consider the epigraph from Heidegger at the opening of this
article concerning the relation between
58
hui
organism and technology. Heidegger saw that
this becoming organic, or becoming ecological,
is no more than the mechanistic-technological
triumph of modernity over nature. This statement has to be accessed beyond the cynical
impression that one may have at first glance.
Heidegger’s critique of cybernetics deserves
our reflection today, since it is not about the celebration of the overcoming of dualism, but
rather serves a call for prudence [phronesis]
and a warning to avert from illusions and false
analysis. Because at first glance, one may be
able to claim that cybernetics has fulfilled an
anti-dualistic critique of modernity. I would
like to suggest, or even better to provoke, that
with the rise of cybernetics and its organismic
model, we may need a new agenda for mesology.
We will have to understand this by rethinking
the relation between technology and the
environment. Instead of seeing technology as a
result of the determination by the geographical
milieu or that the natural milieu is destroyed
by technology, one cannot neglect how the technology–environment complex constitutes its
own genesis and autonomy, and how such
genesis could be rethought or resituated in a
cosmic reality which is proper to the milieu or
fûdo (風土) in the sense of the Japanese philosopher Tetsurō Watsuji. We will elaborate on this
point towards the end of the article.
To be brief – and this will deserve much more
detailed analysis for sure in the future – this
technological–environmental complex could be
understood in two senses which are seemingly
different yet remain intimately related. First
of all, it is what the paleoanthropologist André
Leroi-Gourhan terms technical milieu (Milieu
340–50). The technical milieu is that which
acts as a membrane between the internal
milieu conceived as an unstable and dynamic
“mental tradition,” and the external milieu consisting of the climate, natural resources and the
influences of other tribal groups (334–35).
Leroi-Gourhan uses the cell as an organic metaphor to explain the relation between these three
terms and the permeability and resistance
against technical tendencies. The technical
milieu is that which is produced by the irreducible differences between the internal and
59
external milieus, while at the same time it
filters and diffuses what comes from the external
milieu so that it can maintain the consistency of
the internal milieu. In other words, the internal
milieu and the external milieu form a reciprocal
relation through the mediation of the technical
milieu.
The second sense concerns a techno-geographical milieu, a term coined by Gilbert
Simondon. It literally means that the geographical milieu including natural resources is no
longer simply an object of exploitation but is
rather integrated into the functioning of the
technical object. In On the Mode of Existence
of Technical Objects, Simondon gives us the
famous example of the Guimbal turbine which
successfully integrates the river as both the
driving force (of an engine wrapped by oil
under high pressure) and the cooling agent
(57–58). In this case, the functionality of the
river is multiplied, it becomes an organ belonging to the technical objects; the river is also what
Simondon calls an associated milieu which provides a feedback mechanism for stabilizing and
regulating the dynamic system: the stronger
the current, the faster the turbine moves. Theoretically, more heat is produced which may burn
the engine, while since the current is also fast,
the heat can be more effectively carried away.
The river and the turbine thus form a technoenvironmental complex.
Both Leroi-Gourhan and Simondon were
influenced by the metaphor of the organism in
their conceptualization of the technical milieu
and the associated milieu. This aspiration to
an organismic or holistic model was a significant
intellectual movement of their time. The role of
the technical milieu in Leroi-Gourhan as a membrane between the internal and external milieus,
was similar to what Simondon calls associated
milieu, with the difference that Leroi-Gourhan
still wants to single out the technical from the
cultural (internal) and natural (external), while
in the scheme of Simondon such distinctions
have already disappeared. Simondon calls it a
techno-geographical milieu (this is also the
reason why Simondon was able to conceive of
a conceptual plan for overcoming the antagonism between culture and nature, nature and
machine and ecology
technology, culture and technology). Simondon’s interpretation of the significance of the
Guimbal engine and the notion of the associated
milieu was very much influenced by Wiener’s
cybernetics; and the reflective logic in cybernetics seems to Simondon to have displaced
philosophy; and it is from this point that we
can understand Heidegger’s claim that cybernetics marks the end of philosophy. The river
of Simondon stands in a peculiar relation to
what Heidegger says in The Question Concerning Technology about the hydroelectric plant
in the Rhine river, where the river becomes a
mere standing reserve, to be constantly challenged and exploited by modern technology
(16). Peculiar because at first glance, Simondon’s formulation of the river as a techno-geographical milieu expresses an optimism, while
Heidegger’s description of the Rhine river as
standing reserve is, though not necessarily pessimistic, a critique against the “technization” of
phusis; however, they both refer to the same
end of philosophy but with two different
attitudes.
