Law as Language
Marianne Constable ∗
Abstract
This paper proposes understanding law as language. Doing so offers an alternative both
to jurisprudential accounts of law as a system of rules and to sociological accounts of law
as effective (or ineffective) social power. Part II shows how approaching law as language
takes doctrine and legal texts seriously, as speech acts of claiming that do things, rather
than as nounlike rules or their application. Such an approach recognizes that legal actions
or events of claiming are “imperfect” in a grammatical sense: practical knowledge of law
is incomplete, continual and interruptible, while legal acts occur more and less well under
particular conditions. Understanding law this way, part III shows, also enables one to critique narrow approaches to law as “policy” or as exclusively a problem-solving tool or instrument. The paper not only argues that law may be thought of as language then. It ultimately suggests another law: that we are creatures of language.
“The imperfect is our paradise.”
Wallace Stevens
I. Introduction
Jurisprudence, legal history, and other humanistic disciplines have over the centuries offered a range of insights into the perennial questions of what to do or how best to live,
how we know, and who we are. In so doing, philosophy (Plato), rhetoric (Vico), and social theory (Montesquieu), as well as history and literature, have often questioned the justice of law. That they have done so suggests that law has been taken—or has offered itself—as a site of justice or at least as a site in which issues of justice can be addressed.
Today, as professional law schools turn increasingly to economics and the empirical social sciences to deal with social problems that they would solve through what they
call “policy,” the relation of law as policy-making to traditional humanistic accounts of
justice and how it is addressed becomes an issue, even as the relevance of the humanities
and of humanistic studies to professional legal study is brought into question. The rise of
∗
Professor and Chair, Department of Rhetoric; Zaffaroni Family Professor in Undergraduate Education;
UC Berkeley. Aspects of this article were presented as a brief position paper on “Teaching Law and Humanities,” at Princeton University, February 2013. The author thanks participants there, as well as those in
the Berkeley Law and Humanities group, for their comments. She thanks Juliana Stivanicevic for research
assistance. The article synthesizes one argument from Our Word Is Our Bond: How Legal Speech Acts, forthcoming from Stanford University Press, 2014, with some points from Just Silences: The Limits and Possibilities of
Modern Law (2005). A section of the former was originally discussed at a CAL Workshop at the University
of Toronto Law School in 2012; many thanks are owed to Markus Dubber and especially to Simon Stern
for very helpful suggestions.
ISSN 2291-9732
64
Critical Analysis of Law 1:1 (2014)
law and economics, combined with the marginalization of critical studies and even social
theory in professional law schools in the U.S., means that law seeks to become ever more
“rational,” while sociolegal research becomes increasingly bound to the methodological
requirements and outcomes of statistical empirical research. Policy-makers today address
questions about what to do through problem-solving approaches that rely on economic
and statistical methods and frameworks and tacitly foreclose particular sorts of answers—
and even questions.
Some legal scholars still turn explicitly to humanities over social sciences to improve law in a particular way. They sometimes suggest that law “needs” the humanities,
that the humanities are the conscience of law, that the humanities can make law—or that
humanists can teach law to be—more honest and good. The humanities are not a religion,
though. Humanists are not moralists, priests, nor even judges to be turned to for guidance, absolution, or pronouncements of justice. So what do the humanities offer law?
This paper proposes that if we continue insisting on “the humanities” (itself a
question), then the humanities can be said to be characterized by a sensitivity to language,
broadly understood, in readings (or interpretations or analyses) of texts and images and
other cultural and historical artifacts. The attention paid to language in basic legal education itself suggests that law already belongs in the domain of the humanities. Thinking
about law as language need not be identified with a particular field nor even with a set of
approaches dubbed “law and humanities,” however. Furthermore, that humanists interpret does not mean that they do not make arguments. Indeed, the argument pursued here
is that modern law is fundamentally a matter of language and that there are some things
one cannot understand about law if one does not understand language—and the limits of
speech.
