The Public Administration Case Against
Participation Income 1
Jurgen De Wispelaere
Department of Philosophy, Trinity College Dublin
Email: jurgen.dewispelaere@tcd.ie
Lindsay Stirton
The Norwich Law School, University of East Anglia
Email: l.stirton@uea.ac.uk
[Under review, please do not quote or cite without permission]
Abstract – Anthony Atkinson’s proposal for a participation income (PI) has been
acclaimed by social philosophers and policy experts as a workable compromise
given the problems besetting an unconditional basic income (UBI). While some see
PI as the first step towards a fully unconditional scheme, others regard PI as
superior to UBI on ethical grounds as well as in terms of political feasibility. Both
of these views disregard the administrative complications associated with
introducing a broad participation requirement into welfare entitlements. In this
paper we identify three essential administrative tasks that any welfare scheme
must perform — establishing criteria of entitlement, determining compliance with
those criteria, and allocating benefits to qualified beneficiaries — and show that PI
performs poorly in terms of all three tasks. This suggests what we call the trilemma
of participation income: only at significant costs to administrators and welfare clients
does the scheme retain its apparent ability to satisfy the requirements of both
activation and universal approaches to welfare. Consequently, the main apparent
strength of PI — its capacity to unite different factions within the basic income
debate — is shown to be illusory precisely because competing factions strongly
prefer different resolutions of the trilemma. This, we argue, has far-reaching
implications for the political strategy of basic income advocates as well as the
wider debate on universal welfare reform.
1. INTRODUCTION
This article challenges the idea that the modern welfare state would be improved by
the introduction of a participation income (PI) to accommodate the twin objectives of
universal social protection and broad social participation. Many scholars of the modern
This draft was written partly while Lindsay Stirton was a Visiting Fellow in the Regulatory Institutions Network,
Research School of Social Sciences, Australian National University. Earlier drafts were presented at the Social and
Political Theory Research Seminar, Australian National University, 1 November 2005 and the 5th US Basic Income
Guarantee Network Conference, Philadelphia, 24-26 February 2006. We are grateful to audiences at both events for
comments, and to Geoffrey Brennan, Richard Caputo, David Casassas, John Ferejohn, Bob Goodin, Michael Harker,
Michael Lewis, José Antonio Noguera, Claus Offe, Arvind Thattai, Yannick Vanderborght and Almaz Zelleke for
helpful suggestions. The usual disclaimer applies.
1
1
welfare state agree with Goodin (2000) that the crumbling of its traditional pillars limits
the ability of welfare policies to achieve a range of often contradictory objectives, but
disagree as to which policies might be introduced in their place. In particular, a fault
line separates those favoring increased emphasis on universal mechanisms, such as
unconditional basic income (UBI) or its variants, and those who favor increased targeting
of benefits through a host of conditional and activating measures commonly captured
under the label workfare.2
At first sight PI appears extraordinarily well-suited to bridge the divide between
“universalists” and “selectivists” in welfare reform. Like UBI, PI grants each adult
citizen an individual right to a secure basic income irrespective of living arrangement
or alternative sources of income or wealth (Atkinson 1993, 1996, 1998). However, unlike
UBI, PI insists that recipients satisfy a broad participation requirement, consisting of a
range of socially useful activities such as caring for an elderly relative, volunteering in
a neighborhood project or engaging in a human capital enhancing activity. PI is also
conceptually distinct from workfare because it expands the notion of social
participation well beyond the narrow notion of labor market participation.
Nevertheless, PI retains a strong element of conditionality attached to the receipt of
welfare benefits. It is the latter feature that seemingly allows PI to bridge the positions
of those who believe universal social protection and inclusion are the key objectives of
the modern welfare state and those who think its primary task ought to be the
increased activation of adult citizens.3
In this article we take issue with this view. Unlike those who regard PI as a policy
solution that merges the best features of two worlds — a welfare scheme that appears
genuinely inclusive and activating — we argue that PI has very little to offer either side
of this debate. By critically assessing PI from the standpoint of administrative analysis
and drawing evidence from experience of existing programs, we identify several
concerns at the level of implementation which have largely been ignored in existing
debates. Once these concerns are confronted, it can be seen that the apparent
attractions of PI as a political compromise do not translate into a stable administrative
solution to the competing priorities of those who support PI on different grounds.
Inevitably, because our purpose is to assess an abstract policy proposal, rather than to
evaluate an existing program, empirical evaluation of our argument is problematic.
Our analysis is therefore less an exercise in hypothesis testing as one of hypothesis
formulation.4
2 While workfare advocates occupy the mainstream in contemporary welfare policy, a substantial literature on basic
income and related policy proposals has developed over the past two decades. See in particular Van Parijs (1992, 1995),
Atkinson (1995), Fitzpatrick (1999), Ackerman and Alstott (1999), Standing (1999, 2002, 2005), Van der Veen and Groot
(2000), Van Parijs, Cohen and Rogers (2001), Dowding, De Wispelaere and White (2003), White (2003b), Cunliffe and
Erreygers (2004), Groot (2004), Widerquist, Lewis and Pressman (2005), Ackerman, Alstott and Van Parijs (2006) and
Murray (2006). In June 2006 Basic Income Studies, the first academic journal on basic income published its inaugural issue
(http://www.bepress.com/bis/).
3 Van Parijs (1996, 2004) proposes an unconditional basic income as a solution for simultaneously combating
“exploitation” and “exclusion”, but most policy analysts insist a more activating approach is required to secure
inclusion through labor market participation.
4 We claim support here from F. A. Hayek who argues (contra Popper) that applying theories to new questions is a
central part of scientific inquiry, and one which is separate from that of testing theories. Hayek (1967: 6) argues that
although it is desirable to check one’s conclusions against observations as far as possible, “[t]he conclusions which we
2
The first aim of the present paper is to demonstrate that, in its current
underdeveloped state, PI does not constitute a workable proposal.5 An examination of
the administrability of PI — that is, its capacity to be administered in a practical and
efficient manner in accordance with its primary objectives and within existing
constraints — reveals significant weaknesses which makes its endorsement by UBI
supporters in particular premature, if not altogether gratuitous. While such a negative
assessment primarily affects what we refer to as the first-best justification of PI, it also
impacts importantly on the second-best case for PI. This brings us to the second goal of
this paper. Comparing PI with both UBI and workfare from the point of view of
administrative analysis casts doubt on PI’s ability to serve as a stable compromise
between the competing camps of universalists and selectivists. The administrative
instability of PI, we maintain, confronts would-be supporters of the proposals with the
following trilemma of participation income: only by imposing substantial economic and
moral costs on both welfare bureaucrats and clients in order to enforce a broadlydefined participation requirement effectively can PI satisfy the requirements of both a
UBI and a workfare program. Avoiding the horn of bureaucratic cost might require the
scheme to either compromise on weak enforcement of the participation requirement,
thus rendering PI barely distinguishable from UBI, or designing the participation
condition around selective eligibility criteria which effectively would mutate PI into
workfare. And since advocates of PI hold both explicit and opposing views on how to
resolve this trilemma, it is difficult to see how PI can attract sufficient support for an
enduring coalition. In short, because administrative instability produces political
instability, far from being a perfect compromise between proponents and opponents of
universal welfare reform PI may well constitute the worst of all worlds. The
implications of this conclusion for the broader basic income debate are considered in
the final section of this article.
2. PARTICIPATION INCOME: AN ANALYTICAL OUTLINE
PI is the brainchild of Anthony Atkinson (1993, 1996, 1998), an Oxford economist with
a distinguished track record of research into poverty and social exclusion. Increasingly
dissatisfied with the reliance upon means-tested benefits in the UK since the 1980s,
Atkinson came to look sympathetically upon arguments in favor of universal grants
allocated without a means-test. At the same time, he recognized that “it will be difficult
to secure political support for a citizen’s income while it remains unconditional on
labor market or other activity” (Atkinson, 1996: 67). The solution for Atkinson is a
social assistance program that retains the politically salient notion of social
participation while giving up on means-testing — thus participation income was born.
The broad outline of PI is best described by quoting Atkinson at some length:
can draw from a combination of well-established hypotheses will therefore be valuable though we may not be in a
position to test them.”
5 Fairness requires us to mention that Atkinson is well aware of problems with PI that might not arise with UBI, such as
some people failing to secure a PI where they would have received a UBI, or behavioral adjustments to the program
(Atkinson, 1996: 69).
3
“In my proposal, the basic income would be paid conditional on participation. I should
stress at once that this is not limited to labor market participation. While the qualifying
conditions would include people working as an employee or self-employed, absent from
work on grounds on sickness and injury, unable to work on grounds of disability and
unemployed but available for work, it would also include people engaging in approved
forms of education or training, caring for young, elderly or disabled dependents or
undertaking approved forms of voluntary work, etc. The condition involves neither
payment nor work; it is a wider definition of social contribution.” (Atkinson, 1996: 68-9)
The precise nature of a PI depends crucially on the sort of activities included in the
notion of social participation. It is perfectly possible for a PI to barely expand on
existing labor market-oriented notions of economic participation6; alternatively, a PI
might encompass such a wide range of social activities effectively rendering it virtually
indistinguishable from a genuine UBI. While this flexibility offers valuable
maneuvering room for policy entrepreneurs to construct an enacting coalition – along
the lines of Gibson and Goodin’s (1999) “veil of vagueness” – it raises concerns about
how the precise scope of participation is to be determined and by whom.
A second key concern relates to the question of how compliance with such a
requirement is to be enforced. As Loek Groot and Robert van der Veen (2000) suggest, a
PI with a broad notion of social participation and lax enforcement will evidently bear a
close resemblance to a UBI, while the same policy with a narrowly defined
participation requirement and strict enforcement will in practice bear a close
resemblance to a workfare program. This apparent malleability of PI might lead one to
regard PI as either a mutated UBI proposal or an expanded workfare scheme. However,
the apparent symmetry masks an important distinction between PI and UBI when
compared to workfare schemes: where UBI claims to eradicate a host of social and
economic ails solely by providing cash support, workfare and closely related activating
welfare policies in addition employ two separate but complementary tools. In addition
to using sanctioning devices to “push” workers into the labor market, workfare also
purports to offer additional forms of support in negotiating barriers to employment,
such as training, placement, assistance with transport or care problems, and so on.
