The Quantum Eraser Paradox
C. Bracken,1, 2 J.R. Hance,3, ∗ and S. Hossenfelder4
1
arXiv:2111.09347v2 [quant-ph] 26 Nov 2021
Dept of Experimental Physics, Maynooth University, Maynooth, Co. Kildare, Ireland
2
Astronomy & Astrophysics Section, School of Cosmic Physics,
Dublin Institute for Advanced Studies, Fitzwilliam Place, Dublin 2, D02 XF86
3
Quantum Engineering Technology Laboratories, Department of Electrical and Electronic Engineering,
University of Bristol, Woodland Road, Bristol, BS8 1US, UK
4
Frankfurt Institute for Advanced Studies, Ruth-Moufang-Str. 1, D-60438 Frankfurt am Main, Germany
(Dated: November 29, 2021)
The Delayed-Choice Quantum Eraser experiment is commonly interpreted as implying that in quantum mechanics a choice made at one time can influence an earlier event. We here suggest an extension of the experiment
that results in a paradox when interpreted using a local realist interpretation combined with backward causation
(“retrocausality”). We argue that resolving the paradox requires giving up the idea that, in quantum mechanics, a choice can influence the past, and that it instead requires a violation of Statistical Independence without
retrocausality. We speculate what the outcome of the experiment would be.
I.
INTRODUCTION
In the famous Quantum Eraser experiment [62], an interference pattern can be re-created by erasing which-way information. Even more remarkable, this information can be successfully erased after the which-way information was already
imprinted on the state. This Delayed-Choice Quantum Eraser
[35, 60, 70] is frequently interpreted as showing the possibility of an influence on the past [72].
In [28], it was argued that from the ψ-ensemble perspective
this retrocausal interpretation makes no sense. Instead, if one
wants to explain the outcome in a local realist framework, then
the information about what measurement would take place
must have been available already at the time of preparation.
In a ψ-ensemble, the wave-function is not itself fundamental,
it merely describes a collection of ontic states in an underlying
theory.
Here and in the following we will take a local realist theory
to mean a hidden variables theory that fulfils Bell’s criterion of
local causality. Bell’s theorem [5, 6, 43] requires that any such
local realist theory must violate one of the other assumptions
of the theorem to reproduce the observed violations of Bell’s
inequality. We will here consider the case where Statistical
Independence is violated. This is possible through two options. The first involves assuming that the information about
the measurement settings at detection is contained in the state
of the hidden variables at preparation. This option is known
as superdeterminism1 [30, 31]. The other option is that the
measurement setting at detection influences the initial state,
which is known as retrocausality.
We want to emphasise that this type of retrocausality does
not use the notion of causality which is common in many parts
of physics, in which of two causally related events, one is the
cause of the other if it is in the past light cone of the other.
According to this notion of causality, retrocausality does not
exist by definition [7]. Instead, to analyse experiments in the
∗
1
jonte.hance@bristol.ac.uk
Of which supermeasured theories [29] are a subset.
foundations of quantum mechanics, it has become common
to use the notion of causality derived from causal diagrams
[44, 65, 73] usually referred to as “interventionist causality”.
The relation between these two notions of causality has yet to
be entirely clarified. For a recent discussion see [61].
The purpose of this paper is to propose and discuss an extension of the Delayed-Choice Quantum Eraser suggested by
one of us (CB). We will argue that this extension supports the
hypothesis that Statistical Independence is violated but that
retrocausality is either internally inconsistent or, when internal consistency is enforced, becomes inconsistent with observation.
A variety of retrocausal approaches to quantum mechanics
have been put forward in [1, 11–20, 24, 46–51, 63, 67–69, 71].
We will not discuss any one of those approaches specifically
here, but will instead generally focus on a common feature
that all local realist explanations which exploit retrocausality
must share. Our argument differs from previously made ones
[2, 8, 38] in that we propose a concrete experimental setup
that can be realised in the near future.
This paper is organised as follows. After recalling how the
Quantum Eraser works in Section II, and exploring why it is
puzzling in Section III, we will in Section IV propose an extension of the experiment that, if one believes the retrocausal
explanation, results in a causality paradox. In Section V, we
will discuss what the outcome of such an experiment would
be and in Section VI offer some considerations about the feasibility of the experiment.
The reader who is familiar with the Quantum Eraser experiment, Bell’s theorem, and the Elitzur-Vaidman bomb experiment [22], can jump right to section IV.
II.
THE QUANTUM ERASER
We here briefly summarise the experiment as first realised
in [35], which is close to the original proposal from [62].
For illustration, see Figure 1. Photons are emitted from a
source (S) and sent through a double slit (black). After the
double-slit, they hit a nonlinear optical crystal (grey) which,
by spontaneous parametric down conversion, creates an entan-
2
the distribution of photons on the screen will be given by
|ψ1 |2 +|ψ2 |2 , that is, it will be a combination of the diffraction
patterns of each slit separately, with slightly off-set peaks.
The eraser works by instead using a measurement that
projects the state (1) on a symmetric and an asymmetric combinations of the which-way information |D1 i and |D2 i, for
example
1
|D3 i = √ (|D1 i + |D2 i)
2
1
|D4 i = √ (|D1 i − |D2 i) .
