Siberian Advances in Mathematics
1992, v. 2, No. 2, pp. 114–152
NONSTANDARD METHODS FOR KANTOROVICH SPACES
A. G. Kusraev and S. S. Kutateladze
Abstract. A Kantorovich space or a K-space is an order complete vector lattice.
Such spaces may be viewed as sublattices of the reals via Boolean-valued analysis.
Infinitesimal analysis is also beneficial. Interaction of the two nonstandard ideas
forms the bulk of exposition.
It is universally recognized that the thirties of the 20th century play a special
role in modern science. Outlined at the turn of the century, the tendency towards
drastic reorganization of mathematics has revealed itself since these years. It led to
the creation of a number of new mathematical subjects, functional analysis being
the first of them. Nowadays we realize the exceptional place of the seventies framed
sweeping changes both in volume and in essence of mathematical theories. In the period mentioned, a qualitative leap forward was registered in understanding mutual
interrelation and interdependence of mathematical subjects; outstanding advances
took place in working out new synthetic approaches and in finding solutions to
certain deep and profound problems unsolved for a long time.
The processes indicated above are characteristic of the theory of ordered vector spaces — the latter being one of the most actual and attractive branches of
functional analysis.
This trend marking the beginning of the thirties and due to the influence of contributions of F. Riesz, L. V. Kantorovich, H. Freudenthal, G. Birkhoff, et al., experiences now a certain period of revival connected with assimilating mathematical
ideas related to nonstandard models of set theory. Boolean-valued interpretations
(which acquire a popularity in connection with P. J. Cohen’s final solution to the
continuum hypothesis) open new possibilities of interpreting L. V. Kantorovich’s
heuristic transfer principle.
A. Robinson’s nonstandard analysis has in turn legitimized the development of
infinitesimal methods, substantiating G. W. Leibniz’s logical dream and opening
broad vistas to general monadology of vector lattices. Brand-new nonstandard
methods in K-space theory are under way.
Key words and phrases. nonstandard analysis, internal and external sets, infinitesimals,
monads.
Translated from PRIM, 1989, v. 14, 153–182.
Typeset by AMS-TEX
NONSTANDARD METHODS FOR KANTOROVICH SPACES
115
Expanding the well-known lines of N. S. Gumilëv, we can say that presently Kspaces “... are sloughing their skins to make room for souls to grow and mature ... .”
Many of the arising lacunas are not filled in yet due to the short time for settling the
corresponding problems rather than for the lack of proper understanding. At the
same time a number of principal questions stand in line and waits for comprehension
and novel ideas.
The aim of this paper is to present, to the broad community of specialists interested in methods of the theory of ordered vector spaces, a review of research into
adaptation of the tools of nonstandard set theory for investigating K-spaces and
classes of linear operators acting in them.
1. BASIC AXIOMATIC SET THEORIES
In this section we expose necessary information about formal set theories used
in modern K-space theory. First of all the classical Zermelo–Fraenkel axiomatics is
dealt with. Furthermore, Boolean-valued models ascending to the works of D. Scott,
R. Solovay, and P. Vopenka are tackled. In addition, we present one of the most
powerful and promising variants of external set theories which was recently proposed
by T. Kawai and is widely used in modern infinitesimal analysis.
1.1. Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory
The Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (abbreviated as ZF) is commonly employed as
an axiomatic foundation of mathematics nowadays. We shall briefly recall some of
its notions and introduce necessary notation. The details can be found in [6, 16,
21, 27, 40, 46, 47].
1.1.1. The language of the set theory ZF uses the following symbols (called the
alphabet of ZF): symbols of variables x, y, z, . . . ; the parentheses ( , ); the propositional connectives (= the signs of propositional algebra) ∧, ∨, →, ↔, ¬; the quantifiers ∀, ∃; the equality sign = and the symbol of the special binary predicate of
membership ∈. Informally the domain of variables of ZF is thought of as the world
— universe — of sets. The relation ∈ (x, y) is written as x ∈ y and read as “x is
an element of y.”
1.1.2. The formulas of ZF are defined by the usual recursive procedure. In other
words, a formula of ZF is a finite text formed from atomic formulas such as x = y
and x ∈ y, where x and y are variables of ZF, with the help of sensible arrangement
of parentheses, quantifiers, and propositional connectives. In addition, the ZF
theory is the least set of formulas which contains the axioms of ZF and is closed
under the rules of inference (see 1.1.4 below).
1.1.3. Common mathematical abbreviations are convenient in working with ZF.
Some of them follow:
(∀x ∈ y)ϕ(x) := ∀x (x ∈ y → ϕ(x));
(∃x ∈ y)ϕ(x) := ∃x (x ∈ y ∨ ϕ(x));
∪x := {z : (∃y ∈ x)z ∈ y};
∩x := {z : (∀y ∈ x)z ∈ y};
116
A. G. KUSRAEV AND S. S. KUTATELADZE
x ⊂ y := ∀z (z ∈ x → z ∈ y);
P(x) := “the class of all subsets of x ” := {z : z ⊂ x};
V := “the class of all sets ” := {x : x = x};
“the class A is a set ” := A ∈ V := ∃x∀y (y ∈ A ↔ y ∈ x);
f : X → Y := “f is a function from X into Y ”;
dom(f ) := “the domain of definition of f ”;
im(f ) := “the image of f ”.
1.1.4. The set theory ZF includes conventional axioms and rules of inference of
first-order theory with equality. They fix the standard ways of classical resoning
(syllogisms, the excluded middle, modus ponens, generalization, etc.). In addition,
the following six special or nonlogical axioms are considered (they are written down
with the standard abbreviations being accepted, cf. 1.1.3).
(1) The axiom of extensionality:
∀x∀y((x ⊂ y ∨ y ⊂ x) ↔ x = y).
(2) The axiom of union: ∀x(∪x ∈ V).
(3) The axiom of powerset: ∀x(P(x) ∈ V).
(4) The axiom schema of replacement:
∀x∀y∀z(ϕ(x, y) ∧ ϕ(x, z) → y = z)
→ (∀a)({v : (∃u ∈ a)ϕ(u, v)} ∈ V).
(5) The axiom of foundation: (∀x)(x 6= ∅ → (∃y ∈ x)(y ∩ x = ∅)).
(6) The axiom of infinity: (∃ω)((∅ ∈ ω) ∧ (∀x ∈ ω)(x ∪ {x} ∈ ω)).
The theory ZFC (Zermelo–Fraenkel theory with the axiom of choice) can be obtained from ZF by adding the following postulate.
(7) The axiom of choice:
(∀F )(∀x)(∀y)((x 6= ∅ ∧ F : x → P(y))
→ ((∃f )(f : x → y) ∧ (∀z ∈ x)f (z) ∈ F (z))).
1.1.5. The Zermelo set theory Z can be obtained from ZFC by deleting the axiom
of foundation 1.1.4(5) and replacing the axiom schema of replacement 1.1.4(4) by
its following consequences:
(1) the axiom schema of comprehension:
(∀x){y ∈ x : ψ(y)} ∈ V,
with ψ being a ZF formula;
(2) the axiom of pairing: (∀x)(∀y){x, y} ∈ V.
Thus, the special axioms of the theory Z are 1.1.4(1–3, 6, 7), 1.1.5(1, 2).
NONSTANDARD METHODS FOR KANTOROVICH SPACES
117
So, the theories Z, ZF, and ZFC have one and the same language, one and the
same logical axioms, and differ only in the collection of special axioms.
1.1.6. Remarks.
(1) The Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory slightly restricts a philistine mathematician by the axiom of foundation which, as a matter of fact, was proposed by J. von
Neumann in 1925. At the same time it is the postulate which ensures the basis
of the widely accepted set-theoretic view at the world of sets as at “the von Neumann universe” growing up hierarchically from the empty set — the mathematical
proatom.
(2) The Zermelo–Fraenkel axiomatics did not ban all the ways of searching alternative set-theoretic foundations. In this regard, refer in particular to [7].
1.2. Boolean-valued set theory
The theory of Boolean-valued models of set theory is outlined here in brief. In
[27, 44, 45, 47] more complete introductions are available.
1.2.1. Let B be a fixed complete Boolean algebra. By a Boolean-valued interpretation of an n-ary predicate on a class X we mean a suitably chosen mapping from X n
into B. Suppose that L is a first-order language with the predicates P0 , P1 , . . . , Pn ,
and let R0 , R1 , . . . , Rn be fixed Boolean-valued interpretations of these predicates
on a class X. For an arbitrary formula ϕ(u1 , . . . , um ) of the language L, and for
elements x1 , . . . , xm ∈ X, the truth value [[ϕ(x1 , . . . , xm )]] ∈ B is defined by usual
induction on the length of ϕ. For atomic formulas, write
[[Pk (x1 , . . . , xm )]] := Rk (x1 , . . . , xm ).
In induction steps the following rules are used:
[[ϕ ∨ ψ]] := [[ϕ]] ∨ [[ψ]],
[[ϕ ∧ ψ]] := [[ϕ]] ∧ [[ψ]],
[[ϕ → ψ]] := [[ϕ]] ⇒ [[ψ]],
[[¬ϕ]] := [[ϕ]]∗ ,
^
[[ϕ(x)]],
[[(∀x)ϕ]] :=
x∈X
[[(∃x)ϕ]] :=
_
[[ϕ(x)]],
x∈X
W V
∨, ∧, ⇒, ( · )∗ , , in the right-hand sides of the equalities standing for the Boolean
operations in B(a ⇒ b := a∗ ∨ b).
1.2.2. Say that a statement ϕ(x1 , . . . , xm ), with x1 , . . . , xm ∈ X and ϕ(u1 , . . . , um )
being a formula, is valid (true, veritable, etc.) in the system X := (X, R0 , . . . , Rn )
and write X |= ϕ(x1 , . . . , xm ) if [[ϕ(x1 , . . . , xm )]] = 1. All logically true statements are valid in X. If a predicate P0 symbolizes equality, then the B-system
X := (X, =, R1 , . . . , Rn ) is required to satisfy equality axioms. If this requirement
118
A. G. KUSRAEV AND S. S. KUTATELADZE
is fulfilled, then all logically true statements of the first-order logic with equality, which are expressible in the language L := {=, P1 , . . . , Pn }, are valid in the
B-system X.
1.2.3. Now let us consider a Boolean-valued interpretation on a class X of the language of the set theory ZFC (L := {=, ∈}), i.e., of the first-order language with two
binary predicates = and ∈. We shall denote the interpretations of these predicates
by [[· = ·]] and [[· ∈ ·]], respectively. Thus, [[· = ·]], [[· ∈ ·]] : X × X → B, and
[[= (x, y)]] = [[x = y]],
[[∈ (x, y)]] = [[x ∈ y]]
(x, y ∈ X).
Our nearest aim is to characterize B-systems X := (X, [[· = ·]], [[· ∈ ·]]), which are
models of ZFC and such that X |= ZFC . The last condition is equivalent to the
fact that all the axioms of ZFC are valid in X. So, for instance, by the rules of 1.2.1,
the validity of the axiom of extensionality 1.1.4(1) means that, for all x, y ∈ X,
[[x = y]] =
^
([[z ∈ x]] ⇔ [[z ∈ y]]),
z∈X
where a ⇔ b = (a ⇒ b) ∧ (b ⇒ a) (a, b ∈ B).
1.2.4. A B-system X is called separated whenever for all x, y ∈ X the statement
[[x = y]] = 1 implies x = y. An arbitrary B-system X can be transformed into
a separated one by taking the quotient with respect to the equivalence ∼:= {(x, y) ∈
X 2 : [[x = y]] = 1}. (A quotient class is defined with the help of the well-known
method of Frege–Russell–Scott, see [46].) A B-system X is said to be isomorphic
to a B-system X′ := (X ′ , [[· = ·]]′ , [[· ∈ ·]]′ ), if there is a bijection β : X → X ′ such
that [[x = y]] = [[βx = βy]], [[x ∈ y]] = [[βx ∈ βy]] for all x, y ∈ X.
1.2.5. Theorem. There exists a B-system X unique up to an isomorphism and
such that
(1) X is separated (see 1.2.4);
(2) the equality axioms are valid in X;
(3) the axiom of extensionality 1.1.4(1) and the axiom of foundation 1.1.4(5) are
true in X (see 1.2.3);
(4) if a function f : dom(f ) → B satisfies dom(f ) ∈ V and dom(f ) ⊂ X, then
for some x ∈ X
[[y ∈ x]] =
_
f (z) ∧ [[z = y]]
(y ∈ X);
z∈dom(f )
(5) for each x ∈ X, there exists a function f : dom(f ) → B with dom(f ) ∈ V,
dom(f ) ⊂ X, the equality in (4) being valid for every y ∈ X.
1.2.6. A B-system meeting the requirements 1.2.5(1–5) is called a Boolean-valued
model of set theory and is denoted by the symbol V(B) := (V(B) , [[· = ·]], [[· ∈ ·]]).
The class V(B) is also called the Boolean-valued universe. The basic properties of
V(B) are formulated in the following principles.
(1) The transfer principle. Every axiom, and hence every theorem of ZFC ,
is valid in V(B) ; in symbols: V(B) |= ZFC .
NONSTANDARD METHODS FOR KANTOROVICH SPACES
119
(2) The mixing principle. If (bξ )ξ∈Ξ is a partition of unity in B, and (xξ )ξ∈Ξ
is a family of elements of V(B) , then there exists a unique element x ∈ V(B) such
that bξ ≤ [[x = xξ ]] (ξ ∈ Ξ). The element x is called the mixture of the family (xξ )ξ∈Ξ
with probabilities (bξ )ξ∈Ξ and is denoted by mixξ∈Ξ bξ xξ (the term “mixing” is also
in use).
(3) The maximum principle. For every formula ϕ(u) of ZFC (possibly with
constants from V(B) ) there exists an element x0 ∈ V(B) such that
[[(∃u)ϕ(u)]] = [[ϕ(x0 )]].
It follows, in particular, that if [[(∃!x)ϕ(x)]] = 1, then there exists a unique
x0 ∈ V(B) such that [[ϕ(x0 )] = 1.
1.2.7.There exists a unique mapping x → x∧ from V to V(B) obeying the following
conditions:
(1) x = y ↔ [[x∧ = y ∧ ]] = 1; x ∈ y ↔ [[x∧ ∈ y ∧ ]] = 1 (x, y ∈ V),
W
(2) [[z ∈ y ∧ ]] = x∈y [[x∧ = z]] (z ∈ V(B) , y ∈ V).
This mapping is called the canonical imbedding of V into V(B) and x∧ is referred
to as the standard name of x.
(3) The restricted transfer principle. Let ϕ(u1 , . . . , un ) be a restricted
formula, i.e. with all the quantifiers in the form (∀u)(u ∈ v → . . . ) or (∃u) (u ∈
v ∧ . . . ) abbreviated to (∀u ∈ v), (∃u ∈ v). Then for every x1 , . . . , xn ∈ V,
∧
ϕ(x1 , . . . , xn ) ↔ V(B) |= ϕ(x∧
1 , . . . , xn ).
1.2.8. For an element X ∈ V(B) , its descent X ↓ is defined by designating X ↓=
{x ∈ V(B) : [[x ∈ X]] = 1}. The set X ↓ is cyclic, i.e. closed under mixing its
elements.
1.2.9. Let F be a correspondence from X to Y inside V(B) , i.e., X, Y, F ∈ V(B) and
[[F ⊂ X × Y ]] = [[F 6= ∅]] = 1. There exists a unique correspondence F↓ from X↓ to
Y ↓ such that for every set A ⊂ X↓ inside V(B) the equality F (A)↓= F↓ (A↓) holds.
