Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2021, Biology and Philosophy
In this essay, we discuss Simona Ginsburg and Eva Jablonka's The Evolution of the Sensitive Soul from an interdisciplinary perspective. Constituting perhaps the longest treatise on the evolution of consciousness, Ginsburg and Jablonka unite their expertise in neuroscience and biology to develop a beautifully Darwinian account of the dawning of subjective experience. Though it would be impossible to cover all its content in a short book review, here we provide a critical evaluation of their two key ideas-the role of Unlimited Associative Learning in the evolution of, and detection of, consciousness and a metaphysical claim about consciousness as a mode of being-in a manner that will hopefully overcome some of the initial resistance of potential readers to tackle a book of this length.
Different interpretations of the concept of consciousness and its function in the phylogeny of our species are discussed. The prerequisites of consciousness are investigated, along with its development starting from the simplest of organisms, through great apes, to the modern human.
This review summarises why it is difficult for Darwinian evolutionary theory to explain the existence and function of consciousness. It then evaluates whether Humphrey's book Soul Dust overcomes these problems. According to Humphrey, consciousness is an illusion constructed by the brain to enhance reproductive fitness by motivating creatures that have it to stay alive. Although the review entirely accepts that consciousness gives a first-person meaning to existence, it concludes that Humphrey does not give a convincing account of how this can arise from random variations in the genome. Nor does he demonstrate how first-person experiences might enter into or be reducable to third-person functioning. The review concludes that Humphrey's case is unconvincing, and goes on to suggest that an entirely different, non-reductive approach may be required to understand consciousness.
There have been various attempts to apply Darwinian evolutionary theory to an understanding of the human condition within psychology and the social sciences. This paper evaluates whether Darwinian Theory can explain human consciousness. Starting with a brief definition of phenomenal consciousness and the central features of evolutionary theory, the paper examines whether random variations in the genome that confer a selective, reproductive advantage can explain both the emergence of consciousness and its varied forms. To inform the discussion, the paper reviews what is known about the conditions for consciousness within the human mind/brain, understood in both structural (neural) terms and functional terms (in terms of human information processing), and concludes that " random variations in the genome " provide no explanatory mechanism for why some neural activities (but not others) are accompanied by consciousness. The paper then evaluates the many functional advantages that have been proposed for various forms of phenomenal consciousness once they emerge, and concludes that, on close examination, phenomenal experiences themselves do not carry out the information processing functions attributed to them, which challenges the Darwinian requirement that they could only have persisted (once emergent) it they enhanced reproductive fitness. The paper turns finally to what can be said about wider distribution of consciousness in non-humans, contrasting discontinuity theories with continuity theories. Discontinuity theories argue for a critical functional transition that " switches on consciousness " while continuity theories argue for a gradual transition in consciousness from unrecognisable to recognisable. All theories accept that there is an intimate, natural relationship of conscious experiences with their associated material forms. Consequently, as the material forms evolve, their associated experiences co-evolve—suggesting an indirect mechanism by which the emergence of species-specific forms of consciousness can be influenced by Darwinian evolution. It also allows a non-reductive understanding of human consciousness within the social sciences.
2007
Suppose that consciousness is a natural feature of biological organisms, and that it is a capacity or property or process that resides in a single organ. In that case there is a straightforward question about the consciousness organ, namely: How did the consciousness organ come to be formed and why is its presence maintained in those organisms that have it?
Consciousness in Science and Jain Philosophy (Proceedings of the International Conference on Science and Jain Philosophy held at Florida International University, Miami, USA in 2021), 2024
Despite the immense growth in modern science in the field of evolution, there are still queries, answers of which can only be found through the theory of consciousness. That theory suggests that a being's actions (karma) play the most vital role in its evolution; it also motivates us to consider that evolution takes place on the collective and individual levels and that it occurs in the consciousness first and later gets reflected in the physical body of the being. Ancient Indian Jain scholars (ācāryas) conducted incredible research into the nature of consciousness and the causes of evolution in it. They not only found and experienced the beauty of it but also wrote down their qualitative and quantitative descriptions of consciousness and evolution. To understand consciousness, one should explore two theories at the same time: karmic theory and the other is the theory of transmigration of the consciousness. The karma principle sees evolution and devolution in parallel. This paper describes the attributes of consciousness both in the philosophy of Jainism and in modern science and philosophy; evolution through the cause and effect of karmic actions of a being; how the being acquires five senses, one after the other, in its long journey of evolution; and why it is absolutely necessary to conduct research into consciousness along with evolution to get a clearer picture of the jigsaw puzzle called life, its history, and future.