The emphasis of Simondon for what concerns
the Guimbal engine is not simply about the
exploitation of the river, but also it demonstrates a reciprocity between the technological
and the natural, or what Simondon himself
calls “co-naturality.” The reciprocal and communal structure demonstrated by the Guimbal
engine is only one case of the cybernetic thinking to which Simondon aspires for the overcoming of dualism or its more aggressive form,
antagonism between culture and technology,
nature and technology. After cybernetics,
especially with the notion of “structural coupling” from biologists Hubertus Maturana and
Francisco Varela, the technical functionality of
the river described by Simondon seems to be
present as a generic model of the techno-geographical complex. Environment is not only
that which is modified by technology, but
rather it is also more and more constituted by
technology. Ecological thinking is not simply
about protecting nature, but fundamentally a
political thought based on environments and
territories. Technology’s increasing capacity to
participate in the modulation of the
environment forces us to develop a geophilosophy. This is by no means a new discovery,
however, it is essential to analyze this historical
trajectory in order to understand the stake of
technological development today:
(1) The relation between the human and the
environment is complexified in the
course of time and the semiotics that
defines perception and interpretation has
to be constantly updated according to
the evolution of technical objects in the
sense of Simondon. The continuity and
discontinuity from biological sensory
detection, to the display of signs and
symbols, and to the invention of electronic
sensors that gradually cover the urban and
rural area today entails a technological trajectory which constantly defines and redefines human and nature, which Peter
Sloterdijk might term the domestication
of human beings (89).
(2) The technology which is used for the domestication of livestock is fundamentally a
modulation of the relation between livestock and its environment; or in other
words, human beings intervene into the
environment by controlling its fertility
and sterility in order to modulate the behavior of the livestock on a large scale.
Human communities maintain an apparent autonomy through the invention of
laws, customs and symbolic systems
which define taboos and transgressions.
These constitute social norms and therefore also its opposite, social inadaptability,
which is central to Michel Foucault’s
analysis.
(3) The technology of livestock domestication
has gradually merged with the self-domestication of the human being, which may be
understood in terms of what Foucault calls
governmentality. Human beings’ intervention into the environment constitutes
a specific kind of governmentality which
Foucault calls environmentality. At the
beginning of this environmental thinking,
we see that, and here I quote Foucault,
“the population is the object that
60
hui
government must take into account in all
its observations and knowledge [savoir],
in order to be able to govern effectively
in a rational and conscious manner” (217).
(4) The control of population represents a
molar type of governmentality which
treats human beings in large quantities,
therefore its technique can only be
implemented through the mediation of
laws and regulations which treat each
subject as an equal and particular being.
Technological inventions since the twentieth century supplement this molar mode
of control with a molecular mode,
meaning that each human being is
treated as an individual, which differs
from other individuals. Such an individual
is defined by the relation between the individual and its environment constantly captured and capitalized in the form of data.
This form of governmentality has
become dominant during the coronavirus
pandemic.
The generalization of recursive algorithms
and its implementation in digital computers
concretize cybernetic thinking and its applications in almost all social, economical and political domains. Capital moves from a
mechanistic model accurately observed by
Marx towards an organismic model realized by
informational machines equipped with
complex recursive algorithms. Data is the
source of information, it is that which allows
the recursive models to be ubiquitous and effective. The digital urbanism that is in the process
of developing and which will be the central
theme of the digital economy, is driven by the
recursive operation of data. Data, in Latin,
means something which is already given, like
sense data that determines the falling of the
tick or the red color of the apple in front of
me; since the mid-twentieth century, data has
acquired a new meaning, namely, computational
information, which is no longer “given” from
without, but is rather produced and modulated
by human beings (Hui, Digital Objects 48). In
this sense, we can see that the notion of
“societies of control” described by Gilles
61
Deleuze is far beyond the common discourse
of a society of surveillance, it rather means
societies whose governmentality is based on
the auto-positing and auto-regulation of automatic systems. These systems vary in scale: it
can be a global corporation like Google, a city
like London, a nation state like China and also
the whole planet.