Furthermore, [[F is a mapping from X to Y ]] = 1 if and only if F ↓ is a mapping
from X↓ to Y ↓.
In particular, a function f : Z ∧ → Y inside V(B) , where Z ∈ V, defines its
descent f↓: Z → Y ↓ by f↓ (z) = f (z ∧ ) (z ∈ Z).
1.2.10. Suppose that X ∈ P ( V(B) ). Define a function f : dom(f ) → B by declaring
dom(f ) = X and im(f ) = {1}. By 1.2.5(4) there exists an element X↑∈ V(B) such
that
_
[[x = y]] (y ∈ V(B) ).
[[y ∈ X]] =
x∈X
The element X↑ (which is unique by the axiom of extensionality) is called the
ascent of X. Moreover, the following formulas are true:
(1) Y ↓↑= Y (Y ∈ V(B) ),
(2) X↑↓= mix(X) (X ∈ P(V(B) )),
where mix(X) consists of all mixtures of the form mixbξ xξ , (xξ ) ⊂ X, (bξ ) being
a partition of unity in B.
1.2.11 Assume that X, Y ∈ P(V(B) ) and let F be a correspondence from X to Y .
The following statements are equivalent:
120
A. G. KUSRAEV AND S. S. KUTATELADZE
(1) there exists a unique correspondence F ↑ from X ↑ to Y ↑ inside V(B) such
that dom(F↑) = dom(F )↑ and, for every subset A of the set dom(F ),
F↑ (A↑) = F (A)↑;
(2) the correspondence F is extensional, i.e.,
y1 ∈ F (x1 ) → [[x1 = x2 ]] ≤
_
[[y1 = y2 ]].
y2 ∈F (x2 )
The correspondence F is a mapping from X to Y if and only if [[F ↑: X ↑→
Y ↑]] = 1.
In particular, a mapping f : Z → Y ↓ generates a function f ↑: Z ∧ → Y such
that f↑ (x∧ ) = f (x)(x ∈ Z).
1.2.12. Assume that a B-structure is defined on a nonempty set X, i.e., fix a mapping d : X × X → B satisfying the “metric axioms”:
(1) d(x, y) = 0 ↔ x = y;
(2) d(x, y) = d(y, x);
(3) d(x, y) ≤ d(x, z) ∨ d(z, y).
Then there exists an element X ∈ V(B) and an injection ι : X → X ′ := X↓ such
that d(x, y) = [[ι(x) 6= ι(y)]] and every element x′ ∈ X ′ can be represented in the
form x′ = mixbξ xξ , with (xξ ) ⊂ X and (bξ ) being a partition of unity in B. This
fact enables us to consider sets with B-structure as subsets of V(B) and to handle
them with the help of the rules described above.
Remarks.
(1) Boolean-valued analysis (the term was coined by G. Takeuti) is a branch
of functional analysis which uses Boolean-valued models of set theory. It is interesting to note that at origination Boolean-valued models were not connected with
the theory of vector lattices. The necessary language and technique were already
formed within mathematical logic by 1960. Nevertheless, the main idea leading to
rapid progress in the model theory was absent. Such idea emerged with P. J. Cohen’s establishing the absolute unsolvability (in a precise mathematical sense) of
the classical Continuum hypothesis. It was Cohen’s forcing whose comprehension
resulted in the invention of Boolean-valued models of set theory, the latter being
connected with the names of P. Vopenka, D. Scott, and P. Solovay (see [61, 63, 65,
66]).
(2) The method of forcing is naturally divided into two parts — general and special. The general part is presented by the apparatus of Boolean-valued models of set
theory. The Boolean algebra B is absolutely arbitrary here. The special part consists in constructing a specific Boolean algebra B in order to provide the necessary
(often pathological, even exotic) properties of objects (e.g., of a K-space) sprouting from B. The both parts are of independent interest; but the most impressive
results are obtained by combining the two. Most works on Boolean-valued analysis
use only the general forcing. The future progress in Boolean-valued analysis will
surely be connected with forcing in full strength (cf. [64]).
(3) The detailed information on this section can be found in [18, 21, 27, 64], see
also [10, 23]. Various modifications of tools described in 1.2.8–1.2.11 are widely used
NONSTANDARD METHODS FOR KANTOROVICH SPACES
121
in investigations of the theory of Boolean-valued models. In [17, 22] the machinery is
framed as the technique of descents and ascents which is more suitable for problems
in analysis. The embedding 1.2.12 of sets with Boolean structure into a Booleanvalued universe is carried out in [17]. The motivation of such embedding is the
Solovay–Tennenbaum method previously proposed for complete Boolean algebras
[61].
1.3. External set theory.
From the viewpoint of applications, the existing variants of formally founding
infinitesimal methods within axiomatic external set theory are almost equivalent.
In this connection we present here one of the strongest versions of external set
theory, the NST evoked by T. Kawai [53].
1.3.1. The alphabet of the theory NST is obtained from that of ZFC by adding
two constants VS and VI . Informally, VS is thought of as the universe of standard
sets, and VI as the world of internal sets (in rany material interpretation). We
point out that VS and VI are considered as concrete external sets, i.e., VS ∈ VE
and VI ∈ VE , where VE := {x : x = x} is the class of all external sets. Sometimes
instead of x ∈ VS we write St(x) or “x is a standard set.” In the same way there is
introduced the predicate Int ( · ) which expresses the property of being an internal
set.
The formulas are defined in the natural way. For ϕ ∈ (ZFC ), by the symbol
ϕS (respectively, ϕI ) we denote the relativization of ϕ on VS (on VI , respectively),
i.e., the formula obtained by imagining all variables of ϕ as ranging over standard
(respectively, internal) sets.
If ϕ ∈ (ZFC ) and ϕ is considered as a formula of NST, then sometimes we write
ϕE and call this expression E-formula. The notions of S-formula and I-formula
have the similar meaning.
Henceforth, we use the next conventional and convenient abbreviations of the
form (∀St x)ϕ := (∀x ∈ VS )ϕ; (∃Int x)ϕ := (∃x ∈ VI )ϕ; fin(x) := “x is finite” (=
not admitting a bijective mapping onto its proper subset); etc.
1.3.2. The special axioms of NST can be divided into three groups (the same
situation is typical of other variants of external set theories). The first group
consists of the rules for introducing external sets. The second includes the axioms
on interrelations between the worlds of sets VS , VI , and VE . Finally, the third
group contains the ordinary postulates of nonstandard analysis — the transfer,
idealization, and standardization principles.
1.3.3. We begin with the structure of the universe VE .
(1) The super-rule of introducing external sets: if ϕ is an axiom of ZFC, excluding
the axiom of foundation, then ϕE is an axiom of NST.
Thus, the axioms of the Zermelo theory Z act in NST, and the axiom schema of
replacement is valid. Moreover, we assume
(2) The restricted axiom of foundation:
(∀A)(A = ∅ ∨ A ∩ VI = ∅) → (∃x ∈ A)x ∩ A = ∅,
in other words, the regularity is postulated for external sets lacking in internal
elements.
122
A. G. KUSRAEV AND S. S. KUTATELADZE
Emphasize that VS ∈ VE . In other words, the usual axiom of acceptability is
valid (3.4.7 in [27]. We recall in this connection that an external set A is said to
be of acceptable size (or S-size), if there exists an external function that maps VS
onto A. In this case we write A ∈ Va−size .
1.3.4. The second group of axioms contains the following statements:
(1) the modeling principle (for standard sets) — the world VS is the von Neumann
universe, i.e., for each axiom ϕ of ZFC the standardization ϕS is an axiom of NST;
(2) the axiom of transitivity (for internal sets) — (∀x ∈ VI )x ⊂ VI , i.e., internal
sets are composed of internal elements only;
(3) the axiom of embedding — VS ⊂ VI , i.e., standard sets are internal.
1.3.5. The third group of postulates consists of the following axioms.
(1) The transfer principle —
(∀St x1 ) . . . (∀St xn )ϕS (x1 , . . . , xn ) ↔ ϕI (x1 , . . . , xn )
for every formula ϕ = ϕ(x1 , . . . , xn ), ϕ ∈ (ZFC ).
(2) The standardization principle —
(∀A)(∃St t)(◦A ⊂ t) → (∃St a)(∀St x)
(x ∈ A ↔ x ∈ a),
where ◦ A = A ∩ VS is the standard core of A. The appearing set a is obviously
unique. It is denoted by ∗ A and is called the standardization of A.
(3) The idealization principle (= the axiom schema of saturation) —
(∀Int x1 ) . . . (∀Int xn )(∀A ∈ Va−size )[[((∀z)z ⊂ A ∨ finE (z)
→ (∃Int x)(∀y ∈ z)ϕI (x, y, x1 , . . . , xn ))
→ (∃Int x)(∀Int y ∈ A)ϕI (x, y, x1 , . . . , xn )]]
for every formula ϕ = ϕ(x, y, x1 , . . . , xn ), ϕ ∈ (ZFC ).
1.3.6. Kawai’s theorem. NST is a conservative extension of ZFC .
1.3.7. As usual, inside VE we can construct the universe VC consisting of classical (= standard, or ordinary in Robinson’s approach) sets, by using the class of
standard ordinals, OnSt . Namely,
St
C
VC
β := {x : (∃ α ∈ β)x ⊂ P(Vα )},
VC :=
[
VC
β.
β∈OnSt
Robinson’s standardization ∗ : VC → VS appears in this situation via the recursion
schema:
∗∅ := ∅, ∗A := ∗ {∗a : a ∈ A}.
Robinson’s standardization provides validity of Leibniz’s principle in the form
(∀x ∈ VC ) . . . (∀xn ∈ VC )ϕC (x1 , . . . , xn ) ↔ ϕS (x1 , . . . , xn )
NONSTANDARD METHODS FOR KANTOROVICH SPACES
123
for a formula ϕ = ϕ(x1 , . . . , xn ) ∈ (ZFC ) and its relativizations ϕC and ϕS on VC
and VS respectively.
1.3.8. The world of the radical (and classical) stance of nonstandard analysis also
admits of an axiomatic description.
We shall describe the UNST theory analyzed by T. Kawai.
In UNST variables stand for external sets. There are constants VC , VI and
∗. The corresponding external sets are naturally called the classical world, the
universe of internal sets and Robinson’s standardization.
The special axioms of UNST are similar to those of NST.
1.3.9. The structure of the UNST universe is defined by the following postulates.
(1) The super-rule of introducing external sets (similar to 1.3.3(1)).
(2) The restricted axiom of foundation (cf. 1.3.3(2)).
1.3.10. The axioms of interrelations between the worlds of sets contain such propositions:
(1) the modeling principle (for classical sets) — the world VC is the von Neumann
universe;
(2) the axiom of transitivity (for internal sets) — in the form 1.3.4(2);
(3) the axiom of transitivity (for classical sets) — (∀x ∈ VC )x ⊂ VC , i.e. classical
sets are composed of classical elements only;
(4) the axiom of external assemblage (= the axiom of superstructure) — external
subsets of a classical set are classical;
(5) the axiom of Robinson’s standardization — ∗ is an (external) mapping from
VC into VI .
Obviously, according to 1.3.10(5) there exists a unique set VS consisting exactly
of VS := ∗(VC ). In UNST elements of VS are called standard sets. In analogy with
1.3.3(2), a set A is said to be of classical size (or of C-size) whenever there exists
an external function from VC onto A. In this case we write A ∈ Vc−size .
1.3.11. The postulates of nonstandard analysis in UNST are the following:
(1) The transfer principle in Leibniz’s form, 1.3.5;
(2) The idealization principle in the form of the axiom schema of saturation for
sets of classic size (cf. 1.3.5(3)).
Finally, the standardization ∗ A (which is a subset of an element of VS ) in UNST
of a set A presents the procedure
∗
A := ∗(∗−1 (A ∩ VS )).
The following proposition is immediate from 1.3.6.
1.3.12. The UNST theory is a conservative extension of ZFC .
While working with analytic objects below we shall adopt a free stance close to
the neoclassic and radical credos of nonstandard analysis. In particular, the field
of reals will be considered as a standard element of the world of internal sets, the
classic realization of R will be identified with the standard core ◦ R. The symbols
used in nonstandard analysis for infinitesimals, monads, etc., coincide with those
from [27].
1.3.13. Remarks.
(1) The axiomatic approach to nonstandard analysis has started conquering popularity after the papers of E. Nelson [27, 56], who evoked an axiomatics of internal
124
A. G. KUSRAEV AND S. S. KUTATELADZE
set theory. As a result, views on the essence of infinitesimal methods have changed
drastically (see [34]). The distinctive feature of changes undergone is a refusal of
a “shy” approach viewing infinitesimals as monsters of some exotic status.
(2) The axiomatic theories of external sets were proposed by K. Hrbacek and
T. Kawai (see [27, 34]). The above-indicated version of the theory follows [53].
Among the latest works we mention [14, 40] which expose, as a matter of fact,
convenient formalisms of a “graded” theory of external sets connected with the
conception of relative standardness.
2. BOOLEAN-VALUED ANALYSIS OF VECTOR LATTICES
An essentially new — nonstandard — possibility offered to the theory of ordered
spaces is a formalization of the heuristic view on elements of a K-space as certain
analogs of reals. Strictly speaking, points of a K-space mimic real numbers in
a suitable model of set theory. The corresponding formalism introduced in this
chapter presents one of the most fundamental and indispensable conceptions in the
theory of ordered vector spaces.
2.1. Kantorovich spaces.
The theory of vector lattices is exposed in a number of excellent monographs,
see, for instance, [10, 18, 19, 25, 26, 29, 31, 32, 38, 41, 42, 51]. Vector lattices used
to be also called Riesz spaces. Here we shall briefly dwell on order complete vector
lattices.
2.1.1. A Kantorovich space or, in brief, a K-space is such a vector lattice that
its each order bounded nonvoid subset has a supremum and an infimum. If each
countable order bounded nonempty subset of a vector lattice has a supremum and
an infimum, then this vector lattice is called a Kσ -space. Everywhere below E
designates a K-space.
A band in E is a set of the form
M ⊥ := {x ∈ E : (∀y ∈ M )|x| ∧ |y| = 0},
where M ⊂ E and M 6= ∅. The collection of bands, ordered by inclusion, forms
a complete Boolean algebra B(E), Boolean operations being as follows:
L ∧ K = L ∩ K, L ∧ K = (L ∪ K)⊥⊥ , L∗ = L⊥ (L, K ∈ B(E)).
The algebra B(E) is called the base of E.
2.1.2. To every band K ⊂ E corresponds the unique projection [[K]] so as to ensure
0 ≤ [[K]]x ≤ x for all 0 ≤ x ∈ E. The set P(E) of all these projections is equipped
with the order defined by ρ ≤ π ↔ imρ ⊂ imπ.
Let 1 be a unity in E, i.e. {1}⊥⊥ = E. An element e ∈ E is called unit, or
a fragment (= component) of unity if e ∧ (1 − e) = 0. The set E(E) := E(1) of all
unit elements is furnished with the order induced from E. The ordered sets P(E)
and E(E) are complete Boolean algebras.
2.1.3. Theorem. The mapping K → [[K]] is an isomorphism between the
Boolean algebras B(E) and P(E). And if there is a unity in E, then the mappings π → π1 from P(E) into E(E) and e → {e}⊥⊥ from E(E) into B(E) are also
isomorphism s between the Boolean algebras.