2
FIG. 1. Experimental setup for the Quantum Eraser (as given by
[35]). Single photons are produced at the source (S) and sent through
a double slit (black), then each photon is converted into an entangled
pair. The photons on the upper path (solid/pink) go to a detector (Ds )
which measures whether they interfere. The photons on the lower
path (dashed/green) are either measured at the first pair of detectors
(D1/2 ) which reveal the which-way information, or at the second pair
of detectors (D3/4 ) which erase the which-way information.
gled pair of photons from each photon incident on the crystal
(solid/pink and dashed/green lines).
One of the photons in each entangled pair is sent directly
towards a detector screen (Ds ), depicted as the upper path in
Figure 1. The other two photons are either measured at detectors D1 and D2 which reveal where the photon came from
(the “which-way information”), or they are combined using
mirrors and a semi-transparent plate, and then measured at
detectors D3 and D4 , without revealing the which-way information. The question is whether the photons arriving at the
screen Ds , coincident with arriving at one of the detectors,
will or won’t create an interference pattern.
Theoretically one can understand the setup as follows. The
wave-function |Ψi exiting a double-slit is normally√
a superposition of two contributions |Ψi = (|ψ1 i + |ψ2 i) / 2, where
the indices 1 and 2 refer to the two slits. When time-evolved
forward to the detection screen, these two contributions are
non-orthogonal, giving rise to an interference pattern.
However, creating an entangled pair from each incident
photon at a particular location has the result of imprinting
information about the position of the photon on the wavefunction. We can write this schematically as
1
|Ψi = √ |ψ1 i|D1 i + |ψ2 i|D2 i ,
2
(1)
where |ψ1 i (|ψ2 i) is the photon going to the screen coming
from the upper (lower) slit, and |D1 i and |D2 i are those going
to detector D1 and D2 . The states |D1 i and |D2 i are orthogonal because the locations are spatially separate.
This wave-function, when forward-evolved to the screen
cannot interfere, because it has the orthogonal which-way
information |D1 i and |D2 i imprinted on it. This means,
(2)
The states |D3 i and |D4 i also constitute an orthogonal measurement basis, and it’s this basis which is measured at D3 and
D4 , respectively.
In this basis, the state (1) takes the form
1
[(|ψ1 i + |ψ2 i)|D3 i + (|ψ1 i − |ψ2 i)|D4 i] .
2
(3)
One sees from this expression that when one projects the state
on either |D3 i or |D4 i by measuring the entangled partner,
then the respective contribution which goes to the screen can
interfere. This is just because the orthogonal states |D1 i and
|D2 i are not orthogonal to |D3 i and |D4 i. Loosely speaking,
thus, they each have contributions that can interfere.
One further sees from expression (3), that the two interference patterns, created by projecting on |D3 i or |D4 i, respectively, are not identical. Because of the minus in the second
term, the interference patterns are phase-shifted to each other.
When one adds them together, they re-create the original noninterference pattern. This has to be so because we just made a
basis transformation.
For the Delayed-Choice Quantum Eraser (hereafter
DCQE) one makes the path of the photons to the eraser long
enough so that they are detected after the partner particle appeared on the screen. An interference pattern is still observed
for photons correlated with those going to either D3 or D4 .
It is worth stressing that the measurement outcome on the
screen does not depend on the settings on the other path, that
is, whether the eraser is on or off does not affect the outcome
on the screen. It’s just that one can sample the photons in two
different groups in two different ways [23, 34, 52, 53].
When one uses detectors D1 and D2 , then the entangled
partners of photons reaching each detector separately do not
create an interference pattern on Ds . When one, on the other
hand, uses detectors D3 and D4 , then the partner particles of
photons arriving at only D3 or only D4 create an interference
pattern. But together they do not. This is also the case in setup
of the experiment which employs polarising plates to imprint
the which-way information, used, for example, in [70], though
the symmetric and anti-symmetric combinations differ by a
complex phase.
It has to be the case that the result on the screen is independent of whether one measures the which-way information
or not, because in quantum mechanics the outcome does not
depend on how long after the one photon arrived on the screen
its entangled partner is measured. Therefore, these measure-
3
ments could be causally disconnected (which indeed they are
in [37]). Then, if the pattern on Ds did depend on the measurement settings (D1/2 or D3/4 ), that would violate the nosignalling theorem [64].
III.
INTERPRETATION
First, we want to stress that the measurement results of the
DCQE experiments can full well be understood in the Copenhagen interpretation. If one is willing to accept a non-local
update of the wave-function upon measurement, then there is
nothing puzzling about the experiment. The wave-function
simply propagates until it hits the detectors, and then it ‘collapses’ to a localised state with a probability given by Born’s
rule.
However, many people find the DCQE results more disturbing (weird, strange, counter-intuitive) than, say, those of
Bell-type experiments. We believe this is because a Bell-type
experiment can be visualised (mentally or actually) by a local
process. One simply creates two entangled particles that one
can think of as little balls, those propagate in two different directions, and then they are detected at two separate locations.