Granted, in practice the latter function often becomes crowded-out by a variety of other
priorities (Handler 2004; Handler and Babcock 2006) but the analytical distinction
nevertheless stands, suggesting a close alignment between PI and UBI.
Atkinson’s proposal has gained almost universal, if at times implicit, support
among basic income supporters as well as from a number of UBI’s more sympathetic
critics, despite the fact that little work has been undertaken to flesh out Atkinson’s
original proposal.7 On the other hand, perhaps it is precisely because both the concept
and the policy details of PI remain vague that it has managed to retain the support of
scholars and advocates with widely divergent perspectives. In order to advance the
debate, however, it is now necessary to pierce the veil of vagueness and to consider
those features of PI which make the scheme attractive to different positions within
For instance, Socio-Economic Participation Income (SEPI) discussed by Jordan et al. (1999).
Zelleke (2005: 640-641) is one of the few exceptions, explicitly denouncing PI for its selective treatment of various tax
and benefit measures.
6
7
4
contemporary welfare debates.
Analytically, we can discern three reasons for endorsing PI, each of which may take
priority for some subset of those currently in favor of the proposal. First, one might
endorse PI believing it to be a first-best welfare policy under contemporary conditions,
for example because it allows us to combine generous income support with the
freedom of recipients to engage in a wide range of socially useful activities. Thus,
Stuart White’s relentless and sophisticated arguments against unconditional welfare,
rooted in the view that unconditionality fails to satisfy the basic requirement of “fair
reciprocity”, has led him to endorse PI on several occasions.8 In addition to such
justice-based arguments, first-best proponents of PI may also advance an incentive
argument in which PI encourages an optimal production of socially valuable activities
without relying on overly coercive measures. Here, we could imagine PI fitting nicely
with both feminist approaches to welfare reform (Robeyns 2000, McKay and Van Every
2000, McKay 2001, Pateman 2003, 2004) and with post-productivism in which narrow
employment-driven policies are supplanted by schemes that induce the broad
valuation of social activity, including care work (Offe 1992, Fitzpatrick 1999, Standing
1999, 2002, Van der Veen and Groot, forthcoming). In practice, the justice-based and the
incentive-based perspectives often coincide, but the arguments are sufficiently distinct
to warrant separate mention.9
This approach differs markedly from the views of second-best adherents of PI, who
(like Atkinson himself) favor radically unconditional policies but acknowledge that
UBI may not be a feasible option, for example because it does not command sufficient
political support. Many basic income supporters, including Philippe Van Parijs, Claus
Offe, Robert Goodin, Brian Barry, and many others have subsequently adopted this
position. However, second-best justifications for PI themselves come in two subtle but
distinct variants. First, there are those who regard political feasibility in static terms
and who — perhaps reluctantly — accept PI as a permanent settlement. This seems to
be Atkinson’s position, for example. This position can be contrasted by those who see
PI as a first step towards a more radically unconditional scheme. This more dynamic
view assumes that once a PI is in place, an important benchmark in favor of
universalizing welfare is established; subsequent strategy would then be directed
towards adjusting the scheme along various parameters — such as increasing the level
of the grant to render it more generous, widening the conditions attached to receipt to
render it more universal and encompassing, etc.10 — in order to move from a PI to a
mature UBI.
Recently, a number of basic income scholars have drawn attention to the many
ways in which existing welfare and social support schemes can be made to mimic basic
income in one of its versions. The three most common strategies are: (1) start with a
8 See especially White (2003b); an early view of this requirement can be found in Amy Gutmann & Dennis Thomson
(1996). While White is arguably one of the most eloquent defenders of PI on first-best or justice-based grounds, he is
certainly not the only one.
9 In the language of political philosophy, the justice-based argument is substantially (though not solely) backwardlooking, primarily concerned with ensuring that people are held responsible for past actions, while the incentive-based
argument is genuinely forward-looking, aimed at ensuring that individuals bring about a sizeable social product.
10 For an analytical outline of the various dimensions across which broadly universalist policies can be varied, see De
Wispelaere and Stirton 2004a.
5
partial income and then move towards a full UBI at the level of the poverty line; (2)
start with a UBI in one sector or for part of the population, such as a basic pension or
child benefit, and extend that gradually to the whole target group; or (3) introduce a
combination of schemes that jointly operate as a UBI (Vanderborght 2000, 2005; Van
Parijs 2001, 2004; Van der Veen and Groot 2000 and Standing 2005). Unfortunately, thus
far we have not encountered a genuinely convincing strategy that indicates how to
move from PI to a UBI; in the absence of such a strategy it remains equally plausible
that opponents of universalism might use PI to benchmark a fairly narrow criterion of
social participation and then progressively restrict access to eligibility — by imposing
time constraints, for instance, as in the 1996 Clinton welfare reforms,11 — or effectively
decreasing the level of support.
In summary, the first-best justification sees PI as an ethical compromise between
competing normative claims, while the second-best perspective regards PI essentially
as a political compromise in a constrained policy environment. It can be argued that PI
consequently emerges as a policy that has the capacity to unite a range of different
groups and as such stands out as the welfare policy par excellence — capable not only of
sustaining a coalition based around shared goals, but also allowing different groups to
avoid having to chose for a more extreme policy, be it UBI or workfare. It is this
apparent capacity to unite that in large part explains PI’s success amongst basic income
advocates, and the apparent willingness of most advocates to lend their support
without fully assessing how a PI would operate in practice. Once such an assessment is
carried out, we believe, this apparent capacity to unite may be illusory. In our view, this
illusion is largely maintained by avoiding discussing PI beyond its most basic contours.
To illustrate, even sophisticated thinkers like Philippe Van Parijs (2004) only ever offer
an impressionistic analysis of PI. Once such an exercise is carried out, as we propose to
do in the remainder of this paper, the illusion rapidly disintegrates, and PI reveals itself
as a risky and costly strategy.
3. THE ESSENTIAL FEATURES OF AN INCOME SUPPORT MECHANISM
From the point of view of administrative analysis, there are three essential
administrative tasks which any welfare scheme must perform. First, a scheme must
establish operational criteria of eligibility which define the intended beneficiaries;
second, it must identify those within the population who meet these criteria of
eligibility, and distinguish them from those not eligible; third, it must transfer
payments to eligible beneficiaries at the appropriate level, frequency, etc. Accordingly,
the design of an income support mechanism involves, at a minimum, taking a position
on how each of these tasks is to be performed. The following three sub-sections deal
with each task in turn. We argue that PI performs poorly in terms of administering
each of these three tasks. This is an important conclusion because the inability to
perform one or more of these tasks as required by a particular scheme may undermine
or negate the reasons for preferring that scheme in the first place. Even where such
differences in administerability are not decisive, we may still find that how we resolve
11
The idea of a time-limited unconditional grant is proposed by White (2003a).
6
questions of administrative design has important consequences for the way the scheme
may be expected to operate in practice, and thus for the conclusions we draw about the
normative desirability of different schemes.12
A. STANDARDS CONFERRING ENTITLEMENT
The first step in the design of any welfare benefit is to determine what criteria, if any,
should govern eligibility for a grant, and how these criteria are best encapsulated in a
set of rules or standards. Debates on welfare entitlement have, for the most part,
focused on the first, normative part of this task, neglecting the second, technical-legal
aspect.13 However, these two aspects cannot be completely divorced from one another,
and the relative difficulty of reducing alternative criteria of eligibility into a set of
suitably precise rules is relevant to the balance of considerations for and against
different income support schemes.
Indeed, Colin Diver (1983) has attributed the failure of many public policies to
achieve their intended purposes to inappropriate degrees of rule-precision. Diver
(1983: 67-68) identifies three separate dimensions of rule-precision. First, transparency is
defined as the extent to which the language in which rules are formulated is clearly
defined and has universally accepted meaning. Second, accessibility is the extent to
which rules are readily applicable by those that are required to interpret them in
concrete or “street-level” situations. The third dimension is the extent to which verbal
formulations are congruent with the underlying policy objectives, so that compliance
with the terms of the rules should lead to the outcomes consistent with the policy. A
key part of Diver’s argument is that these three dimensions are not co-linear, and so
policy-makers need to make compromises and trade-offs between the three dimensions,
in order to produce effective rules.
Applying Diver’s analysis to the problems of designing an effective PI scheme
reveals the complex administrative judgment involved in implementing a PI scheme.
As discussed in the previous section, the key feature that distinguishes PI from UBI on
the one hand, and from workfare on the other, is the incorporation of a broad
participation requirement. Applying Diver’s analysis to the problem of legislating
Atkinson’s participation criterion into a set of rules, consider the following three
alternative model standards (inspired by Diver 1983: 69):
Model I: Any person working for at least ten hours per week in employment, selfemployment, for a charitable organization, or in study at university or college, or
caring for dependent parents, children or spouses shall be entitled to receive a PI.
Model II: Any person substantially engaged in an appropriate socially valued
activity shall be entitled to receive a PI.
Polities with limited administrative capacity may find such choices even more severely constrained. The importance
of this point should not be underestimated, given that interest in basic income and related policies of late has been
greatest in some less developed countries (Nattrass and Seekings 2005, Suplicy 2005).
13 Part of the problem may be that the two aspects of this question fall on different sides of a disciplinary divide.
Whereas discussion of abstract criteria comes naturally to the political philosopher or student of public policy, the
problem of reducing abstract criteria into concrete rules has traditionally been part of the subject matter of
administrative lawyers and public administration scholars (Breyer 1982, Chapter 5; Black 1995; Baldwin 1990, 1995; also
Hood 1986).