NONSTANDARD METHODS FOR KANTOROVICH SPACES
125
2.1.4. A K-space E is called universally complete (or extended in the Russian
terminology) if every nonempty set of mutually disjoint elements of E has a supremum. (Elements x and y are disjoint if |x| ∧ |y| = 0.) We shall give the most
important examples of universally complete K-spaces. For the sake of brevity we
restrict ourselves to the case of real scalars.
(1) The space M (Ω, Σ, µ) of equivalence classes of measurable functions, where
(Ω, Σ, µ) is a measure space, and µ is σ-finite (or, more generally, µ possesses the
direct sum property, cf. [46]). The base of the K-space M (Ω, Σ, µ) is isomorphic
to the Boolean algebra Σ/µ−1 (0) of measurable sets modulo sets of measure zero.
(2) The space C∞ (Q) of continuous functions defined on an extremally disconnected compactum Q with values in the extended real line and taking the values ±∞
only on a rare (= nowhere dense) set [10]. The base of this K-space is isomorphic
to the Boolean algebra of clopen (= closed and open) subsets of Q.
(3) The space Bor(Q) of equivalence classes of Borel functions defined on a topological space Q. Two functions are equivalent if they coincide on the complement
of a meager set. The base of the K-space Bor(Q) is isomorphic to the Boolean
algebra of Borel subsets of Q modulo meager sets.
(4) The space A of hermitian (not necessarily bounded) operators in a Hilbert
space which are adjoint to a commutative von Neumann algebra A (see [6, 30, 62]).
The base of the K-space A is isomorphic to the Boolean algebra of all projections
in A.
2.1.5. Let E and F be vector lattices. An operator T : E → F is said to be
positive if T x ≥ 0 for every 0 ≤ x ∈ E, and regular if T = T1 − T2 , with T1 , T2
being positive. The operator T is said to be order bounded (or o-bounded) if T (M )
is a order bounded set in F for every order bounded M ⊂ E. If F is a K-space
then the classes of regular and order bounded operators coincide. Moreover, the
following is true.
2.1.6. Riesz–Kantorovich theorem. If E is a vector lattice and F is a Kspace then the space L∼ (E, F ) of all regular operators from E into F is also a Kspace.
2.1.7. Remarks.
(1) The invention of the theory of vector lattices is customarily connected with
research of G. Birkhoff, L. V. Kantorovich, M. G. Kreı̆n, H.Nakano, F.Riesz,
H. Freudenthal, et al. Nowadays the theory and applications of vector lattices
form a vast domain of mathematics. It is painstakingly charted in monographs [3,
5, 10, 18, 19, 38, 42, 43, 51]. For the prerequisite of Boolean algebras, see [8, 27,
30, 64].
(2) The class of order complete vector lattices, i.e. of K-spaces, was introduced
by L. V. Kantorovich in his first fundamental paper [17]. There he has also suggested the heuristic transfer principle for K-spaces, the crux of the idea is that
elements of a K-space serve as generalized numbers. Later on this principle has
acquired a good deal of clarification in investigations of the author himself and his
disciples. As a matter of fact, the principle became one of the basal ideas playing an
organizing and directing role and led to more deep and elegant theory of K-spaces
abundant in various applications.
126
A. G. KUSRAEV AND S. S. KUTATELADZE
(3) During the first period of the theory development some attempts have already been made which were intended to formalizing the heuristic observation mentioned. In this direction so-called theorems on preservation of relations (sometimes
a less exact term “conservation” is also employed) appeared. They assert that if
an expression containing a finite number of functional relations is proved for reals, then the similar fact is preserved as being also true for elements of a K-space
(see [10, 19]). Unfortunately, there was no satisfactory explanation for the internal
mechanism controlling the phenomenon, the preservation of relations. Limits to
applying the above assertions and the general background of similarity and parallelism between them and their analogs in the classical function theory had not been
sufficiently clarified. The depth and universality of Kantorovich’s principle were
fully explicated within the frames of Boolean-valued analysis (see [13]).
2.2. Reals within Boolean-valued models.
Boolean-valued analysis began with the representation of “genuine” reals in
a Boolean-valued model. Such representation happened to be a universally complete K-space. On selecting a Boolean algebra B (algebra of measurable sets, of
regular open sets, or of projections in a Hilbert space) assumed as initial for the
Boolean-valued model V(B) , different universally complete K-spaces appear (the
spaces of measurable functions, or of semicontinuous functions, or of selfadjoint operators). Thus there was open a broad way of transfering all the knowledge about
numbers to many classical objects of analysis.
2.2.1. Under the field of real numbers we understand such an algebraic system
that the axioms of an archimedean ordered field (with distinct zero and unity) and
the axiom of completeness are valid. Recall two well-known statements.
(1) There exists a field of real numbers R being unique up to an isomorphism.
(2) If P is an Archimedean ordered field, then there exists an isomorphic embedding, h of P into R, such that the image h(P ) is a subfield of R containing the
subfield of rational numbers. In particular, h(P ) is dense in R.
2.2.2. On applying successively the transfer principle and the maximum principle
to 2.2.1(1), find such an element R ∈ V(B) that [[R is a field of real numbers]] =
1. Moreover, for every R′ ∈ V(B) satisfying the condition [[R′ is a field of real
numbers]] = 1, the equality [[ the ordered fields R and R′ are isomorphic ]] = 1 also
holds. In other words, in the model V(B) there is located a field of real numbers,
R, which is unique up to an isomorphism.
2.2.3. Note also that the formula ϕ(R), recording the axioms of an Archimedean
ordered field, is restricted. So, [[ϕ(R∧ )] = 1, i.e. [[R∧ is an Archimedean ordered
field]] = 1. Putting the statement 2.2.1(2) into the transfer principle, we obtain the
fact that [[R∧ is isomorphic to a dense subfield of R]] = 1. On these grounds we
infer below that R is the field of real numbers in the model V(B) , and R∧ is a dense
subfield of it.
Consider now the descent R↓ of the algebraic system R. In other words, we look
at the descent of the carrier set of R equipped with the descended operations and
order. For the sake of simplicity, the operations and order in R and R↓ will be
denoted by the same symbols +, ·, ≤.
2.2.4. Gordon’s theorem. Let R be the ordered field of reals in the model
V(B) . Then R↓ (equipped with the descended operations and order) is a universally
NONSTANDARD METHODS FOR KANTOROVICH SPACES
127
complete K-space with unity 1. Furthermore, there exists an isomorphism χ of the
Boolean algebra B onto the base P(R↓) such that the equivalences
χ(b)x = χ(b)y ↔ b ≤ [[x = y]],
χ(b)x ≤ χ(b)y ↔ b ≤ [[x ≤ y]]
hold for all x, y ∈ R and b ∈ B.
2.2.5. The universally complete K-space R↓ is at the same time a faithful f -algebra
with the ring unity 1, and for every b ∈ B the projection χ(b) is the operator of
multiplication by the unit element χ(b)1. It is clear, therefore, that the mapping
b → χ(b)1 (b ∈ B) is a Boolean isomorphism of B and the algebra of unit elements
E(R↓). This isomorphism is denoted by the same letter χ.
2.2.6. Recall that if E is a K-space with unity and x ∈ E, then the projection
of the unity onto the band {x}⊥⊥ is called the trace of x and is denoted by the
symbol ex . For a real λ, denote by exλ the trace of the positive part of λ1 − x, i.e.
exλ := e(λ1−x)+ . The mapping λ → exλ (λ ∈ R) is called the spectral function or the
characteristic of x.
For every element x ∈ R↓, the following relations hold:
ex = χ([[x 6= 0]]), exλ = χ([[x < λ∧ ]])
(λ ∈ R).
The next result states that every Archimedean vector lattice is realizable as
a sublattice of R in a suitable Boolean-valued model.
2.2.7. Theorem. Let E be an Archimedean vector lattice, then let R be the
field of reals in the model V(B) , and finally let j be an isomorphism of B onto the
base B(E). There exists an element E ∈ V(B) satisfying the following conditions:
(1) V(B) |= E is a vector sublattice of the field R considered as a vector lattice
over R∧ ;
(2) E ′ := E ↓ is a vector sublattice of R↓, E ′ is invariant with respect to every
projection χ(b)(b ∈ B), and each set of positive mutually disjoint elements of E ′
has a supremum;
(3) there exists an o-continuous lattice isomorphism ι : E → E ′ such that ι(E)
is a coinitial sublattice in R↓ (that is (∀0 < x ∈ R↓)(∃y ∈ ι(E))0 < y ≤ x);
(4) for every b ∈ B the projection onto the band generated in R ↓ by the set
ι(j(b)) coincides with χ(b).
2.2.8. The element E ∈ V(B) in Theorem 2.2.7 is called a Boolean-valued realization
of the vector lattice E. Thus, Boolean-valued realizations of Archimedean vector
lattices are vector sublattices of the field of reals, R, considered as a vector lattice
over the field R∧ .
Notice now several corollaries of 2.2.4 and 2.2.7, keeping the previous notations.
(1) If E is a K-space, then E = R, E ′ = R↓ and ι(E) is a foundation (= order
dense ideal) of the K-space R↓. Furthermore, ι−1 ◦ χ(b) ◦ ι is the projection onto
the band j(b) for every b ∈ B.
(2) The image ι(E) coincides with the whole R↓ if and only if E is a universally
complete K-space.
128
A. G. KUSRAEV AND S. S. KUTATELADZE
(3) Universally complete K-spaces are isomorphic if and only if their bases are
isomorphic.
(4) Let E be a universally complete K-space with unity 1. Then in E a multiplication can be uniquely defined in such a way that E becomes a faithful f -algebra
with 1 as a multiplication unity.
2.2.9. Not only Boolean-valued realizations of Archimedean vector lattices lead to
subsystems of the field R, see 2.2.7. We formulate, for instance, several statements
from [27].
Theorem. (1) The Boolean-valued realization of an Archimedean lattice-ordered
group is a subgroup of the additive group of the field R.
(2) An Archimedean f -ring contains two mutually complementing bands, one being a group with zero multiplication and realizable as in (1), and the other possessing
a subring of R as its Boolean-valued realization.
(3) An Archimedean f -algebra contains two mutually complementing bands, one
being a vector lattice with zero multiplication and realizable as in 2.2.7, and another
being representable as a subring and sublattice R considered as an f -algebra over
R∧ .
2.2.10. Remarks.
(1) The Boolean-valued status of the notion of K-space was exposed by Gordon’s
theorem obtained in [11]. This fact can be reformulated as follows: a universally
complete K-space is an interpretation of the field of reals in a suitable Booleanvalued model. Furthermore, every theorem (within ZFC) about real numbers has
its complete analog for the corresponding K-space. The transfer of one theorem
into the other is fulfilled by the instrumentality of precisely-defined procedures:
ascent, descent, canonic embedding, etc., i.e. by an algorithm, as a matter of
fact. Thus, Kantorovich’s motto: “elements of a K-space are generalized numbers”
finds a precise mathematical formulation within Boolean-valued analysis. On the
other hand, the heuristic transfer principle which has played an auxiliary role in
many investigations of the pre-Boolean-valued theory of K-spaces becomes a precise
method of research in Boolean-valued analysis.
(2) If, in 2.2.4, B is the σ-algebra of measurable sets modulo sets of measure zero,
then R↓ is isomorphic to the universally complete K-space of measurable functions
M (Ω, Σ, µ). This fact (for the Lebesgue measure on an interval) was known as far
back as Scott and Solovay’s article (see [60]). If B is a complete Boolean algebra
of projections in a Hilbert space, then R↓ is isomorphic to the space of selfadjoint
operators whose spectral function act into B. The two particular cases of Gordon’s
theorem were intensively and fruitfully exploited by G. Takeuti, see [62] and the
references in [27]. T. Jech [50, 51] also considered the object R↓ for general Boolean
algebras and rediscovered Gordon’s theorem at that. The notable distinction is in
the fact that in [51] a (complex) universally complete K-space with unity is defined
by another axiom system and is called a complete Stone algebra.
(3) The realization theorem 2.2.7 was obtained by A. G. Kusraev [25]. A close result (stated in somewhat different terms) appeared in the paper [52] which develops
the Boolean-valued interpretation of the theory of linearly ordered sets. Corollaries
2.2.7(3,4) are well known (see [10, 19]). The notion of a univesal completion of
a K-space was introduced by A. G. Pinsker in a slightly different way. He also
NONSTANDARD METHODS FOR KANTOROVICH SPACES
129
proved the existence of a unique, up to an isomorphism, universal completion for
an arbitrary K-space. The existence of an order completion of an Archimedean
vector lattice was established by A. I. Yudin. The corresponding references are in
[19]. All these facts can be easily derived from 2.2.4 and 2.2.7 (see [27] for details).
(4) As was already mentioned in 2.2.10(1), the initial attempts at formalizing
heuristic Kantorovich’s principle led to the theorems on preservation of relations
(see [10, 19]). The modern forms of such theorems are presented in [13, 52], see
also [27, 38, 39].
2.3. Functional calculus in K-spaces.
The most important structure properties of vector lattices — representability
by function spaces, the spectral theorem, the functional calculus, etc. — replicate
analogous properties of the field of reals in a suitable Boolean-valued model. We
shall briefly outline the Boolean-valued approach to the functional calculus in Kspaces.
2.3.1. Further we shall need the notion of the integral with respect to a spectral
measure. Let (Ω, Σ) be a measurable space; i.e., Ω is a nonempty set, and Σ is
a fixed σ-algebra of subsets of Ω. A mapping µ : Σ → B is said to be a spectral
measure if µ(Ω − A) = 1 − µ(A) and
µ(
∞
[
An ) =
n=1
∞
_
µ(An )
n=1
for every sequence (An ) of elements of the σ-algebra Σ.
Let B := E(E) be the Boolean algebra of unit elements of a K-space E with
a fixed unity 1. Consider a measurable function f : Ω → R. For an arbitrary
partition of the real line β := (λk )k∈Z , λk < λk+1 (k ∈ Z), limn→±∞ λn = ±∞,
denote by Ak the inverse image f −1 ([λk , λk+1 )) and arrange the integral sums
σ(f, β) :=
∞
X
λk µ(Ak ),
σ(f, β) :=
−∞
∞
X
λk+1 µ(Ak ),
−∞
where summation is performed in E. If there exists an element x ∈ E such that
{σ(f, β)} = x inf{σ(f, β)}, where the supremum and infimum are taken over all
partitions β := (λk ) of the real line, then the function f is said to be integrable with
respect to the spectral measure µ, or we say that the spectral integral Iµ (f ) exists
and write
Z
Z
Iµ (f ) := f dµ := f (t)dµ(t) := x.
Ω
Ω
2.3.2. Theorem. Set E := R↓ and let µ be a spectral measure with values in
B := E(E). Then for every measurable function f , the integral Iµ (f ) is the unique
element of the K-space E satisfying the following condition
[[Iµ (f ) < λ∧ ]] = µ({f < λ})(λ ∈ R),
where {f < λ} := {t ∈ Ω : f (t) < λ}.
It is clear from this theorem that if the integral Iµ (f ) ∈ E exists, then the mapping λ → µ({f < λ}) coincides with the spectral function of Iµ (f ). In particular, if
130
A. G. KUSRAEV AND S. S. KUTATELADZE
E is universally complete, then Iµ (f ) exists for every measurable function f . Moreover, on using elementary properties of the field R, the next result easily follows
from Theorem 2.3.2.
2.3.3. Theorem. Let E be a universally complete K-space, and let µ : Σ →
B := E(E) be a spectral measure. The spectral integral Iµ (·) is a sequentially ocontinuous (linear, multiplication, and lattice) homomorphism from the f -algebra
of measurable functions M(Ω, Σ) into E.
