Romans as ΒΑΡΒΑΡΟΙ: Three Polybian Speeches and the Politics of Cultural
Indeterminacy
Author(s): Craige Champion
Source: Classical Philology , Oct., 2000, Vol. 95, No. 4 (Oct., 2000), pp. 425-444
Published by: The University of Chicago Press
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/270515
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to Classical Philology
This content downloaded from
128.230.234.162 on Tue, 08 Nov 2022 00:01:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
ROMANS AS BAPBAPOI: THREE POLYBIAN SPEECHES AND
THE POLITICS OF CULTURAL INDETERMINACY
CRAIGE CHAMPION
T HE SPEECHES IN POLYBIUs' HISTORIES provide important insights into
what is perhaps the most controversial topic in Polybian studies: the
Greek historian's attitudes towards Rome. A great deal of modern
scholarly debate has revolved around mutually exclusive interpretations that
Polybius was essentially either pro-Roman or anti-Roman.' A close reading
of the Histories suggests a more nuanced approach to the question of Polybius' views on Rome. Viewing Polybius' barbarian category in relation to
his representations of the Romans provides a key to the historian's stance(s)
on Rome, and here his speeches are of the utmost importance. The objectives
of the present study are to analyze Polybius' "barbarology" vis-'a-vis Rome,
with a special focus on the medium of the reported speech, and to explore its
implications regarding the political predicament of Greek statesmen of the
second century in the face of Roman power.
In only one passage in the Histories (12.4b.2-3, discussed in Section II
below), does the Achaean historian say in his own voice that the Romans
were a barbarian people. Yet in three reported speeches, Polybius allows
his historical agents Agelaus, Lyciscus, and a Greek ambassador, probably
the Rhodian statesman Thrasycrates, to call the Romans "barbarians."2 Without discounting the historicity of these ambassadors' charges against the
Romans, I shall argue that Polybius employs these speeches as a vehicle for
indirect expression of hostility towards Rome, a hostility conforming to
widespread Greek public opinion at the time of composition of the Histories.3 I refer to this Greek view of the Romans as fdpfa3pot, according to
1. E.g., Walbank 1972, 166-83, id. 1977, esp. 155-62, and id. 1985, 280-97 (increasingly pro-Roman);
Shimron 1979/80 (essentially anti-Roman); cf. Walbank 1985, 160: "Is he in fact for or against Rome in the
final decision? The answer is not easy." Earlier versions of this paper were presented to the classics communities at Bryn Mawr College, the University of Colorado at Boulder, and the University of Chicago. I thank
those audiences, as well as Arthur Eckstein, Jonathan Hall, and the referees of the journal, for helpful criticism. I also wish to thank Jochen Twele in Princeton and Alfred Breitinger in Aschaffenburg for bibliographic assistance. Any remaining faults are, of course, my own. Unless otherwise indicated, all dates are
B.C.E. I have used Buttner-Wobst's Teubner edition (1889-1904); translated passages of Polybius are from
W. R. Paton's Loeb text ([1922-27] 1979).
2. Polyb. 5.104.1-11 (Agelaus); 9.32.3-39.7 (Lyciscus); 11.4.1-6.8 ([Thrasycrates]). MS F2 gives the
name Thrasycrates as a marginal gloss: Walbank 1967, 16; see n. 33 below.
3. Cf. Polyb. 39.3.8-9: nearly all Greeks ill-disposed to Rome in winter 192/1, on the eve of the First
Romano-Syrian War. For an overview of Greek views on Rome, see Forte 1972. On anti-Roman motivations in Greek authors, see Castiglioni 1928; Fuchs [1938] 1964; Deininger 1971, 3-5 and nn. 3-18; Gabba
1974; Taifacos 1982.
Classical Philology 95 (2000): 425-44
[(? 2000 by The University of Chicago. All rights reserved] 0009-837X/00/9504-0003$
425
This content downloaded from
128.230.234.162 on Tue, 08 Nov 2022 00:01:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
426 CRAIGE CHAMPION
which the Romans emerge as an uncivilized and savage people, as a politics
of cultural alienation; that is, we have a politically-charged Greek repre-
sentation of the Romans as an utterly strange and different cultural group.4
On the other hand, Greeks in the first half of the second century often approached the Romans with conciliatory gestures. Greeks could hail Romans
as common benefactors and as "honorary Greeks"; we might call this Greek
stance towards Rome a politics of cultural assimilation. As we shall see,
there is clear evidence for this approach in Polybius' work, yet this in no way
disproves the politics of cultural alienation for Polybian Romans as barbarians. Rather, a contextualist reading of Polybius' narrative with emphasis
on the time and circumstances of composition of the Histories, as well as on
Polybius' intended readership, makes sense of the seeming contradiction in
these two rival pictures of Romans. These incongruous representations
constitute a politics of cultural indeterminacy.
