Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                
Ethics and Action Theory: An Unhappy Divorce Final author version of paper forthcoming in (ed.) R. Teichmann, Oxford Handbook of Anscombe (Oxford University Press, 2021) Abstract This chapter compares the general form and state of moral philosophy during the first half of the twentieth century (§1) to how it stands today (§3). These two overviews serve as the bread of a GEMA-filled sandwich. In §2 I accordingly consider Anscombe’s criticisms of ‘modern moral philosophy’ from Sidgwick to Ross. Anyone in sympathy with the general line of her criticisms, I argue, must concede that the state of moral philosophy was in far better shape in the decades before she wrote her seminal 1958 paper than it has been ever since. Ironically, contemporary moral philosophy has become what it is partly due to Anscombe’s own unintended role in influencing (i) the formation of ‘virtue theory’ as yet another position within normative ethics, and (ii) the fashioning of ‘moral psychology’ as an altogether distinct—and increasingly empirical— branch of moral philosophy. 1. Moral Philosophy Until Anscombe In her seminal 1958 paper ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’ (MMP), Elizabeth Anscombe complains, inter alia, about the lack of ‘an adequate philosophy of psychology’ within moral philosophy, at least as practiced from Sidgwick onwards. While her complaint (which I review in detail in §2) was not without cause, it remains a striking fact that there was considerably more moral psychology within moral theory before 1957, than there has been ever since. Moreover, much of it was conducted by a number of Anscombe's explicit or implicit targets, particularly G.E. Moore (1903), W.D. Ross (1930) H.W.B. Joseph (1931), A.C. Ewing (1938), John Macmurray (1938), and H.A. Prichard (1949). 1 Anscombe presumably didn’t find 1 It has also been present, not merely in Aristotle (NE) and Aquinas (ST I–II,1–21), but across the entire history of any of this work ‘adequate’ and I shall try to show why this was so. Prima facie, however, her moral psychology and philosophy of action has much in common with many of the abovementioned targets, not to mention Hegel. In order to allow for sufficient depth of comparison, I shall focus my discussion on Ross, who is one of the explicit targets of MMP, but will add comparisons to other philosophers along the way. Ross defends the proto-Anscombean view that ‘any act may be correctly described in an indefinite, and in principle infinite, number of ways’ and that what I do could, for instance, be truthfully described as ‘fulfilling my promise’, ‘putting the book into our friend’s possession’, and ‘the packing and posting of a book’: [A]ny of the acts we do has countless effects […] Every act therefore, viewed in some aspects, will be prima facie right, and viewed in others prima facie wrong. […] any act may be correctly described in an indefinite, and in principle infinite, number of ways. An act is the production of a change in the state of affairs […]I may have promised, for instance, to return a book to a friend […] to send it by a messenger or to hand it to his servant or to send it by post...in each of these cases what I do directly is worthless in itself […]this is not what we should describe, strictly, as our duty; our duty is to fulfil our promise, i.e. to put the book into our friend's possession […] What I do is as truly describable in this way as by saying that it is the packing and posting of a book […] And if we ask ourselves whether it is right qua the packing or posting of a book, or qua the securing of my friend’s getting what I have promised to return to him, it is clear that it is in the second capacity that it is right […] by its own nature and not because of its consequences. (Ross, 1930: 41-4) modern moral philosophy from Suarez onwards (see essays in Sandis 2019c). The ‘Morality’ heading of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right (PR §§ 105-141) is of particular relevance to Anscombe’s interests. For comparisons between Hegel and Anscombe see Taylor (1979 & 1983), Quante (1993), and Sandis (2010). For Aquinas and Anscombe, see Jensen (2010). There is much here that anticipates Anscombe. She would later even apply the same preposition (‘qua’) to distinguish her view that actions may be intentional under a description from the nonsensical claim that actions-under-a-description are intentional (UD).2 So why did Anscombe dismiss Ross’ work in such strong terms? His ‘objectivism’ may have lapsed into a form of ‘consequentialism’ so anathematic to Christian morality (see §II) that she didn’t want to debate its details under the guise of doing ‘moral philosophy’,3 but this is not in itself a reason to dismiss an entire method of doing moral philosophy that is uncannily similar to her own. A clue to our answer may be found in an earlier passage of The Right and the Good. Ross writes: [G]reat confusion […] has been introduced into ethics by the phrase ‘a right action’ being used sometimes of the initiation of a certain change in the state of affairs irrespective of motive, and at other times of such initiation from some particular motive, such as sense of duty or benevolence. I would further suggest that additional clearness would be gained if we used ‘act’ of the thing done, the initiation of change, and ‘action’ of the doing of it, the initiating of change, from a certain motive. We should then talk of a right act but not of a right action, of a morally good action but not of a morally good act. And it may be added that the doing of a wrong act may be a morally good action; for ‘right’ and ‘wrong’ refer entirely to the thing done, ‘morally good’ and ‘morally bad’ entirely to the motive from which it is done. (Ross, 1930: 6-7; cf. Sidgwick, 1874: Book III, Ch. 12 and Macmurray, 1938) From all this he concludes, in a deliberately provocative and paradoxical manner: [N]othing that ought to be done is ever morally good […] the only acts that are morally good are those that proceed from a good motive […] 2 3 For the relation between Ross’ use of the conjunction and his ethic of prima facie duties see Ross (1930:29). Cf. Wiseman (2016b: 10-11). action from a good motive is never morally obligatory […] what is morally good is never right […] That action from a good motive is never obligatory follows from the Kantian principle […] that ‘I ought’ implies 'I can’. […] however carelessly I pack or dispatch the book, if it comes to hand I have done my duty, and however carefully I acted, if the book does not come to hand I have not done my duty. Of course I should deserve more praise in the second case than in the first. (Ross, 1930: 132) Anscombe has little time for this sort of distinction between what is done and the doing of it from a certain motive. She is consequently disinclined to relate the former to the right and the latter to the good, a disposition strengthened by her independent suspicion of the very distinction between good and right action (see §II). It is worth recalling, at this juncture, that Anscombe’s objection was not that moral philosophers lacked a philosophy of psychology or action per se, only that they were in desperate need of one that was ‘sound’, or at least ‘adequate’. The problem, at least from Anscombe’s point of view, is that Ross puts his multiple descriptions of action to the disingenuous use of swallowing up features that would normally be regarded as their consequences, thereby presenting them as intrinsic properties that are ‘utterly independent of consequences’: That which is right is right not because it is an act, one thing, which will produce another thing, an increase in general welfare, but because it is itself the producing of an increase in the general welfare […] we have to recognise the intrinsic rightness of a certain type of act, not depending on its consequences but on its own nature (Ross 1930:47; emphasis in original). Anscombe may have additionally found Ross' argument to the conclusion that an action that is good can never be right (and vice versa) to be 'unsound' because it fails to capture the correct relation between motive, intention, action, and duty. Whatever the explanation, she seems to have thrown the baby out with the bathwater. For there is a sound and morally important difference to be made between the things we do and our doings of them, especially in relation to questions concerning intention, foresight, consequences, and intrinsic wrongness.4 Ross’s point about the rightness of an action being divorceable from the goodness or badness of one’s performing is a sensible and important one, sharing affinities with Mill’s stance that ‘a right action does not necessarily indicate a virtuous character’ and that 'actions which are blameable often proceed from qualities entitled to praise'. (Mill, 1863: 18-20).5 Yet Anscombe’s view that the things we do are happenings or events (I §29, TKEA: 4, PJ: 10-11, UD: 208-210) with morally pertinent descriptions seems to leave no space for it. This is because it rules out the possibility that two people can do the very same thing, even though only of them is acting from a good motive. 