2.3.4. Let e1 , . . . , en : R → B be a finite collection of spectral functions with
values in the σ-algebra B. Then there exists a unique B-valued spectral measure
µ defined on the Borel σ-algebra B(Rn ) of the space Rn , for which
µ(
n
Y
n
^
(−∞, λk )) =
k=1
ek (λk ),
k=1
whenever λ1 , . . . , λn ∈ R.
2.3.5. Consider now an ordered collection of elements (n-tuple) x1 , . . . , xn of a Kspace E with unity 1. Let exk : R → B := E(E) be the spectral function of
xk . According to the proposition indicated above, there exists a spectral measure
µ : B(Rn ) → B such that
µ(
n
Y
(−∞, λk )) =
k=1
n
^
exk (λk ).
k=1
It is clear that the measure µ is uniquely defined by the n-tuple X := (x1 , . . . , xn ) ∈
E n . This allows us to write µX := µ and to say that µX is the spectral measure
of X. For the integral of a measurable function f : Rn → R with respect to the
spectral measure µX the following notations are convenient
b ) := f (X) := f (x1 , . . . , xn ) := Iµ (f ).
X(f
If X := {x} then we also write x
b(f ) := f (x) := Iµ (f ); in addition, the measure
µx := µX is said to be the spectral measure of the element x. For a function
f (t) = t (t ∈ R), Freudenthal’s spectral theorem follows from 2.3.2:
x=
Z
R
tdµx (t) =
Z∞
tdext .
−∞
We recall that the space B(Rn , R) of all Borel functions in Rn is a universally
complete Kσ -space and a faithful f -algebra.
2.3.6. Theorem. The spectral measures of an n-tuple X := (x1 , . . . , xn ) and
of an element f (X) are interrelated as follows
µf (X) = µX◦ f ← ,
NONSTANDARD METHODS FOR KANTOROVICH SPACES
131
with f ← : B(R) → B(Rn ) being the homomorphism defined by A → f −1 (A). In
particular, for arbitrary measurable functions, f ∈ B(Rn , R) and g ∈ B(R, R), the
next identity, (g ◦ f )(X) = g(f (X)), holds; with f (X) and g(f (X)) being existent.
Proof. By 2.3.2, for every λ ∈ R, we have
f (X)
µX (−∞, λ) = eλ
= [[f (X) < λ∧ ]] = µX ◦ f −1 (−∞, λ).
Hence, the spectral measures, µf (X) and µX ◦ f −1 , defined on B(R), coincide on
intervals of the form (−∞, λ). Using standard arguments of measure theory, we
derive that these measures coincide everywhere. To prove the second part, it suffices
to note that (g ◦ f )← = f ← ◦ g ← , and to use twice the statement obtained.
The next fact follows from 2.3.3 and 2.3.6.
2.3.7. Theorem. For each n-tuple X := (x1 , . . . , xn ) of elements of a universally complete K-space E, the mapping
b : f → X(f
b )
X
(f ∈ B(Rn , R))
is a unique sequentially o-continuous homomorphism of the f -algebra B(Rn , R) into
E such that the following condition holds
b λ ) = xk
X(d
k
(k := 1, . . . , n),
with dλk : (λ1 , . . . , λn ) → λk being a coordinate function in Rn .
2.3.8. We will briefly discuss two realizations of the universally complete K-space
R↓ which can be obtained with the help of 2.2.4. We recall the necessary definitions.
For a compactum Q, the symbol C∞ (Q) stands for the set of all continuous functions
from Q into R := R ∪ {+∞, −∞} which take the values ±∞ only on a rare (=
nowhere dense) set.
A resolution of unity in a Boolean algebra B is a mapping e : R → B meeting
the following conditions:
(1) s ≤ t → e(s) ≤ e(t) (s, t ∈ R);
V
W
(2) t∈R e(t) = 1, t∈R e(t) = 0;
W
(3) s∈R,s<t e(s) = e(t) (t ∈ R).
Let R(B) be the set of all resolutions of unity in B.
2.3.9. Theorem. Let B be a complete Boolean algebra. The set R(B) with
suitable operations and order is a universally complete K-space. The function which
maps an element x ∈ R↓ into the resolution of unity λ → [[x < λ∧ ]](λ ∈ R), is an
isomorphism between the K-spaces R↓ and R(B).
2.3.10. Theorem. Let Q be the Stone compactum of a complete Boolean algebra B, and let R be the field of reals in the model V(B) . The vector lattice C∞ (Q)
is isomorphic to the universally complete K-space R↓. The isomorphism is defined
by sending an element x ∈ R↓ to the function xˆ : Q → R according to the formula:
xˆ(q) = inf{λ ∈ R : [[x < λ∧ ]] ∈ q}.
2.3.11. Remarks.
132
A. G. KUSRAEV AND S. S. KUTATELADZE
(1) The notions of unity, unit element, and characteristic (spectral function of
an element) were introduced by H. Freudenthal. He also established the spectral
theorem, see 2.3.5 and [10, 19]. It follows from Theorem 2.3.9 that, for a complete
Boolean algebra B, the set of resolutions of unity is a universally complete K-space
with base isomorphic to B. This fact belongs to L. V. Kantorovich [19]. The
realization of an arbitrary K-space as a foundation of a universally complete Kspace was fulfilled by A. G. Pinsker (see [10, 19]). The possibility of realizing an
arbitrary K-space as a foundation in C∞ (Q) follows from 2.2.8(1) and 2.3.10. This
possibility was first established by B. Z. Vulikh and T. Ogasawara independently
(see [10, 19]).
(2) It follows from 2.3.4 that every spectral function with values in a σ-algebra
defines a spectral measure on the Borel σ-algebra of the real line. This fact was
first mentioned by V. I. Sobolev in [41]. Nevertheless, it was supposed in [41]
that such a measure can be obtained by the Carathéodory extension. As was
shown by D. A. Vladimirov, for a complete Boolean algebra of countable type
the Carathéodory extension is possible only if the algebra is regular. Thus, the
extension method leading to 2.3.4 considerably differs from the Carathéodory extension and is based on the Loomis–Sikorki representation of Boolean σ-algebras.
M. Wright derived Proposition 2.3.4 as a consequence of a Riesz theorem established
for operators with values in a K-space.
(3) Apparently, Borel functions of elements of an arbitrary K-space with unity
were first considered by V. I. Sobolev (see [10, 39]). Theorem 2.3.6 in full generality
is presented in [29, 30]. The Borel functional calculus of (countable and uncountable) collections of elements of an arbitrary K-space is also constructed in [29, 30].
A Boolean-valued proof of Theorem 2.3.7 is also available (see [5]).
(4) For other aspects of Boolean-valued analysis of vector lattices see [5, 23, 24,
27, 51, 52].
3. INFINITESIMALS IN VECTOR LATTICES
The apology to the Infinitesimal offered by A. Robinson immediately opened
new possibilities for the theory of Banach spaces. The central construction here is
the nonstandard hull of a space, the latter being the quotient space of the external
subspace of elements with finite norm over the monad of the space (= the set of
elements with infinitesimal norm). The adaptation of nonstandard hulls to the
theory of lattices is discussed in the first section of the current chapter. The rest
of it is devoted to a scantily explored theme of combining Boolean-valued and
infinitesimal methods. Theoretically two approaches are feasible. The first consists
in studying a Boolean-valued model realized within the internal world of external
set theory. This approach is outlined in Section 3.2. The second approach deals
with exploring a suitable fragment of nonstandard set theory (for instance, in the
form of ultraproduct or ultralimit) located inside the corresponding Boolean-valued
universe. The latter approach is introduced in the third section of the chapter. It is
important to note to this end that in spite of superficial resemblance, the formalisms
considered lead to tremendously different constructions in K-space theory. We
illustrate the arising peculiarities with the theories of cyclic topologies and cyclic
compactness which are of great importance to the Boolean-valued analysis.
NONSTANDARD METHODS FOR KANTOROVICH SPACES
133
3.1. Nonstandard hulls and Banach lattices.
In the geometric theory of Banach spaces the notion of the nonstandard hull is
fundamental.
3.1.1. Let (E, | · |) be an internal normed space. An element x ∈ E is called finite
(infinitesimal) if |x| is finite (infinitesimal). Denote by fin(E) and µ(E) the external
sets of all finite and, respectively, infinitesimal elements of E. Then fin(E) is an
(external) vector space over the field ◦ R, and µ(E) is its subspace. The quotient
b A norm is defined in E
b by the
space fin(E)/µ(E) is denoted by the symbol E.
formula
kπxk = st (kxk) ∈ ◦R (x ∈ fin(E)),
b is the quotient homomorphism. Furthermore, (E,
b k · k) is
where π : fin(E) → E
an external normed space, and is called the nonstandard hull of E. If the internal
b is called a hyperfinite dimensional space. If the
dimension of E is finite, then E
space (E, k · k) is standard, then ◦ E with the induced norm from E is an external
normed space, and the restriction of π on ◦ E is an isometric embedding of ◦ E into
b The inclusion ◦ E ⊂ E
b is usually assumed.
E.
b is a Banach space for every internal (not nec3.1.2. Theorem. The space E
essarily complete) normed space E.
Proof. Let BX (a, r) be a closed ball in X with center a and radius r. Consider
a decreasing sequence of balls BEb (e
xn , rn ) in X such that (xn )n∈◦ N ⊂ E, x
en = πxn ,
◦
(rn )n∈◦ N ⊂ R, and limn→∞ rn = 0. We may assume that rn decrease. Then
the sequence of internal closed balls BE (xn , rn + rn /2n+1 ) ⊂ E decreases. By
idealization principle, there exists an element x ∈ E lying in every of these balls.
The element x
e = π x is a common point of the balls BEb (e
xn , rn ).
3.1.3. Suppose that E is an internal normed lattice. Then we can define an order
b so that the quotient homomorphism π is positive. More precisely, if
relation in E
x
e := πx and y := πy, then we assume by definition
x
e ≤ ye ↔ (∃z ∈ µ(E))x ≤ y + z.
b is a Banach lattice with sequentially o-continuous norm.
The nonstandard hull E
b is order bounded.
Moreover, every increasing and norm bounded sequence in E
At the same time, it is worth noting that the nonstandard hull of an internal
norm lattice is not necessarily a K-space (not even a Kσ -space: for example, b
c0 ,
where c0 is the lattice of vanishing sequences).
3.1.4. Theorem. For an internal normed lattice E, the following statements
are equivalent:
(1) E is a K-space;
b is a Kσ -space;
(2) E
b has an o-continuous norm;
(3) E
b there is no closed sublattice, isometric and order isomorphic to the
(4) in E,
Banach lattice c0 .
3.1.5. A normed lattice is said to be rich in finite-dimensional sublattices, if for
every finite collection x1 , . . . , xn ∈ ◦ E, n ∈ ◦ N, and for arbitrary 0 < ε ∈ ◦ R there
134
A. G. KUSRAEV AND S. S. KUTATELADZE
exists a finite-dimensional sublattice E0 ⊂ ◦ E and elements y1 , . . . , yn ∈ E0 such
that the inequality kxk − yk k < ε holds for all k := 1, . . . , n.
A standard Banach lattice E is rich in finite-dimensional sublattices if and only
b
if ◦ E is contained in a hyperfinite-dimensional subspace of the hull E.
3.1.6. Suppose now that E and F are internal normed spaces and T : E → F is
an internal linear bounded operator. The set
c(T ) := {C ∈ R : (∀x ∈ E)kT xk ≤ Ckxk}
is internal and bounded from above. Hence, kT k := inf c(T ) exists. If kT k is finite
then it follows from the inequality kT xk ≤ kT k·kxk(x ∈ E) that T (fin(E)) ⊂ fin(E)
b → Fb is well defined by the
and T (µ(E)) ⊂ µ(E). Thus, an external operator Tb : E
formula
Tbπx = πT x (x ∈ E).
The operator Tb is linear (over ◦ R) and bounded; moreover, kTbk = st kT k. It is
natural to call Tb the nonstandard hull of T .
If E and F are normed lattices, and the operator T is positive; then Tb is a positive
sequentially o-continuous operator.
3.1.7. It can be easily seen that, for bounded operators S and T , the equality (S ◦
T )∧ = Sb ◦ Tb holds; and, in addition, IeE = IEb , with IX being the identity operator
on X. Thus, the operation of passing to nonstandard hull is a covariant functor (in
the suitable categories of normed spaces). A good deal of questioning about general
properties of this functor arises. How does the nonstandard hull functor cooperate
with other functors of the theory of Banach spaces (lattices)? How do the wellknown properties in the geometrical theory of Banach spaces (Radon–Nikodým
property, Kreı̆n–Mil′ man property, etc.) transform under this functor? What is
the structure of nonstandard hulls of concrete spaces? Analogous questions can be
formulated for operators as well (see [24]), so forth and so on. The main ideas and
methods are exposed in the surveys [1, 4, 5, 27]. Here we shall briefly outline the
three important directions and formulate simple illustrative statements.
3.1.8. Analytical description for nonstandard hulls. The most complete
investigation of this question is carried out for the classical Banach spaces.
Theorem. (1) If E is an internal ALp -space, where p, 1 ≤ p, is a finite element
b is an ALr -space, for r = st (p).
of R, then E
(2) If E is in internal ALp -space, with p being an infinite element of R, or if E
b is an AM -space.
is an internal AM -space, then E
(3) If Q is an internal compactum, and C(Q) is the internal space of continuous
b where Q
b is the
functions from Q to R, then C(Q)∧ is linearly isometric to C(Q),
external completion of Q in some uniformity.
In axiomatic external set theory only general results of this type can be obtained.
Nevertheless, while working in a frame of classical stance of nonstandard analysis
(i.e. in a finite fragment of the von Neumann universe), a more detailed description
of nonstandard hulls is possible.
3.1.9. Local geometry of normed spaces. Some properties of a normed space
are “local” in the sense that they are defined by the structure and localization of
NONSTANDARD METHODS FOR KANTOROVICH SPACES
135
finite-dimensional subspaces of the space. In this regard, nonstandard hulls have
much more preferable structure. For instance, it often appears that if a condition
is satisfied “approximately” on finite-dimensional subspaces, then this condition is
satisfied “exactly” in the nonstandard hull.
Let E and F be Banach lattices. The lattice E is said to be finitely representable
in F (as a Banach sublattice), if for every finite-dimensional sublattice E0 ⊂ E and
every number ε0 there exists a linear and lattice isomorphism T : E0 → F such
that kxk ≤ kT xk ≤ (1 + ε)kxk (x ∈ E0 ).
Theorem. Let E be a standard Banach lattice rich in finite-dimensional sublattices (3.1.5), and let F be an internal Banach lattice. Then ◦ E is finitely representable in F if and only if ◦ E is linearly isometric and lattice isomorphic to
a sublattice of Fb .
3.1.10. Model-theoretic properties. We will introduce a first-order language
LB . The signature of the language is {=, +, P, Q}∪Q, where Q is the set of rationals.
Every Banach space E can be considered as a model of LB via interpreting =
and + respectively as equality and addition, P as {x ∈ E : kxk ≤ 1}, Q as
{x ∈ E : kxk ≥ 1}, and finally, every r ∈ Q as the operation of multiplying by r.