It is easy to imagine that when the particles hit the detectors,
that measurement merely reveals which spin or polarisation
they have, and those outcomes are correlated because the particles had a common origin.
The real puzzle of a Bell-type test lies in the fact that the
correlations in the outcomes of both detectors are, for certain relative orientations of the measurement settings, more
strongly correlated than one would expect from a local, classical theory in which the outcome of the measurement was
determined by hidden, internal properties of the particles. But
this puzzle is buried in the mathematics underlying Bell’s theorem and cannot be straight-forwardly visualised.
In experiments like the Elitzur-Vaidman bomb detector [22]
or the DCQE, on the other hand, it becomes visually apparent that local realist explanations are difficult to come by because these experiments make use of superpositions in position space (particles that “take two paths at once”).
In the bomb experiment (Figure 2), one uses a MachZehnder interferometer with a “bomb” in one path. The bomb
plays the role of an additional detector which reveals whichway information. If the detector is on (the bomb is live) and
doesn’t click (doesn’t explode), one knows the particle is on
the other path.
To explain what happens in the bomb experiment, one first
has to account for the destructive interference at detector D2
when the bomb is a dud. In this case, by assumption, no interaction between the photon and the bomb takes place at all,
and we just have the usual Mach-Zehnder interferometer. The
destructive interference at D2 then requires one to accept that
the photon acts like a wave and takes both possible paths. But
if the bomb is in place, live, and yet didn’t explode, then we
know the photon must have gone the path on which there is no
bomb. This means, if one wants a local explanation, then the
propagation of the photon must depend on the detector setting
(whether the bomb is live or not) – before the photon even
FIG. 2. Sketch of the bomb experiment. Detector D2 only registers
a photon if the bomb was live and didn’t explode. The experiment
can thus reveal information about a counterfactual event which didn’t
happen.
reached the detector (the bomb).
Of course one could argue that we knew this already: a local realist hidden variables explanation of quantum mechanical phenomena requires that the path of a particle depends on
the measurement setting at the time of measurement2 . This,
after all, is what Bell’s theorem tells us: If we insist on a
local explanation, then Statistical Independence must be violated [31], either by superdeterminism or by retrocausality.
However, the bomb experiment makes it much more apparent
just what this entails. Most notably, it makes apparent just
how easy it is to explain the observations by violating Statistical Independence: If one measures the which-way information (bomb is live), the photon either goes via one path or
the other, but not both. Then, it has a 50:50 chance of being
transmitted:reflected by the beamsplitter. That’s it.3
The quantum eraser seems perplexing for a similar reason.
If one measures the which-way information at D1 and D2 ,
then a local realist explanation requires that the original photon either went through the upper slit, triggering the upper
entangled pair (pink/solid line) or the lower slit, triggering the
lower entangled pair (green/dashed line), but not both. If we,
however, ignore the which-way information and use instead
detectors D3 or D4 , then it seems a particle going to, say, D3 ,
must have gone through both slits, so it can interfere with itself (and similarly for D4 ). That is, the choice of whether to
use the eraser or not seems to decide what happened on the
screen earlier (retrocausality) or the photons’ paths depend on
the measurement setting all along (superdeterminism).
This argument doesn’t work as well for the quantum eraser
as for the bomb experiment, because, in combining the two
2
3
The measurement settings in Bell’s theorem are those at the time of measurement. It does not matter at which time or how the settings were chosen,
it only matters what they are when the actual measurement takes place.
In such a case, interaction-free/ “counterfactual” communication/ computation/ imaging, such as that in [26, 27, 32, 55–59], is possible locally
specifically because of this statistical independence violation - the message/information is to some degree encoded in the detector settings.
4
FIG. 4. Retrocausality, causal relations.
FIG. 3. Delayed choice quantum eraser with feedback (arrow). Zigzag in lower two paths indicate that these paths could be much longer
than the upper two.
paths they necessarily have to come together in one place. One
can therefore explain the quantum eraser just by postulating
that the photons always go via only one path, it’s just that at
the beam splitter, half of them pass through and the other half
of them do not, and the positions their entangled partners go
to on the screen are correlated with whether the photons at the
eraser go through the beam splitter or not.
We will in the following argue that the DCQE experiment
can be extended so that, like the bomb experiment, a local
realist explanation is possible only if the path of the photon
either (a) allows a retrocausal influence or (b) depends on the
measurement setting all along. We will then add another twist
to rule out option (a).
IV. THE PARADOX
What goes on in the DCQE experiment becomes clearer
when we replace the interference screen Ds with another
eraser quartet of detectors (see Figure 3; ignore the black arrow for now). That is, we create the entangled state
1
|Ψi = √ |U1 i|D1 i + |U2 i|D2 i ,
2
(4)
where each component of the wave-function is labelled by the
detector it evolves towards. On both paths of the entangled
photons we can chose whether to measure the which-way information (D1/2 , U1/2 ) or whether to erase it (D3/4 , U3/4 ).
The detectors U3 and U4 measure the same superpositions
as defined in (2) just with U’s instead of D’s. Note, in this
local-realist setting, we assume measurement at the detector
collapses the wavefunction.