6 In this she goes against her teacher, Wittgenstein, who cites this very possibility as an explanation for why selfunderstanding can be so difficult to achieve at times: It is hard to understand yourself properly since something that you might be doing out of generosity & goodness is the same as you may be doing out of cowardice or indifference. To be sure, one may act in such & such a way from true love, but also from deceitfulness & from a cold heart too (CV p. 54 [MS 131 38: 14.8.1946], my emphasis; cf. PI §§ 253-254). While Anscombe can allow that two people can do the same thing, she understands this as there being at least one description that is applicable to both deeds (e.g. ‘drinking gin’) though many may not be (e.g. acting cowardly or bravely). But while some descriptions of the things we do have our intention built into them (e.g. to lie is, at least typically, to say something untrue with the intention of deceiving), many do not. Moreover, motives—as opposed to intentions— lend themselves more naturally to descriptions of our doings and not 4 See Hornsby (1993). 5 For contrast see Kant (1788: 5, 147-148). 6 Strictly speaking, one could defend an identity theory between action-event and thing done while still allowing for the subtler distinction between one’s doing X and the event of one’s doing X (see Sandis, 2012: 33), but the stance seems eccentric. our deeds. 7 To be sure, in speaking loosely we may say that someone did a cowardly thing, but all this means is that they acted in a cowardly fashion; the thing they did (drink gin) is itself neither cowardly nor brave. A year after Ross’s book was published, Joseph wrote the following by way of commentary8: The same act, an objector might say, may surely be done from very different motives; and therefore the act must be something, irrespective of the motive. But are they really the same act? Different acts, having different motives, may work themselves into the same movements of bodies; but these are not the acts. A man who was fond of oysters might eat a plateful put before him for the sake of their flavour; a man who loathed them might do so to avoid hurting his host’s feelings; a man who loathed or was indifferent to them might do so to prevent his neighbour, whom he knew to be fond of them and he disliked, from having two portions. I think these are three different acts, one morally good or else kindly, one morally bad or spiteful, one indifferent. They are not three instances of one act, viz. eating a plateful of oysters […]an act proper is not analysable into behaviour and motive; it is indivisible (Joseph 1931:45-46).9 Joseph’s view anticipates Anscombe’s insofar as they both target Ross by maintaining that ‘no act exists except in the doing of it, and in the doing of it there is a motive’.10 The JosephAnscombe thesis offers a persuasive account of our doings, but ignores the distinction (implicit in Wittgenstein and explicit in Ross) between the deeds we do and our doings of them from 7 8 It is perhaps no accident that Ross’ discussion focuses much more on motives and Anscombe’s on intention. Earlier in the chapter, Joseph uses the location ‘it is said’ before discussing views now associated with Ross’ The Right and the Good (Joseph 1931:37), which appeared in print only after Joseph’s proofs had been corrected Joseph 1931:v).The revised 1933 edited adds a footnote to Ross’ book on p.19. 9 I owe this reference to Andreas Lind. 10 Joseph (1931:38). some particular motive. This is done at the cost of allowing that one may do the right thing from the wrong motive. One might object that ‘A did the same thing as B’ simply amounts to there being some description of what A did which is also true of what B did (e.g. ‘give money to X’, or ‘show off to his friends’). But it would be a category mistake to think that such descriptions apply to things done, as opposed to our doings of them. If A murdered X then we can indeed describe this very thing that A did by saying (with some loss in specificity) that A killed X, for the latter is a sub-set of the former. But if A gave money to X, we cannot truthfully describe the thing done (give money) as showing off, since one can do this very same thing without even intending to showing off in the process. A particular instance of giving money may be truthfully describable as showing off, but the things we do, in the sense in which two people can do the same thing, are not instances of anything. In the case of the person whose donating a large sum of money is a case of showing off, then, there is not one single thing done that is good under one description and bad under another but, rather, one event of someone acting badly in doing two distinct things (one right, the other wrong). Hursthouse writes: [A]ct honestly, charitably, generously; do not act dishonestly, etc. […] the adverbs connote not only doing what the virtuous agent would do, but also doing it ‘in the way’ she would do it, which includes ‘for the same sort(s) of reason(s)’ […] What is misleading about this phrase is that it obscures the fact that, in one way, the agent is not ‘doing the right thing’. What she is doing is, say, trying to impress the onlookers, or hurting someone's feelings, or avoiding punishment. (Hursthouse, 1999: 29, fn. 7 & 125) But while one’s act of donating to charity may also be correctly described as one’s trying to impress the onlookers, this doesn’t give us a reason to deny that in so acting a person may do (at least) two things: donate to charity and impress the onlookers, one of which is right and the other wrong. Anscombe can, of course, allow that one can donate to charity with the (bad) intention of impressing the onlookers. On her view, however, this provides a true description of what was done, thereby leaving no space for the view that one can do the right thing with a bad intention. This forces us to say that what was done was right under one description and wrong under another. But this is to confuse acting rightly with doing what happens to be the right thing to do, despite ones nefarious motives.11 In Ross’ terminology, it is to confuse such things as ‘doing what is just’ with such things acting ‘in the spirit of justice’ (Ross 1930:53). Anscombe’s underlying account of action as a happening contrasts with that of Prichard, according to whom to do something is to bring about a change: It is, no doubt, not easy to say what we mean by ‘an action’ or by ‘doing something’. Yet we have in the end to allow that we mean by it originating, causing, or bringing about the existence of something viz. some new state of an existing thing or substance, or, more shortly, causing a change of state of some existing things […] by ‘moving our hand’ we mean causing a change of place in our hand; by ‘posting a letter’ we mean bringing about that a letter is in a pillar-box. (Prichard, 1932: 84-85) The view outlined above anticipates those of G. H. von Wright (1963) and, more recently, Maria Alvarez and John Hyman (1998). By the end of World War II, however, Prichard had come to embrace a volitionist account of action as a form of mental activity (1945: 272-274).12 Contra Macmurray and Ross, he now claimed that the term ‘action’ was not ambiguous at all: it referred to our mental ‘doings’ and not to their effected changes, which constitute our ‘deeds’ (Ibid.: 275; cf. von Wright 1963: 37 ff.). Anscombe would have undoubtedly rejected Prichard’s invalid inference from the thought that we might conceivably fail to achieve anything we set out to do, to the conclusion that all we ever have a duty to do is to set ourselves (viz. will) to bring something about. Indeed, no adequate philosophy of psychology could ever allow for such an inference. But if, in uttering ‘I do what happens’, Anscombe had been running a million miles from Prichard’s volitionism, then she ended up too far in the other direction. 