A formula ϕ of LB of the form (Sx1 ) . . . (Sxn )(ϕ1 ∧ . . . ∧ ϕn ), where S is a restricted
quantifier and ϕk is a conjunction of formulas of the form u = v, P (u), Q(u), is
called a restricted positive formula. If ϕ is such a formula and m is a natural (6= 0),
then ϕm is a new formula constructed as follows: in the subformulas ϕ1 , . . . , ϕn
the expression u = v should be replaced by P (m(u − v)), P (u) by P ((1 − 1/m)u),
Q(u) by Q((1 + 1/m)u). If ϕm is valid in E for all m ∈ N, then ϕ is said to
be approximately valid in E. Banach spaces E and F are called approximately
equivalent, if the same restricted positive formulas are approximately valid in them.
Theorem. (1) Banach spaces are approximately equivalent if and only if their
nonstandard hulls are isometric.
(2) Let µ and ν be σ-finite measures, and 1 ≤ p < ∞. The spaces Lp (µ) and
Lp (ν) are approximately equivalent if and only if the measures µ and ν either have
the same finite number of atoms or both possess an infinite number of atoms.
3.1.11. Remarks.
(1) The nonstandard hull of a Banach space was introduced by W. A. J. Luxemburg [27]. The ultraproducts of Banach spaces introduced by D. Dacunha—Castelle
and I. L. Krivine [45] are very similar to nonstandard hulls. About the role of these
notions in the theory of Banach spaces, the most important results, and further
references, consult [27, 57].
(2) The first-order language described in 3.1.10 was employed first by W. Henson and later on by J. Stern (see [57]). The notion of finite representability had
come into the theory of Banach spaces long before appealing to the set-theoretic
technique. It was introduced by A. Dvoretsky (the term is due to R. C. James).
(3) About 3.1.4, 3.1.5 and 3.1.9 see W. Henson’s article in [57].
3.2. Boolean-valued modeling in the nonstandard universe.
In Boolean-valued analysis a new important class of mathematical objects is
introduced — the class of structures with cyclic property (= closure under mixing,
136
A. G. KUSRAEV AND S. S. KUTATELADZE
see 1.2.6(2)). These objects are the descents of corresponding formations in V(B) ,
see 1.2.8. As a matter of fact, the methodology developed by infinitesimal analysis
is connected with inventing a special machinery for studying filters — monadology.
Let F be a standard filter, let ◦ F be its standard core, and let a F := F \ ◦ F be
the external set of astray or distant elements of F. If
µ(F) := ∩◦ F = ∪a F
is the monad of F, then F = ∗ ss({µ(F)}), with ss(A) standing for the collection
of all supersets of A. The notion of monad is central to the external set theory.
In this connection the development of combined methods, in particular, applying
infinitesimals and ascents simultaneously in K-space theory requires adaptation
of the notion of monad for filters and their images. In this section we pursue
an approach in which the ordinary monadology is applied to descents of objects.
An alternative way — applying the standard monadology inside V(B) with further
descending — will be considered in the next section.
3.2.1. We shall recall some constructions from the theory of filters in V(B) .
Let G be a filterbase on X, and X ∈ P(V(B) ). Write
G ′ := {F ∈ P(X↑)↓: (∃G ∈ G)[[F ⊃ G↑] = 1};
G ′′ := {G↑: G ∈ G}.
Then G ′ ↑ and G ′′ ↑ are bases of one and the same filter G ↑ on X ↑ inside V(B) .
The filter G ↑ is called the ascent of G. If mix(G) is the set of all the mixtures
of nonempty families formed by elements of G, and G consists of cyclic sets, then
mix(G) is a filterbase on X and G ↑ = mix(G)↑ .
If F is a filter on X inside V(B) , then write F ↓ := ss({F↓: F ∈ F↓}). The filter
↓
F on X↓ is called the descent of F. A filterbase G on X↓ is called extensional, if
there is a filter F on X such that ss(G) = F. Finally, the descents of ultrafilters
in X are called proultrafilters on X↓. A filter having a base of cyclic sets is called
cyclic. Proultrafilters are maximal cyclic filters.
3.2.2. Fix a standard complete Boolean algebra B and the corresponding Booleanvalued universe V(B) thought of as being composed of internal sets. If A is an
external set, then the cyclic hull, mix(A), is introduced as follows. Say that an element x ∈ V(B) belongs to mix(A), if there is an internal family (aξ )ξ∈Ξ of elements
of A and an internal partition (bξ )ξ∈Ξ of unity in B, such that x is the mixture
of (aξ )ξ∈Ξ with probabilities (bξ )ξ∈Ξ , i.e. bxξ = bξ aξ for ξ ∈ Ξ or, equivalently,
x = mixξ∈Ξ (bξ aξ ).
3.2.3. Theorem. For a filter F on X↓, consider
F↑↓:= ss({F↑↓: F ∈ F}).
Then mix(µ(F)) = µ(F↑↓), and F↑↓ is the greatest cyclic filter coarser than F.
In connection with this theorem, the monad of F is called cyclic, if µ(F) =
mix(µ(F)). Unfortunately, cyclicity of a monad is not completely responsible for
NONSTANDARD METHODS FOR KANTOROVICH SPACES
137
extensionality of a filter. In this connection, the cyclic monad hull µc (U ) of an
external set U should be introduced. Namely, we are compelled to set
x ∈ µc (U ) ↔ (∀St V = V ↑↓)V ⊃ U → x ∈ µ(V ).
In particular, if B = {0, 1}, then µc (U ) coincides with the monad of the standardization of the external filter of supersets of U , i.e. with the so-called (discrete)monad
hull µd (U ) (the word “monadic” is also employed).
3.2.4. The cyclic monad hull of a set is the cyclic hull of its monad hull
µc (U ) = mix(µd (U )).
e
A special role is played by essential points of X ↓ constituting the external set
X. By definition, e X consists of elements of proultrafilter monads in X↓.
Criterion for essentiality. A point is essential if and only if it can be separated
by a standard set from every standard cyclic set not containing the point.
3.2.5. If in the monad of ultrafilter F there is a an essential point, then µ(F) ⊂ e X,
and moreover, F↑↓ is a proultrafilter.
The next statement follows from the constructions and considerations presented
above.
3.2.6. Criterion for filter extensionality. A filter is extensional if and only
if its monad is the cyclic monad hull of the set of its own essential points.
3.2.7. A standard set is cyclic if and only if it is the cyclic monad hull of its own
essential points.
3.2.8. Nonstandard criterion for a mixture of filters. Let (Fξ )ξ∈Ξ be
a standard family of extensional filters, and let (bξ )ξ∈Ξ be a standard partition of
unity. The filter F is the mixture of (Fξ )ξ∈Ξ with probabilities (bξ )ξ∈Ξ if and only
if
(∀St ξ ∈ Ξ)bξ µ(F) = bξ µ(Fξ ).
A peculiarity of the approach presented exposes itself in applications to the
descents of topological spaces through a special new role of essential points. In this
connection, we note some properties of the latter.
3.2.9. The following statements are true:
(1) the image of an essential point with respect to an extensional mapping is an
essential point of the image;
(2) let E be a standard set, and let X be a standard element of V(B) . Consider
∧
the product X E inside V(B) , where E ∧ is the standard name of E in V(B) . If x
∧
is an essential point of X E ↓, then for every standard e ∈ E the point x↓ (e) is
essential in X↓;
(3) let F be a cyclic filter in X ↓, and let e µ(F) := µ(F) ∩ e X be the set of
essential points of its monad. Then
e
µ(F) = e µ(F ↑↓ ).
Let (X, U ) be a uniform space inside V(B) . The uniform space (X↓, U ↓ ) is called
procompact (= cyclic compact), if (X, U ) is compact inside V(B) . The similar sense
is implied in the notion of pro-total-boundedness and so on.
138
A. G. KUSRAEV AND S. S. KUTATELADZE
3.2.10. Nonstandard criterion for procompactness. Every essential point
of X↓ is nearstandard (i.e. infinitesimally close to a standard point) if and only if
X↓ is procompact.
It is easily seen from Theorem 3.2.10, that the Boolean-valued criterion of procompactness differs from the usual one: “a compact space is a space formed by
nearstandard points.” The existence of a great number of procompact and noncompact spaces provides the variety of examples of nonessential points. We note
here that a combined application of 3.2.10 and 3.2.9(2), of course, allows us to produce a nonstandard proof of a natural analog of Tychonoff’s theorem for a product
of procompact spaces — “the descent of Tychonoff’s theorem in V(B) .”
3.2.11. Nonstandard criterion for proprecompactness. A standard space
is a descent of a totally bounded uniform space if and only if its every essential
point is prenearstandard (i.e. is in the monad of a Cauchy filter).
We shall apply the approach presented to description for o-convergence in a Kspace Y . To save space, we restrict ourselves to the consideration of filters containing order intervals (or, equivalently, filters with bounded monads). In addition, in
accordance with the same end, the K-space Y is assumed to be universally complete. By Gordon’s theorem, the space Y can be assumed to be realized as the
descent R↓ of the element R representing the field of reals R in the Boolean-valued
universe V(B) constructed over the base B of the space Y . Let us denote by E the
filter of order units in Y , i.e. the set E := {ε ∈ Y+ : [[ε = 0]] = 0}. We write x ≈ y
whenever elements x, y ∈ Y are infinitely close with respect to the descent of the
natural topology of R in V(B) , i.e. x ≈ y ↔ (∀St ε ∈ E)|x − y| < ε. For a, b ∈ Y ,
we write a < b if [[a < b]] = 1, in other words, a > b ↔ a − b ∈ E. Thus, there is a
deviation from the understanding of the theory of ordered vector spaces. Of course,
this circumstance is necessitated if we want to follow the principles of introducing
notations for descents and ascents. Let ≈ Y be the nearstandard part of Y . For
y ∈ ≈ Y , denote by ◦ y (or by st (y)) the standard part of y, i.e. the unique standard
element infinitely closed to y.
3.2.12. Theorem. For a standard filter F in Y and a standard z ∈ Y , the
following statements are true:
(1) inf F ∈F sup F ≤ z ↔ (∀y ∈ ◦ µ(F↑↓))◦ y ≤ z ↔ (∀y ∈ e µ(F↑↓))◦ y ≤ z;
(2) supF ∈F infF ≥ z ↔ (∀y ∈ ◦ µ(F↑↓))◦ y ≥ z ↔ (∀y ∈ e µ(F↑↓))◦ y ≥ z;
(3) inf F ∈F sup F ≥ z ↔ (∃y ∈ ◦ µ(F↑↓))◦ y ≥ z ↔ (∃y ∈ e µ(F↑↓))◦ y ≥ z;
(4) supF ∈F infF ≤ z ↔ (∃y ∈ ◦ µ(F↑↓))◦ y ≤ z ↔ (∃y ∈ e µ(F↑↓))◦ y ≤ z;
o
(5) F → z ↔ (∀y ∈ e µ(F↑↓))y ≈ z ↔ (∀y ∈ µ(F ↑↓ ))y ≈ z. Here ◦ µ(F ↑↓) :=
µ(F ↑↓) ∩ ≈ Y , and, as usual, e µ(F ↑↓) is the set of essential points of the monad
µ(F↑↓), i.e. e µ(F↑↓) = µ(F↑↓) ∩ e R.
Proof. To illustrate we shall prove (3).
Suppose, at first, that in the greater set ◦ µ(F↑↓) there is an element y such that
◦
y ≥ z. For every standard F ∈ F we have y ∈ F↑↓. Hence, if ε ∈ ◦ E then y z − ε
and sup F = sup F ↑↓ z − ε. By Leibniz’s principle we obtain: (∀St F ∈ F)(∀St ε >
0) sup F ≥ z, i.e. (∀F ∈ F) sup F ≥ z and inf F ∈F sup F ≥ z.
NONSTANDARD METHODS FOR KANTOROVICH SPACES
139
To prove the rest, begin with noting that by properties of the upper limit in R
and by the transfer principle of Boolean-valued analysis we have
[[(∃G)(G is an ultrafilter in R ∧ G ⊃ F ↑ ∧ inf sup G ≥ z)]] = 1.
G∈G
According to the maximum principle, there is a proultrafilter G such that G ⊃ F ↑↓
and inf G∈G sup G ≥ z. Using the transfer and idealization principles, we obtain
successively
(∀St G ∈ G) sup G ≥ z ↔ (∀St G ∈ G)[[sup G↑= z]] = 1
↔ (∀St G ∈ G)[(∃ε > 0)(∃g ∈ G↑)g > z − ε]] = 1
↔ (∀St G ∈ G)(∀ε > 0)(∃g ∈ G↑↓)g > z − ε
↔ (∀St G ∈ G)(∀St ε > 0)(∃g ∈ G↑↓)g > z − ε
↔ (∀Stfin G0 ⊃ G)(∀Stfin E0 ⊂ E)(∃g)
(∀G ∈ G0 )(∀ε ∈ E0 )(g ∈ G↑↓ ∨g > z − ε)
↔ (∃g)(∀St G ∈ G)(∀St ε0)(g ∈ G↑↓ ∨g > z − ε)
↔ (∃g ∈ µ(G ↑↓ ))◦ g ≥ z ↔ (∃g ∈ µ(G))◦ g = z.
The observation,
µ(G) ⊂ e µ(F ↑↓ ) = e µ(F↑↓) ⊂ ◦ µ(F↑↓),
completes the proof.
3.2.13. Remarks.
(1) The monadology as a philosophical doctrine was developed by G. W. Leibniz
[37]. The general theory of monads of filters was proposed by W. A. J. Luxemburg.
Cyclic topologies are widely used in Boolean-valued analysis. The theory of cyclic
compactness and the principles of dealing with images of filters are presented in
[24, 33, 35]. Our introducing the cyclic monadology follows the general line of [33,
35].
(2) Considering ultraproducts inside the Boolean-valued universe causes no difficulty in principle and was adopted in several papers. We do not discuss here how
Robinson’s standardization is introduced in V(B) ; as a matter of fact, an axiomatic
approach is also possible. The decisive element is the appearance of excrescences
on K-spaces sprouting, generally speaking, out of the uncustomary way of standardizing the source space (effect of essential points). Our presentation follows
[28].
3.3. Infinitesimal modeling inside the Boolean-valued universe.
In this section we assume a complete Boolean algebra B and a separated universe
V(B) to be fixed.
Applying methods of infinitesimal analysis we adopt the classical A. Robinson’s
approach realized inside V(B) . In other words, in concrete situations the classical
and internal universes and the corresponding *-map (Robinson’s standardization)
140
A. G. KUSRAEV AND S. S. KUTATELADZE
are understood as elements of V(B) . Moreover, the nonstandard world is supposed
to be saturated to a degree required.
3.3.1. The descent of the *-map will be called the descent standardization. Side
by side with the term of descent standardization we also use the expressions as
“B-standardization,” “prostandardization,” etc. Furthermore, for Robinson’s standardization of a B-set A the symbol ∗ A is used. Respectively, the descent standardization of a set A with B-structure (i.e. a subset of V(B) ) is defined as (∗ (A↑))↓ and
is denoted by the symbol ∗ A (it is meant here that A↑ is an element of the standard
world located in V(B) ). Thus, ∗ a ∈ ∗ A ↔ a ∈ A↑↓. The descent standardization ∗ Φ
of an extensional correspondence Φ is also defined in a natural way. While considering descent standardizations of standard names of elements of the von Neumann
universe V, for convenience we shall use the abbreviations in writing ∗ x := ∗ (x∧ )
and respectively ∗ x := (∗ x) ↓ for x ∈ V. The rules of placing and omitting (by
default) asterisks in using the descent standardization are also assumed to be as
free as those for Robinson’s ∗-map.