This modification makes the similarity to Bell-type experiments obvious. We could now either measure the which-way
information on both sides (D1/2 , U1/2 ), and find that the results are perfectly correlated. Or we could erase the whichway information on both sides (D3/4 , U3/4 ) and find the results are also perfectly correlated. Or we could measure the
which-way information on one side and not on the other (
(D1/2 and U3/4 ) or (D3/4 and U1/2 )) and find the results are
entirely uncorrelated. So far, so unsurprising.
In this case it is still possible to come up with a local realist explanation as previously. One just imagines the photons
are particles going via one specific path, which go through
the beam splitter half of the time. The entangled photons do
the same on each of their beam splitters. No retrocausality or
superdeterminism required.
One thing one could do now is to create a mixture of whichway and erasure settings. That would constitute a Bell-type
experiment. Then we could use violations of Bell’s inequality
to draw conclusions about violations of Statistical Independence. However, this setup it is technically cumbersome and
also teaches us nothing new.
Instead, we can make a third type of measurement, which is
similar to that in the bomb experiment: Measure on the upper
path with U3 and U4 , but measure on the lower path with D3 ,
D4 and D1 . Now remember that to explain the previous measurements with a local realist visualisation, we had to settle
on the case where we have a particle going one particular path
(pink or green, but not both), and at a beam splitter, it goes
through only half of the time, and pairs of entangled particles do the same at their respective splitters. This explanation
would tell us that in this third type of measurement, for those
photons that do not appear in detector D1 , outcomes for their
entangled partners at U3/4 and D3/4 are still correlated. Alas,
in quantum mechanics they should now be uncorrelated.
To fix this problem (in a locally-realist way), we can then
either (a) require that turning on detector D1 determines what
happened at U3/4 , that is, in the past. This is the retrocausal
option whose causal relations are depicted in Figure 4. Or we
(b) accept that the paths of the photons were dependent on the
detector settings4 already at emission. This is the superdeterministic option whose causal relations are depicted in Figure
4
Again we want to stress that those are the detector settings at the time of
5
result is always U3 and D3 together. This is internally consistent – no causal paradox occurs – but it’s not what quantum
mechanics predicts. A sequence of photons that go to U3 and
D3 is exponentially unlikely. The longer the sequence, the less
likely. The retrocausal explanation can hence be ruled out experimentally. If this was achieved, we could concluded that
Statistical Independence must have been violated all along.
As previously discussed in [28], this also solves the measurement problem and removes other known inconsistencies of
quantum mechanics, such as the contradictions resulting in
the Extended Wigner’s Friend scenario.
FIG. 5. Superdeterminism, causal relations.
VI. FEASIBILITY
FIG. 6. Retrocausality with feedback loop, causal relations.
5.
To rule out (a), we propose to use a detection at U4 to turn
on D1 , which creates the causal relations depicted in Figure
6. If using detector D1 indeed retrocausally determined that
the entangled partner of a photon which did not go to D1 must
have had a 50% chance of going to U3 , then in half of the runs
we create a causal paradox: The photon went to U4 , so we
turned on D1 , but as a result it went to U3 !
This feedback loop seems to realise an instance of the wellknown grandfather paradox, in which you go back in time and
kill your own grandfather, so you’re never born and can’t go
back in time to kill your own grandfather. Did you, or did you
not, kill your grandfather? We can ask here the same way:
“Did, or didn’t, the photon go to U4 ?”
V. RESOLVING THE PARADOX
It seems that retrocausality cannot predict what will happen
in this experiment. Clearly the contradiction itself will not
manifest, for what would that mean? Would the world end in a
poof? Would an error message pop up, crashing the simulation
that is our reality? Certainly not (we hope). But then what
would happen?
In a retrocausal framework, there is only one consistent outcome, which is that the photon on the upper path just never
goes to U4 . If it doesn’t go to U4 , D1 never turns on, and the
measurement. If the path could depend on the detector setting at an earlier
time, that would be non-local, not superdeterministic.
By combining the bomb experiment and the quantum
eraser, the experiment proposed above allows us to perform
a new test of local realist theories. We will now discuss what
it would take to perform this experiment.
The most practical method to create high-intensity
polarisation-entangled photon states is to use spontaneous
parametric down-conversion (SPDC), as demonstrated by
[36], for example. The constraints of energy conservation in
SPDC requires that the sum of the energies of the two downconverted photons must equal the energy of the pump photon
[33]. This technique typically utilises nonlinear crystals such
as barium borate (BBO) [21], or radiative cascade of calcium
atoms [3]. We will focus on the former for our purposes.
When a monochromatic light source illuminates the BBO
crystal with wavelength λ0 , it places the crystal in an energy state above ground state. When the atoms within the
crystal then de-excitate, a pair of down-converted photons are
emitted at wavelength λDC . Because of the difficulty in producing short-wavelength lasers, and the limits on the operational wavelength range of non-linear crystals, experiments
to date [35, 37, 60] have typically used optical or ultraviolet
λ0 ≈ 350 − 450 nm ‘pump’ frequencies to excite the crystals. The resulting down-converted photons then each exhibit
a wavelength of precisely λDC = 2λ0 . Each of the photons in
the entangled pair has exactly half the energy of the incident
photon, typically in the red or infrared range (depending on
the pump λ0 ).