It must be said that the idea that Polybius employed speeches in order to
express criticism of Rome is not new. F A. Brandstaeter made this suggestion in his 1844 study of Aetolia; in 1857 Paul La Roche voiced the same
idea; and in 1949 Elpidio Mioni briefly argued along similar lines. All of
these scholars offered this interpretation only in passing; to the best of my
knowledge, the idea has lain dormant ever since. Walbank notes both Brand-
staeter's and La Roche's political reading of Romans as fa3ppapot in his
Commentary, but he dismisses the idea without argumentation. Reappraisal
of the question is warranted.5
Section One briefly lays out evidence for Greek politics of cultural assim-
ilation and alienation in relations with Rome before Polybius composed his
Histories. The topic, of course, is a large one; a detailed investigation would
require a separate study. It is sufficient for my purposes to establish that
Greek views on Rome were very divided in Polybius' day and that the historian was working within a Greek ideological tradition that could represent
Romans either as "honorary Greeks" or as barbarians.
Section Two analyzes a startling instance of an assimilationist representation of the Romans in the Histories (2.35), as well as Polybius' depiction
of a Roman military encounter with barbarians in which Romans exercise
Hellenic koy7tjios against barbarian Ougo'6 (2.30). The analyses of these
passages as examples of a cultural assimilation of Romans to Hellenism
serve as preliminary points of contrast to the study of the one passage in
which Polybius ranks the Romans as barbarians in his own voice and these
three ambassadorial speeches in which Romans appear as barbarians. Con-
4. Cf. Plin. HN 29.14: Cato the Censor stated that Greek physicians took oaths to kill the Roman "barbarians" (iurarunt inter se barbaros necare omnes medicina). We need not accept the historicity of the state-
ment, but it does provide evidence for Roman perceptions of Greek sentiment; see Gruen 1992, 78. For
further Roman reflection of the Greek view of the Romans as barbarians in the second century, see Plaut.
Asin. 11, Capt. 492, 884, Mil. 211, Mostell. 828, with Gruen 1984, p. 263 and n. 79.
5. Brandstaeter 1844, 250; La Roche 1857, 68; Mioni 1949, p. 115, n. 4, cf. pp. 24, 85. Walbank (1967, 176
ad 9.37.6, and 1985, 152-53), in agreement with Schmitt (1957/58, 5-11), maintains that Polybius did not
regard the Romans as barbarians; cf. Dubuisson 1985, 284-85, arguing that Polybius' long familiarity with
Romans precluded him from calling them Pdppapot.
This content downloaded from
128.230.234.162 on Tue, 08 Nov 2022 00:01:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
ROMANS AS BAPBAPOI 427
sideration of the semantic registers of Polybius' uses of the word fa3pfapos
shows its primarily negative connotations.
Section Three offers a context for the Polybian image of the Romans as
barbarians through examination of the likely time of composition of these
passages, some key political and military interactions and diplomatic ex-
changes between Rome and the Achaean Confederation during Polybius'
lifetime, and consideration of Polybius' intended audiences. This part of the
analysis furnishes suitable motivational contexts for Polybius' desire to indicate the cultural ambiguity of the Romans.
I. GREEK CULTURAL POLITICS OF ASSIMILATION
AND ALIENATION AND ROME
As early as the mid-fourth century, Plato's pupil Heraclides of Pontica refer-
red to Rome as a Greek city.6 Timaeus, writing c. 280, incorporated Rome
into the Hellenic-Homeric tradition when he maintained that the Romans
were descendants of the Trojans (Polyb. 12.4b, discussed below in Section
II). In the 230s Rome intervened with the Aetolian Confederation on behalf
of the Acarnanians. This diplomatic interchange is of interest for the politics
of cultural assimilation because Strabo reports that the Acarnanians claimed
that they had not participated in the Trojan expedition in order to win Roman
support. In so doing the Acarnanians, like Timaeus, incorporated the Romans
into the venerable Homeric tradition, and we may add that, like Heraclides,
they acknowledged the civilized nature of the Romans, as the Trojans after
all were refugees from a city.7 Even the Macedonian king Philip V, who in
215/14 was at war with Rome, advised the Thessalian city of Larissa to follow the liberal policy of the Romans concerning the enfranchisement of citizens: further evidence for a Greek view of Rome as an orderly and rational
community.8 Clearly, then, Greeks were willing to think of Romans as part
of the civilized world insofar as they lived in an impressively organized city.