3.3.2. The transfer principle. Let ϕ = ϕ(x, y) be a formula of the Zermelo–
Fraenkel theory (without any free variables except x and y). For a nonempty
element F in V(B) and for every z we have:
(∃x ∈ ∗ F )[[ϕ(x, ∗ z)]] = 1 ↔ (∃x ∈ F↓)[[ϕ(x, z)]] = 1;
(∀x ∈ ∗ F )[[ϕ(x, ∗ z)]] = 1 ↔ (∀x ∈ F↓)[[ϕ(x, z)]] = 1.
If G is a subset of V(B) , then the following equivalences are true:
(∃x ∈ ∗ G)[[ϕ(x, ∗ z)]] = 1 ↔ (∃x ∈ G↑↓)[[ϕ(x, z)]] = 1;
(∀x ∈ ∗ G)[[ϕ(x, ∗ z)]] = 1 ↔ (∀x ∈ G↑↓)[[ϕ(x, z)]] = 1.
3.3.3. The idealization principle. Let X↑ and Y be classical elements of V(B)
and let ϕ = ϕ(x, y, z) be a formula of the Zermelo–Fraenkel theory. For an internal
element z in V(B) we have:
(∀fin A ⊂ X)(∃y ∈ ∗ Y )(∀x ∈ A)[[ϕ(∗ x, y, z)]] = 1
↔ (∃y ∈ ∗ Y )(∀x ∈ X)[[ϕ(∗ x, y, z}]] = 1.
For a filter F of sets with B-structure, its descent monad m(F) is defined as
follows:
\
∗
F.
m(F) :=
F ∈F
3.3.4. Theorem. Let E be a set of filters and let E ↑ := {F ↑ : F ∈ E} be its
ascent in V(B) . The following statements are equivalent:
(1) the set of cyclic hulls E↑↓:= {F↑↓: F ∈ E} is bounded above;
(2) the set E ↑ is bounded above inside V(B) ;
(3) ∩{m(F) : F ∈ E}6 = ∅.
Moreover, if the conditions (1)–(3) are satisfied, then
m(sup E↑↓) = ∩{m(F) : F ∈ E};
sup E ↑↓ = (sup E)↑ .
It is useful to note that for an infinite set of descent monads, its union (and even
the cyclic hull of this union) is not a descent monad in general. The situation here
is the same as for ordinary monads.
NONSTANDARD METHODS FOR KANTOROVICH SPACES
141
3.3.5. Nonstandard criteria for a proultrafilter. The following statements
are equivalent:
(1) A is a proultrafilter;
(2) A is an extensional filter with inclusion-minimal descent monad;
(3) the representation A = (x)↓ := ss({A↑↓: x ∈ ∗ A}) holds for each point x of
the descent monad m(A);
(4) A is such an extensional filter that its descent monad can be easily caught by
a cyclic set, i.e. for every U = U↑↓ we have either m(A) ⊂ ∗ U or m(A) ⊂ ∗ (X \U );
(5) A is a cyclic filter satisfying the condition: for every cyclic U , if ∗ U ∩m(A) 6=
∅ then U ∈ A.
3.3.6. Nonstandard criterion for a mixture of filters. Let (Fξ )ξ∈Ξ be
a family of filters, let (bξ )ξ∈Ξ be a partition of unity, and let F = mixξ∈Ξ (bξ Fξ↑ ) be
the mixture of (Fξ↑ )ξ∈Ξ with probabilities (bξ )ξ∈Ξ . Then
m(F ↓ ) = mixξ∈Ξ
(bm
ξ (Fξ )).
It is useful to compare 3.3.6 with 3.2.8.
A point y of the set ∗ X is called descent-nearstandard (or simply nearstandard if
there is no danger of misunderstanding) whenever for some x ∈ X↓ one has ∗ x ≈ y
(i.e. (x, y) ∈ m(U↓ ), with U being the uniformity on X).
3.3.7. Nonstandard criterion for procompactness. The set A↑↓ is procompact if and only if every point of ∗ A is descent-nearstandard.
It is reasonable to compare 3.3.7 with 3.2.10.
Finally, we will formulate certain general principles of using the descent standardization.
3.3.8. Let ϕ = ϕ(x) be a formula of the Zermelo–Fraenkel theory. The truth value
of ϕ is constant on the descent monad of every proultrafilter A, i.e.
(∀x, y ∈ m(A))[[ϕ(x)]] = [[ϕ(y)]].
3.3.9. Theorem. Let ϕ = ϕ(x, y, z) be a formula of the Zermelo–Fraenkel
theory and let F, G be filters of sets with B-structure. The following quantification
rules are valid (for internal y, z in V(B) ):
(1) (∃x ∈ m(F))[[ϕ(x, y, z)]] = 1
↔ (∀F ∈ F)(∃x ∈ ∗ F )[[ϕ(x, y, z)]] = 1;
(2) (∀x ∈ m(F))[[ϕ(x, y, z)]] = 1
↔ (∃F ∈ F ↑↓ )(∀x ∈ ∗ F )[[ϕ(x, y, z)]] = 1;
(3) (∀x ∈ m(F))(∃y ∈ m(G))[[ϕ(x, y, z)]] = 1
↔ (∀G ∈ G)(∃F ∈ F ↑↓ )(∀x ∈ ∗ F )(∃y ∈ ∗ G)[[ϕ(x, y, z)]] = 1;
(4) (∃x ∈ m(F))(∀y ∈ m(G))[[ϕ(x, y, z)]] = 1
↔ (∃G ∈ G ↑↓ )(∀F ∈ F)(∃x ∈ ∗ F )(∀y ∈ ∗ G)[[ϕ(x, y, z)]] = 1.
Moreover, for standardized free variables, we have:
(1) (∃x ∈ m(F))[[ϕ(x, ∗ y, ∗ z)]] = 1
↔ (∀F ∈ F)(∃x ∈ F↑↓)[[ϕ(x, y, z)]] = 1;
(2) (∀x ∈ m(F))[[ϕ(x, ∗ y, ∗ z)]] = 1
142
A. G. KUSRAEV AND S. S. KUTATELADZE
↔ (∃F ∈ F ↑↓ )(∀x ∈ F )[[ϕ(x, y, z)]] = 1;
(3) (∀x ∈ m(F))(∃y ∈ m(G))[[ϕ(x, y, ∗ z)]] = 1
↔ (∀G ∈ G)(∃F ∈ F ↑↓ )(∀x ∈ F )(∃y ∈ G↑↓)[[ϕ(x, y, z)]] = 1;
(4) (∃x ∈ m(F))(∀y ∈ m(G))[[ϕ(x, y, ∗ z)]] = 1
↔ (∃G ∈ G ↑↓ )(∀F ∈ F)(∃x ∈ F↑↓)(∀y ∈ G)[[ϕ(x, y, z)]] = 1.
4. NONSTANDARD ANALYSIS OF POSITIVE OPERATORS
Positive operators are central to the theory of ordered vector spaces.
The principal possibility, provided by nonstandard methods, is that the formalisms appeared allows us to considerably simplify the analysis of operators by
reducing the situation to functionals and sometimes even to numbers. In the current
chapter we will illustrate the general methods of nonstandard analysis of operators
in connection with the problems of their extension and decomposition and in dealing
with the structure of homomorphisms and Maharam operators.
We shall also pay attention to the problem of generating fragments of a positive
operator, because the complete description of the latter was successfully and easily
obtained by a consistent usage of nonstandard analysis both in Boolean-valued and
in infinitesimal variants.
4.1. Extension and decomposition of positive operators.
We shall demonstrate in this section that many questions of the theory of order bounded operators can be reduced to the case of functionals with the help of
Boolean-valued models.
4.1.1. The statement that E is a vector lattice can be rewritten as a restricted
formula, say, ϕ(E, R). Hence, by the restricted transfer principle, we have the
identity [[ϕ(E ∧ , R∧ )]] = 1, i.e. E ∧ is a vector lattice over the ordered field R∧
inside V(B) . Let E ∧∼ be the space of all R∧ -linear regular functionals from E ∧
to R. It can be easily seen that E ∧∼ := L∼ (E ∧ , R) is a K-space in the model
V(B) . The descent E ∧∼↓, as the descent of a K-space, is a K-space. Consider the
universally complete K-space F := R↓ (see 2.2.4). We recall that for every operator
T ∈ L∼ (E, F ) the ascent T↑ is defined by the equality [[T x = T↑ (x∧ )]] = 1(x ∈ E).
Note that if τ ∈ E ∧∼ , then [[τ : E ∧ → R]] = 1; hence, the operator τ ↓: E → F is
determined. Moreover, τ↓↑= τ . On the other hand, T↑↓= T .
4.1.2. Theorem. For every T ∈ L∼ (E, F ) the descent T↑ is a regular R∧ -form
on E ∧ inside V(B) , i.e. [[T ↑∈ E ∧∼ ]] = 1. The mapping T → T ↑ is a linear and
lattice isomorphism of the K-spaces L∼ (E, F ) and E ∧∼↓.
4.1.3. We shall formulate certain corollaries to 4.1.2. First of all, let us introduce
necessary definitions. An operator S ∈ L∼ (E, F ) is called a fragment of an operator
T ≥ 0, if S ∧ (T − S) = 0. We shall say that the operator T is F -discrete, whenever
[[0, T ]] = [[0, IF ]] ◦ T ; i.e., for every 0 ≤ s ≤ t there exists an operator 0 ≤ α ≤ IF
∼
such that S = αT . Let L∼
a (E, F ) be the band of the space L (E, F ) generated by
⊥
∼
∼
F -discrete operators, and write Ld (E, F ) := La (E, F ) . The bands (E ∧∼ )a and
(E ∧∼ )d are introduced similarly. Elements of L∼
d (E, F ) are usually referred to as
F -spread or F -diffuse operators. R-discrete or R-diffuse operators are called, for
the sake of simplicity, discrete or diffuse functionals. Consider S, T ∈ L∼ (E, F )
and write τ := T↑, σ := S↑. The following equivalences are true:
NONSTANDARD METHODS FOR KANTOROVICH SPACES
143
(1) T ≥ 0 ↔ [[τ ≥ 0]] = 1;
(2) “S is a fragment of T ”↔ [[σ is a fragment of τ ]] = 1;
(3) “T is F -discrete”↔ [[τ is discrete]] = 1;
∧∼
(4) T ∈ L∼
)a ]] = 1;
a (E, F ) ↔ [[τ ∈ (E
∼
∧∼
(5) T ∈ Ld (E, F ) ↔ [[τ ∈ (E )d ]] = 1.
We need one more fact which follows from 4.1.2 by direct computation of Boolean
truth-values.
(6) “T is a lattice homomorphism”↔ [[τ is a lattice homomorphism ]] = 1.
4.1.4. Theorem. Let E be a vector lattice, let F be a K-space, and suppose
that T ∈ L∼ (E, F ). The following statements are equivalent:
(1) T is an F -discrete element of the K-space L∼ (E, F );
(2) T is a lattice homomorphism;
(3) T preserves disjointness, i.e. if x, y ∈ E and x ⊥ y then T x ⊥ T y.
Proof. Draw 4.1.2, 4.1.3 and use the well-known result on characterization of
discrete functionals (= Theorem 4.1.4 for F = R).
4.1.5. It is easy to verify that if a functional f ∈ E ∼ preserves disjointness, then
|f | has the same property. By 4.1.4(1) the functionals f + and f − are proportional
to |f |, and since f + ⊥ f − , either f + = 0 or f − = 0. This means that either f ≥ 0
or f ≤ 0. In particular, for the functional τ := T ↑ we have [[τ ≥ 0]] ∨ [[τ ≤ 0]] = 1.
If π := χ[[τ ≥ 0]] then π ⊥ ≤ χ[[τ ≤ 0]] and the inequalities πτ ≥ 0 and π ⊥ τ ≤ 0 are
true. The application of descents leads to the following result.
For a regular disjointness preserving operator T ∈ L∼ (E, F ) there exists a projection π ∈ P(F ) such that πT = T + and π ⊥ T = T − . In particular, for all 0 ≤ x,
y ∈ E we have (T x)+ ⊥ (T y)− .
4.1.6. A subspace E0 ⊂ E is called massive, or coinitial, or even cofinal whenever
for every x ∈ E there exist x and x ∈ E0 such that x ≤ x ≤ x. Suppose that
T0 ∈ L(E0 , E) and write τ0 := T0↑. Obviously, the following take place:
(1) “E0 is massive in E” ↔ [[E0∧ is massive in E ∧ ]] = 1;
(2) “T is an extension of T0 ”↔ [[τ is an extension of τ0 ]] = 1.
The Kreı̆n–Rutman theorem states that a positive functional defined on a massive subspace admits a positive extension to the whole space. The theorem remains
valid if the word “positive” be replaced in it by “discrete.” Putting these facts into
V(B) and using the statements (1), (2) and 4.1.3(3), we obtain the following results.
4.1.7. Kantorovich’s theorem. Let F be an arbitrary K-space. If E0 is
a massive subspace of E, then every positive operator T0 : E0 → F admits a positive
extension T ∈ L∼ (E, F ).
4.1.8. Theorem. Under the conditions of 4.1.6, every F -discrete operator T0 :
E0 → F admits an F -discrete extension T : E → F . In particular, if E0 is
a massive sublattice, then, for a lattice homomorphism T0 : E0 → F , there exists
a lattice homomorphism extending T0 .
4.1.9. Theorem. For a positive operator T : E → F , the following statements
are equivalent:
(1) T is F -diffuse;
144
A. G. KUSRAEV AND S. S. KUTATELADZE
(2) for all 0 ≤ x ∈ E, 0 ≤ ε ∈ F , and b ∈ B such that bε 6= 0, there exists
a nonzero projection ρ ≤ b and mutually disjoint positive operators T1 , . . . , Tn such
that
T = T1 + . . . + Tn , |ρTk x| ≤ ε (k := 1, . . . , n);
(3) for all 0 ≤ x ∈ E, 0 ≤ ε ∈ F , and b ∈ B such that bε 6= 0, there exists
a countable partition of unity (bn ) such that for every n ∈ N the operator T can
be decomposed into the sum of mutually disjoint positive operators T1,n , . . . , Tkn ,n
satisfying the inequalities bn |Tk,n x| ≤ ε (k := 1, . . . , kn ).
Proof. The proof is obtained by interpreting inside V(B) the following scalar
fact: a positive functional f is diffuse if for all x ≥ 0 and 0 < ε ∈ R there are
positive mutually disjoint functionals f1 , . . . , fn such that f = f1 + . . . + fn and
|fk (x)| < ε (k := 1, . . . , n).
4.1.10. Theorem. For every positive operator T : E → F , the following representation holds:
X
Tξ x (x ∈ E)
T x = T0 x +
ξ∈Ξ
with T0 being an F -diffuse operator and (Tξ )ξ∈Ξ being a family of mutually disjoint
lattice homomorphisms.
The operator T0 is uniquely determined and the family (Tξ ) is unique up to
“transposing” and “mixing.” To prove the theorem, we need the fact that, by
transfer principle in V(B) , every K-space (E ∧∼ in our case) can be decomposed
into the direct sum of the band of diffuse operators and the band generated by
discrete elements; the latter being the concatenation of one-dimensional bands, i.e.
bands generated by discrete elements. After this 4.1.3(3–5) are easy to be inferred.
4.1.11. Remarks.
(1) The material of this section can be viewed as an illustration to the following
heuristic principle formulated by L. V. Kantorovich in the article [17], where he
has introduced K-spaces: “Introduction of these spaces allows us to study linear
operations of one general class (operations with values in such spaces) as linear
functionals.”