At such low photon energies, conventional detector arrays
such as charge-coupled devices (CCDs) simply can not reliably count individual photons due to read noise – the semiconductor energy band gap is the same order of magnitude as
the energy of the photons themselves (≈ 1 eV). Because of
this, noise contributions can be mistaken for photon events,
and only a large number of photon events can generate a reliable signal. This is obviously not ideal for photon-counting
experiments such as we would like to do with the quantum
eraser.
We believe the proposed measurements to be possible
due to the significant advances in detector technology for
optical/near-infrared photons in recent years. If largeformat multiplexing is required, the most promising of these
technologies is the microwave kinetic inductance detector
(MKID) array [4, 25, 39, 40, 42, 66]. An array of MKIDs
6
can sample the spatial domain to a resolution of better than
100 microns, while providing time resolution of around 100
ns on each pixel with zero read noise. The only false counts
result from cosmic rays, but these events display a different
profile and can easily be filtered. Thus, it is feasible to monitor the full measurement plane if required (for a quantumeraser type experiment), as MKIDs are easily multiplexed to
arrays of many thousands of pixels through frequency division
multiplexing [4, 41].
VII. CONCLUSION
Conveniently though, in the novel set-up proposed here, it
becomes unnecessary to measure a large plane, because we
do not need the entire interference pattern. We can simply
measure correlations in particular detector combinations using coincidence detection. For this, a single pixel (or a small
array) on each detector location will suffice. What will be
of paramount importance though, is speed of response and
the ability to minimise noise. Single-photon avalanche diode
(SPAD) arrays have undergone rapid and significant development over the past 18 years since first demonstrated in 2003
[54]. SPADs are solid-state detectors that allow photon counting, with unparalleled time-resolution on the order of a few
picoseconds [9, 10, 45, 74, 75]. While multiplexing to large
arrays remains challenging with this detector technology, this
will not be an issue for the experiment outlined in Figure 3 as
large-format multiplexing will not be required.
We have here proposed a new experiment that combines the
Delayed-Choice Quantum Eraser with the Elitzur-Vaidman
thought/gedanken bomb experiment. When one tries to explain what happens in this experiment using a local realist interpretation, one is left with two choices: superdeterminism or
retrocausality. The retrocausal option can lead to a causality
paradox. When one prevents the paradox by requiring a consistent time-evolution, then retrocausality requires measurement outcomes which differ from the predictions of quantum
mechanics. The difference is measurable and we have laid out
a way to do this measurement in the near future.
Acknowledgements: We thank Tim Palmer and John Rarity
for useful comments. CB acknowledges support by Enterprise
Ireland under the HEU award, grant number EI/CS20212057BRACKEN. SH acknowledges support by the Deutsche
Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG, German Research Foundation) under grant number HO 2601/8-1. JRH is supported by
the University of York’s EPSRC DTP grant EP/R513386/1,
and the EPSRC Quantum Communications Hub (funded by
the EPSRC grant EP/M013472/1).
Competing Interest Statement: The authors declare that
there are no competing interests.
Data Availability: Data sharing not applicable to this article
as no datasets were generated or analysed during the current
study.
Author Contribution Statement: All authors contributed to
this article equally. Authors are listed alphabetically.
[1] D Almada, K Ch’ng, S Kintner, B Morrison, and KB Wharton. Are retrocausal accounts of entanglement unnaturally
fine-tuned? arXiv preprint arXiv:1510.03706, 2015. URL:
https://arxiv.org/abs/1510.03706.
[2] Frank Arntzenius. Spacelike connections. British Journal for
the Philosophy of Science, 45(1):201–217, 1994. doi:10.
1093/bjps/45.1.201.
[3] Alain Aspect, Philippe Grangier, and Gérard Roger. Experimental realization of einstein-podolsky-rosen-bohm gedankenexperiment: A new violation of bell’s inequalities. Phys. Rev.
Lett., 49:91–94, Jul 1982. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.
49.91.
[4] Eoin Baldwin, Mario De Lucia, Colm Bracken, Gerhard Ulbricht, and Tom Ray. Frequency domain multiplexing with
the Xilinx ZCU111 RFSoC board. In X-Ray, Optical, and
Infrared Detectors for Astronomy IX, volume 11454. International Society for Optics and Photonics, SPIE, 2020. doi:
10.1117/12.2561108.
[5] John S Bell.
On the einstein podolsky rosen paradox.
Physics Physique Fizika, 1(3):195, 1964. doi:10.1103/
PhysicsPhysiqueFizika.1.195.
[6] John S Bell. Speakable and unspeakable in quantum mechanics: Collected papers on quantum philosophy. Cambridge University Press, 2 edition, 2004.
[7] Hanoch Ben-Yami. The impossibility of backwards causation.
The Philosophical Quarterly, 57(228):439–455, 2007.
[8] Joseph Berkovitz. On explanation in retro-causal interpretations of quantum mechanics. In Probabilities, Causes and
Propensities in Physics, pages 115–155. Springer, 2011. doi:
10.1007/978-1-4020-9904-5_6.