11 12 See Sandis (2017 & 2021). The general shape of Prichard’s account is retained in the early work of Jennifer Hornsby, who replaces willing with trying (1980: 46-48, 60-63; retracted in Hornsby, 2010). 2. ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’ MMP remains as divisive today as it was when it was first published sixty years ago. Some hail it to be of huge philosophical and historical importance, not least by effectively giving birth to neo-Aristotelian Virtue Ethics as exemplified by Philippa Foot, Rosalind Hursthouse, Alasdair MacIntyre, and John McDowell (Richter, 2011 Solomon, 2008: 110-111). Others present it as a dated or otherwise irritating text containing baffling and unsubstantiated claims, the deciphering of which is not worth the candle (e.g. Blackburn, 2005). One recurring complaint has been that Anscombe is unfair in dismissing the ideas of dead white men with brief statements that contain more disrespect than they do argument. Bishop Butler is ‘ignorant’ (MMP 27), Immanuel Kant ‘useless’ and ‘absurd’ (ibid.), David Hume ‘sophistical’ (MMP 28), and J.S. Mill ‘stupid’ (MMP 33). These are the philosophers she likes. The rest of them are something much worse: ‘consequentialists’. Anscombe uses the term in MMP as a pejorative13 , but it was quickly reclaimed as a badge of honour by all its major proponents. It is fashionable nowadays to remark that Anscombe meant something rather different by ‘consequentialism’ than we do today.14 Yet her own characterisation of it as the view that the “right” action is that which produces the best possible consequences (MMP 33, quoted below) is one endorsed by most contemporary consequentialists.15 The exegetical difficulty arises because Anscombe protects the utilitarian Mill from this particular charge yet includes ‘objectivists’ such as her near-contemporary W. D. Ross, best known for defending the view that actions can be wrong in virtue of their intrinsic value, regardless of their consequences: There is a startling change that seems to have taken place between Mill and Moore. Mill assumes […] that there is no question of calculating the particular consequences of an action such as murder or theft […] In 13 14 15 For an earlier coinage by her see BERKMAN in this volume, See, for example, Diamond (1997), Teichmann (2008: 86), and Wiseman (2017: 18). Cf. M. Geach (2008: xvii). Moore and in subsequent academic moralists of England we find it taken to be pretty obvious that "the right action" is the action which produces the best possible consequences (reckoning among consequences the intrinsic values ascribed to certain kinds of act by some “Objectivists”. (MMP 33)16 This double-move is key to understanding the last of three related theses that MMP famously sets out to defend. These have proven to be as hard to interpret as they are easy to state: T1) It is not profitable for us at present [1958] to do moral philosophy; that should be laid aside at any rate until we have an adequate philosophy of psychology, in which we are conspicuously lacking. T2) The concepts of obligation, and duty – moral obligation and moral duty, that is to say— and of what is morally right and wrong, and of the moral sense of “ought”, ought to be jettisoned if this is psychologically possible; because they are survivals, or derivatives from survivals, from an earlier conception of ethics which no longer survives, and are only harmful without it. T3) The differences between the well-known English writers on moral philosophy from Sidgwick to the present day are of little importance. Anscombe. (MMP 26)17 What makes T3 true for Anscombe is that the philosophers in question are all ‘consequentialists’. Henry Sidgwick’s predecessor, Mill, is off the hook from this charge for 16 Entire papers could be written about the degree to which this passage offers plausible interpretations of either Mill or Moore. There is room for disagreement, for example, on whether murder and theft could ever fall under Mill’s ‘knotty points’ (Mill, 1861: 25), the answer depending on whether he conceives of them as being unjust by definition (discussed further below). 17 CHAPPELL in this volume argues that Anscombe’s main complaint is T3 and that T1 and T2 are ‘little more than auxiliary theses’. two distinct reasons. First, he was careful (at least according to Anscombe) to distinguish intended from merely foreseen consequences of an action. To understand how this helps to avoid ‘consequentialism’, one needs the ‘adequate philosophy of psychology’ required to reveal the role played by intention in determining the nature of any given action.18 Second, Mill explicitly states that utilitarianism can never conflict with justice, going out of his way to explain why his philosophy is compatible with Christian morality in particular (Mill, 1861: 27). He thus allows that utilitarianism lead us to re-evaluate whether acts of stealing or kidnapping must always be unjust, while rejecting the consequentialist conviction that an unjust act could ever be permissible, let alone obligatory: Have mankind been under a delusion in thinking that justice is a more sacred thing than policy, and that the latter ought only to be listened to after the former has been satisfied? While I dispute the pretensions of any theory which sets up an imaginary standard of justice not grounded on utility, I account the justice which is grounded on utility to be the chief part, and incomparably the most sacred and binding part, of all morality. Justice is a name for certain classes of moral rules which concern the essentials of human well-being more nearly, and are therefore of more absolute obligation, than any other rules for the guidance of life […] to save a life, it may not only be allowable, but a duty, to steal or take by force the necessary food or medicine, or to kidnap and compel to officiate the only qualified medical practitioner. In such cases, as we do not call anything justice which is not a virtue, we usually say, not that justice must give way to some other moral principle, but that what is just in ordinary cases is, by reason of that other principle, not just in the particular case. By this useful accommodation of language, the character of indefeasibility attributed to justice is kept up, and we are saved from the 18 This is partly because Anscombe primarily conceives of ‘consequentialism’ as a view regarding the sphere of personal responsibility (see Frey, 2019: 10-12). For more on Mill’s anti-consequentialist utilitarianism see Vogler (2001). necessity of maintaining that there can be laudable injustice. (Mill, 1861: 57-58 & 62) Is Mill paying mere lip service to justice here or does he take the thickness of the concept to entail that no plausible moral theory can be at odds with it? In not counting him as a ‘consequentialist’, Anscombe charitably opts for the latter understanding viz. that he would give no weight to unjust actions, no matter what their effects: Mill assumes, as we saw [27], that there is no question of calculating particular consequences of an action such as murder or theft. (MMP 33) Yet Mill’s view ultimately seems to be that any action prescribed by utilitarianism must be just by definition. If so, Anscombe would be wrong in her assessment that ‘it did not occur to him that acts of murder and theft could be otherwise described’ (MMP 27). Indeed, we may plausibly attribute to Mill the view that some thefts are just precisely because they can be described as the taking of necessary food or medicine. On this point, the difference between Mill and someone like Aquinas is more semantic than it is moral. Unlike Mill, Aquinas maintains that