(2) The elementary theorem, 4.1.2, serves as the basic technical method raising
the heuristic principle formulated to the level of investigating precisely (within the
range of problems considered). Other variants are in [5, 12, 13, 27, 38].
(3) The equivalence (1)↔(2) in Theorem 4.1.4 was obtained by S. S. Kutateladze
(see [26]) by standard methods. The scalar case (F = R) is well known. As regards
4.1.5, see [43].
(4) A standard proof of Theorem 4.1.7 is presented in many monographs. The
theorem is also valid if E is an ordered vector space. Extending a positive operator
with additional properties (discreteness or preserving the lattice operations as in
4.1.8) is a rather dominant theme. We will only note here that this topic is close
to studying the extreme structure of special convex sets, see, e.g., [4, 5, 26].
Fragments of positive operators
In this section we shall dwell on the problem of computing fragments of positive
operators. This problem can be scrutinized rather deeply with the help of consistent
NONSTANDARD METHODS FOR KANTOROVICH SPACES
145
usage of nonstandard methods. As in the previous section, E denotes a vector lattice
and F stands for a K-space.
4.2.1. A set P of projections in the K-space L∼ (E, F ) is said to generate fragments of an operator T , 0 ≤ T ∈ L∼ (E, F ), if T x+ = sup{P T x : P ∈ P} for
all x ∈ E. The last being valid for every 0 ≤ T ∈ L∼ (E, F ), the set P is called
generating. Write F := R↓ and let P be a projection in L∼ (E, F ). Then
(1) there exists a unique element P ↑∈ V(B) such that [[P ↑ is a projection in
∧∼
E ]] = 1 and (P T )↑= P↑ T↑ for all T ∈ L∼ (E, F ).
Now consider a set P of projections in L∼ (E, F ) and a positive operator T ∈
∼
L (E, F ). Write τ := T↑ and P↑:= {P↑: P ∈ P}↑. Then [[P↑ is a set of projections
in E ∧∼ ]] = 1 and the following statements are true:
(2) “P generates fragments of T ” ↔ [[P↑ generates fragments ofτ ]] = 1;
(3) “P is a generating set” ↔ [[P↑ is a generating set]] = 1.
4.2.2. For a set A in a K-space denote by A∧ the result of adjoining to A
suprema of its every nonempty finite subsets. The symbol A↑ is used for the result
of adjoining to A suprema of nonempty increasing nets of elements of A. The
symbols A↑↓ and A↑↓↑ are naturally interpreted. The sign ≈ in a K-space F has
the ordinary meaning: x ≈ y for x, y ∈ F symbolizes that ∀St e ∈ E)|x − y| ≤ e,
where E is the filter of units in F . It is clear that if F := R then this stands for
infinitesimality of the number x − y.
Our results on positive operators will be obtained by the same schema as in 4.1
with the help of Boolean-valued models. At first it is necessary to investigate the
case of functionals. We shall use the notation P(f ) := {P f : P ∈ P}. Henceforth,
in the subsections 4.2.3–4.2.5 E is a vector lattice over a dense subfield of R, P is
a set of projections in E ∼ .
4.2.3. Theorem. The following statements are equivalent:
∨(↑↓↑)
(1) P(f )
= E(f );
(2) P generates fragments of f ;
(3) (∀x ∈ ◦ E)(∃p ∈ P)pf (x) ≈ f (x+ );
(4) a functional g in [0, f ] is a fragment of f if and only if for every 0 ≤ x ∈ E
the following identity holds
inf (pg(x) + p(f − g)(x)) = 0;
p∈P
(5) (∀g ∈ ◦ E(f ))(∀x ∈ ◦ E+ )(∃p ∈ P)|pf − g|(x) ≈ 0;
(6) inf{|pf − g|(x) : p ∈ P} = 0 for all fragments g ∈ E(f ) and positive elements
x ≥ 0;
(7) for x ∈ E+ and g ∈ E(f ) there is an element p ∈ P(f )∨(↑↓↑) satisfying the
identity |pf − g|(x) = 0.
Proof. The implications (1)→(2)→(3) are obvious.
(3)→(4). We shall work within standard entourage. Note first of all, that validity
of the required identity for all functionals g and f such that 0 ≤ g ≤ f provides, for
a standard x ≥ 0, the existence of such p ∈ P that p⊥ g(x) ≈ 0 and p(f − g)(x) ≈ 0.
Thus, ◦ p(g ∧ (f − g))(x) ≤ ◦ p(f − g)(x) = 0 and ◦ p⊥ ((f − g) ∧ g)(x) ≤ ◦ p⊥ g(x) =
0, i.e. g ∧ (f − g) = 0.
146
A. G. KUSRAEV AND S. S. KUTATELADZE
Prove now that under conditions (3) the required identity is provided by the
ordinary criterion of disjointness:
inf{g(x1 ) + (f − g)(x2 ) : x1 ≥ 0, x2 ≥ 0, x1 + x2 = x} = 0.
For a fixed standard x, find internal positive x1 and x2 such that x = x1 + x2
and, moreover, g(x1 ) ≈ 0 and f (x2 ) ≈ g(x2 ). By the condition (3), it follows from
the Kreı̆n – Mil′ man theorem that the fragment g belongs to the weak closure of
P(f ). In particular, there is an element p ∈ P satisfying g(x1 ) = pf (x1 ) and
g(x2 ) ≈ pf (x2 ). Thus, p⊥ g(x2 ) ≈ 0 because p⊥ g ≤ p⊥ f . Finally, p⊥ g(x) ≈ 0.
Hence,
p(f − g)(x) = pf (x2 ) + pf (x1 ) − pg(x) ≈ g(x2 ) + g(x1 ) − pg(x) ≈ p⊥ g(x) ≈ 0.
This provides the needed identity.
(4)⇒(5). By the equality |pf − g|(x) = p⊥ g(x) + p(f − g)(x) we can select p ∈ P
such that p⊥ g(x) ≈ 0 and p(f − g)(x) ≈ 0. This provides the required statement.
The equivalence (5)↔(6) is clear. The implications (5)⇒(7)⇒(1) can be proved
with the help of methods presented in [43].
4.2.4. Theorem. For positive functionals f and g and for a generating set of
projections P, the following statements are equivalent:
(1) g ∈ {f }⊥⊥ ;
(2) for every finite x ∈ fin E := {x ∈ E : (∃x ∈ ◦ E)|x| ≤ x} one has pg(x) ≈ 0
whenever pf (x) ≈ 0 for p ∈ P;
(3) (∀x ∈ E+ )(∀ε > 0)(∃δ > 0)(∀p ∈ P)pf (x) ≤ δ → pg(x) ≤ ε.
4.2.5. Theorem. Let f , g be positive functionals on E and let x be a positive
element of E. The following representations of the projection πf onto the band
{f }⊥⊥ are valid:
(1) πf g(x) ⇀ inf ∗ {◦ pg(x) : p⊥ f (x) ≈ 0, p ∈ P} (the sign ⇀ means that the
formula is exact, i.e. the equality is accessible);
(2) πf g(x) = supε0 inf{◦ pg(x) : p⊥ f (x) ≤ ε, p ∈ P};
(3) πf g(x) ⇀ inf ∗ {◦ g(y) : f (x − y) ≈ 0, 0 ≤ y ≤ x};
(4) (∀ε > 0)(∃δ > 0)(∀p ∈ P)pf (x) < δ → πf g(x) ≤ p⊥ g(x) + ε;
(∀ε > 0)(∀δ > 0)(∃p ∈ P)pf (x) < δ ∨ p⊥ g(x) ≤ πf g(x) + ε;
(5) (∀ε > 0)(∃δ > 0)(∀0 ≤ y < x)f (x − y) ≤ δ → πf g(x) ≤ g(y) + ε;
(∀ε > 0)(∀δ > 0)(∃0 ≤ y ≤ x)f (x − y) ≤ δ ∨ g(y) ≤ πf g(x) + ε.
Putting the statements 4.2.3–4.2.5 inside V(B) , while using 4.2.1, we infer the
items 4.2.6–4.2.9 presented below.
4.2.6. For a set of projections P in L∼ (E, F ) and 0 ≤ S ∈ L∼ (E, F ), the following
statements are equivalent:
(1) P(S)∨(↑↓↑) = E(S);
(2) P generates fragments of S;
(3) an operator T ∈ [[0, S] is a fragment of S if and only if for every 0 ≤ x ∈ E
the identity holds:
inf (P − T x + P (S − T )x) = 0;
P ∈P
NONSTANDARD METHODS FOR KANTOROVICH SPACES
147
(4) (∀x ∈ ◦ E)(∃P ∈ P↑↓)P Sx ≈ Sx+ .
4.2.7. For positive operators S and T and a generating set P of projections in
L∼ (E, F ), the following statements are equivalent:
(1) T ∈ {S}⊥⊥ ;
(2) (∀x ∈ fin E)(∀P ∈ P)(∀π ∈ B)πP Sx ≈ 0 → πP T x ≈ 0;
(3) (∀x ∈ fin E)(∀π ∈ B)πSx ≈ 0 → πT x ≈ 0;
(4) (∀x ≥ 0)(∀ε ∈ E)(∃δ ∈ E)(∀P ∈ P)(∀π ∈ B)πP Sx ≤ δ → πP T x ≤ ε;
(5) (∀x ≥ 0)(∀ε ∈ E)(∃δ ∈ E)(∀π ∈ B)πSx ≤ S → πT x ≤ ε.
4.2.8. Theorem. Let E be a vector lattice and let F be a K-space with the filter
of units E and the base B. Suppose that S, T are positive operators in L∼ (E, F ) and
R is the projection of T onto the band {S}⊥⊥ . For a positive x ∈ E, the following
representations are valid:
(1) Rx = supε∈E inf{πT y + π ⊥ Sx : 0 ≤ y ≤ x, π ∈ B, πS(x − y) ≤ ε};
(2) Rx = supε∈E inf{(πP )⊥ T x : πP Sx ≤ ε, P ∈ P, π ∈ B}, where P is a generating set of projections in L∼ (E, F ).
4.2.9. For an element 0 ≤ e ∈ E define the operator πe S by the formulas:
(πe S)x := sup S(x ∧ ne)
(x ∈ E+ ),
n∈N
(πe S)x := (πe S)x+ − (πe S)x−
(x ∈ E).
It is easy to see that πe S ∈ L∼ (E, F ). Moreover, πe S is a fragment of the
operator S and the mapping S → πe S (S ≥ 0) can be naturally extended onto
L∼ (E, F ) as an order projection. The set of projections P := {πe : 0 ≤ e ∈ E} is
generating. Hence, from 4.2.6 follows the formula
E(S) = {(ρ ◦ πe )S : ρ ∈ P(F ), 0 ≤ e ∈ E}∧(↑↓↑) .
4. .2.10. Remarks.
(1) The formulas for projections in the form 4.2.8(1,2) have been constructed
gradually. A survey of this history can be found with the help of [31, 43]. The
general approach proposed in [36] is taken as basic to this section. It allows us to
derive various formulas of projections via choosing concrete generating sets.
(2) A formula like 4.2.9(1) was established for the first time by B. de Pagter (see
[31, 45]) with two essential restrictions: F has a total set of o-continuous functionals
and E is order complete. The first restriction was removed in [31], the second – in
[36]. All these cases correspond to different generating sets of projections.
(3) The main idea proposed in [36] is as follows. The fragments of a positive operator T are the extreme points of the order interval [0, T ]. The latter set coincides
with the subdifferential at zero (the supporting set) ∂P of the sublinear operator
P x = T x+ . Thus, studying fragments of a positive operator can be reduced to
describing the extreme structure of subdifferentials. Such a description for general
sublinear operators was obtained for the first time in the paper of S. S. Kutateladze
(see the details in [26]). Note that the approach developed in [36] solves, in particular, the problem of an extreme extension of a positive operator (for the references
on this subject, see [4, 26]).
148
A. G. KUSRAEV AND S. S. KUTATELADZE
4.3. Order continuous operators.
The methods exposed in the two previous sections can not be directly applied to
order continuous operators; because, while ascending an operator (see 4.1.2), the
property of order continuity is lost. We shall consider here another approach based
on D. Maharam’s ideas.
4.3.1. A positive operator T : E → F is said to satisfy Maharam’s condition,
if for every 0 ≤ x ∈ E one has T [[0, x]] = [[0, T x]], i.e. if for all 0 ≤ x ∈ E and
0 ≤ z ≤ T x there exists a 0 ≤ y ∈ E such that T y = z and 0 ≤ y ≤ x. A positive
order continuous operator satisfying this condition is customarily called a Maharam
operator.
Everywhere in this section E and F are K-spaces, and for simplicity we assume F
to be universally complete. By the symbol ET we denote the carrier of the operator
T , i.e. the set {x ∈ E : T (|x|) = 0}⊥ . Write FT := (imT )⊥⊥ and let Dm (T ) stand
for the greatest foundation in a universal completion of E, onto Dm (T ) the operator
T being extendable with preserving order continuity. If ET = E and T ≥ 0 then
the operator T is said to be essentially positive.
4.3.2. Theorem. Let E be a K-space, F := R ↓, and let T : E → F be
a Maharam operator such that E = ET = Dm (T ) and F = FT . Then there exist
E ∈ V(B) and τ ∈ V(B) satisfying the following conditions:
(1) V(B) |=“E is a K-space and τ : E → R is an essentially order continuous
functional”;
(2) E ↓ is also a K-space, τ ↓: E ↓→ R↓ is a Maharam operator, furthermore,
E↓= Dm (τ↓);
(3) there exists a linear and lattice isomorphism h from E onto E ↓ such that
T = τ↓ ◦h.
4.3.3. For a Maharam operator the decomposition 4.1.10 can be elaborated. Let
e be an order unit in E. Then [[e is an order unit in E]] = 1. The functional τ is
P∞
representable as τ = τ0 − k=1 τk where τ0 is a diffuse functional and τk are order
continuous lattice homomorphisms. All these functionals are uniquely defined by
measures on the base of unit elements. Furthermore, an atomless measure corresponds to τ0 , and two-valued measures correspond to τk . Interpreting this situation
in V(B) , we obtain the result presented below. Recall that Maharam’s condition for
a positive vector measure µ : E(e) → F has precisely the same meaning as in 4.2.1,
i.e. µ[[0, a]] = [[0, µ(a)]] (a ∈ E(e)). If µ is an isomorphism of Boolean algebras then
µ∗ stands for the resulting isomorphism of the corresponding universally complete
K-spaces.
4.3.4. Theorem. Let E be a K-space with the unity e and let T : E → F
be an essentially positive Maharam operator. Then there exist sequences (ek )∞
k=0 ,
∞
∞
(ck )∞
,
(µ
)
,
(α
)
such
that
k k=0
k k=1
k=1
(1) (ek ) is a partition of unity of the Boolean algebra E(e) and (ck ) is a sequence
of fragments of the element c = T e;
(2) µ : E(e0 ) → F is a strictly positive order continuous measure satisfying
Maharam’s condition;
(3) µk : E(ek ) → E(ck ) is a Boolean isomorphism, αk is a positive invertible
orthomorphism in {ck }⊥⊥ ;
NONSTANDARD METHODS FOR KANTOROVICH SPACES
149
(4) the representation
Tx =
Z∞
−∞
λ·
dµ0 (exλ0 )
+
∞
X
αk µ∗k (xk )
k=1
holds, with xk being the projection of the element x onto the band {ek }⊥⊥ .