But Greek attitudes towards Rome in the late third and second centuries were
for the most part instrumental: when Romans acted in Greek interests, as in
the case of the Acarnanians, Greeks engaged what I have called a politics of
cultural assimilation, treating Romans as "honorary Greeks"; when they
acted in brutal fashion in Greek lands, the Romans became 3a'ppapot throu
a Greek politics of cultural alienation.
Polybius' account of the First Illyrian War illustrates the first approach.
Illyrian piracy in the Adriatic reached alarming proportions by c. 230. The
Ardean queen-regent Teuta was unable to provide the Romans with assurances that she could control the marauding activities of the independent
Illyrian tribesmen.9 In 229/8, Rome's first military action across the Adriati
6. Plut. Cam. 22.2: nr6ktv 'EXilvi&a TP6sijv, with Gruen 1992, 10.
7. Just. Epit. 28.1.5-2.14; Strabo 10.2.25 (C 462); cf. Polyb. 22.5.3 (Ilium and Rome in the aftermath of
the Roman victory over Antiochus III); and the catalogue of early Greek-Roman interactions at Eisen 1966,
9-1 1; Golan 1971 on Greek perceptions of Rome before 229. On kinship diplomacy, see now Jones 1999.
8. Syll.3 543 (4).26-39; cf. Eratosth. ap. Strabo 1.4.9 (C 66): Romans and Carthaginians might be considered civilized because of their political institutions and urban lifestyles.
9. Polyb. 2.8.8-9; Dell 1967, 97-98, 101; cf. Champion 1997, 119-20.
This content downloaded from
128.230.234.162 on Tue, 08 Nov 2022 00:01:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
428 CRAIGE CHAMPION
came in response to Teuta's rebuff of a Roman commission. Illyrian resistance quickly crumbled under Rome's superior forces, and Teuta accepted
terms in the spring of 228.10 Polybius states that the Roman commander
L. Postumius Albinus sent legates to Achaea and Aetolia explaining the reasons for Roman involvement across the Adriatic and relaying the terms of the
treaty. The Senate dispatched other envoys to Athens and to Corinth, where
the Corinthians admitted the Romans as "honorary Greeks" to the Isthmian
Games." Polybius remarks that in defeating the Illyrians, the Romans had
delivered the Greeks from fears of the common enemy of humankind.'2
Increasing Greek familiarity with Roman war making from the time of the
First Macedonian War and the later phases of the Hannibalic War, both in
Greece and in Sicily, led to a different Greek view of Rome. Reports of
Roman behavior from the western Greeks in the last decade of the third
century perhaps constituted much of what mainland Greeks knew of Rome;
those reports would have been alarming (cf. Livy 31.29.4-16). Rome's harsh
actions at Syracuse and Tarentum, especially the massacres and destructive
looting, alienated Greek opinion-and made Greeks think of typically bar-
barian behavior.'3
Many Greeks will have had their first direct experience of the Romans in
the First Macedonian War as a result of the Romano-Aetolian alliance of
212/1 1. Those perceptions will not have been favorable to Rome, and, as
we shall see, Polybius provides evidence that many Greeks condemned the
Aetolians for forming an alliance with the Roman barbarian. Macedonia's
second war with Rome confirmed the brutality of Roman war making. Besides the usual sacked Greek cities, we have the story that Philip V was
shocked at the brutality of Roman battle techniques. Yet he was equally as-
tonished at the ordered arrangement of the Roman military camp; it sur-
passed belief that this could be the camp of barbarians."4 Thus the Romans
were in Greek eyes impressive, even by Hellenic standards, in their orga10. Polyb. 2.11.1-12.4; App. lll. 7-8; Gruen 1984, 359-73 for an account of the events, and references
to earlier works on the aftermath at p. 57, n. 17.