4 ecology of machines
Here we would like to return to the question
raised earlier: is cybernetics and its continuation
in the twenty-first century via the systems
theory of Niklas Luhmann et al. already a
response to the critique of industrialism which
inherited the dualistic tendency of early
modern thought, like what Ludwig von Bertalanffy once outlined in his 1936 General
System Theory that:
The mechanical world view, taking the play
of physical particles as ultimate reality
found its expression in a civilization which
glorifies physical technology that has led
eventually to the catastrophes of our time.
Possibly the model of the world as a great
organization can help to reinforce the sense
of reverence for the living which we have
almost lost in the last sanguinary decades of
human history? (49)
With the becoming reflective of cybernetic
machines, is it possible to surpass modernity
and hence the epistemologies which accompany
it? Or is the generic model suggested by cybernetics for overcoming dualism still within the
paradigm of modernity, as Heidegger suggested
in the 1930s? What does it mean to be still
within the paradigm of modernity? It means, I
suggest, that it undermines the necessity of
locality and diversity because it insists upon a
universal episteme and upon the concept of
progress.
Although it is true that machines are becoming organismic, it is in the permanent process of
“becoming” as Simondon has observed, no
matter how concrete a technical object is, that
it still retains reminiscences of abstract
schemes, while a living being is always already
machine and ecology
completely concrete. It is within the parallax
between the “not being completely concrete”
and the illusion of being able to replace
nature with digital informational technology
that we find the question of politics today.
The former remains a humanist critique while
the latter is rather transhumanist. Heidegger’s
response is neither humanist nor transhumanist, but rather, according to our interpretation,
local. Being for Heidegger is a notion specific
to a locality, which is called the land of the
evening [Abendland]; not at least from a linguistic point of view, the concept of being
didn’t have its correspondence in Chinese
language and thought (Graham 322–59). We
could find it in his reading of Hö lderlin’s
hymn “Der Ister,” in which the river is conceived as both locality [Ortschaft] and wandering (or journeying) [Wanderschaft] at its
origin (Heidegger, Hölderlin’s Hymn 30). The
river, which is the external milieu for LeroiGourhan and the associated milieu for Simondon, is the locality which is by default keeping
stationary, and it is the wandering which
moves forward. This seemingly contradictory
movement, forward and backward, constitutes
the historicity of “being there” (Da-sein).
However, the destiny of locality is not yet
clear in the technological epoch, and this ambiguity is the source of reactionary politics. It is
because the question of the truth of Being can
only take place in the danger brought about by
human’s frenzy for the gigantic, in the form of
an event of appropriation initiated by a “shock
of deep awe” (Schrecken der Scheu) (Heidegger,
Beiträge zur Philosophie 8). However, shall one
wait for this eschatology to happen, or should
one instead take other paths which don’t
follow the history of Western thought as long
as the universal has to be contested? It is the
question of Being which Heidegger wants to
explore that brings us back to the question of
locality and historicity. The claim that with
the invention of network technology, there is a
compression of time and space sometimes prevents us from seeing what has always been
already there and beyond. Indeed, one of the
major failures of the twentieth century is the
inability to articulate the relation between
locality and technology and the reliance on an
almost standardized ecological thinking
endowed with a strong European humanism;
technology became a provocation of either reactionary politics which is based on a dualism
between tradition and modernity or a fanatic
accelerationism which believes that the problems that we have and have inherited will
finally be resolved by technological advancement, be it geoengineering for repairing the
earth or the subversion of capitalism by accelerating towards full automation. From the economic and technocratic perspective, there is
very little value in taking locality into consideration besides for its relevance to the availability
of natural resources. The advancement of
network technology will speed up the spatial
compression and therefore there is no more
value to discuss what could be called “geographicality” since all exchanges are done at the
speed of light. This ignorance of the milieu is
also an ignorance of locality; it fails to establish
an intimate and complicit relation between the
earth seen from the perspective of the territory
and globalizing technology.
We still have to add why cybernetics is not
yet sufficient as a non-dualistic solution before
we arrive at understanding locality. The logic
of cybernetics remains formal; therefore, it
underestimates the milieu by reducing it to
mere functionality based on feedback so that
the milieu can be integrated into the operation
of the technical object. In this respect, the
milieu is exposed as a scientific and technological object, while its position within the genesis
of technicity is ignored. This is also why until
Part III of On the Mode of Existence of Technical Objects, Simondon declared that analysis
of the evolution of technical objects and the
analysis of the relation between the human
and technics are not sufficient to understand
technicity, and that it is necessary to situate
technical concretization within the genesis of
technicity, which means to relate technological
thought to other thoughts. Simondon’s unfinished project (judged from the standpoint of
cosmotechnics) suggests conceiving a genesis
starting with a magic phase which constantly
bifurcates, firstly into technics and religion,
62
hui
then in the second stage, each of them bifurcates
into the theoretical and practical part. Simondon understands technological development as
a constant entanglement with religious thinking, aesthetic thinking and philosophical thinking oscillating between technology’s exigency to
diverge and thinking’s necessity to converge.