all theft is unjust, but he also asserts that in cases of dire emergency it is not theft to take from another’s possessions: When a person is in extreme need of material things, and there is no way of emerging from his extremity but by taking what belongs to another, the surplus which another possesses becomes common property, and the taker is not guilty of theft. (ST, IIaIIae.66.7) 19 Anscombe’s evaluation of Mill contrasts starkly with that of Ross, according to whom any ‘intrinsic’ property of action, including that of being unjust, may in principle be outweighed by sufficiently positive consequences: 19 I owe this reference to Sophie Grace Chappell. Oxford Objectivists of course distinguish between ‘consequences’ and ‘intrinsic values’ and so produce a misleading appearance of not being consequentialists. But they do not hold – and Ross explicitly denies – that the gravity of, e.g., procuring the condemnation of the innocent is such that it cannot be outweighed by, e.g., national interest. Hence their distinction is of no importance. (MMP 33, f.n. 4.) So understood, Ross allows that there are times when, all things considered, we are not only permitted but morally obliged to commit acts of murder, adultery, or whatever. Anscombe rejects his thesis that there is no value so sacred that it cannot in principle be trumped by the greater good as being ‘consequentialist’, despite the fact that Ross’ ethic of prima facie duties explicitly allows that goods of beneficence and non-maleficence are often outweighed by concerns of fidelity, gratitude, justice, (Ross 1930:21ff.). As Christopher Coope has argued, she would have also rejected some of Hursthouse’s views on the same grounds.20 Despite her own definition, then, Anscombe cannot ultimately view ‘consequentialism’ as the simple equation of ‘rightness’ with producing the best consequences. As Mary Geach puts it, one might hold the ‘consequentialist’ view that ‘there is no act so bad [that] it might on occasion be justified by its consequences’ while rejecting the consequentialist view that ‘the right action is always that which produces the best consequences’ (M. Geach, 2008: xvii). In his 1956 article ‘Good and Evil’, Peter Geach denounces Ross’ moral outlook for very similar reasons. I quote at some length: I am deliberately ignoring the supposed distinction between the Right and the Good […] Aquinas […] finds it sufficient to talk of good and bad human acts. When Ross would say that there is a morally good action but not a right act, Aquinas would say that a good human intention had issued in what was, in fact, a bad action; and when Ross would say that there was a right act but not a morally good action, Aquinas would say that there was a bad human act performed in circumstances in which a similar act 20 Coope (2006: 46 ff.) Whilst I agree with Coope on this point, I don’t share the conception of justice he uses to frame it. with a different intention would have been a good one (e.g. giving money to a beggar for the praise of men rather than for the relief of his misery) […] [P]eople who think that doing right is something other than doing good will regard virtuous behaviour as consisting, not just in doing good and eschewing evil, but in doing, on every occasion, the right act for the occasion. This speciously strict doctrine leads in fact to quite laxist consequences. A man […] if he knows that adultery is an evil act, will decide that (as Aristotle says) there can be no deliberating when or how or with whom to commit adultery. But a man who believes in discerning, on each occasion, the right act for the occasion, may well decide that on this occasion, all things considered, adultery is the right action. Sir David Ross explicitly tells us that on occasion the right act may be the judicial punishment of an innocent man "that the whole nation perish not" for in this case “the prima facie duty of consulting the general interest has proved more obligatory than the perfectly distinct prima facie duty of respecting the rights of those who have respected the rights of others.” (P. Geach, 1956: 41-42)21 Geach’s outing of Ross as a crypto-consequentialist is, of course, directly linked to T3.22 His further rejection of Ross’ distinction between goodness and rightness is closely tied to Anscombe’s other two theses. In particular, his contention that we should make do without the concept of a ‘right action’ at all helps to explain why Anscombe keeps “the right action” within scare quotes. It also sheds light on her middle thesis (T2) that we must try to jettison 21 To this he sneeringly adds: ‘We must charitably hope that for him the words of Caiaphas that he quotes just had the vaguely hallowed associations of a Bible text, and that he did not remember whose judicial murder was being counselled.’ 22 Geach and Anscombe would presumably be equally hostile to the moral particularist claim that there are no principles concerning right action (e.g. Dancy, 2004). But particularism at the level of things done may be combined with generalism at the level of character traits (Sandis, 2020, 2021; cf. Swanton, 2015). Were Anscombe open to a conceptual distinction between doings and things done (see §III) she could more easily allow for such a view, whose origins lie with Aristotle’s thought that the mean is grasped through perception and not by reasoning (EN 1109b; but see Price, 2005). the concept of a distinctly moral obligation. Terms like ‘moral obligation’ and ‘morally right action’ ought to be jettisoned because they are survivals of an earlier, quasi-legal conception of morality, and make no sense outside of the related contexts and practices that originally gave them meaning. This is not a rejection of morality, nor even of a moral ought, but only of the distinctively secular and mesmeric ‘moral ought’ that has been detached from the aforementioned conceptions.23 James Doyle (2018) has recently offered a more radical reading of T2. According to Doyle, Anscombe’s claim is that the term ‘moral’ as ordinarily used is literally meaningless, standing for an empty pseudo-concept that provokes a certain feeling in us but has no content whatsoever.24 Divine commands, on this understanding, neither describe nor create distinctly moral obligations, but only religious ones. Whatever the merits of the view itself (Doyle finds it more plausible than I do), we should be wary of it as an interpretation of what is going on in MMP, not least because there are plenty of later writings in which Anscombe endorses law conceptions of morality with no sign of having had the slightest change of mind. In ‘Authority in Morals’ (AM), Anscombe speaks of ‘moral conclusions’, ‘revelation of moral belief’, of a ‘moral truth’ concerning ‘what kinds of thing ought to be done and ought not to be done’ as well as of ‘the moral law’ as a ‘range’ and of taking one’s morality from someone else, concluding that ‘the content of moral law, i.e., the actions which are good and just, is not essentially a matter of revelation’. Similarly, in ‘The Moral Environment of the Child’, Anscombe states that ‘Catholic Christianity teaches a strict moral code’ and speaks, without scepticism, of ‘truth in the moral code’ and ‘our morality' (METC 231). This Christian morality is contrasted with ‘a morality which consisted solely of absolute prohibitions on fairly definitely described actions’ (presumably Kant’s). The idea of two contrasting moralities forms the core of her short essay 23 Cf. Solomon (2008: 114) and Gremaschi (2017), the latter finding Anscombe’s concerns much more parochial than the former. White (1968:77ff.) convincingly distinguishes between ‘obliged to do’ and ‘ought to do’. 