This argument challenges the claims of legal philosophers and social scientists that
law is fundamentally a matter of coercion or of social power. The point that law is a matter of language is not a return to the privileging of doctrine, however. It also goes beyond
simply claiming that to engage in the practice of U.S. or Canadian law at this time, one
must have some facility in reading, writing, and speaking the English language. It emphasizes in part what legal practitioners certainly know: that words do a lot of different things
that are generally described philosophically as “speech acts.” 1 Practitioners develop, to
varying degrees, the skills required to carry out legal acts which, to be successful, must
fulfill particular conditions. Legal practitioners also know, as well as humanists, that language, however beloved or despised, is always susceptible to going wrong. As practitioners of language, practitioners of law must become adept at using words and at judging
what words say. The imperfections of law correspond at least in part to the imperfections
of language. Words promise truth. They ostensibly show us the world as it is. Words can
be misspoken, misheard, and misunderstood, though. Words can be inappropriate or misappropriated, deceptive, inaccurate, or wrong, even downright dangerous. So too can law
and legal claims.
1
J.L. Austin, How to Do Things with Words (1962).
Constable — Law as Language
65
The first section (part II) shows how law corresponds with various aspects of language. One distinguishes particular utterances or speech acts from practical knowledge of
language. Such knowledge is, in a grammatical sense, “imperfect.” The imperfect names
the incomplete, continuous, ongoing, routine, habitual, interruptible aspect of action, as
in, “She is running every day, except when it rains” or “We were speaking English when we
made the agreement.” The “perfect” refers to a completed act: “She ran” or “It rained” or
“We spoke” or “We agreed.” As in language, so too in law, one can distinguish perfected
or completed legal acts or events from an “imperfect” or ongoing tradition of background
practical knowledge.
The second section (part III) shows how the language of modern law reveals insights into who we—as problem-solvers—are and what we know, as well as into what we
do. Attending to law as language, the paper concludes, may provide entry into fresh questions about the nature of modern law and justice, an issue that far too many contemporary philosophers and scholars of law take for granted.
II. Law as Language that Acts
Despite the ostensible crisis that today is contributing to discussion of curricular reform
in U.S. law schools, professional legal education still emphasizes reading and writing in its
classrooms, showing law to be a matter of language. 2 Students in legal writing courses
learn that “good legal writing should not differ, without good reason, from ordinary wellwritten English.” 3 They learn the basic tenets of a plain style and to “prefer the active
voice,” for instance. 4 Such elements of style reinforce the grammatical division of the
world into the subjects and predicates required by “complete” sentences. In this world of
“doers and deeds,” as Nietzsche puts it, subjects control and are held responsible for the
acts or deeds they predicate. “I fear we are not getting rid of God,” the ultimate SubjectCreator, he writes, “because we still believe in [the] grammar” of subjects that predicate. 5
In law, the attribution of responsibility for a criminal act requires, as the U.S. Supreme
Court put it, “concurrence of an evil-meaning mind with an evil-doing hand” or of mens
rea with actus reus; it requires a subject whose mind or soul is joined through adverbial intention or will to an act as predicate or verb. 6 The rule of law may establish “no punishment without a crime, no crime without a law”; the rule of grammar mandates that there
be no sentence without the conviction of a subject who predicates.
2
For a study of the teaching of first year contracts, see Elizabeth Mertz, The Language of Law School:
Learning to “Think Like a Lawyer” (2007). As to the crisis, proposals for developing core competencies and
for reducing time to degree abound. Even the skills that clinical classes and experiential education aim to
promote require hearing, speaking, reading, and writing.
3
Richard Wydick, Plain English for Lawyers (5th ed. 2005).
4
Id. at 5.
5
Friedrich Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols § 5, in Twilight of the Idols and The Anti-Christ (R.J. Hollingdale trans., 1968).
6
Morissette v. United States, 342 U.S. 246 (1952).