Technicity means here the cosmo-geographical
specificity of technology and how such cosmogeographical particularity has participated in
shaping the technological mentality, which
includes understanding of technology, a sensibility towards matter, form and other forms of
existence, relation between art and spirit, etc.
It is also for this reason that Simondon’s
project has to be pursued further by looking
into the cosmological specificity of cultures.
For example, Tetsurō Watsuji has tried to
point out almost a century ago how the milieu
affects the way of seeing and painting. The Japanese word fûdo comes from the two Chinese
characters for wind (風) and soil (土). Watsuji
classifies three types of fûdo, namely,
monsoon, desert and meadow. To give brief
examples of Watsuji’s observations, he thinks
that, since Asia is heavily affected by monsoons,
the resulting relative lack of seasonal change
creates an easy-going personality. In Southeast
Asia especially, since the weather is always
very warm, nature provides a plenitude of foodstuffs, and therefore there is no need to labor
too much in order to survive, or to worry
about the possibility of day-to-day living. Similarly, he argues that the lack of natural resources
in the deserts of the Middle East creates solidarity between peoples, so that the Jewish people,
although they live in diaspora, remain united;
while in the meadowlands of Europe, clear and
regular seasonal changes demonstrate the constancy of the laws of nature, thus suggesting
the possibility of mastering nature with science.
This cosmological specificity gives rise to
different technics, for example, in Greece the
plenitude of sun and clear sky gives priority to
the form, while the obscure fûdo in Asia gave
rise to the style of haziness in painting
(Watsuji 90). Cosmo-geographicality constitutes
an important dimension of locality.
63
Cybernetic thinking remains a thinking of
totalization, since it aims to absorb the other
into itself, like Hegelian logic, which sees polarity
not as oppositional but rather as a motivation
towards synthesized identity. This is also why
the Hegelian and cybernetician Gotthard
Gü nther considers cybernetics fundamentally
the operational (technical) realization of Hegelian
reflexive – i.e., dialectical – logic (95). The complexification of cybernetic logic finally leads to an
absolute totality. Bearing this in mind, without
being able to reiterate Gü nther’s interpretation
of the place of Hegelian reflexive logic in cybernetics here,2 we can probably formulate our
claim as follows: to think beyond cybernetics is
to think beyond the totalizing effect of a nondualist thinking. In other words, how to reintroduce the question of locality into the discourse of
machine and ecology today? And how does this
reintroduction of locality contribute to the discourse on machines?
We are not opposing machine and ecology as
if machines are those things that only rape
Mother Nature and violate the harmony
between the human and nature, an image attributed to technology since the end of the eighteenth century. We must advance instead
towards an ecology of machines. Neither are
we following the Gaia theory that the earth is a
single super organism or a collectivity of organisms in line with the thought of James Lovelock
and Lynn Margulis. Instead, I would like to
propose to reflect on an ecology of machines.
To open this ecology of machines, we will
need first of all to go back to the concept of
ecology. The fundament of ecology is diversities, since it is only with biodiversities (or multispecies including all forms of organisms
including bacterial) that the ecological system
can be conceptualized. To discuss the ecology
of machines, we will need a different notion in
parallel to biodiversity, which we call technodiversity. Biodiversity is the correlate of technodiversity, since without technodiversity, we will
only witness the disappearing of species by a
homogenous rationality. Take the example of
pesticide, which is made to kill a certain
species of insects regardless of their
machine and ecology
geographical locations precisely because it is
based on chemical and biological analysis.
However, we know that the use of the same pesticide may lead to different disastrous consequences in different environments. Before the
invention of pesticide, there were different techniques employed to combat insects threatening
the harvest of agricultural products, for
example, natural resources found in the
region. Namely, there was a technodiversity
prior to the employment of pesticide as a universal solution. Pesticide is apparently more effective in the short term, but it is well established
today that we have been only looking at our toes
when we think about the distant future. We can
say that technodiversity is fundamentally a
question of locality. Locality doesn’t necessarily
mean ethnocentrism, nationalism or fascism,
but rather, it is that which forces us to rethink
the process of modernization and globalization
and allows us to reflect on the possibility to resituate modern technologies. Locality is also key
to conceive of a multiplicity of cosmotechnics.