24 Cf. Richter (2019). Doyle has since revised his view, but still maintains that Anscombe thought—and was right to think—that nothing could count as understanding the word ‘moral’ (Doyle, 2019). This goes against the more natural reading of Anscombe’s quasi-Nietzschean genealogy as having been at least partly motivated by Wittgenstein’s thought that the meaning of any given term or expression is dependent upon the practices that give it life (see Sandis, 2019a; cf. Frey, 2018). Wittgenstein’s influence on Anscombe’s understanding of normativity is further made evident in her discussions of forcing and stopping modals (PJ, RRP, SAS). ‘Morality’(1982), in which she explicitly rejects the thought that there is such a thing as morality, not because she is a sceptic about moral concepts—she writes that ‘human beings have always had morality’ and talks of ‘that part of morality which is associated with duties to God’ (M 113)—but because she finds Christian morality so distinct from the consequentialist one that they amount to two entirely different moralities: one that prohibits murder, and one that not only permits—but can even demand—it. As Mary Geach writes in a 2005 letter to the Times Literary Supplement,25 Anscombe herself, of course, had no intention of jettisoning the concepts of moral obligation and duty, which are needed to frame her other principal claim, which is that certain things are forbidden, whatever the consequences.’ While Christian morality does indeed require us to embody certain virtues, the question of which virtues we ought to have may also be addressed from the point of view of what is good for us, qua human. In pointing this out, Anscombe is in no way abandoning deontic terminology in favour of the aretaic (see Coope, 2006: 22). The deontic and the aretaic are simply two different frameworks for talking about the very same goodness. By returning to Aristotle’s talk of human excellence and virtue, MMP thus seeks to find a common language through which religious and secular thinkers alike (including Anscombe and her friend Philippa Foot) may converse about morality, and perhaps even reach agreement.26 3. Contemporary Normative Ethics Anscombe’s first thesis in MMP is that ‘[i]t is not profitable for us at present [1958] to do moral philosophy; that should be laid aside at any rate until we have an adequate philosophy of psychology, in which we are conspicuously lacking’ (MMP 26). By ‘philosophy of psychology’, she is not referring to the philosophy of cognitive science that currently goes 25 M. Geach (2005a; see also 2005b). 26 Anscombe became increasingly pessimistic about the latter happening on any kind of wide scale (see essays in GG1). Jennifer Frey informs me that Aquinas was far more sanguine on this front. under that name today,27 nor to the philosophy of mind that used to share it,28 but to an investigation into the concepts of action, character, intention, motive, desire, pleasure, and the relations between them: In present-day philosophy an explanation is required how an unjust man is a bad man, or an unjust action a bad one […] it cannot even be begun until we are equipped with a sound philosophy of psychology […] This part of the subject matter of ethics is, however, completely closed to us until we29 have an account of what type of characteristic a virtue is - a problem, not of ethics, but of conceptual analysis - and how it relates to the action in which it is instanced […] For this we certainly need an account at least of what a human action is at all, and how its description as "doing suchand-such" is affected by its motive and by the intention or intentions in it; and for this an account of such concepts is required (MMP 29).30 The blueprint for this philosophy of action had already been laid down by her the year before in her masterpiece Intention. This book had already made good on MMP’s request for ‘an account at least of what a human action is at all, and how its description as “doing such-andsuch” is affected by its motive and by the intention or intentions in it’ (MMP 29).31 Whether Anscombe herself thought she had already provided an adequate philosophy of psychology, or merely a sketch of one, is a moot point. The term ‘philosophy of psychology’ has long since been hijacked by philosophers of 27 See, for example, Botterill and Caruthers (1999), Bermúdez (2005), Thagard (2007), and Weiskopf and Adams (2015). 28 For example, Block (1980). 29 See Sandis (2019b). 30 Anscombe’s contention here remains unaffected by John Rawls’ famous argument for the independence of moral theory from the sorts of issues he associates with epistemology and the philosophy of mind and language (Rawls, 1975). But even if Rawls’ argument could be extended to show that many issues in moral theory are independent from philosophical psychology, we should not expect a theory of right action to remain silent on the relation of action to motive, intention, and consequence. 31 For an excellent account, see Wiseman (2016a: Ch. 2 & 2016b: §3). cognitive science to describe what they do, leaving ‘philosophical psychology’ as the term of choice for those still interested in asking philosophical questions about human psychology, and ‘moral psychology’ and ‘philosophy of action’ for the areas covering the kinds of issues that Anscombe is referring to. Indeed, both these fields owe part of their existence as we know it to Anscombe. In the aftermath of Intention and MMP, the ‘philosophy of action’ developed into a subject in its own right, albeit more closely associated with the philosophy of mind than with ethics.32 Such branching-off comes at a heavy price, for ethics without philosophy of action is blind, and philosophy of action without ethics empty. The philosophy of mind and action during the past sixty years has thus developed alongside that of normative ethics, with very little interaction between them. This has enabled philosophers to defend theories of ‘right action’ while remaining conspicuously silent about what actions are, or how to best conceive of their relation to intentions (on the one hand) and consequences (on the other). As a result of all this, contemporary moral philosophy has been neatly divided into the following four branches, which had yet to properly separate in 1958: a) Meta-ethics b) Normative Ethics (‘moral theory’) c) Practical or ‘applied’ ethics d) Moral Psychology To be sure, theorists debate the extent to which views within (a-d) are interrelated, but they are generally content to teach them as separate ‘modules’ and have been known to profess expertise in any one of the above while claiming near-ignorance on the remaining three. People do, of course, defend philosophical positions according to which one cannot do (c) without (b) and/or (b) without (a), but even these are parasitic on the divisions in question. Most importantly, (d) is typically reserved for questions relating to agency, motivation, moral responsibility, akrasia, and so on that are thought to be largely independent of (a-c). In complete opposition to this, MMP’s first thesis effectively tells us that one cannot do (a-c) at all without first doing (d). While Anscombe certainly cared for ‘practical’ issues relating to 32 For a brief period, philosophy of mind was also called ‘philosophy of psychology’ (see, for example, Block, 1980). everyday life as well as to medical, military, and legal policies, she did not see these issues as remotely separable from either moral philosophy or the philosophy of psychology.33 I shan’t concern myself much with (a) and (c), save to recall that the contemporary obsession of engaging in (c) by comparing intuitions about increasingly absurd trolley-cases is an unintended consequence of an argument made by Foot in which she defends, against Hare’s consequentialism, an original combination of the doctrine of double effect and the doctrine of doing and allowing.34 Anscombe would have been much more horrified by much of what falls under either of these ‘branches’ today than anything she was objecting to in 1958. Hardly any of it can be attributed as an effect of MMP though. This is not the case with (2) and (4), so I shall focus on these. I begin with some paradigmatic mainstream positions within normative ethics or ‘moral theory’: Act consequentialism is the claim that an act is morally right if and only if that act maximizes the good (Sinnott-Armstrong, 2015). An act is wrong if and only if it is forbidden by the code of rules whose internalization by the overwhelming majority of everyone everywhere in each new generation has maximum expected value in terms of well-being (Hooker, 2000: 32). [A]n act is wrong if it would be disallowed by any principle that no one could reasonably respect. (Scanlon, 1998: 197) 33 This is evident across all her work in ethics, but particularly so in TD (for which, see Wiseman 2016b). 