66
Critical Analysis of Law 1:1 (2014)
This is not to say that law or language is reducible to statements of rules, much
less to formal grammars or models of rationality. Neither law nor language consists of the
sort of discrete or exhaustive system of rules that some take law to be, insofar as rules—
whether of law or of language—never completely determine what to do or to say. In English, poets break rules; expert writers dispense with them; breaches of grammar become
conventional figures of speech. At best, semantic and syntactic rules serve as pedagogical
aids. Likewise, in law, statements of rules alone cannot tell one what to do. As a blogger
on the new legal realism website puts it, citing the University of Wisconsin Law School
website, “Knowing the rules is like learning to play scales when you study a musical instrument. Playing scales is essential, but it isn’t music. And knowing the rules is essential,
but it isn’t being a lawyer.” 7
In any number of venues, formal legal officials and others complain, rebut, demur,
swear, testify, instruct, hold, appeal, object, overrule, sustain, enact, appoint, find, dismiss,
amend, approve, reject, deny, declare, agree, offer, accept, promise, qualify, hold, dissent,
remand, sentence, wed, bequeath, annul, and so on. Like these speech acts done in the
name of law, statements of (defeasible and indefeasible) legal rules make claims; they assert truths and they demand recognition. To be successful, they must fulfill particular
conditions. As J.L. Austin puts it, performative utterances (which he later identifies with
illocutionary speech acts) must be uttered (or written) by an appropriate party, in appropriate circumstances; they must be carried out correctly and completely; and they must be
heard. 8
If statements of rules do not exhaust legal speech acts, neither are legal speech
acts simply applications of rules. The language of “appropriateness” suggests that the
conditions of success for legal acts such as those above may be met more or less well, by
more and less skilled parties, in circumstances that the act may fit more or less closely. A
man cannot marry a monkey, as J.L. Austin writes, but whether two men can wed today
depends on the jurisdiction. 9 A legal act that is not signed may be invalid, but whether a
particular signatory actually has power of attorney on a given date may be at issue. A particular judgment may be authoritative and correct, but the reasoning presenting it weak;
7
Bill Clune, Law in Action and Law on the Books: A Primer (June 12, 2013)
(http://newlegalrealism.wordpress.com/2013/06/12/law-in-action-and-law-on-the-books-a-primer/). Wisconsin was a key hub for the development of sociolegal scholarship. The New Legal Realism aims to develop better “translations” between law and social science. See New Legal Realism: Empirical Law and Society
(http://www.newlegalrealism.org/about.html).
8
Even so-called “constative” utterances that “state” something are performative, Austin ultimately argues.
He describes the requirements for the success of “performatives” as their “felicity conditions,” in Lectures 2
and 3 of How to Do Things with Words. Adolf Reinach, writing half a century before Austin, discusses the requirement that what he calls “social acts” must be heard. The A Priori Foundations of Civil Law (John
Crosby trans., 1983) (1913). For fuller discussion of social acts and the ways that they can go wrong, see
Marianne Constable, Our Word Is Our Bond: How Legal Speech Acts chs. 3 & 4 (forthcoming 2014). For a
genealogical account of the way that ostensibly neutral or impersonal judicial statements are themselves
performative, see Caleb Smith, The Oracle and the Curse: A Poetics of Justice from the Revolution to the
Civil War (2013).
9
Austin, supra note 1, at 24.
Constable — Law as Language
67
conversely a questionable result or losing claim may be skillfully presented. Although rules
often circumscribe the circumstances in which a particular act is appropriate (acceptance
occurs once an offer has been made) and conventions may make some responses more
likely than others, neither rules nor conventions completely determine or circumscribe
what actually occurs, as sociolegal scholars are quick to remind us.
Taking up the early twentieth-century legal realist distinction between “law-onthe-books” and “law-in-action,” that is, law-and-society scholarship rejects the rules that it
associates with law-on-the-books, in favor of studying legal behavior or “the way the legal
system works and how it works” in a “so-called real world.” Identifying with a “social science perspective” that makes “claims about facts”, 10 law-and-society’s emphasis on institutions and behavior contrasts, according to Lawrence Friedman, to non-law-and-society
scholars’ understanding of law as “norms, or language, or ideology, or rhetoric or ‘consciousness,’ or discourse—anything but behavior.” 11 Law and society compares its own
empirical study of the effects of law to the “insider” view of law of lawyers, judges, and a
Mr. and Mrs. Public concerned “not so much with empirical reality, with what is going on
in the world, as . . . with what is correct, or what ought to be.” 12 Law has too much of an
impact, law-and-society scholarship claims, to be left to insiders who identify law with
rule-formulations that are taken to articulate what should be and, hence, often and mistakenly, what law is.
Legal speech acts are indeed social acts, although not exactly in the way that sociolegal realists would have it. As social acts that must be heard, legal acts complicate any
strong realist distinction between “law-on-the-books” and “law-in-action.” Claims made
in the name of the law act in asserting and demanding. That legal speech acts involve
speakers and hearers means that they are dialogic. Even today’s impersonal codes and
neutral acts of law addressed “to whom it may concern” are “mandates” or “imperatives”
in a grammatical sense, asking for recognition of their claims from hearers, who may retrospectively constitute themselves as the addressees “to whom it may concern.” In responding to the “I” who speaks in the name of the law, that is, hearers—even those who
object—become “you” who share, with those who speak, a common language. The
“name” of law to which speaker and hearer appeal functions as a third-party proxy representing what “I” take “you” to understand “our” shared law to be. Like all third parties,
such law may be misrepresented. “You” may choose to ignore “me” or to challenge “it”
as what “we” do. The point is that fluid and practical knowledge of “juris-diction,” or of
the saying of law, constitutes speaker and hearer together as “we” who are speaking with
one another and recognize the same language and law, however contestable and imperfectly articulable.