12
7
Model III: A person shall be eligible to receive a PI, provided he or she undertakes
activities as prescribed in the following table. This is followed by a detailed table
displaying various types of employment, positions within voluntary organizations,
approved college and university courses, disabilities, care work activities, etc.
Comparing these three alternatives, we observe that model I is clearly both
transparent and accessible — it is relatively easy to know what it means, and whether
it applies to any particular case, provided one is familiar with the relevant facts — but
it performs poorly in terms of congruence with the underlying policy of promoting an
inclusive conception of active citizenship as demanded by reciprocity theorists
(Anderson 2001, Galston 2001, White 2003b). Specifically, the formulation is in certain
respects “under-inclusive”: one can envisage many socially valuable activities that are
not captured by the formulation, such as non-university-based education and other
non-credited forms of training, or caring for dependents outside of the prescribed
relationship. It may also be “over-inclusive” in other respects: it is debatable whether
all charitable organizations contribute unambiguously to the public good.14 Moreover,
in the absence of clear standards we can expect a proliferation of charitable
organizations, many of which may be set up with the explicit objective of exploiting the
scheme. This is an example of the phenomenon of “creative compliance”, discussed
below.
The fact that a PI might end up inadvertently supporting negatively or neutrally
valued activities, while at the same time failing to support activities that are generally
considered beneficial to society at large, is a topic of some concern amongst advocates
as well as adversaries of the scheme.15 It is also a concern well-documented in the
literature on welfare reform, where it is referred to as goal congruence. Goal congruence
requires that policy systems allow political agents who decide on formal policy goals to
adequately transmit these goals throughout the system, and provide street-level case
workers with both resources and incentives to implement policy accordingly. Recent
research argues that congruence between formal policy goals and street-level,
operational goals is a prerequisite for effective welfare administration (Meyers et al.
2001). However, goal congruence is immensely difficult to achieve when either policy
goals or the operational policy environment (delivery systems) are complex; complex
policy goals invite conflict and ambiguity regarding the proper interpretation and
ranking of goals, while complex administrative environments introduce conflicting
incentives into the equation. Unsurprisingly, Marcia Meyers and her colleagues show
that where both policy goals and the administrative environment are complex, a
decoupling of formal and substantive policy goals often occurs.
One strategy to avoid such decoupling would be to start with clearly defined
policy goals (Riccucci et al. 2004). This is the approach taken in Model II, which directly
elucidates the policy intention behind the rule. However, Model II manages to avoid
14 As an example, for a period one of us played in an amateur orchestra, established as a charitable organization which
has never, in its forty-year existence, given a single public performance.
15 The problem is a political one in the sense that the content of the participation requirement ideally should form part
of a political consensus. In practice, however, it is likely that policy-makers and bureaucrats decide where to draw
boundaries.
8
this problem only by offering a vague, all-encompassing criterion of participation,
leaving it open to conflicting interpretations by clients, welfare officers, policy-makers
and even the general public, and thus scoring poorly in terms of accessibility. Of course,
for various political reasons, often “elected officials are pre-disposed to providing
vague or ambiguous policy directives” (Meyers et al. 2001: 166). This is particularly the
case when policy goals are contested, providing incentives to decision-makers to shift
responsibility to administrative agencies and case workers (Brodkin 1990, 1997). While
some, as noted, regard a political predisposition towards vagueness an opportunity, it
may also encourage strategies of blame-avoidance (Weaver 1986).
Model III, in turn, may get round this problem, providing both high accessibility
and congruence, provided policy-makers can foresee all the socially valuable activities
of which individuals can conceive, but is likely to be extremely complex; so these gains
come at the cost of poor transparency.16 Of course, we could attempt to get round this
particular problem by combining different versions of the models. For example, we
could combine Model II with a set of guidelines similar to Model III, leaving residual
discretion of some official to “include” other cases. However, this may combine the
weaknesses of different approaches as well as their strengths, and may furthermore
come at the cost of considerable complexity.
While Models II and III may avoid problems of goal congruence, Model II
confronts another central problem in welfare administration, namely that it confers
excessively broad discretion on welfare administrations to determine unilaterally the
eligibility of clients (Diller 2000). Poor accessibility exacerbates this problem because
unless there is a firmly established consensus among the “interpretative community”
on which activities are socially valued, highly unlikely in modern plural societies
(Black 1995), key decisions are typically passed through the system to street-level case
workers.
Similarly, Model III may be regarded as highly congruent with the underlying
policy goal of instituting a broad participation criterion, but avoids these problems
only by creating another: poor transparency increases the de facto discretionary power
of street-level administrators because of imperfect and asymmetrical knowledge of the
regulations amongst and across welfare workers and clients (see Baldwin, 1995: pp. 1533). The literature on the implementation of welfare policies demonstrates that case
workers are frequently overwhelmed by forms, rules and regulations and are often
forced to take on responsibilities for which they are insufficiently trained, leaving little
or no time for actual engagement with clients (Sandfort 2000; Handler and Hasenfeld,
forthcoming).17 Consequently, non-transparent rules have been shown in some cases
to lead administrators to base decisions on cues and heuristics that may themselves be
incompatible with underlying policy concerns, or be otherwise arbitrary. This has been
shown to lead to the creaming of easy cases and the dumping of problem clients, the
selective provision of key information to clients and the arbitrary use of compliance
and sanctioning (Handler 2004). Paradoxically, attempts to curtail welfare workers’
The manifold presumptions that drive current social policy is often regarded as a key advantage of universal
measures which, in the words of Goodin (1992), are “minimally presumptuous”.
17 To illustrate, Jody Sandfort notes how the mere list of standardized forms to be used in the processing and follow-up
of welfare claimants adds up to an astounding 33 pages (Sandfort 2000: 735)!
16
9
discretion by expanding rules, regulations and other attempts at routinizing welfare
implementation have proven counter-productive because they incite case workers to
ignore cumbersome procedures and to use their discretion to achieve what they
perceive as the primary goal, typically case-load reduction (Meyers et al. 1998; Handler
2004; Hander and Hasenfeld, forthcoming). “Because staff recognize the limited ability
of the programs to move all clients into work, they develop alternative definitions of
organizational success” (Sandfort 2000: 739).
How does PI compare to rival schemes in this respect? It is often assumed that UBI
side-steps the problem of rule formulation, since eligibility is nominally unconditional.
This point, while not entirely without force, should not be overstated: even in its most
inclusive formulation such a grant must restrict entitlement to some subset of the
inhabitants of one country, or perhaps of some supra-national region such as the EU
(Van Parijs 1995; Vanderborght and Van Parijs 2001; also Howard 2006). In addition
there will be rule specifications pertaining to the level of the grant, its uniformity, the
time scale at which it operates and so on, all of which involve considerably more
regulation than is appreciated by many UBI supporters (De Wispelaere and Stirton
2004a). Nevertheless, reducing a proposal for a radical UBI scheme into a set of
transparent, accessible and congruent rules is likely to be a relatively straightforward
matter, based on comparably well-defined criteria compared with other forms of
welfare grants, including PI.
At the other extreme, in our view workfare schemes may also be superior to PI in
terms of ease-of-administration even though they incorporate strict conditions. There
are a number of reasons why workfare might outperform PI in terms of defining a
standard conferring entitlement. First, the sheer volume of activities captured by a
broad participation requirement compared to the eligibility requirements under a
workfare program is likely to impact on the performance of each of these two
respective policies. Second, precisely because of its formality a formal work condition
is likely to be more easily expressed as a rule. Third, because work conditions are more
easily embedded in existing practices and labor market institutions, they are more
likely to engender accessible and transparent regulations. This again contrasts
favorably with PI which demands the institution of newly valued activities; or at least
activities that are “new” from a rule perspective. Of course, research has shown that
workfare in practice faces many complicated problems and in fact manages to gather
support despite its record of obtaining goals and objectives (Meyers et al. 1998; Sandfort
2000; Handler 2004; Handler and Hasenfeld, forthcoming). Nevertheless, from both a
political and an administrative perspective, it makes a considerable difference whether
the task of conferring standards of entitlement is initiated from a clear and coherent
perspective or one that is by its very nature covers a diverse and heterogeneous range
of activities. Irrespective of actual outcomes, workfare and PI do not appear to start on
a similar footing in this respect.
In short, all welfare schemes face the sort of hard choices and trade-offs inherent in
Diver’s optimal precision calculus, but different schemes score differently in how well
they negotiate these trade-offs. The basic formulation of PI as a non-means-tested grant
subject to a broad participation requirement ignores the distinctive ways in which the
latter can be operationalized. Bringing the operational dimension to the foreground, as
10
we have done in this section, demonstrates PI faces considerably greater problems in
implementation compared with both UBI and workfare.
B. IDENTIFICATION AND MONITORING OF BENEFICIARIES
The task of determining whether individuals satisfy criteria of eligibility, and whether
beneficiaries have complied (or continue to comply) with conditions attached to the
receipt of a grant is a familiar problem in welfare administration. From the perspective
of administrative analysis, this question focuses attention on the informational
demands associated with different schemes, as well as the potential for strategic
behavior on the part of potential beneficiaries, who may evade conditions of
entitlement or engage in creative compliance (McBarnett & Wheelan 1991). As we shall
see, these issues are closely intertwined with the issues of rule design addressed in the
previous section: rules that perform poorly along any of the three dimensions of rule
precision discussed in the previous section typically give rise to further monitoring and
enforcement problems.18 This section addresses these issues by examining the features
of benefit schemes that lend themselves to the effective identification of beneficiaries,
by assessing how far the alternative formulations of the participation requirement
discussed in the previous section can readily embody these features, and how the
challenges associated with monitoring and enforcement of a participation requirement
compares with equivalent implementation issues posed by UBI and workfare,
respectively.