For Maharam operators the dual analogs of 4.1.4 and 4.1.5 are valid.
4.3.5. Theorem. Let T : E → F be a positive order continuous operator. The
following statements are equivalent:
(1) T satisfies Maharam’s condition;
(2) for every operator 0 ≤ S ≤ T there exists an orthomorphism α : E → E,
0 ≤ α ≤ IE such that Sx = Sαx(x ∈ E);
(3) if T x = f1 + f2 for some 0 ≤ x ∈ E and 0 ≤ f1 , f2 ∈ F , and if f1 ⊥ f2 , then
there are 0 ≤ x1 , x2 ∈ E such that x = x1 + x2 , x1 ⊥ x2 , and T xk = fk (k = 1, 2).
Proof. Without loss of generality we may assume T to be essentially positive.
If (1) is true then T = τ ↓ ◦h (see 4.3.2). Since τ is R-linear, then T is R↓-linear.
If 0 ≤ S ≤ T then S is also R↓-linear and, hence, a Maharam operator. By 4.3.2,
S = σ ↓ ◦h where [[σ ∈ E ∼ ]] = [[0 ≤ σ ≤ τ ]] = 1. The statement (2) for the
functionals τ and σ follows from the Radon–Nikodým theorem. Taking descents,
we obtain (2) for the operators T and S. The rest implications are plain.
4.3.6. Let S : E → F be a regular operator such that T := |S| is a Maharam
operator. Then there exists a projection π ∈ R(F ) such that S + = Sπ and S − =
Sπ ⊥ .
Proof. Again we may assume that T := τ ↓, where τ is an essentially positive
o-continuous functional inside V(B) . As in 3.4.5 we obtain the fact that there exists
a regular functional σ ∈ E such that τ = |σ|. If p is a projection in E onto the
carrier (= the band of essential positivity) of σ + . Order continuous functionals are
disjoint if and only if their carriers are disjoint. Hence, σ + = σp and σ − = σp⊥ .
Writing π := p↓ and taking descents, we complete the proof.
4.3.7. Thus, the general properties of Maharam operators can be deduced from the
corresponding facts about functionals with the help of Theorem 4.3.2. Nevertheless,
the methods described may be also useful in studying arbitrary regular operators.
Fix a positive operator Φ which acts from a vector lattice X into F . By Theorem
4.1.2, there exists a positive R∧ -linear functional ϕ : X ∧ → R such that the identity
[[Φ(x) =ϕ(x∧ )]] = 1 holds for all elements x ∈ X. Equip X ∧ with the seminorm
ρ(x) := ϕ(|x|). Let X be the completion of the quotient lattice X ∧ /ρ−1 (0) with
respect to the quotient norm. Then X is a Banach lattice and there exists a unique
positive (R-linear) functional ϕ : X → R such that ϕ = ϕ ◦ ι, where ι : X ∧ → X
is the quotient homomorphism. Moreover, ϕ is order continuous and essentially
positive. Now, working with descents and ascents, one can obtain the following
result.
4.3.8. Theorem. There exists a K-space X and an essentially positive Maharam operator Φ : X → F satisfying the following conditions:
150
A. G. KUSRAEV AND S. S. KUTATELADZE
(1) there are lattice homomorphisms i : X → X and j : Z(X) → Z(X) (with
Z(X) being the ideal of X generated by the identity operator) such that j is also
a ring homomorphism and αΦx = Φ(j(α)i(x)) for all elements x ∈ X and α ∈
Z(F ); in particular, Φ(x) = Φ(i(x));
(2) i(X) is a massive sublattice in X and j(Z(F )) is an o-closed sublattice and
subring of Z(X);
(3) X = b(X ⊗ Z(F ))↓↑ , with b : X ⊗ Z(F ) → X being the lattice operator
defined by the relation b(x ⊗ α) := j(α)i(x)(x ∈ X, α ∈ Z(F )).
The pair (X, Φ) is defined uniquely up to an isomorphism. Moreover, if an
essentially positive Maharam operator Φ1 : X 1 → F and a lattice homomorphism
i1 : X 1 → F satisfy the condition Φ = Φ1 ◦ i1 , then there exists an isomorphism h
from X onto an o-closed sublattice in X such that Φ = Φ1 ◦ h and h ◦ i = i1 .
Denote by mX a universal completion of a K-space X. Fix, in mX, an order
unity, thus an f -algebra structure is uniquely defined. Let L1 (Φ) be the greatest
foundation in mX, onto which Φ can be extended with preserving o-continuity. The
following result is a variant of the Radon–Nikodým theorem for positive operators.
4.3.9. Theorem. For every operator T ∈ {Φ}⊥⊥ there exists a unique element
z ∈ mX such that
T x = Φ(z · i(x)) (x ∈ X).
The correspondence T → z establishes a linear and lattice isomorphism between
the band {Φ}⊥⊥ and a foundation in mX defined by the formula {z ∈ mX :
z · i(X) ⊂ L1 (Φ)}.
4.3.10. Remarks.
(1) In a long sequence of papers published in the 1950, D. Maharam proposed
an original approach to studying positive operators. The concept of a Maharam
operator and the idea of extending a positive operator to a Maharam operator
(see 4.1.8) ascend to those papers. It is worth to note that within Boolean-valued
analysis D. Maharam’s approach is notable for clarity of the idea and for certain
simplicity, because a considerable part of the theory can be reduced to manipulating
numerical measure and integral in a suitable Boolean-valued model.
(2) Several results of D. Maharam were transfered to vector lattices by W. A. J.
Luxemburg and A. R. Schep (see [26]). Theorem 4.3.2 is due to A. G. Kusraev.
(3) The equivalence (1)↔(2) in 4.3.5 is a restricted version of the Radon–
Nikodým theorem for a Maharam operator. The complete form of this theorem
was proved in [24] by standard methods, and in [5] — with the help of 4.3.2. The
statement 4.3.6 is an operator variant of the Hahn theorem on the decomposition of measure. For an operator acting between spaces of measurable functions,
D. Maharam established Theorem 4.3.4 by her original method.
(4) The problem of extending a positive operator to a Maharam operator was
thoroughly studied (see [5, 24, 26]). In these papers the details of 4.3.8 and 4.3.9
can also be found. The structure of such extension can be rather complicated, but
sometimes admits a functional description.
ҜЇЎҖӨҐЎҮӨҐ
1. Albeverio S., Fenstad J., Hoegh-Krohn R., and Lindstrfim T., Nonstandard Methods in Stochastic Analysis and Mathematical Physics, Acad. Press, New York, 1986.
NONSTANDARD METHODS FOR KANTOROVICH SPACES
151
2. Akilov G. P., Kolesnikov E. V., and Kusraev A. G., On order continuous extension of a positive
operator, Sibirsk. Mat. Zh. 29 (1988), no. 5, 24–35.
3. Akilov G. P. and Kutateladze S. S., Ordered Vector Spaces, Nauka, Novosibirsk, 1978.
4. Bukhvalov A. V., Order bounded operators in vector lattices and spaces of measurable functions, Mathematical Analysis. Vol. 26, VINITI, Moscow, 1988, pp. 3–63.
5. Bukhvalov A. V., Korotkov V. B., Kusraev A. G., Kutateladze S. S. and Makarov B. M.,
Vector Lattices and Integral Operators, Nauka, Novosibirsk, 1991.
6. Wang H. and Mcnaughton R., Les Systemes Axiomatiques de la Theorie des Ensemblas,
Paris–Louvain, 1962.
7. Vdovin A. M., Fundamentals of a new axiomatic set theory, Izv. Akad. Nauk SSSR Ser. Mat.
54 (1990), no. 5, 1113–1118.
8. Vladimirov D. A., Boolean Algebras, Nauka, Moscow, 1969.
9. Vopenka P., Mathematics in the Alternative Set Theory, Moscow, Mir.
10. Vulikh B. Z., Introduction into the Theory of Semiordered Spaces, Moscow, Fizmatgiz, 1961.
11. Gordon E. I., The reals in Boolean-valued models of set theory and K-spaces, Dokl. Akad.
Nauk SSSR 237 (1977), no. 4, 773–775.
12. Gordon E. I., K-spaces in the Boolean-valued models of set theory, Dokl. Akad. Nauk SSSR
258 (1981), no. 4, 777–780.
13. Gordon E. I., On theorems about preservation of relations in K-spaces, Sibirsk. Mat. Zh. 23
(1982), no. 5, 55–65.
14. Gordon E. I., Relatively standard elements in E. Nelson’s internal set theory, Sibirsk. Mat.
Zh. 30 (1989), no. 1, 89–95.
15. Gumilev
- N. S., Verses and Poems, Sovetskij Pisatel′ , Leningrad, 1988.
16. Jech T. J., Lectures in Set Theory with Particular Emphasis on the Method of Forcing,
Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1971.
17. Kantorovich L. V., On semiordered linear spaces and their applications to the theory of linear
operations, Dokl. Akad. Nauk SSSR 4 (1935), no. 1–2, 11–14.
18. Kantorovich L. V. and Akilov G. P., Functional Analysis, Nauka, Moscow, 1984.
19. Kantorovich L. V., Vulikh B. Z., and Pinsker A. G., Functional Analysis in Semiordered
Spaces, Gostekhizdat, Moscow–Leningrad, 1950.
20. Kolesnikov E. N., Decomposition of a positive operator, Sibirsk. Mat. Zh. 30 (1989), no. 5,
70–73.
21. Cohen P., Set Theory and the Continuum Hypothesis, Mir, Moscow, 1973.
24. Kusraev A. G., Vector Duality and Its Applications, Nauka, Novosibirsk, 1985.
25. Kusraev A. G., Number systems in the Boolean-valued models of set theory, VIII Vsesojuznaja
Konf. po Mat. Logike, Moscow, 1986, pp. 99.
26. Kusraev A. G. and Kutateladze S. S., Subdifferential Calculus, Nauka, Novosibirsk, 1987.
27. Kusraev A. G. and Kutateladze S. S., Nonstandard Methods in Analysis, Nauka, Moscow,
1990.
28. Kusraev A. G. and Kutateladze S. S., On combining nonstandard methods, Sibirsk. Mat. Zh.
31 (1990), no. 5, 111–119.
29. Kusraev A. G. and Maliugin S. A., Product and projective limit of vector measure, SIBAM 1
(1991), no. 2, 77–98.
30. Kusraev A. G. and Maliugin S. A., On atomic decomposition of a vector measure, Sibirsk.
Mat. Zh. 30 (1989), no. 5, 101–110.
31. Kusraev A. G. and Strizhevskij V. Z., Lattice normed spaces and majorizable operators, PRIM
9 (1987), 132–157.
32. Kutateladze S. S., Ascending and descending, Dokl. Akad. Nauk SSSR 272 (1983), no. 2,
521–524.
33. Kutateladze S. S., Cyclic monads and their applications, Sibirsk. Mat. Zh. 27 (1986), no. 1,
100–110.
34. Kutateladze S. S., Credenda of nonstandard analysis, SIBAM 1 (1991), no. 1, 109–137.
35. Kutateladze S. S., Monads of proultrafilters and extensional filters, Sibirsk. Mat. Zh. 30
(1989), no. 1.
36. Kutateladze S. S., On fragments of positive operators, Sibirsk. Mat. Zh. 30 (1989), no. 5,
111–119.
37. Leibniz G. W., Monadology. Vol. 1, Works, Mysl′ , Moscow, 1982, pp. 413–429.
38. Lubezkij V. A., Sheaves and values, Uspekhi Mat. Nauk 44 (1989), no. 2, 99–153.
152
A. G. KUSRAEV AND S. S. KUTATELADZE
39. Lubezkij V. A. and Gordon E. I., Boolean completions of uniform structures, Investigations
into Nonclassical Logic and Formal Systems, Nauka, Moscow, 1983, pp. 82–153.
40. Pairer I., General theory of infinitesimals, Sibirsk. Mat. Zh. 31 (1990), no. 3, 103–124.
41. Sobolev V. I., On semiordered measure of sets, measurable functions, and some abstract
integrals, Dokl. Akad. Nauk SSSR 91 (1990), no. 1, 23–26.
42. Aliprantis C. D. and Burkinshaw O., Locally Solid Riesz Spaces, Academic Press, New York,
1978.
43. Aliprantis C. D. and Burkinshaw O., Positive Operators, Academic Press, New York, 1985.
44. Bell T. L., Boolean Valued Models and Independence Proofs in Set Theory, Clarendon Press,
Oxford, 1979.
45. Dacunha-Castelle D. and Krivine I. L., Applications des ultra-produits a l’etuete des espaces
et des algebras de Banach, Studia Math 41 (1972), 315–334.
46. Fremlin D. H., Topological Riesz Spaces and Measure Theory, Cambridge Univ. Press., Cambridge, 1974.
47. Halmos P. R., Lectures on Boolean Algebras, Van Nostrand, Toronto etc., 1963.
48. Le Jonge E. and Van Rooij A. C. M., Introduction to Riesz Spaces, Mathematich Centrum,
Amsterdam, 1977.
49. Jameson G. J. O., Ordered Linear Spaces, Springer-Verlag, Berlin etc., 1970.
50. Jech T. J., Abstract theory of abelian operator algebras: an application of forcing, Trans.
Amer. Math. Soc. 289 (1985), no. 1, 133–162.
51. Jech T. J., First order theory of complete Stonean algebras, Canad. Math. Bull. 30 (1987),
no. 4, 385–392..
52. Jech T. J., Boolean-Linear Spaces, Pennsylvania Univ., Pennsylvania, 1987.
53. Kawai T., Nonstandard analysis by axiomatic method, Southeast Asian Conference on Logic,
North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1983, pp. 55–76.
54. Lindenstrauss J. and Tzafriri L., Classical Banach Spaces. Function Spaces, Springer-Verlag,
Berlin etc., 1979.
55. Luxemburg W. A. J. and Zaanen A. G., Riesz Spaces. Vol. 1, North-Holland, Amsterdam–
London, 1971.
56. Nelson E., Internal set theory. A new approach to nonstandard analysis, Bull. Amer. Math.
Soc. 83 (1977), no. 6, 1165–1198.
57. Nonstandard Analysis. Recent Development, Berlin etc., Springer-Verlag, 1983.
58. Schaefer H. H., Banach Lattices and Positive Operators, Berlin etc., Springer-Verlag, 1974.
59. Schwarz H.-V., Banach Lattices and Operators, Leipzig, Teubner, 1984.
60. Solovay R., A model of set theory in which every set of reals is Lebesgue measurable, Ann.
Math. 92 (1970), no. 2, 1–56.
61. Solovay R. and Tennenbaum S., Iterated Cohen extensions and Souslin’s problem, Ann. Math.
94 (1972), no. 2, 201–245.
62. Takeuti G., Two Applications of Logic to Mathematics, Iwanami and Princeton Univ. Press,
Tokyo–Princeton, 1978.
63. Takeuti G. and Zaring W. M., Introduction to the Axiomatic Set Theory, Springer-Verlag,
New York etc., 1971.
64. Takeuti G. and Zaring W. M., Axiomatic Set Theory, Springer-Verlag, New York etc., 1973.
65. Vopenka P., General theory of ´-models, Comment. Math. Univ. Carolinae 7 (1967), no. 1,
147–170.
66. Vopenka P. and Hajek P., The Theory of Semisets, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1972.
67. Wong Y.-Ch. and Ng K.-F., Partially Ordered Topological Vector Spaces, Clarendon Press,
Oxford, 1973.
68. Zaanen A. G., Riesz Spaces. Vol. 2, North-Holland, Amsterdam etc., 1983.