1 1. Polyb. 2.12.4-8 and MRR 1.228 on Postumius. For the Romans as "honorary Greeks" at the Isthmia,
see Holleaux 1921, 129, Gelzer 1933, 132, Deininger 1971, p. 25, n. 12. Habicht 1997, 184-85, briefly
considers Roman motivations.
12. Polyb. 2.12.6, cf. 21.41.1-3: Greek embassies bearing crowns to the consul Cn. Manlius Vulso at
Ephesus in 189 for having delivered them from the lawless violence (i5ptq, Trapavo%ia) of the Galatian trib
For Greek appeals to Romans as common benefactors, see, e.g., Syll.3 630.17-18 (Amphictyonic decree of
182); IG 22.1134.69 and 103; FD III, 2.70.46; Volkmann 1954, p. 467 and nn. 1-6, p. 468 and nn. 1-3;
Erskine 1994 and 1997; Ferrary 1988, 124-32, and 1997; Habicht 1997, p. 279 and n. 48. For monuments in
Greece of L. Mummius, destroyer of Corinth, see Paus. 5.10.5 and 24.4; IVO 278-81, 319-24. Some of the
epigraphical evidence probably represents replacements of the Augustan age or later, according to Dittenberger and Purgold (IVO, 406, 446).
13. For harsh Roman war making in general, see Eckstein 1976, 131-42. For a detailed analysis of
Marcellus' campaign in Sicily, Eckstein 1987a, 157-69, 345-49. For Marcellus' Syracusan spoils, Livy
25.40.1-3; Petrochilos 1974, 70; Eckstein 1987a, p. 163 and nn. 28-29; Ferrary 1988, 573-78; Gruen 1992,
94-103. For Tarentum, Livy 27.16.1-9 with Toynbee 1965, 2:28: "a horrifying picture of the customary
behaviour of Roman troops when they took a city by storm"; cf. Nottmeyer 1995, 157-58.
14. Livy 31.34.8; Nissen 1863, 128, for the Polybian derivation. On Roman methodical brutality in
warfare, cf. the sack of Carthago Nova in 209 at Polyb. 10.15.4-5; Diod. 32.2.1, 4.5. Harris (1979, p. 52 and
nn. 1-5, p. 53 and n. 1, and pp. 263-64) sees the Roman brutality well enough, but misses Polybius' point
that the Romans are brutal in warfare, but also highly organized, in contradistinction to Greek practice. On
this point, see now Eckstein 1997.
This content downloaded from
128.230.234.162 on Tue, 08 Nov 2022 00:01:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
ROMANS AS BAPBAPOI 429
nizational capacities; yet they also were barbarous in the brutality of their
conduct of war. Direct Greek experience with Rome in this period therefore
informed the two Greek responses to Rome canvassed in this section, the
cultural politics of assimilation and of alienation.
II. AUTHORIAL STRATEGIES AND THE ROMANS AS BAPBAPOI
IN POLYBIAN SPEECHES
There is clear evidence in Polybius' text for both of the Greek politicocultural approaches to the Romans outlined above. Polybius' narrative assimilates Greeks and Romans by emphasizing the importance of political and
social institutions as prime determinants in the formation of collective characteristics. Since institutions are subject to historical change, it therefore follows from Polybius' political theory that a given people's group character
may evolve for either good or ill over time. Polybius' biological model for
the rise and fall of states and his aVaKUiKkXO)rt; theory in Book 6 presuppose
natural laws of social psychology arising from a universal human nature.
Furthermore, Polybius begins his analysis of the Roman politeia with an
account of simple constitutional development based on Greek political
theory. In short, Rome appears as some sort of extraordinary Greek po
Indeed, even at the level of lexical analysis, Polybius practices an assimilation of Romans to Hellenism, as the historian, who knew some Latin and
whose long sojourn in Rome left imprints of Latin interference in his phraseology, routinely prefers to give Greek equivalences of Roman institutions
and social practices, rather than transliterations of Roman terms.16 Polybius
use of the phrase KaO' ipd OakacTTca (3.37.6, 4.42.3-4, 16.29.6) is suggestive in this context; the inclusionary "we" may refer to both the historian's
Greek and Roman readerships.17 Another sort of assimilationalist narrative
strategy lies in the insertion of a brief history of the Achaean Confederation,
the so-called Achaean RTPOKaTCaLKCUT, in the otherwise Roman Book 2.18 It
is in the transition from Roman to Greek affairs in this book that we find a
highly significant example of Polybian assimilation of Romans to Hellenism.