In several writings Christopher Hood (1985; 1986: 74-81; 1994: Ch. 7) has discussed
in detail the features that make a tax more or less administerable for a given sociotechnical environment. The features identified by Hood can also be applied to the
crediting of income support grants. First, Hood (1994: 118) coins the term standard
clarity to denote “the property of being relatable to values that can be ascertained
relatively economically and ‘objectively’.” While this is arguably just an enforcement
perspective on Diver’s criterion of accessibility discussed in the previous section, it
reinforces the point that where standards cannot readily be applied to particular
circumstances, determining compliance is likely to be costly and difficult — potentially
leading, as Diver suggests, to policy failure. Next, Hood (1994: 118; 1986: 76-77) argues
that ease of administration requires that the scheme’s targets must be cadasterable; that
is, they must possess “the property of being applicable to a readily identifiable
population of [‘creditable’] units, if possible from sources that are available in advance
and cannot be easily contaminated by evasive action.” This also implies that individual
circumstances that are likely to change frequently — for example, the amount of hours
worked out by casual employees — constitute a poor basis for entitlement because they
lead to a rapidly changing and therefore unstable target population. This is not merely
a problem for welfare administrators, but also for clients themselves, since they often
fail to understand when they are in violation of an eligibility constraint (Handler and
Hasenfeld, forthcoming; Handler and Babcock, 2006)19
It is worth noting that one of the key reasons identified in the regulation literature for regulatory failure is a lack of
sensitivity on the part of rule-makers to the challenges of enforcement and compliance (Baldwin 1990).
19 Conversely, as often pointed out by basic income supporters, rule complexity prevents many eligible individuals
from understanding when they qualify for a particular benefit.
18
11
Building on the argument of the previous section, our hypothetical implementation
of a participation requirement again helps to illustrate how alternative rule
descriptions can lead to divergent outcomes by virtue of their effects on determining
compliance. 20 In Model I and Model III, decisions about what constitutes active
citizenship are made in advance; determining compliance requires only knowledge of
the facts of individual circumstances. While information about employment can be
gleaned from payroll information and enrolment in education can be assessed from
matriculation records, there are no such comprehensive or reliable sources of
information about the distribution and extent of care work in the home. Effective
monitoring of care work would indeed require overly intrusive forms of monitoring;
alternatively, some form of self-certification might be used, but this would in turn be
susceptible to manipulation by those not meeting the participation requirement, in
particular when not all eligible clients might be aware of their entitlement.
Model II, faces all of these problems and more. In particular, this model performs
poorly in terms of standard clarity. In the absence of a strong interpretative consensus,
basing entitlement on an abstract definition of a “socially valued activity” places a
broad discretion on administrators to decide whether different activities qualify. As
well as raising concerns about due process, such as what (if any) appeals procedures
should be made available to enable those who are denied a grant to challenge such a
decision (Danz, 2000; Lens and Vorsanger 2005), this may also be a recipe for
inconsistent application—an acute concern, especially where different agencies are
involved (Stoker and Wilson 1998; Meyers et al. 2000).
There is, however, at least one respect in which Model II outperforms its
competitors: it is less susceptible to the form of manipulation termed creative compliance
in the legal literature; that is, compliance with the technical requirements of a rule or
standard in such a way as to undermine the purpose of the rule (McBarnett & Whelan,
1991). Model I, for instance, might encourage enrolment at a university, leading to a
proliferation of what former UK Higher Education Minister Margaret Hodge has called
“Mickey Mouse courses” — a B.Sc. in Surfing, anyone? Tackling such opportunistic
exploitation through further detailed rules along the lines of Model III, which might
specify “approved” university courses, in turn requires further detailed monitoring to
allow administrators to distinguish between those courses which are deemed valuable
and those which are not. By avoiding formalism, Model II at least potentially permits
administrators to respond flexibly to such attempted exploitation—albeit at the price of
placing substantial discretionary authority in the hands of administrators.
Consideration of the task of identification of beneficiaries and monitoring
compliance also gives rise to questions as to what (if any) sanctioning mechanisms
should complement information-gathering. When clients fail to abide by conditions
attached to the receipt of a grant they normally face some form of sanction — typically
in the form of partial or complete withdrawal of the benefit itself (Handler 2004). The
20 This is a separate concern from the distinction made by Stoker and Wilson (1998) between client-based and
organization-based forms of claims verification. While this distinction draws attention to the important point that clients
too need to be able to verify their eligibility to particular benefits, reliance on clients’ assessments to determine
compliance with conditions of entitlement could be expected to result in a systematic bias in favor of overpayment.
For an analytical argument see Prendergast (forthcoming).
12
link between monitoring and sanctioning appears straightforward, and this has
arguably had the effect that strategies of moral persuasion to induce behavioral
compliance and change have been relatively undervalued (Mead 1996; Hasenfeld and
Weaver 1996; Riccio and Hasenfeld 1996). However, recent research casts doubt on
various assumptions implicit in the design and operation of common approaches to
sanctioning welfare recipients (Wilson et al. 1999; Hasenfeld et al. 2004; Handler and
Hasenfeld, forthcoming). First, it remains unclear whether sanctioning is mandated by
moral or utilitarian arguments (Hasenfeld et al. 2004; Handler and Hasenfeld,
forthcoming). In addition, it is questionable whether sanctioning really produces
desired outcomes; that is, do non-compliant welfare recipients really learn a moral
lesson or are sanctions merely pre-selecting (“creaming”) less demanding clients where
welfare systems face too many pressures (Wilson et al. 1999), without taking account of
the manifold “barriers to compliance” that may intersect with clients’ behavioral
disposition (Hasenfeld et al. 2004)?
Again, comparing the analysis of PI with that of UBI and workfare, respectively, is
instructive. The unconditional nature of UBI again implies that monitoring and
enforcement is strictly speaking a non-issue. If we grant each and every individual
citizen a grant unconditionally, there is neither need for, nor a point to, monitoring
recipients of the grant. There might nonetheless be other reasons for retaining some
form of monitoring, if only to ensure that all citizens end up receiving the UBI they are
entitled to: in the absence of existing mechanisms to monitor citizens generally it is
impossible to assess their take-up (a point we elaborate in the next section). Although
monitoring might constitute an important built-in safety mechanism, the need for a
monitoring apparatus is nonetheless significantly reduced, if not rendered superfluous,
in a basic income welfare state. Similarly, UBI would reverse the sanctioning
philosophy implicit in current welfare programs.
What about workfare? Workfare programs stipulate a narrow conception of active
citizenship based on labor market categories and institutions. Most of these categories
already feature prominent in various cadasters and this would suggest they are more
easily to monitor, at least in theory. In practice, evidence shows that monitoring
remains one of the most challenging issues in the administration of workfare (Handler
and Babcock, 2006; Handler and Hasenfeld, forthcoming). The evidence suggests that
monitoring is both costly and error-prone, with case workers often making decisions
on the basis of outdated, inaccurate or incomplete information. This in turn has
potentially disastrous implications concerning the subsequent assessment of eligibility,
sanctioning, and so forth. The situation becomes more complicated if we move from
pure “people-processing” technology to the “people-changing” requirements inherent
in workfare’s ambitious activation goals (Hasenfeld and Weaver 1996). As has been
reported throughout the relevant literature, agencies embracing an eligibilitycompliance culture find it hard simultaneously to endorse notions of self-sufficiency
(Bane and Elwood 1994).
We do not wish to downplay the problems associated with current welfare-towork administration, but the point remains that where workfare faces difficulties,
monitoring and enforcement of a broad participation requirements becomes practically
unworkable because of its inherent ambiguities. One important variable to consider is
13
the default-position when there is implicit uncertainty about the outcome of a
verification procedure: do we assume that a client is eligible unless proof to the
contrary is offered, or do we shift the burden of proof entirely on the client (Stoker and
Wilson 1998)? Another variable is a measure of proportionality between “infraction”
and “sanction”. There is ample evidence that the bulk of sanctioned TANF clients in
the US, some of who lose their entire entitlement, are effectively being sanctioned for
missing an appointment or not properly filling out a form (Cherlin et al. 2002). Clearly
both concerns bear a close relation to the distinction between narrow and broad
participation requirements and their strict or lax enforcement, discussed in a previous
section. In addition, PI also faces a major problem of inter-agency coordination since
the broadening of approved activities also implies an implosion of agencies that need
to cooperate to produce the required information (cf. Stoker and Wilson 1998). Finally,
the inherent ambiguities of PI will also interact with the doctrine of sanctioning: the
uncertainty about when clients deserve to be sanctioned under PI may introduce
further arbitrary and unequal treatment.21
The task of determining the target population eligible for a particular entitlement
and its subsequent monitoring and, if required, sanctioning, proves to be one of the
major challenges for any welfare system. In this section we argued that, for reasons
closely related to its failures in the specification of rules or standards of eligibility, PI
fares badly compared to UBI and workfare. When properly considered, the difficulties
in identifying and monitoring the relevant target population appear rather
insurmountable. Again, we must conclude that looked at from a public administration
perspective, we have little reason to embrace PI.
C. CREDITING PAYMENTS TO BENEFICIARIES
The third essential feature of a welfare scheme is the means to credit payments to those
who have been identified as the proper beneficiaries of the grant. Discussion of
alternative welfare proposals often takes this aspect of a welfare scheme for granted,
but its importance should not be underestimated. A set of standards may confer
eligibility on a set of beneficiaries with an appropriate degree of precision, and those
who meet eligibility criteria may have been identified, yet unless the design of welfare
scheme includes the effective means of crediting payments to beneficiaries it must be
judged a failure. Further, vulnerability to fraud or opportunism may undermine the
legitimacy as well as the program efficiency of a scheme.
Again, Christopher Hood’s work on tax administration offers theoretical
inspiration for our attempt to identify the place of the administrative factor in debates
on welfare reform. Hood’s concept of the conduitability of a tax, defined as “the
property of being assessable and collectable through a relatively small number of
surveillable channels or ‘bottlenecks’ at which oversight can be applied” (Hood, 1994:
118) has its counterpart in the administration of welfare grants. In the present context,
we can think of conduitability in terms of the degree of fit or complementarity between
At least one study shows that what clients learn from sanctioning interventions is not any deeper moral lesson on
what constitutes appropriate behavior, but simple lessons on how to properly cooperate with welfare workers who
determine eligibility. “In the end, paternalist reform seems to be a lesson about power, not responsibility” (Wilson et al.