10 Law & Society: Readings on the Social Study of Law, at xxx, 2, 6 (Stewart Macaulay et al. eds., 1995)
[hereinafter Law & Society].
11
Lawrence M. Friedman, The Law and Society Movement, 38 Stan. L. Rev. 763, 775 (1986).
12
Law & Society, supra note 10, at 3.
68
Critical Analysis of Law 1:1 (2014)
The strange retrospective temporality involved in recognizing oneself as having
been the addressee of law that is articulated in a common tongue suggests that legal acts
are neither strictly causal nor chronological, as empirical studies would have it. Rather,
discrete legal speech acts have the structure of the future perfect, as Derrida writes of the
American “Declaration of Independence.” Derrida refers to the signing of the Declaration by the people’s representatives as a paradoxical moment of founding that establishes
“we, the people.” To sign the document as representatives of the people, the representatives must already have been authorized to do so in the name of the people. At the moment of the signing, however, the people is not yet in existence. 13 Likewise, the retrieval
of dicta and the use of common-law precedent—the binding of oneself in a present to
what will in the future be a newly discovered past—reveals the peculiar temporality of the
future perfect tense. As Mark Currie puts it in his study of reading and life, “[I]f a narrative is a story we tell about the past, the present must also be a story about the past that
we will tell in the future. Questions of retrospection and anticipation are in fact inseparable if we consider that we experience the present as the object of a future memory, or live
the present in a mode of anticipation of the story we will tell about it.” 14
At the same time as speech acts of law, like other speech acts or speech events,
require as their temporal condition the future perfect to be complete, the unpredictability
of speech and of the world suggests another aspect of law: an ongoing instability or imperfection that cannot be ignored. In grammar, the “imperfect” aspect of a verb normally
indicates incomplete, ongoing, continuous, routine, habitual, or interruptible action: we
were speaking English, when someone knocked, for instance; or we were speaking together, when the (future) perfect legal act of declaration occurred. In law, some have taken imperfection to refer to the “gap” between law-in-action and law-on-the-books; others
take it as the inadequacy of legal utterances or speech acts and events to measure up to a
more perfect or even unreachable justice. In the context of law as language, however, the
imperfect aspect or incompleteness of law suggests that just as language is never exhausted by the sum of its utterances or by what is said, nor even by all that will have been said,
so too law is more than the sum of its present and future perfect legal acts. It is an ongoing, continuous, routine, and habitual practice. Utterances as acts of language emerge
from language. Legal speech acts or events, too, emerge from and interrupt law as a background of practical knowledge of what to do, or as an idiom—imperfect and incompletely
articulable, but not itself inaccessible—of justice. Legal speech acts may stand out as
events against this background or may merge back into it as that against which other less
routine legal acts or events can stand out.
In this context of law as imperfect practice or tradition, subjects’ knowledge is also imperfect. Practical knowledge of speech and of language varies by speaker and group.
Knowledge of language serves as the grammatically-imperfect background (“we were
speaking English”) that differentiates communities of speakers (“they were speaking
13
Jacques Derrida, Declarations of Independence, 7 New Political Sci. 7 (1986).
14
Mark Currie, The Expansion of Tense, 17 Narrative 353, 356 (2009).
Constable — Law as Language
69
Spanish”), against which discrete speech acts can occur (“when she promised the land,” in
some presumably common tongue) more or less skillfully (“in vague terms” or “unwillingly” or “fully aware of what she was doing”). So too, imperfectly shared knowledge of law
serves as the ongoing background against which discrete legal acts (of promise, of agreement, of complaint, and so forth) occur, in more and less imperfect or routine ways.