Adopting an ‘‘archetypal’’ reading of analytical psychology, this paper seeks to explore the often encountered assumption that consciousness is ‘‘evolving.’’ The author considers parallels between the work of C.G. Jung and Jean Gebser, arguing that the ideas of both figures have at times been improperly understood and misappropriated in support of the evolutionary paradigm. It is suggested that the insights of archetypal psychology might help dismantle some of the long-standing assumptions of transpersonal theorizing, thus supporting the emergence of a more participatory outlook. Such an outlook proposes that consciousness is both culturally- embedded, yet self-creatively vitalized. This approach finds further support from the work of Jacques Lacan, Owen Barfield, and Jorge Ferrer.
Consciousness - An Adventure on the Anthropic Pathway, 2021
What is consciousness? How did it arise? Why did it evolve? These are among the most profound questions ever asked. More than three thousand years ago, consciousness was described in the Rig Veda as being a fundamental property of human life. Since then, numerous conjectures, dogmas, and mystical beliefs have been put forward to explain the origin and nature of consciousness. None have gained general acceptance. But today, a compelling solution to the mystery of consciousness is at hand. The scientific disciplines, empowered by sophisticated technological tools, have identified the elements necessary to formulate a comprehensive theory of consciousness. The purpose of this book is to elucidate the new theory. In so doing, we will take an adventure on the Anthropic Pathway—the branch of evolution where consciousness originated and ascended. Some original concepts include: 1- Elementary consciousness vs. mental consciousness —“Organisms that can self-encode and utilize knowledge acquired from prior experiences have elementary consciousness… an amoeba that can seek out, recognize, and engulf paramecia, while continuously improving its survival skills on the basis of accrued knowledge, has elementary consciousness. However, this organism lacks the means to be aware, mentally, of its experiences, for such an aptitude requires yet another level of complexification and holism—and the realization of mental consciousness.” 2- Integrated Information Theory expanded Structures representing integrated information are dual to structures able to collectively sense that information. These collective structures also affect the nature of an organism’s qualia and behaviors. —“Interneurons are specialized to manage the integration of information, as well as to assemble complementary structures able to collectively sense, or “ultrasense,” that information. The ultrasensation of integrated information is implemented exclusively within an emergent, novel realm of neuronal functionality, the interneuronal domain, where mental consciousness is made possible. (In vertebrae, the interneuronal domain is located entirely within the skeletal confines of the central nervous system, whereas the peripheral nervous system is absent of interneurons.)… Also, pages 4-5 and 15-18 of the book outline the emergence of the interneuronal domain in primitive species such as Platynereis dumerilii, how the collective ultrasensory structure and mental experientiality evolved, and why the trait selected for unitarity.” —“Mental consciousness has three experiential components: the experiencer (the collective ultrasensory structure), the experienced (integrated information), and phenomenal experience (the essence of mental consciousness that supervenes upon the experiencer).” 3- Dendritic arbors are the (content-specific) neural correlate of mental consciousness The question was raised (by TgB), “If dendritic connections are the physiological key, how come standard anesthetic agents allow neurological functioning to continue, but without consciousness?” The answer is: while dendritic arbors continue to support brain regions subliminally, anesthetics prevent their global synchronization, thus impeding the (particular function of) formation of a content-specific neural correlate of consciousness. Anesthetics operate on components of the full neural correlate of consciousness by impeding (or altering) frequency locking of brain regions—e.g., in the case of pain, anesthetic alteration of alpha network and harmonics across insular, cingulate, and prefrontal cortices, thalamus, brainstem, etc. In turn, a content-specific correlate of consciousness (dual information-ultrasensory process-structure described in excerpt 2), which requires sustained, reentrant cycling through a spatiotemporally distributed network of dendritic arbors, is precluded. —"The interface between the experiencer and the experienced consists of the group of dendritic arbor synapses active during an event of mental consciousness...ranging in complexity from the neuropil in the cerebral ganglia of a primitive sea star to those that foliate the pyramidal neuron/interneuron framework of a human neocortex...dendritic arbors are also [crucially] the repositories of memories encoded in the configuration of synaptic spines studding the surface of each dendrite." —“Interactions between collective structures and integrated information are fundamental to both consciously experienced and