1999; see also Hasenfeld and Weaver 1996).
21
14
the way in which beneficiaries are defined and identified, and the means by which
payments are credited. Relatedly, the arrangements for paying a benefit should ideally
lend themselves to “cross-checking” entitlement to a benefit (see Hood, 1986: 78-79).
There are two ways in which conduitability, defined in this way, may be considered
important to the administerability of a welfare scheme. First, the monitoring of
payments is essential to ensuring that benefits are received by all those who are entitled,
combating “false negatives”. Second, by incorporating as far as possible robust
oversight mechanisms into the arrangements for payment of a benefit, the design of a
scheme plays an important part in ensuring that payments are only made to those who
meet — and continue to fulfill — conditions of entitlement, eradicating “false
positives”. To the extent that these two desiderata have conflicting implications for the
design of a grant, addressing the question of the conduitability calls for skilful
administrative judgment.
Broadly speaking, there are two strategies for ensuring the effective crediting
payments to claimants. The first is to rely on as few alternate payment channels as are
sufficient to reach the target population, in the extreme case, making use of a single but
universally accessible payment mechanism. It is often suggested that a scheme with a
smaller number of surveillable channels is to be preferred on administrative grounds
because it lacks the complications arising from connecting up multiple devices. For
example, in the UK, the National Audit Office (NAO) has argued with reference to the
frequently maligned Child Support Agency, that “the parallel running of separate
systems makes the customer interface more complex” (NAO 2005: ¶2.29). However, we
need to be careful with such cursory assessments since the specific design of payment
schemes matters a great deal. Consider, for instance, the institution of a single payment
channel with heavy monitoring, such as where a case-officer presents a cheque after a
face-to-face encounter. This design may perform well in terms of further ensuring
compliance with the general eligibility requirements, but is likely to prove costly,
especially if a scheme is intended to benefit a large population of beneficiaries. A single
payment scheme that eschews monitoring might perform better in terms of reaching
eligible claimants, but at the same time the absence of monitoring may make a scheme
vulnerable to false positives.22
The alternative strategy is to positively embrace redundancy and to credit
payments through multiple, overlapping mechanisms. While this foregoes the ease-ofoversight provided by a single channel, overlapping devices may make it easier to
reach the full spectrum of beneficiaries. Overlapping systems have a decisive
advantage in cases where the very circumstances that make a particular beneficiary
group difficult to reach make such a group a priority in terms of welfare policy.
Homelessness, for example, or exclusion from the formal labor market, and hence from
firms’ payroll systems, are typical examples. Even so, the advantages of the multiplechannels approach may not always be so decisive in practice. Complementary
payments may suffer from common mode failure: for example, both electronic payment
of funds and account payee cheques require that the intended recipient has access to a
In addition, the absence of any monitoring implies we often do not know precisely how comprehensive a delivery
system is.
22
15
bank account. And as the NAO report (2005) mentioned above suggests, any
advantages of redundancy comes at the cost of complexity, potentially leading to
mistakes on the part of claimants and benefit staff and to increased fraud and barriers
to accessing particular benefits. In summary, effective design of payment systems
achieves an appropriate balance between targeting the full spectrum of beneficiaries
and delivering benefits through a small number of surveillable channels.
Administrative failure can lead to unequal access to benefits and to irregular take-up
rates in diverse ways.
Two general observations follow if we apply this formulation of the concept of
conduitability to the design of welfare schemes. First, crediting payments cannot be
considered merely as an afterthought to other aspects of the design of welfare schemes.
There is a central administrative dimension to securing effective channeling of
payments to beneficiaries which goes beyond simply instituting the proper
technological environment, as suggested by some scholars and practitioners.
Specifically, it is a mistake to assume that in societies with well-established payment
systems, existing payment systems will render this aspect of welfare design
unproblematic. 23 Second, as with our discussion of identifying and monitoring
beneficiaries above, the requirement that a scheme must make — and monitor —
transfers to a sub-set of beneficiaries who fall outside institutionalized payment and
oversight mechanisms challenges the extent to which any scheme will fully achieve its
intended results. In the remainder of this section we consider the performance of PI in
comparison to its rivals in relation to the criterion of conduitability.
Given UBI’s radically inclusive philosophy, ensuring payments reach all those
found eligible can be considered to be the more important aspect of conduitability for
this scheme. UBI takes this approach to its extreme by eschewing conditionality and
altogether dispensing with the need for payment systems to act as a check on
entitlement. In practical terms, discussion of UBI usually propose one of the following
payment schemes: UBI can be implemented through integration into existing tax-credit
schemes, turning it de facto into a refundable tax credit; alternatively, UBI proponents
occasionally advance the idea of a “basic income debit card” from which recipients
draw their grant as and when it is convenient to them, just like a regular cash
withdrawal using a bank card. Both of these approaches reflect the implicit – and
sometimes explicit – assumption among the basic income community that removing
the “gatekeeper” role of welfare case-workers is desirable both because it would
increase claimants’ autonomy and improve take-up rates. One potential shortcoming of
both tax-benefit integration and the basic income debit card may be that these
approaches offer little or no means of checking whether people have actually received
their grants, a point that so far seems to have escaped the radar of UBI advocates.24
23 Consider, for example, the finding of the UK Office of Fair Trading: “In Birmingham in the early 1990s, five of the 39
electoral wards had no bank or building society branches, while a further six wards had only one. But 28% of the city’s
population lived in the relevant areas—including some of its poorest inhabitants.” (Office of Fair Trading, 1999: 22-23).
One can imagine how these issues multiply in rural areas or in countries with less developed electronic payment
systems.
24 It is worth noting a crucial difference between the two types of delivery mechanism. While a refundable tax-credit
scheme retains a measure of monitoring – typically in terms of means testing – both the extent and the approach to
monitoring payments differ considerably from standard welfare programs. Nevertheless a basic capacity to monitor
16
Workfare approaches, on the other hand, eschew payment systems which dispense
with oversight altogether. Quite the contrary, workfare relies on extensive intervention
from case-workers. This approach provides for face-to-face oversight but faces
considerable variable costs which increase as the number of claimants increases. While
these might be considered to be tolerable as long as benefits are targeted more
narrowly at those in formal employment and training, this approach may well be
regarded as infeasible as the target population expands. An obvious solution to this
problem is restricting access to benefits and pro-actively reducing the number of
beneficiaries; however this solution significantly shifts the goals of workfare (Handler
2004; Handler and Babcock 2006). A second mechanism in favor of workfare is that the
aforementioned focus of eligibility on training and formal employment provides a host
of institutionally embedded oversight mechanisms, including payroll systems and
university matriculation records, which in theory allow for effective cross-checking –
assuming the necessary administrative resources are kept in place. Both mechanisms
make it possible for workfare to properly monitor the delivery of payment systems,
even if conduitability under workfare is achieved by restricting eligibility largely those
who are part of the formal employment sector.
UBI and workfare clearly take opposite approaches to the issue of conduitability: in
the case of workfare by restricting the class of beneficiaries to those who can be reached
by existing well-defined channels; in the case of UBI by radically minimizing the
oversight requirements associated with ensuring that conditions of eligibility are met.
Each of these has problems but both may be regarded as broadly viable strategies. In
contrast, the problem of PI is that it possesses the strengths of neither of these two
schemes. Since eligibility is conditional on the satisfaction of a participation
requirement, PI does not share UBI’s ability to dispense with oversight mechanisms
required to prevent payment without the fulfillment of conditions. Combining either
tax-benefit integration or the basic income debit card idea with monitoring and
oversight of conditions associated with PI seems to invite the risks associated with
complexity, identified most recently by the NAO.25 Similarly, because PI is intended to
be more broadly-targeted than workfare, the variable costs of face-to-face monitoring
by case-workers may become prohibitive. Furthermore, the intention that the
participation requirement should be satisfied by informal activities (care work, etc.)
limits the extent to which control can be exercised through surveillable payment
channels, such as employer payroll systems or payment to students at the point of
college registration.
Returning to a point made earlier, PI may be regarded as having one modest
advantage over UBI. Because the scheme is targeted at a narrower set of beneficiaries it
may retain some of the capacity for ex post monitoring of benefit receipt. However,
depending on how broad the participation criterion is interpreted, this capacity may be
very modest indeed, effectively leaving a considerable subclass of the intended group
remains in place. In contrast, while the basic income debit card mechanism in theory also allows for the monitoring of
payment into the account, this scheme retains little capacity to monitor whether the benefit actually reaches the
intended beneficiary.
25 Specifically, complexity poses risks for the implementation of bespoke IT systems for welfare payments that may
defeat attempts at automation and require substantial case-worker intervention (NAO, 2005 paras. 3.24-3.31).
17
unprotected – in particular those who find themselves near the informal end of the
participation spectrum. This violates the goal of providing equal security across the
population, one of the core concerns of a wide range of policy analysts (Standing 1999,
2002). But this modest advantage of PI is in turn trumped by workfare simply because
the latter set of beneficiaries will always be more restricted than that associated with PI,
which implies both a smaller and more homogeneous set.
It seems then that, as with the previous two administrative tasks, PI performs
worse than either UBI or workfare in terms of the crediting of payments to beneficiaries.
Admittedly, compared to the previous two tasks, these arguments may not seem
decisive to the same extent. What is important to carry the overall argument of this
paper is that administrative analysis of the task of channeling payments does not offer
countervailing arguments in favor of PI that might outweigh the disadvantages of PI
discussed in the previous sections.