In sum, this section has proposed attending to law as language that acts. Such attention addresses concerns of both the law school professoriate and sociolegal scholars. It
also values the experiences of practitioners and other who engage with and know law. On
the one hand, it takes doctrine and legal texts seriously, as speech acts of claiming that do
things, rather than as nounlike rules or their application; on the other, it focuses on legal
action and events by recognizing that claiming is an imperfect activity occurring more and
less well under particular conditions. In this context, visual studies of law, unspoken traditions of law, and even silences of law can no longer be relegated to the periphery of legal
studies. 15 They become relevant to properly understanding the imperfect aspect of law—
the incomplete, continuous, and interruptible knowledges and practices that constitute law
as language. Not only as utterances and acts that emerge from language and silence, but
also as an imperfect tradition of practical knowledge, law is a matter of language. It reveals
who we are and what we do, as the next section shows.
III. Modern Legal Language
The previous section argued that law corresponds to language in various ways. Legal acts
occur in a particular grammar and vocabulary; as speech acts, they involve more than
statements or applications of rules; as social acts, they make claims of others in dialogic
exchanges that must appeal to imperfect, shared practical knowledge. This section considers further how understanding law as language can contribute to legal study, focusing
briefly on policy as a manifestation of modern law.
The account of law as language above suggests, first, that the communities in
which we participate and to which we belong correspond to law and language as practices
or forms of knowledge. We do not need to agree to share language or law. As Wittgenstein put it, “What human beings say is true or false; they agree in their language (der
Sprache). That is not agreement in meanings [about which human beings may dispute, as
in his previous section], but in lifeform.” 16 To think law as language thus draws attention
15
Visual studies of law represent a burgeoning field. See Peter Goodrich, Legal Emblems and the Art of
Law (2013); Judith Resnik & Dennis Curtis, Representing Justice (2011); Richard Sherwin, Visualizing Law
in the Age of the Digital Baroque (2011). For accounts of law that grapple with traditions that are what I call
grammatically imperfect, see Martin Krygier, Thinking Like a Lawyer, in Ethical Dimensions of Legal Theory 67 (Wojciech Sadurski ed., 1991); Martin Krygier, Law as Tradition, 5 Law & Phil. 237 (1986); and numerous studies of the laws of First Nations and indigenous peoples.
16
I have adjusted the standard translation in keeping with the emphasis in the original, which is found in
German on the facing page of Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations § 241 (G.E.M. Anscombe
trans., 3d ed. 1958). The Anscombe translation is: “It is what human beings say that is true and false, and
they agree in the language they use. That is not agreement in opinions but in form of life.”
70
Critical Analysis of Law 1:1 (2014)
to the many different overlapping jurisdictions to which persons belong. 17 Many kinds of
legal and linguistic non-state communities exist, as conflicts of law attests. 18
Thinking law as language moreover highlights the relevance of such matters as
translation, bilingualism, interpretation, education, and other issues of language and
speech, to who “we” variously are or become as we engage with others in public. The existence of language tests for state citizenship confirms that even in the context of positive
law, law and membership are bound to practices of speech.
Finally, thinking about law as language in the context of the state also contributes
to understanding the limitations of state-centered sociolegal positivism. Much work in
anthropology, history, and religion already points to the inadequacy of taking the state and
its law as a universal model of law. Sociolegal positivism identifies a cluster of characteristics around which sociology and legal positivism converge. 19 Legal positivism, the dominant philosophical view of law today, views law as a system of man-made rules whose existence is supported by social pressure and maintains that there is no necessary connection
between law and morality. 20 Positive law often refers to the bodies of doctrine taught in
professional law schools or to domestic or international law that officials will enforce.
Like legal positivism, sociolegal positivism relegates connections between law and justice
to empirically contingent social realities. Sociolegal positivism presumes that law is humanly articulable either as the declarations of officials or in scholars’ descriptions of human social systems. It posits the exclusivity of positive or manmade law as law and views
law as an instrument or strategy in a field or fields of social power. Even officials of positive law, however, appeal to language when, however crudely and wordlessly, they insist
that they carry out their duties in the “name” of law. As an account of law, sociolegal positivism appears most compatible then with understanding law as the codification and articulation, in the broadest sense, of state power.
Discourses of the state constitute particular forms of knowledge, however, which
a large historical literature—on the rise of statistics, on “imagined communities,” and on
colonialism—points out are not, and have not always been, universally known. Today,
state discourses of positive law have largely come to correspond with “policy.” Policy depends on language. Policies are developed and implemented as efficient and effective
means to particular ends. The development of policy generally involves: articulation of a
17
On juris-diction, see the articles in 48(2) English Language Notes (2010). See also Sara Kendall, Contested
Jurisdictions: Legitimacy and Governance at the Special Court for Sierra Leone (Ph.D. dissertation, Rhetoric, University of California, 2009).