Polybius' Achaean iRpoKatct)CaKi forms part of an historical account of
the Achaean Confederation running parallel to his historical narrative of
Rome in Books 1-5; in these books, we see both the Achaean and Roman
polities in their optimal state.19 Polybius concludes his account of the
Romano-Gallic wars of the third century, culminating in the overwhelming
Roman victory at Telamon in 225, with some generalized reflections on the
triumph of Hellenic rationality or koyiPos over barbarian mindlessness
15. Walbank 1972, 130-56; Eckstein 1997; Hahm 1995, with comprehensive bibliography on Book 6.
16. Dubuisson 1985, 113-14, and esp. 149-50, 216-17, and 258-70 for Polybius' familiarity with
Latin. A large number of Polybius' latinisms occur in technical descriptions of Roman military matters.
17. I see no basis in Polybius' text for the claim of Dubuisson 1985, 214: "Quant 'a i] KaO' iliq Ocukarta,
ce n'est pas sa forme, mais son contenu qui est anormal: en derniere analyse, ~i&liq n'y d6signe plus les
Grecs, mais bien les Romains."
18. Polyb. 2.37-71, with Gelzer 1940a and 1940b. Petzold (1969, 25-128) emphasizes differences
between Rome and Achaea in Polybius' thought: Rome's rise was based on military power; Achaea's on
ethical principles. The emphasis here is on similarities; i.e., Roman "Hellenic" qualities; cf. n. 45 below.
19. Champion 1993, 20-123, esp. 11 1-22.
This content downloaded from
128.230.234.162 on Tue, 08 Nov 2022 00:01:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
430 CRAIGE CHAMPION
recklessness, and ill-planned campaig
2.35.3-6). This passage serves as a transition to the account of Achaea's
rise. Here the Roman victories over the Gauls stand alongside famous feats
in the Greeks' history, the victory in the Persian Wars of the fifth century
and the defense of the Delphic sanctuary against a Gallic incursion in 279,
and they serve as paradigmatic examples of Hellenic rationality triumphing
over barbarian irrationality against overwhelming odds. The Romans in this
chapter are "honorary Greeks"; it is a remarkable historiographical piece
of evidence for a Greek politics of cultural assimilation.20
If rationality or X07to*5 is the key characteristic of Hellenic virtue in
Polybius, then we can see that the barbarian, by way of contrast, frequently
points out the Hellenism of the Romans in Polybius' work. The account of
the decisive battle between Romans and Gauls at Telamon in 225 precedes
the reflective passage at 2.35; it presents the differences between the op-
posing forces of Romano-Hellenic order and rationality and barbarian chaos
and irrationality in action. In recounting the movements before the battle,
Polybius reveals that the Gauls were not bereft of tactical strategy, and he
admits that their formation was well adapted to their predicament, trapped
between two consular armies (2.28.6-7, cf. 29.5: Celtic KoYo5). Yet once
the battle begins, the barbarian stereotype comes into full play. According to
Polybius, the Romans possessed a decided advantage from the start in the
superiority of their military equipment (2.30.7-8). The battle opened with
the Roman iaculatores or javelineers hurling their spears in compact, effec-
tive volleys against the ineffectual shields and naked bodies of the front
ranks of the Gauls. The barbarians were soon in a state of confusion and
perplexity; some rushed upon the Roman troops in an impotent, irrational,
self-destructive rage ('ir6 Tcoi OUjioi Kaci Ti5 adXoyi ia, 30.4). As a counterweight to the Gallic rage and desperate fury, we learn that the Roman consul
and army exhibited self-possession in sending the spoils back to Rome and
returning the booty of the barbarian to its rightful owners (31.1-4).21
In such Polybian passages, then, the Romans emerge as practitioners of
Hellenic X07toY906; according to a politics of cultural assimilation, we may
say that they act as "honorary Greeks." The images of Romans in the ambassadorial speeches of Agelaus, Lyciscus, and [Thrasycrates] are a polar