4. THE TRILEMMA OF PARTICIPATION INCOME
From the analysis of the previous two sections, it follows that PI proponents face a
trilemma of participation income. The first horn of the trilemma consists of the
requirement that PI must remain substantively inclusive if it is to satisfy the concerns
of basic income advocates. The second horn is constituted by the equally important
requirement, insisted upon this time by reciprocity theorists and “soft” workfare
proponents, that recipients must satisfy a genuine participation requirement, which in
turn demands that any PI scheme must be capable of differentiating between those
who fulfill their social obligations, however defined, and those who do not. Finally, the
third horn is made up of the concerns pertaining to the economic and human costs
related to administrability, discussed in detail in the previous sections. The trilemma
arises because PI can only avoid two of three horns simultaneously, inevitably getting
pinned on a third. This leaves us with three possible routes to move the policy forward.
This remainder of this section discusses each of these three routes in turn, and makes
the argument that each of these routes will appeal, if at all, only to a small subset of
those attracted at a general level to PI, with obvious negative consequences for the
political feasibility of PI.
A. THE IRONCLAD ADMINISTRATION STRATEGY
A first possible resolution of the trilemma would be to reject any compromise on easeof-administration considerations, taking the view that where these conflict with a
participation requirement the former should always give way. In this way, PI might
hope to retain the support of both UBI and workfare supporters, as well as those who
support PI on first-best grounds. While this constitutes a coherent position which some
PI proponents implicitly seem willing to adopt, there are nevertheless important
consequences which adherents to this position may be reluctant to accept.
In particular, the ironclad administration strategy sacrifices some of the chief
advantages that are claimed for non-means-tested benefits, in particular the ability to
use bureaucracy sparingly. Christopher Hood (1983: pp 142) has identified two senses in
which one may seek to use bureaucracy sparingly: first, by economizing on the
18
administrative resources or on the administrative capacity of the state required in the
execution of welfare policy, and second, by minimizing what Adam Smith calls the
“trouble, vexation and oppression” visited upon the citizenry by the welfare
administrators. Concerns with using bureaucracy sparingly in the former sense are
captured by the notion of program efficiency in welfare analysis (Goodin, Headey et al.
1999). The latter sense is captured in concerns about welfare administrations constantly
interfering with individuals’ lives — an all too familiar issue in welfare policy, often
cited as one of the key advantages of universal and unconditional measures (Van Parijs
1992, 2004, Offe 2005, Standing 1999, 2002, Fitzpatrick 1999; also Wolff 1999).26
To the extent that one or both of these two senses of using bureaucracy sparingly
may be considered material to the feasibility and desirability of any income support
scheme, considerations of administerability are obviously material to the choice
between rival income support mechanisms. A PI scheme which fails to use
bureaucracy sparingly in the first sense may achieve its objectives only at considerable
administrative cost, satisfying demands for improved target efficiency — if at all — only
at the cost of poor program efficiency (Goodin, Headey et al. 1999). Poor program
efficiency in turn is likely to impact negatively on the capacity of PI to attract a
necessary enacting coalition; it would also impact negatively on the wider public
opinion because one of the core arguments of UBI, namely, low-cost administration, is
no longer attainable.
When a proposed scheme also fails to use bureaucracy sparingly in Hood’s second
sense, the administrative demands of effectively enforcing a broad participation
requirement are borne not only by administrators, but also directly by welfare
recipients, and even by the general population. Intrusive inspections, threats and
punitive sanctions, and the like may all prove necessary to discourage cheating where
compliance cannot be easily and objectively determined. This is an important
consideration with clear impact on the freedom and respect considerations that often
inform universal approaches to income support (Wolff 1999, Eyal 2006). Even where
UBI supporters do not endorse a robust libertarian or left-libertarian position (Van
Parijs 1995), lack of freedom and respect still constitute a personal cost that counts
against the scheme. In short, negotiating the “trilemma” by embracing ironclad
administration comes at considerable cost, with workfare proponents typically
lamenting the increased resource cost of welfare administration and UBI proponents
primarily denouncing the interference cost associated with increased monitoring and
disciplining.
B. THE SOFT WORKFARE STRATEGY
A second approach would be to deliberately formulate the participation requirement in
an under-inclusive fashion; effectively drafting a participation requirement in such a
way as to include only those activities that are easy to specify precisely and to monitor
Incidentally, while UBI is often justified because of its optimal efficiency in regard to both senses of using
bureaucracy sparingly, we urge some caution in this assessment: UBI has the inherent flaw of not only making part of
the administrative apparatus redundant, but as such possibly also breaking down administrative redundancies and
even administrative capacity in general. The former we believe to be a good thing, but the latter may cause problems
that UBI proponents have thus far failed to appreciate. See our analysis in De Wispelaere and Stirton 2004b.
26
19
efficiently, and including — as far as possible — those beneficiaries to whom it is
administratively simple to make payments. As discussed previously, the latter strategy
of creaming “suitable” welfare applicants is familiar in the workfare literature (Handler
2004; Wilson et al. 1999).
While this approach is less attractive in principle than the broad participation
requirement envisaged by Atkinson and others, it might be regarded as a viable
compromise between the theoretical advantages of PI and the requirements of ease-ofadministration outlined above. At the same time it clearly narrows the gap between PI
and selective workfare schemes, for in practice the scheme will necessarily focus on
those social categories or activities that already feature prominently in current
administrative systems. In other words, here PI exhibits the conservative tendency of
reinforcing existing institutionalized practices and activities at the cost of an expanding
valuation of alternative social activities, such as voluntary work or care work. And here
lies the problem: such a solution would be unacceptable to those UBI proponents –
notably feminists and post-productivists – who have made the recognition and
valuation of non-traditional forms of work a key objective of welfare reform.27 Moving
away from the broad acceptance of non-traditional forms of work is likely to lose the
support of political factions representing these points of view, or possibly even incur
active resistance.
In the extreme, there is even a danger that PI would prove less inclusive than
workfare because, as mentioned before, it lacks the myriad of support programs
pertaining to training, in-work assistance, or placement that constitute an integral part
of workfare (at least in theory).28 Of course PI advocates may well acknowledge the
need to supplement basic security with additional activation support. But such “PIPlus” programs face two important constraints. First, faced with permanent austerity
and the sort of political constraints that we witness in relation to workfare programs in
the US and UK (Pierson 2001), one must retain a healthy skepticism about the
likelihood of such programs being instituted at a large scale, with appropriate levels of
funding, if they are to be designed and implemented on top of a PI scheme. But this is
not all. Even if we could resolve such concerns as they pertain to labor market
activation, part of the attraction of PI is that it expands the notion of social participation
to include a wider range of activities. It remains unclear whether a “PI-Plus” proposal
would offer support for individuals to engage in such activities over and beyond the
grant they receive; and if so, what form such support will take.29 Failure to offer
assistance across the whole range of social participation appears to reinforce the
current employment-focused paradigm. Taken these difficulties together it becomes
clear that moving ahead with PI on this first approach raises serious questions in terms
of whether PI will still command the sort of support amongst UBI supporters it enjoys
27 More generally, Guy Standing (2006: 180) argues that “a subversive politics should be about wrestling control over
time for the ‘dispossessed’, and it should recognize that such control is the essence of real security.”
28 PI remains crucially underspecified in this respect: it is compatible with but does not explicitly require the installment of
programs offering support to individuals facing difficulties entering the labor market.
29 Perhaps we are too pessimistic here. Both Claus Offe and Steve Shafarman have independently pressed the point
upon us that civil society might take over at this point. Even if we were to accept this argument – and there are reasons
to be cautious – the asymmetric valuation of formal employment compared to alternative economic or social activities
implied in such a scheme is still worth noting.
20
at present time – or, indeed, that it should.
C. THE LAX ENFORCEMENT STRATEGY
A third resolution of the trilemma suggests an alternative compromise between the
incorporation of a participation requirement and ease-of-administration by adhering to
a broad specification of the participation requirement, accepting all the time that
effective monitoring of compliance with this requirement is going to be problematic –
the welfare state equivalent of de Toqueville’s “rigid rules and lax enforcement”. If the
previous approach narrows the gap between PI and workfare, the present strategy all
but obliterates any distinction between PI and UBI.
Instituting an overly broad PI implies that a participation requirement de facto only
exists as a symbolic commitment to eliminating free-riders. This would more than
likely be acceptable to those who would ideally adopt a UBI and only supported PI as a
politically feasible, second-best option. In addition, it is likely to satisfy political
entrepreneurs who oppose UBI on purely strategic grounds, and who regard this
second route as a unique opportunity to save on administrative resources, opposing
big government and the like, while retaining a firm and public stand on the need for
social participation in return of state support.30
However, this route out of the trilemma would hardly be acceptable to those who
favor PI as a first-best policy. Symbolism aside, lax enforcement of a broadly specified
notion of social participation does not engender commitment to promoting reciprocity
or a stand against free-riding. Of course, once PI no longer serves the need of one of the
core partners of a fragile compromise they will be looking elsewhere for other, more
suitable policies with robust activation components. In addition to more “genuine”
workfare schemes, research of the past 10 years has opened up some interesting
possibilities. One option being investigated is the use of time-limited policies. Stuart
White (2003b), for instance, suggests combining unconditional, time-limited policies
with conditional unlimited schemes. Another possibility is the recent surge of interest
in (conditional) asset-based welfare schemes in both US and UK (Ackerman and
Alstott 1999; Nissan and LeGrand 2003; Goodin 2003; Paxton et al. 2006).
5. IMPLICATIONS FOR THE WIDER BASIC INCOME AGENDA
Our analysis of the difficulties in administering a PI scheme, and of the resulting
trilemma, points to several potentially far-reaching implications for the basic income
debate. First, it calls into question the assumption that a PI can be easily slotted into
existing social security and welfare assistance arrangements. Our discussion has
emphasized the challenges posed in the formulation, application and fulfillment of
standards instituting a broad participation requirement, the defining feature of PI, as
part of welfare policy. Because both UBI and workfare negotiate these difficulties,
albeit in very different ways, these alternative visions of welfare may be regarded as
better able to meet these challenges, which are faced to a greater or lesser extent by all
Charles Murray’s recent proposal for introducing a “Plan”, his version of what essentially amounts to a neo-liberal
UBI scheme for the US, would fit this scenario (Murray 2006).