34 Foot (1967: 23 ff.); for more context see Hacker-Wright (2013: 107-109) and Coope (2015). Anscombe anticipates and rejects a crucial component of trolley reasoning in MMP 40. Sixty years later, philosophy’s most prominent appearance in popular culture is in the trolley-obsessed The Good Place, in which one of central characters (Chidi Anagonye) is a ‘Professor of Ethics and Moral Philosophy’. The droll conjunction reminds me of the first time I taught ‘Ethics’ for Florida Institute of Technology’s study abroad programme at Oxford. All of the other professors introduced themselves as teaching courses ‘X’ and ‘Y’ to great enthusiasm from the students. But when I introduced myself as the lecturer for ‘Moral Philosophy’, I was greeted with baffled silence, until one of the students hesitantly asked ‘Do you mean “Ethics”?’, to all-round relief. An action is right iff it is what a virtuous agent would characteristically do in the circumstances. (Hursthouse, 1999: 17, see also 28–29) An act is wrong just when such acts are disallowed by the principles that are optimific, uniquely universally willable, and not reasonably rejectable. (Parfit, 2011: 413)35 What makes an action morally right is that it originates in a person’s good will. (Sullivan, 1989: 117) [D]eontologists think that acts are wrong because of the sorts of acts they are. (Davis, 1991: 210) 36 It’s hardly news that Anscombe would be particularly hostile to consequentialist theories, whose current division into several sub-species (act and rule focusing on actual, probable, expected, or intended consequences) has partly resulted as a response to some of Anscombe’s arguments in MMP and elsewhere. But what about deontology and virtue ethics? Surely, as a believer in Divine Command Theory and the view that some actions are absolutely prohibited, Anscombe could have no problem with deontology? And was MMP not striving towards a kind of virtue ethics? My answer to both these questions is a negative one. To begin with, the very issue of what all of the above theories are doing viz. attempt to provide accounts of ‘the right action’ is problematic, for two reasons. First, as we have already seen (§I), Anscombe follows Geach in being troubled by the very notion of an action being morally right or wrong, as opposed to good or bad. This worry relates to the larger question of what is meant by ‘action’ in the first place. Robert M. Adams expresses a commonplace certainty when he writes that ‘[w]hat every competent user of “wrong” must know about wrongness is, first of all, that wrongness is a property of actions (perhaps also of intentions and various attitudes, but certainly of actions)’ (Adams, 1979: 74). Accordingly, 35 The word ‘virtue’ cannot be found in any of the three volumes of Parfit’s On What Matters. 36 Andreas Lind has brought to my attention the fact that normative theories frequently conflate accounts of rightness conditions with accounts of right/wrong-making. normative theorists feel licensed to remain silent on the question of what an action is. In fact, it is shocking quite how little they are prepared to say on this topic. The optimistic assumption is that one can simply ‘plug in’ one’s favourite account of action, without this affecting the plausibility of the theory in question, let alone what it would even mean for an action to be right.37 One explanation for this might be that there is nothing to puzzle over here. As Prichard notes: The question ‘What is acting or doing something?’ seems at first unreal, i.e. a question to which we already know the answer. For it looks as though everyone knows what doing something is and would be ready to offer instances. No one, for instance, would hesitate to say to another ‘You ought to go to bed’, on the ground that neither he nor the other knows the kind of thing meant by ‘going to bed'. Yet, when we consider instances that would be offered, we do not find it easy to state the common character which we think they had which led us to call them actions. (Prichard, 1945: 272) Moral theorists might occasionally say something about whether they take actions to be events, or whether they are talking of act ‘types’ or ‘tokens’.38 By and large, however, one finds little conceptual exploration of the relation between motive, intention, action, and consequence, save perhaps on questions of merely adjacent interest to the main event, such as the ‘doctrine of double effect’ or ‘the doctrine of doing and allowing’. In the second half of the 20th century, the prevailing view of actions was Davidson’s (Anscombe-inspired) contention that they are a sub-set of events.39 Yet hardly anyone seems to care about what it might mean for an event to be right or wrong (morally or otherwise) or, for that matter, morally good or bad.40 Proponents of all sides share a related tendency to 37 See Sandis (2017). Schapiro (2001 & 2021) and Hurley (2018) also argue that different conceptions of action render competing normative views plausible, but what they really have in mind are different theories of agency. 38 Cf. Wetzel (2006: § 2.2) and Hanser (2008). 39 Davidson (1963). 40 By contrast, we know what it is for an event to be considered non-morally good or bad for us or other creatures (e.g. for a drought to be a bad thing, and subsequent rain good). draw a hard distinction between the deontic and the evaluative, focusing their interest in action on its rightness or wrongness, and reserving terms like ‘good’ and ‘bad’ for its motives and/or consequences. From this big leap, it is but a small step to the conclusion that that normative ethics is in the business of providing deontic accounts, leaving evaluative concerns to the ‘branch’ that is moral psychology.41 Anyone who insists otherwise is branded a virtueethicist. Should we not at least rejoice in the post-MMP ‘revival of virtue ethics’? For some the writing was on the wall from the outset: [W]hen the phrase ‘virtue ethics’ first came on the scene a number of people, I suspect, must have had a certain sinking feeling—without perhaps quite realizing why. The thing, we supposed, was almost bound to go to the bad. This gloomy assessment has I think proved quite realistic (Coope, 2006: 20). Anscombe argued that a philosophical concern with virtue should permeate moral philosophy. Instead, it has led to just one more theory, competing with deontology, consequentialism, and contractualism to provide the best account of right and wrong action.42 Julia Annas laments: Doing the right thing turns out not to be so central in an ethics in which virtue is central. A virtue ethical theory will be interested in virtuous action, but will not get much out of the notion of right action. (Annas, 2011: 47) No one has done more than Rosalind Hursthouse to put forward virtue ethics on the map as ‘a genuine rival to utilitarianism and deontology’ which can ‘give an account of right action in such a way as to provide action guidance’ (Hursthouse, 1999: 26 & 28; see also Hursthouse, 41 Consequentialism and other mainstream normative theories involve the promotion of goodness (see Korsgaard, 1993), while virtue ethics sees goodness as a (not necessarily causal) mark of right action, but neither approach offers accounts of good action. 42 Cf. Solomon (1988 & 2003) and Coope (2015). 1996). While she did well to emphasise the guiding power of being concerned with virtue, the offering of a normative theory of right action could not be further removed from what Anscombe was hoping to achieve with MMP. 43 This may serve to explain Hursthouse’s ambivalence towards this aspect of her own work. She may boast that virtue ethics ‘is at least a possible rival to deontological and utilitarian theories’—one that ‘can come up with an account of’ right action,—but she tellingly adds that it only does this ‘under pressure, only in order to maintain a fruitful dialogue with the overwhelming majority of modern philosophers for whom “right action” is the natural phrase’ (Hursthouse, 1999: 223 & 69; cf. Swanton, 2003: 245). It’s as if the wimpy school nerd feels reassured to have finally been accepted by those big nasty bullies, experiencing just a shade of residual resentment. Virtue ethics thus solidifies itself as just one more position within moral theory, offering an account of right action in terms of what the virtuous agent would characteristically do in the circumstances. Such theories allow one to ask whether virtue ethics and consequentialism might be compatible. It is, after all, conceivable that the virtuous person is one disposed to perform whichever actions are expected to promote the greatest amount of good.44 If this is what constitutes moral philosophy then Anscombe is not making a move within it. Her morality is not in direct competition with other normative theories, because it isn’t in the business of producing a theory of right action at all. 4. Conclusion Sixty years after MMP, contemporary moral philosophy is replete with consequentialist 43 The point is put forth with a panoply of arguments by Coope (2006: 26-39). 