opposite to Polybius' assimilationist representation of Romans at 2.35 and in
the account of the Gallic tumultus. There can be no doubt as to the pejorative
force of the references to Romans as barbarians in these speeches. In ancient
Greek thought, of course, the Hellenic-barbarian dichotomy was a bipolar
politico-cultural construct that served to foist undesirable characteristics,
such as sloth, irresolution, greed, irrationality, and uncontrolled violence,
20. Champion 1996, 324-28.
21. Walbank 1957, 204-7. For Romano-Gallic interaction in this period, Eckstein 1987a, 3-23, and id.
1995, 122-24, on Polybius' depiction of barbarous Celtic practices and irrationality. Other dramatic Polybian
examples of Roman koytcy.i6q vs. barbarian Out6q include 1 1.31.1-33.6, where Scipio outmaneuvers the barbarous, brave, but disorganized Ilergetes, and 33.10, where Opimius' highly organized and disciplined army
defeats the wild and uncoordinated Ligurian Oxybii and Deciates, who had begun this war with outrages
against Roman envoys and violation of the ius gentium. Clearly this theme was attractive to Polybius.
This content downloaded from
128.230.234.162 on Tue, 08 Nov 2022 00:01:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
ROMANS AS BAPBAPOI 431
upon the non-Greek Other. The term dpfp3apos was essentially a negative
term that could only take on meaning when opposed to Hellenism; it conventionally became a sort of short-hand way of pointing out the absence of
temperance, moderation, balance, and reason, the hallmarks of the Hellenic,
civilized society.22
Polybius follows this conventional practice in his uses of the word f3apfapos and its cognates. In his thought, barbarians, along with mercenaries,
the masses, youth, and women, pose a threat to the social order. Eckstein has
suggested that in Polybius these threats form several concentric circles from
beyond the borders of the civilized Mediterranean world to within the Greek
aristocratic household itself. The outermost circle consists in the barbarian;
the innermost is comprised of the women of the most secluded section of the
Greek household, the "women's quarters," or yuVcatKcia. Lack of self-control,
impulsive, violent behavior, and unbridled passion run throughout these
circles. All of these menacing groups lack the fully developed rational faculty, and these categories, as in the case of the Illyrian queen-regent Teuta,
sometimes overlap in the Histories, overdetermining the irrational threat to
the orderly society. The individual leadership skills of the adult male aristocracy, in Polybius' view, are the only bulwark against these irrational forces.
For Polybius, reasoning power or koyi(ygo6 was the weapon to combat them,
and the historian worried that not enough males of the ruling elite actually
possessed the required characteristics.23 In Polybius' work, contemporary
Greeks frequently exhibit negative traits the historian usually attributes to
barbarians; indeed, in one passage Polybius states that it would be difficult to
find such mindlessness and general lack of judgment among barbarians as
the Achaeans exhibited at the time of the so-called Achaean War.24 Such
allegations against Greeks are consistent with Polybius' political theory,
which, as noted above, sees collective social characteristics as being historically contingent upon the health of institutional structures and customary
practices.
In this context it would be very significant if Polybius never used the term
fa3pfapot of the Romans. It is equally significant that scholars have mistakenly maintained that he did not. In an important passage from the methodological Book 12, which has not received the careful attention it deserves,
Polybius calls the Romans fa3ppapot in his own voice. Here, he is discussing
the errors of the Sicilian Greek historian, Timaeus. Polybius has been chas-
tising Timaeus for his petty and unjust charges against Theopompus and
Ephorus, and he proceeds to list a series of Timaeus' own blunders. First
among these is Timaeus' discussion of the "October Horse" ceremony at
Rome. In his account of King Pyrrhus, Timaeus stated that the Romans
22. For the typology, see Hall 1989, Cartledge 1993, passim; for exhaustive treatment of the barbaria
category in Roman thought, see Dauge 1981.
23. Eckstein 1995, 118-60, esp. 119-25 on barbarians, and 158-60, 285-89 for Polybius' concerns
about the impact of moral failings on the Greek elite. For the Roman imposition of order in the outermost
of the concentric circles, the oiKouitvvj, see Polyb. 3.3.5.
24. 38.18.7-8. For a catalogue of Polybius' negative assessments of Hellenistic Greek states in the
military sphere, see Eckstein 1997, 176-78.