30
21
income support mechanisms. Our analysis of the trilemma points to various
resolutions, each of these has important consequences for first- and second-best
supporters of PI alike.
Supporters of PI on first-best grounds must squarely confront the issue of whether
the advantages they claim for PI are sufficient to justify the high costs to administrators
and welfare clients of ironclad administration; if not, are these same advantages
sufficiently realized either by a scheme which is close to workfare or one which is
barely distinguishable from UBI? For supporters of PI on second-best grounds, the
trilemma is still more uncomfortable: because support for PI on second-best grounds
represents a political compromise between different positions, the risk arises that such
a compromise would evaporate once the tough choices in the design and
implementation of a scheme are confronted, specifically about how each of the three
tasks discussed in the previous section are to be accomplished. Except under the
somewhat implausible assumption that supporters of universal and active welfare
could compromise on ironclad administration, these two positions opt for incompatible
routes out of the trilemma. In short, at some point in the implementation process the
political compromise is expected to break down.
These considerations lead to a second significant implication for basic income
debates. Implicit in many discussions of universal welfare reform is the assumption
that in key respects PI closely approximates a UBI. The trilemma suggests, however,
that depending on the fine-grained details of any proposed scheme, PI may just as
likely come to resemble workfare schemes (though without the benefit of the activation
mechanisms that in theory are part of the workfare program). This undermines the
dynamic as well as the static version of the second-best case for PI. In a recent essay
Brian Barry writes: “I guess something like participation income might be necessary
politically to get a basic income introduced, but that the expense and intrusiveness of
administering it (as well as lending itself so easily to fraud) would lead either to
abandoning the whole experiment or moving to an unconditional basic income” (Barry
2001: 66). There is, however, a third plausible alternative, namely that given the
problems identified by Barry, criticism of such a scheme would lead to a tightening of
both the formulation and enforcement of the participation criterion. The resulting
outcome is essentially a workfare scheme.
It is worth pointing to two more general implications of our analysis for the basic
income agenda. First, UBI advocates need to consider seriously whether they ought to
lend their support to PI. Our analysis shows that for UBI supporters, endorsement of PI
comes at considerable risk. We caution against those such as Barry, Offe, Vanderborght
or Van Parijs who apparently see the political and administrative instability of PI as an
opportunity for a strategy of introducing basic income by stealth. In addition to the risk
that these features might lead to the abandonment of experiments with universalism,
there is a further and equally plausible possibility that the fine-tuning of such schemes
might open the door for workfarist schemes to which they are implacably opposed.
Furthermore, our analysis shows how this “backdoor” strategy might plausibly require
universalists to sacrifice one of the greatest advantages of their preferred policies,
namely ease-of-administration and non-intrusiveness.
22
The final lesson of our analysis is that supporters of basic income and related
policies cannot ignore the administrative realities of welfare reform. Abstract
discussion of the pros and cons of a broad participation requirement or other features
of a universal grant proposals can be extremely limited, potentially obliterating crucial
conditions on which the desirability or otherwise of particular proposals depends.
While falling short of proper empirical study and comparison, we have shown how
administrative analysis generates important insights beyond abstract theorizing, which
UBI supporters ignore at their peril. Much progress can be made from applying the
insights gleaned from studies of existing welfare policies in order to anticipate the
likely effects of proposed schemes. In this particular case, such analysis clearly
suggests important weaknesses of PI as a welfare policy. While none of our conclusions
are necessarily decisive, together they amount to a strong public administration case
against participation income.
REFERENCES
Ackerman, Bruce and Anne Alstott 1999. The Stakeholder Society. New Haven: Yale University
Press.
Ackerman, Bruce, Anne Alstott and Philippe Van Parijs eds. 2006. Redesigning Distribution: Basic
Income and Stakeholder Grants as Cornerstones for an Egalitarian Capitalism. London/New York:
Verso.
Anderson, Elisabeth 2001. “Optional Freedoms” in What’s Wrong With a Free Lunch?, edited by
Philippe Van Parijs, Joshua Cohen and Joel Rogers. Boston: Beacon Press.
Atkinson, Anthony 1993. Beveridge, the National Minimum, and Its Future in a European Context.
Working Paper WSP/85. London: London School of Economics, STICERD.
Atkinson, Anthony 1995. Public Economics in Action: The Basic Income/Flat Tax Proposal. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Atkinson, Anthony 1996. “The Case for a Participation Income”, The Political Quarterly 67 (1): 6770.
Atkinson, Anthony 1998. Poverty in Europe. Oxford: Blackwell.
Baldwin, Robert 1995. Rules and Government, Oxford, Clarendon Press.
Baldwin, Robert 1990. “Why Rules Don’t Work”, Modern Law Review 53 (3): 321-337.
Bane, Mary Jo and David Elwood 1994. Welfare Realities. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press.
Barry, Brian 2001. “UBI and the Work Ethics” in What’s Wrong With a Free Lunch?, edited
Philippe Van Parijs, Joshua Cohen and Joel Rogers. Boston: Beacon Press.
Black, Julia 1995. “Which Arrow? Rule Type and Regulatory Policy”, Public Law: 94-117
Breyer, Stephen 1982. Regulation and its Reform, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Brodkin Evelyn 1990. “Implementation as Policy Politics” in Implementation and the Policy Process,
edited by D. Palumbo and D. Calista. New York: Greenwood Press.
Brodkin Evelyn 1997. “Inside the Welfare Contract: Discretion and Accountability in State
Welfare Administration”, Social Service Review 71 (1): 1-33.
Cherlin, Andrew, Karen Bogen, James Quane and Linda Burton 2002. “Operating within the
Rules: Welfare Recipients’ Experiences with Sanctions and Case Closings”, Social Service
Review 76: 387-405.
Cunliffe, John and Guido Erreygers eds. 2004. The Origins of Universal Grants. An Anthology of
Historical Writings on Basic Capital and Basic Income. Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Danz, Sheri 2000. “A Non-Public Forum or a Brutal Bureaucracy? Advocates’ Claims of Access
23
to Welfare Center Waiting Rooms”, New York University Law Review 75 (4): 1004-1044.
De Wispelaere, Jurgen and Lindsay Stirton (2004a) “The Many Faces of Universal Basic Income”,
The Political Quarterly 75 (3), pp. 266-274.
De Wispelaere, Jurgen and Lindsay Stirton (2004b) “The Administration of Universal Welfare”
paper presented at the 10th Basic Income European Network Congress, Barcelona.
Diller, Matthew 2000. “The Revolution in Welfare Administration: Rules, Discretion, and
Entrepreneurial Government”, New York University Law Review 75 (5): 1121-1220.
Diver, Colin 1983. “The Optimal Precision of Administrative Rules”, Yale Law Journal 93: 65-109.
Dowding, Keith, Jurgen De Wispelaere and Stuart White eds. 2003. The Ethics of Stakeholding.
Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Ewalt, Jo Ann and Edward Tenning 2004. “Administration, Governance and Policy Tools in
Welfare Policy Implementation”, Public Administration Review 64 (4): 449-462.
Eyal, Nir 2006. “Basic Income Guarantee and the Social Basis of Self-Respect” paper presented
at the 5th USBIG conference, Philadelphia, 24-26 February 2006.
Fitzpatrick, Tony 1999. Freedom and Security: An Introduction to the Basic Income Debate.
Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Galston, William 2001. “What About Reciprocity?” in What’s Wrong With a Free Lunch?, edited
by Philippe Van Parijs, Joshua Cohen and Joel Rogers. Boston: Beacon Press.
Gibson, Diane and Robert Goodin 1999. “The Veil of Vagueness: A Model of Institutional
Design” in Organizational and Institutional Factors in Political Life: Essays in Honour of Johan P.
Olsen, edited by Morton Egeberg and Per Laegreid. Oslo: Scandinavian University Press.
Goodin, Robert 1992. “Towards a Minimally Presumptuous Social Policy” in Arguing for Basic
Income, edited by Philippe Van Parijs. London/New York: Verso.
Goodin, Robert 2000. “Crumbling Pillars: Social Security Futures”, The Political Quarterly 71 (2):
144-150.
Goodin, Robert 2003. “Sneaking Up on Stakeholding” in The Ethics of Stakeholding, edited by
Keith Dowding, Jurgen De Wispelaere and Stuart White. Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Goodin, Robert, Bruce Headey, Ruud Muffles and Henk-Jan Dirven 1999. The Real Worlds of
Welfare Capitalism. Cambridge University Press.
Groot, Loek 2004. Basic Income, Compensatory Justice and Unemployment. Dordrecht: Kluwer
Academic Publishers.
Groot, Loek and Robert van der Veen 2000. “How Attractive is a Basic Income for European
Welfare States?” in Basic Income on the Agenda, edited by Robert van der Veen and Loek
Groot eds. Amsterdam University Press.
Groot, Loek and Robert van der Veen (forthcoming) “Post-Productivism and Welfare States: A
Comparative Analysis” British Journal of Political Science.
Gutmann, Amy & Dennis Thomson 1996. Democracy and Disagreement. Cambridge, Mass.:
Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Handler, Joel 2003. “Social Citizenship and Workfare in the US and Western Europe: From
Status to Contract”, Journal of European Social Policy 13 (3): 229-243.
Handler, Joel 2004. Social Citizenship and Workfare in the United States and Western Europe: The
Paradox of Inclusion. Cambridge University Press.
Handler, Joel and Amanda Sheela Babcock 2006. “The Failure of Workfare: Another Reason for
a Basic Income Guarantee” Basic Income Studies 1 (1): 1-22.
Handler, Joel and Yeshekel Hasenfeld 1997. We the Poor People: Work, Poverty and Welfare. New
Haven: Yale University Press.
Handler, Joel and Yeshekel Hasenfeld (forthcoming) Blame Welfare, Ignore Poverty and Inequality.