Locality doesn’t mean identity politics here,
but rather the capacity to reflect on the technological becoming of the local, not to retreat to
traditionalism of one form or another, but
rather for multiple localities to invent their
own technological thought and future – an
immunology or rather immunologies yet to be
written.
What are the localities of non-European
countries such as Japan, China and Brazil,
today? Heidegger’s long exposition on the
relation between technology and Western philosophy is occidentally oriented. We should
take the term orientation in a literal sense
here, namely, as Erörterung, i.e., an identification as to where one is and as to what one
will become. It is in this sense that Heidegger
is also a thinker of geopolitics. To take up the
project of Heidegger, but also to go beyond
him today, is to carry his reflection beyond
Europe. I want to put this challenge into a
speculative question: for non-European cultures, can we identify their own technological
thought in the same way that they also have
different fûdo? Can these technological
thoughts contribute to the imagination of
technological futures, which are now unfortunately dominated by the transhumanist ideology? I tend to believe that it is possible and
necessary to rediscover different technologies,
which I call cosmotechnics. Cosmotechnics is
not simply about, different ways of making
things, for example, different techniques of
knitting or dyeing. I gave it a preliminary definition in The Question Concerning Technology
in China as the unification of the moral and the
cosmic through technical activities. The term
unification will have to be further elaborated,3
for our purpose here, cosmotechnics should be
understood as an Urtechnik, it challenges our
current understanding of technology and therefore also its future. This cosmological specificity
must be rethought beyond astral physics,
beyond the conceptualization of the universe
as a thermodynamic system; it also reopens
the question of moral beyond ethical rules
which are added posteriorly as constraints to
new technologies. Technical activities unify
the moral order and the cosmic order; and by
unification I mean reciprocal processes which
constantly enforce each other to acquire new
meanings. This is the reason why I wanted to
reinterpret what André Leroi-Gourhan calls
technical tendency and technical facts
(L’homme 27–35). Technical tendency is what
seems to be universal, like laws of nature, for
example, the use of flint to produce fire and
the invention of wheels for transportation
could be found in almost every civilization (we
rarely see any triangular wheels if only in our
imagination). Technical facts are the particular
features that vary from one civilization to
another; in the process of diffusion, technology
was filtered and modified according to constraints intrinsic to the internal milieu. For
Leroi-Gourhan, technical facts are determined
by numerous factors, but largely by material
constraints, while I tend to think that the differences in technical facts entails different cosmologies and their moral constraints, which
encompass far more than functional aesthetics.
I would like to conclude by picking up the biochemist-turned-sinologist Joseph Needham’s
question here, namely, why didn’t modern
science and technology develop in China and
64
hui
India but only in Europe? Historians who
attempt to answer this question tend to carry
out comparative studies on the advancement of
technology in Europe and China as if the
essence of technology concerns merely efficiency
and mechanical causalities: for example, papermaking in the second century in China was
more advanced than in Europe. However, this
line of inquiry, it seems to me, has betrayed
Needham’s own stance. This is so because
Needham was actually suggesting that there
were two different trajectories of technology in
China and in Europe, which were less constrained by material causes than by their different ways of thinking and forms of life. To put
it in other words: answering Needham’s question
is not to show who is more advanced than the
other, but rather to elaborate on the different
systems of technological thought. It is the
reason why The Question Concerning Technology in China was aiming to be a response to
Needham by taking his implicit thesis further.
The technological upheaval since the nineteenth century has presented us with a convergence which at times seems inevitable while at
the same time seems problematic and necessary
to be fragmented in favor of other forms of convergence. The inquiry into the relation between
machine and ecology is less about how to
design more intelligent machines, but rather
requires first of all a discovery of cosmotechnical
diversity, while such diversity has to be thought
through by going back to the question of locality,
therefore re-articulating the concept of technics
by resituating it within the geographical milieu,
culture and thinking. The task that is left to all
of us is the effort to rediscover these cosmotechnics in order to reframe modern technologies,
namely, by reframing the enframing [Gestell]; only through such a
reframing can we imagine a “new
earth and people that do not yet
exist” (Deleuze and Guattari
108).
disclosure statement
No potential conflict of interest was reported by
the author.