This content downloaded from
128.230.234.162 on Tue, 08 Nov 2022 00:01:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
432 CRAIGE CHAMPION
sacrificed a horse in the Campus Martius on an appointed day each year in
order to commemorate their disaster at Troy, because the famous wooden
horse had led to the sack of Rome's ancestral city. Polybius calls this a most
childish statement (irp&yj7a irav-cwv Rcat6aptuo6EnTaTov). In making his poin
against Timaeus, Polybius argues that the Roman practice is a common
custom among almost all the barbarians (nrdvTcat T0ou appous).25 He says
that, if we were to follow Timaeus, then all barbarians must be descendants
of the Trojans, since practically all of them sacrifice a horse on the eve of
battle, divining the future from the way the animal falls. In 1 2.4c. 1, Polybius
charges Timaeus with both lack of experience (dRciptav) and superficial
learning (6VtiaOactv) in connecting the sacrifice of a horse at Rome to the
Roman myth of Trojan origins. Within the framework of our discussion, we
may note that in asserting the Roman connection to Troy Timaeus was dealing with a Greek politics of cultural assimilation of the Romans to Helle-
nism-a politics that Polybius here explicitly denies. In this instance,
Polybius takes exception to both Timaeus' linking of Rome to the Homeric
tradition and his implication that the original Romans were refugees from
the civilized city of Troy. Greater learning and diligence, Polybius maintains,
would have led Timaeus to realize that the answer was much simpler: horse
sacrifice is nearly universal among fa3ppapot. Romans, as barbarians, act
according to a widespread barbarian custom. If Timaeus had realized this, he
would not have relayed the silly story of the Trojan horse in this context.26
In the historical narrative proper, there is some other indirect evidence for
Romans as barbarians in Polybius' eyes. At 1.11.7 Polybius states that King
Hieron II of Syracuse saw an opportunity of expelling the "barbarians"
occupying Messana. The statement is vague, but it is just possible that both
Romans and Mamertines represent the Ja'pjapot. In any case, the Mamertines are certainly barbarians here, and in 1.10.2 Polybius says that the
Mamertines were kinsmen of the Romans, 0'po(pukot.27 In the account of the
First Romano-Carthaginian War, Polybius remarks that the Romans use
force (f3fa) in all endeavors. When they obstinately attempt to apply Iica
against the forces of nature, they act in opposition to kXyos, which is of
course a characteristic fault of barbarians.28 The same suggestion arises in
Cicero's statement that Polybius criticized the Romans for their neglect of
formal ncat&6ia, a quintessential mark of Hellenic culture.29
25. Walbank (1967, 328 ad loc. ["not including the Romans, whom P. never calls barbarians except in
reported speeches"]) misses Polybius' obvious point. For Polybius' sustained polemic against Timaeus, see
Meister 1975, 3-55, Sacks 1981, 21-95.
26. This is the only possible interpretation of this passage according to which Polybius offers his own
account for the Roman "October Horse" ceremony. Any reading denying that Polybius is here calling the
Romans barbarians must assume that in his impassioned attack on Timaeus, Polybius, for whom aitiat are so
crucial (locus classicus 3.6.1-7.7, with Pedech 1964, 54-98, Walbank 1972, 157-60, Mohm 1977, 151-57),
forgot to provide his own causal explanation for horse sacrifice at Rome.
27. Contra Lazenby (1996, 47), who believes that 1.1 1.7 refers only to the Mamertines; for our purposes,
the point remains the same; i.e., the Romans are 6O6(p6kot of barbarians.
28. 1.37.7; cf. Wiedemann 1990, 298, on Polybius' representation of Hannibal: "Polybius seems to be
indicating that he is uncertain whether Hannibal is civilised or barbarous; it is unclear whether he tries to
control his audience through logos or through bia." For a less pejorative interpretation of 1.37.7, see Eckstein
1997, 178-79.
29. Cic. Rep. 4.3.3 with MacMullen 1991, p. 434 and n. 53.
This content downloaded from
128.230.234.162 on Tue, 08 Nov 2022 00:01:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
ROMANS AS BAPBAPOI 433
These passages (which scholars have not collected together before) suggest a Polybian image of Romans as barbarians, but even cumulatively they
do not constitute in themselves compelling evidence for a Polybian politics
of cultural alienation from Rome. I argue, however, that the historian
further engages in this cultural politics, if only indirectly, through the
medium of the reported speech. It is in the context of this Greek politicocultural stance vis-'a-vis Rome that we must view the Polybian speeches of
Agelaus, Lyciscus, and [Thrasycrates].