Cambrige: Cambridge University Press.
Hasenfeld, Yeshekel and Dale Weaver 1996. “Enforcement, Compliance and Disputes in
24
Welfare-to-Work Programs”, Social Service Review 70: 235-256.
Hasenfeld, Yeshekel, Toorjo Ghose and Kandyce Larson 2004. “The Logic of Sanctioning
Welfare Recipients: An Empirical Assessment”, Social Service Review 78: 304-319.
Hayek, F.A. 1967. “Degrees of Explanation” in Studies in Philosophy, Politics and Economics,
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul
Hood, Christopher 1983. The Tools of Government, Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Hood, Christopher 1986. Administrative Analysis. Brighton: Wheatsheaf.
Hood, Christopher 1994. Explaining Economic Policy Reversals, Buckingham, Open University
Press
Howard, Michael 2006. “Basic Income and Migration – A Moral Dilemma?”, Basic Income Studies
1 (1): 1-22.
Jordan, Bill, Phil Agulnik, Duncan Burbridge and Stuart Duffin. 1999. Stumbling Towards Basic
Income: The Prospect for Tax-Benefit Integration. London, Citizens’ Income Trust.
King, Desmond 1995. Actively Seeking Work? University of Chicago Press.
Lens, Vicky and Susan Vorsanger 2005. “Complaining After Claiming: Fair Hearings After
Welfare Reform”, Social Service Review 29: 430-453.
McBarnett, Doreen & Wheelan, Christopher. 1991. “The Elusive Spirit of the Law: Formalism
and the Struggle for Legal Control”, Modern Law Review 54 (6): 848-873.
McKay, Ailsa 2001. “Rethinking Work and Income Maintenance Policy: Promoting Gender
Equality through a Citizens Basic Income”, Feminist Economics 7 (1): 97-118.
McKay, Ailsa and Jo Van Every 2000. “Gender, Family and Income Maintenance; A Feminist
Case for Citizens' Basic Income”, Social Politics 7 (2): 266-288.
Mead, Lawrence 1986. Beyond Entitlement. New York: Free Press.
Meyers, Marcia K. 2002. “How Welfare Offices Undermine Welfare Reform” in Making Work
Pay: America After Welfare, edited by Robert Kuttner. New York: The New Press.
Meyers, Marcia, Bonnie Glaser and Karin MacDonald 1998. “On the Frontlines of Welfare
Delivery: Are Workers Implementing Policy Reform?”, Journal of Policy Analysis and
Management 17 (1): 1-22.
Meyers, Marcia, Norma Riccucci and Irene Lurie 2001. “Achieving Goal Congruence in Complex
Environments: The Case of Welfare Reform”, Journal of Public Administration Research and
Theory 11 (2): 165-201.
Murray, Charles 2006. In Our Hands. Washington D.C.: IAE Press.
National Audit Office 2005. Department of Work and Pensions: Dealing With the Complexity of the
Benefits System. London: The Stationery Office.
Nattrass, Nicoli and Jeremy Seekings 2005. “The Political Economy of the Basic Income Grant in
South Africa” in The Ethics and Economics of the Basic Income Guarantee , edited by Karl
Widerquist, Michael Lewis and Steven Pressman eds.. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Nissan, David and Julian LeGrand 2003. “A Capital Idea: Helping the Young to Help
Themselves” in The Ethics of Stakeholding, edited by Keith Dowding, Jurgen De Wispelaere
and Stuart White eds. Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Offe, Claus 1992. “A Non-Productivist Design for Social Policies” in Arguing for Basic Income.
Edited by Van Parijs ed. London/New York: Verso.
Offe, Claus 1996. “The Acceptance and Legitimacy of Strategic Options in Social Policy” in
Modernity and the State: East, West. Cambridge: Polity Press
Offe, Claus 2001. “Pathways from Here” in What’s Wrong With a Free Lunch?, edited by Philippe
Van Parijs, Joshua Cohen and Joel Rogers. Boston: Beacon Press.
Offe, Claus 2005. “Wasteful Welfare Transfers” in Promoting Income Security as a Right: Europe and
North-America, edited by Guy Standing. London: Anthem Press.
25
Office of Fair Trading 1999. Vulnerable Consumers of Financial Services: The Report of the Director
General's Inquiry. London: The Office of Fair Trading.
Orbach, Barak 2006. “Unwelcome Benefits: Why Welfare Beneficiaries Reject Government Aid”,
Law and Inequality 24 (107): 107-150.
Pateman, Carole 2003. “Freedom and Democratization: Why Basic Income Is to Be Preferred to
Basic Capital” in The Ethics of Stakeholding, edited by Keith Dowding, Jurgen De Wispelaere
and Stuart White eds. Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Pateman, Carole 2004. “Democratizing Citizenship: Some Advantages of a Basic Income”,
Politics and Society 32 (1): 89-106.
Paxton, Will, Stuart White and Dominic Maxwell 2006. The Citizen’s Stake. Bristol: The Policy
Press.
Pierson, Paul ed. 2001. The New Politics of Welfare. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Prendergast, Canice (forthcoming) “The Motivation and Bias of Bureaucrats”, American
Economic Review.
Riccio, James and Yeshekel Hasenfeld 1996. “Enforcing a Participation Mandate in a Welfare-toWork Program”, Social Service Review 70: 516-542
Riccucci, Norma, Marcia Meyers, Irene Lurie and Jun Seop Han 2004. “The Implementation of
Welfare Reform: The Role of Public Managers in Front-Line Practices”, Public Administration
Review 64 (4): 438-448.
Robeyns, Ingrid 2000. “Hush Money or Emancipation Fee? A Gender Analysis of Basic Income”
in Basic Income on the Agenda, edited by Robert van der Veen and Loek Groot. Amsterdam
University Press.
Sandfort, Jodi 2000. “Moving Beyond Discretion and Outcomes: Examining Public Management
from the Front Lines of the Welfare System”, Journal of Public Administration Research and
Theory 10 (4): 729-756.
Standing, Guy 1999. Global Labor Flexibility. Seeking Distributive Justice. Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Standing, Guy 2002. Beyond the New Paternalism. London/New York: Verso.
Standing, Guy 2006. “CI, COAG and COG: A Comment on a Debate” in Redesigning Distrbution:
Basic Income and Stakeholder Grants as Cornerstones for an Egalitarian Capitalism, edited by
Bruce Ackerman, Anne Alstott and Philippe Van Parijs. London/New York: Verso.
Standing, Guy ed. 2005. Promoting Income Security as a Right: Europe and North-America. London:
Anthem Press.
Stoker, Robert and Laurie Wilson 1998. “Verifying Compliance: Social Regulation and Welfare
Reform”, Public Administration Review 58 (5): 395-405.
Suplicy, Eduardo Matarazzo 2005. “The Approval of the Basic Income Guarantee in Brazil” in
The Ethics and Economics of the Basic Income Guarantee, edited by Karl Widerquist, Michael
Lewis and Steven Pressman. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Tennings, Edward and Dale Krane 1994. “Coordination and Welfare Reform: The Quest for the
Philosopher’s Stone” Public Administration Review 54 (4): 341-348.
Van der Veen, Robert and Loek Groot eds. 2000. Basic Income on the Agenda. Amsterdam
University Press.
Van Parijs, Philippe 1992. “The Marriage of Justice and Efficiency” in Arguing for Basic Income,
edited by Philippe Van Parijs. London/New York: Verso.
Van Parijs, Philippe 1995. Real Freedom for All. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Van Parijs, Philippe 1996. “Basic Income and the Two Dilemmas of the Welfare State”, The
Political Quarterly 67 (1): 63-66.
Van Parijs, Philippe 2001. “Reply” in What’s Wrong With a Free Lunch?, edited by Philippe Van
Parijs, Joshua Cohen and Joel Rogers. Boston: Beacon Press.
Van Parijs, Philippe 2004. “Basic Income: A Simple and Powerful Idea for the Twenty-first
26
Century”, Politics and Society 32 (1): 7-39.
Van Parijs, Philippe and Yannick Vanderborght 2001. “From Euro-stipendium to Euro-dividend.
A Comment on Schmitter and Bauer”, Journal of European Social Policy 11: 342-46.
Van Parijs, Philippe, Joshua Cohen and Joel Rogers eds. 2001. What’s Wrong With a Free Lunch?
Boston: Beacon Press.
Van Parijs, Philippe ed. 1992. Arguing for Basic Income: Ethical Foundations for a Radical Reform.
London/New York: Verso.
Vanderborght, Yannick 2000. “'The VIVANT Experiment in Belgium” in Basic Income on the
Agenda, edited by Robert van der Veen and Loek Groot. Amsterdam University Press.
Vanderborght, Yannick 2005. “The Basic Income Guarantee in Europe: The Belgian and Dutch
Back Door Strategies” in The Ethics and Economics of the Basic Income Guarantee, edited by
Karl Widerquist, Michael Lewis and Steven Pressman. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Weaver, Kent 1986. “The Politics of Blame Avoidance”, Journal of Public Policy 6: 371-398.
White, Stuart 2003a. The Civic Minimum. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
White, Stuart 2003b. “Freedom, Reciprocity and the Citizen’s Stake” in The Ethics of Stakeholding,
edited by Keith Dowding, Jurgen De Wispelaere and Stuart White. Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Widerquist, Karl, Michael Anthony Lewis and Steven Pressman eds. 2005. The Ethics and
Economics of the Basic Income Guarantee. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Wilson, Laura, Robert Stoker and Dennis McGrath 1999. “Welfare Bureaus as Moral Tutors:
What Do Clients Learn from Paternalistic Welfare Reforms”, Social Science Quarterly 80 (3):
473-486.
Wolff, Jonathan 1999. “Fairness, Respect, and the Egalitarian Ethos”, Philosophy and Public Affairs
27: 97-122.
Zelleke, Almaz 2005. “Basic Income in the United States: Redefining Citizenship in the Liberal
State”, Review of Social Economy 63 (4): 633-648.
27