18
Symposium, Transdisciplinary Conflict of Laws, 71 Law & Contemp. Probs. 1 (2008).
19
This description has been adapted from Marianne Constable, Just Silences: The Limits and Possibilities of
Modern Law 10 (2005).
20 H.L.A. Hart’s now-classic statement of Anglo-American legal positivism, The Concept of Law (1961), is now
in its third edition (2013). Hart argues that the modern municipal legal system is a combination of primary
rules that citizens generally obey and secondary rules that officials (in fact) accept. He uses John Austin’s
The Province of Jurisprudence Determined, originally published in 1832, as his straw man. Austin argued that law is
the habitually obeyed command of a sovereign backed by threats. Hans Kelsen, Pure Theory of Law (Max
Knight trans., 1967), argues that a basic norm grounds the validity of all legal norms and acts of a system.
Constable — Law as Language
71
problem and data-gathering about it; consideration and analysis of options for addressing
the problem; selection of a strategy or set of strategies; implementation of that strategy
and of mechanisms for its assessment. Policy accompanies a vocabulary of administration
that testifies to a proliferation of procedures of accountability and transparency rivaling
any public articulations of a “people” or of an aspiring democracy committed to equality
and liberty. If, as Foucault noted in Discipline and Punish, the “carceral archipelago” has
become “a carceral continuum,” so too the jargon of bureaucracy has overflowed its institutional borders and become ubiquitous. 21 Not only do state and international organizations adopt policies, that is, but “policy” governs in private enterprises and community
groups. Although “policy” in this sense sounds incredibly broad, one can still say something about its vocabulary and grammar, its speech acts and claims, and its appeal to a
particular sort of shared knowledge.
Note that the richness of the English tongue often allows one to say the same
thing (or enables the presentation of identical content via employment of alternative
communicative symbols) in short Anglo-Saxon words or in a polysyllabic Latinate vocabulary! Passive constructions and nominalizations allow one to make nouns, such as
“employment” and “nominalization,” from verbs or other parts of speech. The passive
language of spokespersons from schools to hospitals to prisons diffuses responsibility, at
the same time as surveillance and control over “target populations” grow. Bureaucratese
suits an institutional ethos that seeks to acknowledge that mistakes may have been made
without necessarily holding anyone responsible. Generalities in institutional statements
allow regulatory expansion while intricate classificatory details circumscribe inclusions and
exclusions of coverage.
As a discourse of calculation, policy transforms otherwise incommensurable material goods and immaterial “values” into fungible units that can be exchanged or analyzed
in terms of costs and benefits. The most basic matters—including health, happiness, pain,
love—become subject to quantitative measure. For an especially egregious example, consider the Department of Justice’s cost-benefit report accompanying the promulgation of
its rule for preventing, detecting, and responding to prison rape. 22 Empirical research and
quantitative study ostensibly combine with rational decision-making to produce efficient
solutions to problems. When legal systems “depend heavily on useful numbers and calculations,” as Reid Hastie puts it, it is indeed useful to produce numerical scales for assessing the numerical judgments of legal decision-makers. 23 One must be alert to the dangers of producing numerical scales for assessing judgments expressed in non-numerical
21
Michel Foucault, Discipline & Punish: The Birth of the Prison 297-98 (Alan Sheridan trans., 1977).
22 The situation is described in Lisa Heinzerling, Cost-Benefit Jumps the Shark: The Department of Justice’s
Economic Analysis of Prison Rape, Georgetown Law Faculty Blog (June 13, 2012)
(http://gulcfac.typepad.com/georgetown_university_law/2012/06/cost-benefit-jumps-the-shark.html). I
thank Dan Farber for drawing this example to my attention. For further discussion, see Christina Reichert,
Debate over OIRA’s Virtues and Vices Continues, Penn Program on Regulation Reg Blog (June 26, 2013)
(http://www.regblog.org/2013/06/26-reichert-oira-virtues-vices.html).
23
Reid Hastie, The Challenge to Produce Useful “Legal” Numbers, 8 (supp. s1) J. Empirical Legal Stud. 6, 6 (2011).