44 See M. Geach (2008: xvii-xviii). Roger Crisp has argued for a ‘Utilitarianism of the Virtues’ according to which the virtuous agent lives ‘in such a way that the total amount of utility in the history of the world is brought as close as possible to the maximum.’ (Crisp, 1992: 154; cf. Hursthouse, 1999: 5 & 7-8). More recently, Crisp has defended the additional view that if we understand virtue ethics as providing an account of right and wrong action (as Hursthouse does), then it collapses into a form of deontology. He suggests, further, that this can be avoided by focusing on the question of the value of virtue, as opposed to the notion of right action (Crisp, 2015 & 2019: 142-145; cf. Baron, 1997 and Singleton, 1999). Anscombe’s insight, by contrast, is that we cannot even begin to answer questions concerning right action without understanding what it is to act virtuously. It would be a mistake, however, to attempt to transform such an understanding into a normative theory. thinking obsessed with trolley-cases, a re-branded ‘philosophy of psychology’ that replaces conceptual explorations with unrefined findings from cognitive science, an experimental form of ‘moral psychology’ that culminates in the situationist skepticism about character traits, and the espousal of virtue ethics as a theory of ‘morally right action’ that may even be compatible with utilitarianism. By Anscombe’s lights, moral philosophy would seem to have been in far better shape between Moore and MMP than it is now. Whatever one’s assessment of the views of action that Anscombe sought to combat and the account that she put forward in their place, MMP seems to have inadvertently created a wedge between ethics and action theory. This has largely been the result of two consequences that Anscombe could not have easily foreseen, and most certainly didn’t intend. The first is the establishment of ‘virtue ethics’ as one more position within normative ethics, theorizing that an action is right if (and only if) it is what the virtuous agent would (advise us to) do. The second is the development of ‘moral psychology’ as an independent and increasingly empirical ‘branch' of ethics whose interest in questions of motivation, agency, and responsibility have been largely sawed off investigations into the good and the right. Ironically, before these interventions British moral theorists were less inclined to separate their defence of any particular account of ‘right action’ from their views in moral and philosophical psychology. Within the work of Joseph, Ross, and Prichard alone, we find a properly philosophical psychology (one that includes conceptual explorations of the relation of action to motive, intention, and the will) to be central to moral thought. To end with a ray of hope: the 21st century has seen a resurgence of neo-Anscombeans producing impressive work in moral philosophy (e.g. Coope, 2006; Solomon, 2003, 2008; Thompson, 2008; Brewer, 2009; Vogler, 2009; Teichmann 2011, Frey, 2019 and Hain, 2019). This welcome revival of interest in her work is an opportunity for moral philosophers to work well and finally put things right.45 45 An earlier version of this chapter was published in 2020 as ‘Modern Moral Philosophy Before and After Anscombe’, in (eds). S . Miguens & Mª D. García-Arnaldos, Reason, Reasoning, and Action (special issue of Enrahonar dedicated to G.E.M. Anscombe), 39-62. Special thanks to Louise Chapman, Sophie Grace Chappell, Jennifer Frey, David Hunter, Andreas Lind, and Roger Teichmann, who have all helped to improve it, though it has not improved half as much as they would have liked. References ADAMS, Robert Merrihew (1979). “Divine Command Metaethics Modified Again”. The Journal of Religious Ethics, 7 (1), 66-79. ALVAREZ, Maria & HYMAN, John (1998). “Agents and their Actions”. Philosophy, 73, 218-245. ANNAS, Julia (2011). Intelligent Virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ARISTOTLE (c. 350 BC). Ethica Nicomachea (EN). BYWATER, I. (ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1894. AQUINAS, Thomas (1265–1274), Summa Theologica [ST], Opera Omnia - Bilingual Edition, Vols.13-22 (Aquinas Institute, 2013). BARON, Marcia (1997). “Kantian Ethics”. In: BARON, Marcia W.; PETTIT, Phillip & SLOTE, Michael (eds.). Three Methods of Ethics. Oxford: Blackwell, 3-91. BERMÚDEZ, José Luis (2005). Philosophy of Psychology: A Contemporary Introduction. London: Routledge. BLACKBURN, Simon (2005). “Anscombe’s Ethics”, letter to Times Literary Supplement, Oct 14: https://www.the-tls.co.uk/articles/private/anscombes-ethics-5/ BLOCK, Ned (1980). Readings in Philosophy of Psychology, Vol. 1. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press). BOTTERILL, George & CARUTHERS, Peter (1999). The Philosophy of Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. BREWER, Talbot (2009), The Retrieval of Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press). COOPE, Christopher (2006). “Modern Virtue Ethics”. In: CHAPPELL, Timothy (ed.). Values and Virtues: Aristotelianism in Contemporary Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 20-52. — (2015). “Review of David Edmonds’ Would You Kill the Fat Man?’”. The Philosophical Quarterly, 65 (259), 275-313. CRISP, Roger (1992). “Utilitarianism and the Life of Virtue”. The Philosophical Quarterly, 42 (167),139160. — (2015). “A Third Method of Ethics?”. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 90 (2), 257-273. — (2019). Sacrifice Regained: Morality and Self-Interest in British Moral Philosophy from Hobbes to Bentham. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DANCY, Jonathan (2004). Ethics Without Principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DAVIDSON, Donald (1963). “Actions, Reasons, and Causes’. Journal of Philosophy. 60, 685-700. DAVIS, Nancy (Ann) (1991). “Contemporary Deontology”. In: SINGER, Peter (ed.). A Companion to Ethics. Oxford: Blackwell, 205-18. DIAMOND, Cora (1997). “Consequentialism in Modern Moral Philosophy and in ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’”. In: ODERBERG, David S. & LAING, JACQUELINE A. (eds.). Human Lives: Critical Essays on Consequentialist Bioethics. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 13-38. DOYLE, James (2018). No Morality, No Self: Anscombe’s Radical Scepticism. Harvard University Press. — (2019). “How Should We Understand Anscombe’s Claim that ‘Moral’ Does Not Express a Concept?”, unpublished. EWING, Alfred C. (1938). “What is Action?”. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume XVII, 86-101. FOOT, Phillipa (1967). “The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of Double Effect”. Oxford Review, 5, 5-15; as reprinted in her Virtues and Vices (Oxford University Press, 1978), 19-32, to which any page numbers refer. FREY, Jennifer A. (2018, September ). “Review of No Morality, No Self”. Notre Dame Book Reviews. Retrieved from https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/no-morality-no-self-anscombes-radical- skepticism/ — (2019). “Revisiting Modern Moral Philosophy”. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 87, 1-23. GEACH, Mary (2005a, October 14). Anscombe’s Ethics [Letter]. Times Literary Supplement, 5349. Retrieved from https://www.the-tls.co.uk/articles/private/anscombes-ethics/ — (2005b, October 21). Anscombe’s Ethics [Letter]. Times Literary Supplement, 5350. Retrieved from https://www.the-tls.co.uk/articles/private/anscombes-ethics-3/ — (2008). “Introduction”. In: GEACH & GORMALLY 2008, xiii-xxi. GEACH, Peter (1956). “Good and Evil”. Analysis, 17, 33-42. GEACH Mary & GORMALLY, Luke. (eds.) (2005). Human Life, Action and Ethics: Essays by G. E. M. Anscombe. Exeter: Imprint Academic. — (2008). Faith in a Hard Ground: Essays on Religion, Philosophy and Ethics: Essays by G. E. M. Anscombe.Exeter: Imprint Academic. GREMASCHI, Sergio (2017). “Anscombe on the Mesmeric Force of ‘Ought’ and a Spurious Kind of Moral Realism”. Ethics & Politics, 19 (2), 51-86. HACKER-WRIGHT, John (2013). Philippa Foot’s Moral Thought. London: Bloomsbury. HAIN, Raymond (ed.) (2019). Beyond the Self: Virtue Ethics and the Problem of Culture. Waco, Texas: Baylor University Press. HANSER, Matthew (2008). “Actions, Acting, and Acting Well”. In: SHAFER-LANDAU, Russ (ed.). Oxford Studies in Metaethics, Vol. 3, 171-198. HEGEL, G. W. F. (1821). Elements of the Philosophy of Right (A.W. Wood, Ed.; H. B. Nisbet, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991. HOOKER, Brad (2002). Ideal Code, Real World. Oxford: Oxford University Press. HORNSBY, Jennifer (1980). Actions. London: Routledge. — (1993). “On What’s Intentionally Done”. In: SHUTE, Stephen; GARDNER, John & HORDER, Jeremy (eds.). Action and Value in Criminal Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 57-74. — (2010). “Trying to Act”. In: O’CONNOR, Timothy & SANDIS, Constantine (eds.). A Companion to the Philosophy of Action. UK: Wiley-Blackwell, 18-25. HURLEY, Paul (2018). “Consequentialism and the Standard Story of Action”. The Journal of Ethics, 22 (1), 25-44. HURSTHOUSE, Rosalind (1996). “Normative Virtue Ethics”. In: CRISP, Roger (ed.). How Should One Live? Essays on the Virtues. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 19-33. — (1999). Virtue Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. JENSEN, Steven J. (2010). Good & Evil Actions: A Journey Through Saint Thomas Aquinas. Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press. JOSEPH, H.W.B. (1931/1933), Some Problems in Ethics, 2nd (corrected) impression (Oxford: Clarendon Press). KANT, Immanuel (1788). Kant: Critique of Practical Reason (M. J. GREGOR, Ed. and Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997. KORSGAARD, Chirstine (1993). “The Reasons We Can Share: An Attack on the Distinction Between Agent-relative and Agent-neutral Values”. Social Philosophy and Policy, 10 (1), 24-51. MACMURRAY, John (1938). “What is Action?”. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume XVII, 69-85. MILL, John Stuart (1861). Utilitarianism.(SHER, George, ed.). Indianapolis, CA:Hackett Publishing Company, 1979. MOORE, George Edward (1903). Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. PARFIT, Derek (2011). On What Matters: Vols. I & II. Oxford: Oxford University Press. PRICE, Anthony W. (2005). “Was Aristotle a Particularist?”. Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 21, 191-212. PRICHARD, Harold Arthur (1932). “Duty and Ignorance of Fact”, as published in Prichard (2004: 84-101). — (1945). “Acting, Willing, Desiring”, as published in Prichard (2004: 272-281). — (2004). Moral Writings. (MACADAM, Jim, ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press. QUANTE, Michael (1993), Hegel’s Concept of Action (D. Moyer, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. RAWLS, John (1974-1975). “The Independence of Moral Theory”, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, Vol. 48, 5-22. RICHTER, Duncan (2011). Anscombe’s Moral Philosophy. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books. — (2019). “Morality and Moral Law: A Reply to James Doyle”. Forma de Vida, 17 (Anscombe). Retrieved from https://formadevida.org/dritcherfdv17. ROSS, W. D. (1930). The Right and the Good. Oxford: Clarendon Press. SANDIS, Constantine (2010) “The Man Who Mistook his Handlung for a Tat: Hegel on Oedipus and Other Tragic Thebans”. Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain, 62, 35-60. — (2012). The Things We Do and Why We Do Them. London: Palgrave Macmillan. — (2017). “The Doing & the Deed: Action in Normative Ethics”. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 80: Philosophy of Action, 105-126. — (2019a, May 24). “Neo-Anscombians”. Times Literary Supplement. Retrieved from https://www.the-tls.co.uk/articles/private/neo-anscombians/ — (2019b). “Who Are ‘We’ for Wittgenstein?”. In: APPELQVIST, Hanne (ed.). Wittgenstein and the Limits of Language. London: Routledge, 172-196. — (2019c) (ed.). Philosophy of Action from Suarez to Anscombe. London: Routledge. — (2020). “Was Jesus a Moral Particularist?”. The Philosophers’ Magazine, 89,6-8. — (2021). “Virtue Ethics and Particularism”, 95th Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Vol. 95, Iss.1 SCANLON, Thomas, M. (1998). What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press. — (2008). Moral Dimensions: Permissibility, Meaning, Blame. New Jersey: Harvard University Press. SCHAPIRO, Tamar (2001). “Three Conceptions of Action in Moral Theory”. NOÛS, 35 (1), 93-117. — (2021). “Kant's Approach to the Theory of Agency”. In: SYLVAN, K. & CHANG, R. (eds.). The Routledge Handbook of Practical Reason, forthcoming. SIDGWICK, Henry (1874). The Methods of Ethics. London: Macmillan. SINGLETON, Jane (1999). “Virtue Ethics, Kantian Ethics, and Consequentialism”, unpublished. SOLOMON, David (1988). “Internal Objections to Virtue Ethics”. Midwest Studies in Philosophy XIII, 428440. — (2003). “Virtue Ethics: Radical or Routine?”. In: ZAGZEBSKI, Linda & DEPAUL, Michael (eds.). Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 57-80. — (2008). “Elizabeth Anscombe’s ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’: Fifty Years Later”. Christian Bioethics , 14 (2), 109-122. SULLIVAN, Roger, J. (1989). Immanuel Kant’s Moral Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. SWANTON, Christine (2003). Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic View. Oxford: Oxford University Press. — (2015). “A Particularist but Codifiable Virtue Ethics”. In: TIMMONS, Mark (ed.). Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics, Vol. 5, 38-63. TAYLOR, Charles (1979). “Action as Expression”. In: DIAMOND, C. & TEICHMAN, Jenny (eds.). Intention and Intentionality. Sussex: Harvester Press, 73-89. — (1983). “Hegel and the Philosophy of Action”. As reprinted in: LAITINEN, Arto & SANDIS, Constantine (eds.). Hegel on Action. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 22-41. TEICHMANN, Roger (2008). The Philosophy of Elizabeth Anscombe. Oxford: Oxford University Press. — (2011), Nature, Reason, and the Good Life: Ethics for Human Beings (Oxford: Oxford University Press). THAGARD, Paul (ed.) (2007). The Philosophy of Psychology and Cognitive Science. Amsterdam: North Holland. THOMPSON, Michael (2008). Life and Action: Elementary Structures of Practice and Practical Thought. Boston, MA: Harvard University Press. VOGLER, Candace (2001). John Stuart Mill's Deliberative: An Essay in Moral Psychology. New York, NY: Garland Publishing Inc. — (2009). Reasonably Vicious. Boston, MA: Harvard University Press. VON WRIGHT, Georg Henrik (1963). Norm and Action. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. WEISKOPF, Daniel & ADAMS, Fred (2015). An Introduction to the Philosophy of Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. WETZEL, Linda (2006). “Types and Tokens”. In: ZALTA, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2018 Edition). Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/types-tokens . WHITE, Alan, R. (1968). “On Being Obliged to Act”. Royal Institute of Philosophy lectures Vol.1 : 196667, 64-82. London: Macmillan. WISEMAN, Rachael (2016a). Anscombe’s Intention. London: Routledge. — (2016b). “The Intended and Unintended Consequences of Intention”. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, 90 (2), 207-227. — (2017). “G. E. M. Anscombe.” Oxford Bibliographies in philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. WITTGENSTEIN, Ludwig (1953). Philosophical Investigations (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell. — (1977/1998). Culture and Value, (eds.) G.H. von Wright with H. Nyman, tr. Peter Winch, 2nd ed. revised by A. Pichler (Oxford: Blackwell).