Claudio Bruschin, Harald Harald Homulle, Ivan Michel Antolovic, Samuel Burri, and Edoardo Charbon. Single-photon
avalanche diode imagers in biophotonics: review and outlook.
Light: Science & Applications, 8, 2019. doi:10.1038/
s41377-019-0191-5.
E Charbon. Single-photon imaging in complementary metal oxide semiconductor processes. Philosophical Transactions of the
Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences, 372(2012):20130100, 2014. doi:10.1098/rsta.
2013.0100.
Eliahu Cohen, Marina Cortês, Avshalom Elitzur, and Lee
Smolin. Realism and causality. i. pilot wave and retrocausal
models as possible facilitators. Phys. Rev. D, 102:124027, Dec
2020. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.102.124027.
Eliahu Cohen, Marina Cortês, Avshalom C. Elitzur, and Lee
Smolin. Realism and causality. ii. retrocausality in energetic
causal sets. Phys. Rev. D, 102:124028, Dec 2020. doi:10.
1103/PhysRevD.102.124028.
Richard Corry. Retrocausal models for epr. Studies in History
and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 49:1–9, 2015. doi:10.1016/
j.shpsb.2014.11.001.
O Costa de Beauregard. Time symmetry and the einstein paradox. Il Nuovo Cimento B (1971-1996), 42(1):41–64, 1977.
doi:10.1007/BF02906749.
O Costa de Beauregard. Time symmetry and the einstein
[9]
[10]
[11]
[12]
[13]
[14]
[15]
7
[16]
[17]
[18]
[19]
[20]
[21]
[22]
[23]
[24]
[25]
[26]
[27]
[28]
[29]
[30]
[31]
[32]
[33]
paradox.-ii. Il Nuovo Cimento B (1971-1996), 51(2):267–279,
1979. doi:10.1007/bf02743436.
O Costa de Beauregard. On some frequent but controversial statements concerning the einstein-podolsky-rosen correlations. Foundations of Physics, 15(8):871–887, 1985. doi:
10.1007/BF00738320.
O Costa de Beauregard. On the zigzagging causality epr model:
Answer to vigier and coworkers and to sutherland. Foundations of physics, 17(8):775–785, 1987. doi:10.1007/
BF00733266.
Phil Dowe. Process causality and asymmetry. Erkenntnis,
37(2):179–196, 1992. doi:10.1007/BF00209321.
Phil Dowe. Backwards causation and the direction of causal
processes. Mind, 105(418):227–248, 1996. doi:10.1093/
mind/105.418.227.
Phil Dowe. A defense of backwards in time causation models
in quantum mechanics. Synthese, 112(2):233–246, 1997. doi:
10.1023/A:1004932911141.
D. Eimerl, L. Davis, S. Velsko, E. K. Graham, and A. Zalkin.
Optical, mechanical, and thermal properties of barium borate.
Journal of Applied Physics, 62(5):1968–1983, 1987. doi:10.
1063/1.339536.
Avshalom C. Elitzur and Lev Vaidman. Quantum mechanical interaction-free measurements. Foundations of Physics,
23(7):987–997, Jul 1993. doi:10.1007/BF00736012.
David Ellerman.
Why delayed choice experiments do
not imply retrocausality. Quantum Studies: Mathematics
and Foundations, 2(2):183–199, 2015. doi:10.1007/
s40509-014-0026-2.
Peter W Evans. Retrocausality at no extra cost. Synthese, 192(4):1139–1155, 2015.
doi:10.1007/
s11229-014-0605-0.
Jiansong Gao. The Physics of Superconducting Microwave Resonators. PhD thesis, California Institute of Technology, Califoria, U.S.A., May 2008. doi:10.7907/RAT0-VM75.
Jonte R Hance, James Ladyman, and John Rarity. How
quantum is quantum counterfactual communication? Foundations of Physics, 51(1):12, Feb 2021. doi:10.1007/
s10701-021-00412-5.
Jonte R Hance and John Rarity. Counterfactual ghost imaging.
npj Quantum Information, 7(1):1–7, 2021. doi:10.1038/
s41534-021-00411-4.
JR Hance and S Hossenfelder. The wave-function as a true
ensemble. arXiv preprint arXiv:2109.02676, 2021. URL:
https://arxiv.org/abs/2109.02676.
J.R. Hance, S. Hossenfelder, and T.N. Palmer. Supermeasured:
Violating statistical independence without violating statistical
independence. arXiv preprint arXiv:2108.07292, 2021. URL:
https://arxiv.org/abs/2108.07292.
Sabine Hossenfelder. Superdeterminism: A guide for the
perplexed. arXiv preprint arXiv:2010.01324, 2020. URL:
https://arxiv.org/abs/2010.01324.
Sabine Hossenfelder and Tim Palmer. Rethinking superdeterminism. Frontiers in Physics, 8:139, 2020. doi:10.3389/
fphy.2020.00139.
Onur Hosten, Matthew T Rakher, Julio T Barreiro, Nicholas A
Peters, and Paul G Kwiat. Counterfactual quantum computation
through quantum interrogation. Nature, 439(7079):949–952,
2006. doi:10.1038/nature04523.