subliminal neural operations. For an informational representation to be consciously experienced it must attain a certain threshold of stability. Experiments in cognitive psychology have correlated consciously reportable events with sustained, reentrant states of informational representation; whereas brief or variable representations are always subliminal (although they may affect sensory-limbic, executive-motor, cognitive, memory, and other functionalities). Over extended durations, the reentrant cycling of information through a series of incrementally updated stable states has the effect of endowing mental consciousness with a coherent temporal flow.” —The collective structure of the experiencer consists of a patterned array of postsynaptic dendrites, and the informational representation it experiences is rendered by an inversely patterned array of presynaptic axons. Signaling between the experiencer and the experienced is conducted both through and around the core synaptic interface. Feedforward signals transmitted from the presynaptic side of the interface bypass it in order to shape the collective structure directly, priming it to interact with only the most salient and contextually relevant informational signals passing through the interface. In turn, feedback signals transmitted from the postsynaptic side of the interface cycle back and reenter the presynaptic input stream, prioritizing, filtering, and qualifying the very (sustained, recycling) information being experienced by the collective structure. Thus, the visual image of a cat (presynaptic signaling pattern originating in the retina) might induce (based on the form of the postsynaptic collective structure) an experience [qualia] of fondness in a human being but one of fright in a mouse." —"At this level of complexity, the physical distinction between the experiencer and the experienced is inscrutable. Nevertheless, while the core interface may be subsumed in the complexity of the neuronal group, the reciprocative duality between the experiencer and the experienced retains its archetypal, causative influence on the third component of mental consciousness, phenomenal experience, which has its own, subjective, ontological nature.” 4- Mind-body problem —“The explanatory gap is illusory, dispelled by recognition that both the first- and third-person ontologies refer to the same state [Searle state is physically identified in the book]. The one physical state is the bridge, connecting two perspectives. The bridge does not connect the physical brain to a distinct experiential mind; rather, it connects the third-person objective ontology conjectured about a physical state [based on empirical observations], to the first-person subjective ontology based on that state’s experiential essence.” 5- Anthropic Pathway —“In Chapter 15, the ‘fine tuning problem’ is investigated, i.e., what was the cause or reason for the universe to have possessed the improbable coincidence of property values necessary for complexity and conscious life to emerge and evolve? The multiverse solution to the fine tuning problem is negatively critiqued; instead, a specific evolutionary pathway that has developed within the event horizon of our observable universe is delineated. This pathway has traversed an extremum between order [arising from gravitational entropy] and disorder [from thermodynamic entropy], proceeding inexorably toward an anthropic attractor of complexity, and the conscious human brain.”
2014
What is consciousness? The conference is about consciousness, one of the most fascinating but also most problematic phenomena studied by contemporary empirical science. While be attractive enough for philosophers to produce an endless stream of hot debates, empirical scientists have long hesitated or refused to consider consciousness a valid or fruitful scientific problem. Even worse, many people would be happy to see the workings of the human mind not being explained away, because it touches so fundamentally the way we see ourselves in the universe, shaking the hope for our own personal survival, which many see very much in terms of the continuity of their own consciousness. All that may end up in curiously sardonic definitions of consciousness, like “Consciousness is a fascinating but elusive phenomenon; it is impossible to specify what it is, what it does, or why it evolved. Nothing worth reading has been written about it ” (Sutherland 1989), or, even more cynical, “Nobody has th...
International Journal of Innovative Research in Technology, 2021
CAA.review, 2024
AVELAR, Alexandre (org.) alexandre de sá avelar (organizador). História para quê, para quem? Teresina: Cancioneiro., 2024
Erika Winda Mustika, 2022
Journal of Motor Behavior, 2014
Commemorative Spaces of the First World War: Historical Geographies at the Centenary, 2018
2019
New Bhartiya Book Corporation,Delhi, 2016
Urartian Red Burnished Ware in local context: An archaeometric study of the assemblage from Metsamor (Armenia, South Caucasus), 2024
Biochemical Pharmacology, 2013
イタリア学会誌 (Studi italici), , 1998
Tarım Bilimleri Dergisi, 2009
Safety Protocols and Infection Control, 2020
Universidade Federal do Espírito Santo, 2018
Environmental Earth Sciences, 2016
Pielęgniarstwo i Zdrowie Publiczne, 2018
Revista Española de Enfermedades Digestivas, 2005