65
notes
1 Note that a lot of biologists use this term and it is
generally considered to be a biological discipline
studying relationships of biotic and abiotic elements.
2 For a more detailed analysis please see Hui,
Recursivity and Contingency, ch. 2.
3 I will elaborate on this notion of “unification” in
my forthcoming book Art and Cosmotechnics (Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, Nov. 2020).
bibliography
Arendt, Hanna. The Human Condition. Chicago:
Chicago UP, 1998. Print.
Bergson, Henri. Time and Free Will: An Essay on the
Immediate Data of Consciousness. London: Allen,
1913. Print.
Berque, Augustin. Thinking through Landscape.
Trans. Anne-Marie Feenberg-Dibon. London:
Routledge, 2014. Print.
Bertalanffy, Ludwig von. General System Theory.
New York: George Braziller, 2015. Print.
Deleuze, Gilles, and Félix Guattari. What is
Philosophy? Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Graham
Burchell. New York: Columbia UP, 1994. Print.
Foucault, Michel. Power: Essential Works of Foucault,
1954–1984. Ed. James D. Faubion. Trans. Robert
Hurley et al. New York: New, 2001. Print.
Graham, A.C. Studies in Chinese Philosophy and
Philosophical Literature. New York: SUNY, 1990.
Print.
Günther, Gotthard. Das Bewußtsein der Maschinen
Eine Metaphysik der Kybernetik. Baden-Baden: Agis,
1963. Print.
Haeckel, Ernst. Generelle Morphologie der
Organismen. Berlin: Georg Reimer, 1866. Print.
Heidegger, Martin. Beiträge zur Philosophie (vom
Ereigni). Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann,
1989. Print.
Heidegger, Martin. Hölderlin’s Hymn “The Ister.”
Trans. William McNeill and Julia Davis.
Indianapolis: Indiana UP, 1996. Print.
Heidegger, Martin. Ponderings XII–XV: Black
Notebooks 1939–1941. Trans. Richard Rojcewicz.
Indianapolis: Indiana UP, 2017. Print.
machine and ecology
Heidegger, Martin. The Question Concerning
Technology and Other Essays. Trans. William
Lovitt. New York: Garland, 1977. Print.
Hui, Yuk. On the Existence of Digital Objects.
Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2016. Print.
Hui, Yuk. The Question Concerning Technology in
China. An Essay in Cosmotechnics. Falmouth:
Urbanomic, 2016. Print.
Hui, Yuk. Recursivity and Contingency. London:
Rowman, 2019. Print.
Jonas, Hans. The Phenomenon of Life: Toward a
Philosophical Biology. Evanston: Northwestern UP,
2001. Print.
Leroi-Gourhan, André. L’homme et la Matieère.
Paris: Albin Michel, 1973. Print.
Leroi-Gourhan, André. Milieu et technique. Paris:
Albin Michel, 1973. Print.
Lovelock, James. Gaia: A New Look at Life on Earth.
Oxford: Oxford UP, 2000. Print.
McLuhan, Marshall. “At the Moment of Sputnik the
Planet Became a Global Theatre in which There
Are No Spectators but Only Actors.” Journal of
Communication 24.1 (1974): 48–58. Print.
Needham, Joseph. The Grand Titration: Science and
Society in East and West. London: Routledge,
2013. Print.
Richards, Robert J. The Tragic Sense of Life: Ernst
Haeckel and the Struggle over Evolutionary Thought.
Chicago: U of Chicago P, 2009. Print.
Simondon, Gilbert. On the Mode of Existence of
Technical Objects. Trans. Cecile Malaspina and
John Rogove. Minneapolis: Univocal, 2017. Print.
Sloterdijk, Peter. Not Saved: Essays after Heidegger.
Trans. Ian Alexander Moore and Christopher
Turner. Cambridge: Polity, 2017. Print.
Uexküll, Jakob von. A Foray into the Worlds of
Animals and Humans. With a Theory of Meaning.
Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2010. Print.
Watsuji, Tetsurō . Climate and Culture: A
Philosophical Study. Trans. Geoffrey Bownas.
Westport, CT: Greenwood, 1961. Print.
Wiener, Norbert. Cybernetics: Or Control and
Communication in the Animal and the Machine.
Cambridge, MA: MIT P, 1985. Print.
Yuk Hui
City University of Hong Kong
School of Creative Media
F/7 Run Shaw Creative Media Centre
18 Tat Hong Avenue
Kowloon
Hong Kong
E-mail: yukhui@cityu.edu.hk