Suman Karan, Shaurya Aarav, Homanga Bharadhwaj, Lavanya Taneja, Arinjoy De, Girish Kulkarni, Nilakantha Meher,
and Anand Jha. Phase matching in β-barium borate crystals
for spontaneous parametric down-conversion. arXiv preprint
arXiv:1810.01184, 2018. URL: https://arxiv.org/
abs/1810.01184.
[34] R. E. Kastner. The ‘delayed choice quantum eraser’ neither
erases nor delays. Foundations of Physics, 49(7):717–727, Jul
2019. doi:10.1007/s10701-019-00278-8.
[35] Yoon-Ho Kim, Rong Yu, Sergei P Kulik, Yanhua Shih,
and Marlan O Scully. Delayed “choice” quantum eraser.
Physical Review Letters, 84(1):1, 2000. doi:10.1103/
PhysRevLett.84.1.
[36] Paul G. Kwiat, Klaus Mattle, Harald Weinfurter, Anton
Zeilinger, Alexander V. Sergienko, and Yanhua Shih. New
high-intensity source of polarization-entangled photon pairs.
Phys. Rev. Lett., 75:4337–4341, Dec 1995. doi:10.1103/
PhysRevLett.75.4337.
[37] Xiao-Song Ma, Johannes Kofler, Angie Qarry, Nuray Tetik,
Thomas Scheidl, Rupert Ursin, Sven Ramelow, Thomas Herbst,
Lothar Ratschbacher, Alessandro Fedrizzi, Thomas Jennewein,
and Anton Zeilinger. Quantum erasure with causally disconnected choice. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences, 110(4):1221–1226, 2013. doi:10.1073/pnas.
1213201110.
[38] Tim Maudlin. Quantum non-locality and relativity: Metaphysical intimations of modern physics. John Wiley & Sons, 2011.
[39] B. A. Mazin, K. O’Brien, S. McHugh, B. Bumble, D. Moore,
S. Golwala, and J. Zmuidzinas. ARCONS: a highly multiplexed
superconducting optical to near-IR camera. In Ground-based
and Airborne Instrumentation for Astronomy III, volume 7735
of Proc. of SPIE, page 773518, July 2010. arXiv:1007.
0752, doi:10.1117/12.856440.
[40] Benjamin A. Mazin, Bruce Bumble, Seth R. Meeker, Kieran
O’Brien, Sean McHugh, and Eric Langman. A superconducting focal plane array for ultraviolet, optical, and near-infrared
astrophysics. Opt. Express, 20(2):1503–1511, Jan 2012. doi:
10.1364/OE.20.001503.
[41] Sean McHugh, Benjamin A Mazin, Bruno Serfass, Seth
Meeker, Kieran O’Brien, Ran Duan, Rick Raffanti, and Dan
Werthimer. A readout for large arrays of microwave kinetic inductance detectors. Review of Scientific Instruments,
83:044702, 2012. doi:10.1063/1.3700812.
[42] Seth Meeker et al. DARKNESS: A Microwave Kinetic Inductance Detector Integral Field Spectrograph for High-contrast
Astronomy. Publications of the Astronomical Society of the
Pacific, 130(6), June 2018. doi:10.1088/1538-3873/
aab5e7.
[43] Travis Norsen. John s. bell’s concept of local causality. American Journal of Physics, 79(12):1261–1275, 2011. doi:10.
1119/1.3630940.
[44] Judea Pearl. Causality. Cambridge university press, 2009.
[45] Matteo Perenzoni, Lucio Pancheri, and David Stoppa. Compact
spad-based pixel architectures for time-resolved image sensors.
Sensors, 16(5):745, 2016. doi:10.3390/s16050745.
[46] Huw Price. The philosophy and physics of affecting the
past. Synthese, pages 299–323, 1984. doi:10.1007/
BF00485056.
[47] Huw Price. A neglected route to realism about quantum mechanics. Mind, 103(411):303–336, 1994. doi:10.1093/
mind/103.411.303.
[48] Huw Price. Time’s arrow & Archimedes’ point: new directions
for the physics of time. Oxford University Press, 1996.
[49] Huw Price. Toy models for retrocausality. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and
Philosophy of Modern Physics, 39(4):752–761, 2008. doi:
10.1016/j.shpsb.2008.05.006.
[50] Huw Price. Does time-symmetry imply retrocausality? how
the quantum world says “maybe”? Studies in History and Phi-
8
[51]
[52]
[53]
[54]
[55]
[56]
[57]
[58]
[59]
[60]
[61]
[62]
losophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy
of Modern Physics, 43(2):75–83, 2012. doi:10.1016/j.
shpsb.2011.12.003.
Huw Price and Ken Wharton. Disentangling the quantum
world. Entropy, 17(11):7752–7767, 2015. doi:10.3390/
e17117752.
Tabish Qureshi. Demystifying the delayed-choice quantum
eraser. European Journal of Physics, 41(5):055403, 2020.
doi:10.1088/1361-6404/ab923e.
Tabish Qureshi.
The delayed-choice quantum eraser
leaves no choice.
International Journal of Theoretical Physics, 60(8):3076–3086, 2021.
doi:10.1007/
s10773-021-04906-w.