72
Critical Analysis of Law 1:1 (2014)
ways though. 24 As speech acts, policy statements are not themselves calculable in the way
that numbers are, nor propositional in the manner of symbolic logic. 25 If one must be
wary, as some have argued, of “gap” studies that appear to take legal rules for granted
when they point to the ways that law-in-action does not live up to law-on-the-books, then
one must be equally wary of policy reports that can say what they do only in particular
ways. 26 Like the legal acts and events mentioned in part II, policy statements are claims:
asserting, positing, describing, finding, proposing, recommending, demanding, and so
forth. They claim and act more and less well in a manner that is not only a matter of calculation but involves a shared background and practical knowledge of language.
Training reinforces the expertise and ways of reasoning embedded in policy language. Foucault writes that particular social projects—the leper colony, the plague city,
the Panopticon—carry with them their own “political dreams.” 27 A perfect vehicle for
neo-liberal commitments, policy places calculation and risk-assessment in the service of a
dream of security and welfare. 28 Insofar as it uses a language of management, rather than
top-down control, policy appears to be an alternative to the sovereign model of law that
prefers—or desires—an active voice. But if management, with its passive voice and economic calculations, is not on the surface a language of action and desire, then it too leaves
much unsaid and unsayable. It too binds subjects and objects of law into particular relations, this time of service and consumption, that raise questions about who we are and
what we appeal to in the name of our law.
In the context of social policies and expertise about human services, that is, all become “users.” 29 The user is the offspring of rational choice and marketing theory. In government and in the market alike, this figure embodies the joint hopes born from the
shortcomings of both the “rational actor” and the “consumer.” While the “rational actor”
assumed by law and economics is too abstract and ethereal, too ungrounded in the things
of the world, to serve as a model citizen, the market “consumer” is too indiscriminating
and materially oriented to be taken seriously as an expert. The “service user” of policy
research and internet cookies is heir to both. The “user” combines the techniques of costbenefit analysis and concern for economic efficiency with utilitarian calculations as to
“satisfaction,” in new civic form. The user manipulates the things of this world, seemingly
24
Wendy N. Espeland & Mitchell L. Stevens, Commensuration as a Social Process, 24 Ann. Rev. Sociology
313 (1998).
25
Valerie P. Hans, Jeffrey J. Rachlinski & Emily G. Owens, Editors’ Introduction, in Symposium, Judgment by
the Numbers: Converting Qualitative to Quantitative Judgments, 8 (supp. s1) J. Empirical Legal Stud. 1 (2011).
26
Austin Sarat & Susan Silbey, The Pull of the Policy Audience, 10 Law & Policy 97 (1988).
27
Foucault, supra note 21, at 198.
28
On neo-liberalism, see Wendy Brown, Neo-liberalism and the End of Liberal Democracy, 7 Theory &
Event (2003); for a more recent paper on the usefulness of the concept in law, see David Singh Grewal &
Jedediah S. Purdy, Introduction: Law and Neoliberalism (Feb. 6, 2014) (http://ssrn.com/abstract=2341068).
29
The description of the service-user is a slight revision of material in Constable, supra note 19, at 21-28;
see also Marianne Constable, On the (Legal) Study Methods of Our Time: Vico Redux, 83 Chi.-Kent L.
Rev. 1303 (2008).
Constable — Law as Language
73
distinguishing between needs and desires. The user draws on experience of these needs to
contribute, both actively and passively, to representations of the public or publics through
user surveys, satisfaction polls, and online data gathering. Data, as Cornelia Vismann puts
it, are the substrate of the files that make administration possible. 30 As experts on their
own lives, users are simultaneously data-points and informants as to administrative practices. 31
The site of expertise changes. Even as insurance companies, health maintenance
organizations and managed-care providers, charter school programs, credit-checking outfits, private security and transportation companies, private prisons, and partnerships between volunteer organizations and local governments, expand their range and jurisdiction,
they are regulated in the name of deregulation. Expertise no longer belongs exclusively to
their specialists or to social researchers, or even to more generic planners and efficiency
experts, who formerly could be held accountable to professional norms and external
goals. Rather, as state agencies, quasi-public organizations, and private parties alike adopt
the techniques of management, accounting, and evaluation that characterize interdependent market enterprises, expertise belongs concurrently to the local citizen-user. Appealed
to as responsible community member and local expert for input and feedback, today’s
citizen-user engages with others within circumscribed social structures to provide information. (“Responsible,” “strategic,” and “effective,” are the top three words used in 2013
resumes, according to LinkedIn.) 32 The citizen-user participates in a particular politics of
association made all the more apparent in today’s networked material world. He or she
contributes at the click of a key to policies that increasingly manage what may loosely be
termed the activities of everyday life: working, eating and drinking, learning, resting and
recreating, traveling, reading, watching television, driving, and so forth. Formerly “invited” to “visit” websites, viewers no longer simply “like” or “friend” institutions on Facebook; they “follow” them on Twitter, as was recently pointed out on public radio, and
become data-points from which to design and figure indices and values. 33 Transformations in public engagement and participation go to the heart of modern law, as serviceusers partner with service-providers, or the non-strictly-state institutions and organizations, including social media, that have emerged to shape the public sphere and exercise
functions which, earlier in the twentieth century, had themselves come to be associated
with the federal state or provinces and states.