A Rochas, M Gani, B Furrer, PA Besse, RS Popovic, G Ribordy, and N Gisin. Single photon detector fabricated in a complementary metal–oxide–semiconductor high-voltage technology. Review of Scientific Instruments, 74(7):3263–3270, 2003.
doi:10.1063/1.1584083.
Hatim Salih. Protocol for counterfactually transporting an unknown qubit. Frontiers in Physics, 3:94, 2016. doi:10.
3389/fphy.2015.00094.
Hatim Salih, Jonte R. Hance, Will McCutcheon, Terry Rudolph,
and John Rarity. Deterministic teleportation and universal computation without particle exchange. arXiv preprint
arXiv:2009.05564, 2020. URL: https://arxiv.org/
abs/2009.05564.
Hatim Salih, Jonte R Hance, Will McCutcheon, Terry Rudolph,
and John Rarity. Exchange-free computation on an unknown
qubit at a distance. New Journal of Physics, 23(1):013004, jan
2021. doi:10.1088/1367-2630/abd3c4.
Hatim Salih, Zheng-Hong Li, Mohammad Al-Amri, and
Muhammad Suhail Zubairy. Protocol for direct counterfactual
quantum communication. Phys. Rev. Lett., 110:170502, Apr
2013. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.110.170502.
Hatim Salih, Will McCutcheon, Jonte Hance, and John Rarity. Do the laws of physics prohibit counterfactual communication?
arXiv preprint arXiv:1806.01257, 2018. URL:
https://arxiv.org/abs/1806.01257.
G. Scarcelli, Y. Zhou, and Y. Shih. Random delayed-choice
quantum eraser via two-photon imaging. The European Physical Journal D, 44(1):167–173, May 2007. doi:10.1140/
epjd/e2007-00164-y.
David Schmid, John H Selby, and Robert W Spekkens. Unscrambling the omelette of causation and inference: The
framework of causal-inferential theories.
arXiv preprint
arXiv:2009.03297, 2020. URL: https://arxiv.org/
abs/2009.03297.
Marlan O Scully and Kai Drühl. Quantum eraser: A proposed
photon correlation experiment concerning observation and” delayed choice” in quantum mechanics. Physical Review A,
25(4):2208, 1982. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.25.2208.
[63] Indrajit Sen. A local ψ-epistemic retrocausal hidden-variable
model of bell correlations with wavefunctions in physical space.
Foundations of Physics, 49(2):83–95, 2019. doi:10.1007/
s10701-018-0231-7.
[64] Abner Shimony. Controllable and uncontrollable non-locality,
volume 2, page 130–139. Cambridge University Press, 1993.
doi:10.1017/CBO9781139172196.010.
[65] Peter Spirtes, Clark N Glymour, Richard Scheines, and David
Heckerman. Causation, prediction, and search. MIT press,
2000.
[66] M. Strader. Digital Readout for Microwave Kinetic Inductance
Detectors and Applications in High Time Resolution Astronomy. PhD thesis, University of California Santa Barbara, Califoria, U.S.A., September 2016.
[67] Roderick I Sutherland. Bell’s theorem and backwards-intime causality. International Journal of Theoretical Physics,
22(4):377–384, 1983. doi:10.1007/BF02082904.
[68] Roderick I Sutherland. Density formalism for quantum theory. Foundations of Physics, 28(7):1157–1190, 1998. doi:
10.1023/A:1018850120826.
[69] Roderick I. Sutherland. How retrocausality helps. AIP Conference Proceedings, 1841(1):020001, 2017. doi:10.1063/
1.4982765.
[70] S. P. Walborn, M. O. Terra Cunha, S. Pádua, and C. H. Monken.
Double-slit quantum eraser. Physical Review A, 65(3), Feb
2002. doi:10.1103/physreva.65.033818.
[71] Ken Wharton. A new class of retrocausal models. Entropy,
20(6):410, 2018. doi:10.3390/e20060410.
[72] John Archibald Wheeler. The “past” and the “delayed-choice”
double-slit experiment. In Mathematical foundations of quantum theory, pages 9–48. Elsevier, 1978.
[73] Christopher J Wood and Robert W Spekkens. The lesson of
causal discovery algorithms for quantum correlations: Causal
explanations of bell-inequality violations require fine-tuning.
New Journal of Physics, 17(3):033002, 2015. doi:10.
1088/1367-2630/17/3/033002.
[74] F. Zappa, A. Tosi, A. Dalla Mora, F. Guerrieri, and S. Tisa.
Single-photon avalanche diode arrays and CMOS microelectronics for counting, timing, and imaging quantum events. In
Manijeh Razeghi, Rengarajan Sudharsanan, and Gail J. Brown,
editors, Quantum Sensing and Nanophotonic Devices VII, volume 7608, pages 717 – 731. International Society for Optics
and Photonics, SPIE, 2010. doi:10.1117/12.840362.
[75] Franco Zappa, Simone Tisa, Alberto Tosi, and Sergio Cova.
Principles and features of single-photon avalanche diode arrays. Sensors and Actuators A: Physical, 140(1):103–112,
2007. doi:10.1016/j.sna.2007.06.021.