To think law as language then is in part to recognize the contemporary grip of
policy and administration on law. It is to consider how policy formulations and practices
30
Cornelia Vismann, Files: Law and Media Technology (Geoffrey Winthrop-Young trans., 2008).
31
See, for instance, the discussion in Frank Pasquale, Grand Bargains for Big Data: The Emerging Law of
Health Information, 72 Md. L. Rev. 682 (2013).
32
Christine Choi, Top 10 Overused LinkedIn Profile Buzzwords of 2013 (Dec. 11, 2013)
(http://blog.linkedin.com/2013/12/11/buzzwords-2013/).
33
Tom Pick, 101 Vital Social Media and Digital Marketing Statistics (Aug. 6, 2013)
(http://socialmediatoday.com/tompick/1647801/101-vital-social-media-and-digital-marketing-statistics-rest-2013).
74
Critical Analysis of Law 1:1 (2014)
correspond to particular ways of life. The point of doing so is not to come up with better
policies as such, but to keep open to us ways of thinking and speaking that policy discourses appear to preclude or to disfavor. It is to counter discourses that make law into a
set of optimal solutions or strategies and that associate imperfection with useless, irrational, unnecessary, ineffective, or inefficient means to ends, which must be fixed. It is instead
to recall the active voice, to insist that passions and desires are not necessarily calculable,
and to honor the imperfect—ongoing and interruptible, incompletely articulable—aspect
of other, non-efficient, non-policy traditions of law and of language. 34
Thinking about law as language thus goes beyond displacing dominant views of
law that consider power, force, threat, or command as most fundamental to law or that
define law as a system of rules. To think law as language is to think beyond the jurisdiction of an official or formally-sovereign state. Thinking law as language allows one to consider what modern law and policy says and does not say; to explore what bodies or communities of law show and do not show; to interpret what legal archives express, suppress,
and repress; and to do so unconstrained by demands of policy regulation. 35 In doing so,
one is bound neither to what has become an increasingly impossible romance with natural
law nor to the ostensibly realist cynicism and skepticism of law as social domination.
One responds more freely to the assertions and demands of policy as philosopher,
historian, lawyer, scholar, or other speaker or writer, than one can as a participant in the
limited-option instruments of policy research. In speaking of language and of the language
of law, we speak of law in a manner that is free of circumscribed demands of and for efficiency. With this freedom to speak comes our indebtedness to language, which indebtedness is neither a policy problem nor a solution. Indebtedness to language and freedom to
speak implicate another law, of which we have not yet explicitly spoken. All who speak—
including policy makers who, like Bartleby, 36 may prefer not to—are bound in the world,
as if by law, to language. The law of language is a gentle law, as Heidegger writes. 37 Human beings speak, by law, as what they are: speaking animals. 38 The manifestations and
materialities of language come as gifts of law revealing—ever imperfectly—who we are.
34
In addition to scholarship on “other” law traditions, see discussions of “justice” in the common-law tradition, as in Markus D. Dubber: The Sense of Justice: Empathy in Law and Punishment (2006).
35
On archives, see Jacques Derrida, Archive Fever: A Freudian Impression (Eric Prenowitz trans., 1995); on
the manner in which files act in accord with practices of legal reasoning, see Bruno Latour, The Making of
Law: An Ethnography of the Conseil d’Etat (Marina Brilman & Alain Pottage trans., 2010).
36
Herman Melville, Bartleby, the Scrivener: A Story of Wall Street (1853).
37
Martin Heidegger, The Way to Language, in On the Way to Language 111, 128-29 (Peter D. Hertz trans., 1982).
38
Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, I:13, refers to man as zoon logon echon.