At the end of Book 5, Polybius highlights the speech of the Aetolian
ambassador Agelaus at the peace conference at Naupactus in 217, the dra-
matic setting for the introduction of the historian's (7l4P1tkOK1, the histor
moment at which the events of the Mediterranean world became an inter-
connected whole.30 At this crucial historical juncture in the Histories the
Romans appear as barbarians (5.104.1-2):
'O E&f 6&AV paXltyTa pjV pf&TOTe ToXepelV TOUR -EXXkvaq dkkXkotq, dkk& P&
XdptV EX&tV TOi 06Ooi, 6i k'YOVTFq &V Ka TauT6 oaaVTEi Kal (YUPnTXKOVT'r Ta&
KaOadT&p oi TOUq COtTaPOUq 6taaivovTre, 6UvatvTo Ta& TOV apf36pwv Ep66ouq do
pevot cYucYcYq@etV cY(paq autou6 Kat taq T6kelq.
It would be best of all if the Greeks never made war on each other, but regarded it as the
highest favor in the gift of the gods could they always speak with one heart and voice,
and marching arm in arm like men fording a river, repel barbarian invaders and unite in
preserving themselves and their cities.
Agelaus goes on to state that the ultimate victor in the war raging between
Rome and Carthage would be sure to invade Greece, transgressing the
bounds of justice (5.104.3-4). The Aetolian ambassador ends his speech
with what is perhaps the most memorable passage in the Histories, referring
to the western powers as "clouds that loom in the west to settle on Greece"
(104.10). In Agelaus' representation, the Romans are therefore a barbarian
people who do not know justice, threatening Greece as some ominous cloud
from the west.31
In late spring 210 Philip V and the Aetolians again were at war. Macedonian and Aetolian representatives went to neutral Greek states in order to
strike up alliances. Aetolia had already formed an alliance with Rome.32 In
Book 9, Polybius records a pair of speeches; one from the Macedonian side,
the other from the Aetolian camp, delivered at Sparta. Lyciscus, an Acarnanian ambassador, appeals to the Spartans on Macedonia's behalf. The
bulk of his speech emphasizes the great services the Macedonians had
performed for the rest of the Greek world in fighting off the barbarians to
30. On the GUpVXOK1, see Mohm 1977, 68-76, Walbank 1985, 313-24, and Champion 1997, 112-17.
31. See Deininger 1971, 25-29. The speech reveals much of Polybius' historiographical practice in
recording speeches. For summary and extension of recent debates, see Champion 1997; on Polybian speeches
generally, Sacks 1981, 79-95; Walbank 1985, 242-61.
32. Livy 26.24.8-16, cf. Polyb. 18.38.7-9 (Flamininus); Deininger 1971, 29-31. For exhaustive
discussion of the Laevinus treaty and the inscription from Thyrrhion (SEG 13, 382 = IG 9 12, 1, 241 = SVA
3, 536), see Lehmann 1967, 51-134; cf. Dahlheim 1968, 181-207, Gruen 1984, p. 18, n. 20.
This content downloaded from
128.230.234.162 on Tue, 08 Nov 2022 00:01:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
434 CRAIGE CHAMPION
the north. In reference to the Romano-Aetolian alliance, he chastises the
Aetolians (9.37.5-6): tit 6? vUV KOtvoVCi?tC t&iv EXki6Civ, i1 npO6 Troiav
KcaLXLTC to6`ouo cyumj4naxtav; ap' ou npo6 -iqv tcov ,3app,3pov; ("[W]h
common cause with you at present or what kind of an alliance do you invite
them to enter? Is it not an alliance with barbarians?") The Acarnanian
stresses the danger posed by Rome, warning that Greece is now threatened
by a foreign race whose intention is to enslave the Hellenes. Lyciscus re-
peats Agelaus' famous metaphor of Rome as an ominous cloud from the
west (37.10), and he chides the Spartans for entertaining the idea of an alliance with barbarians against Greece (38.5). Near his speech's end, Lyciscus calls to mind the image of the women of Anticyra being carried off
by the Romans to suffer what must be suffered by those who fall into the
power of aliens (39.3). As Agelaus had done indirectly in his speech at
Naupactus, Lyciscus in Polybius' text thus represents the Romans as an
unjust, barbarous, and violent people bent on enslaving Greeks.
In 207 a Greek embassy, with participants from Egypt, Chios, Mytilene,
and King Amynander of Athamania, addressed the Aetolian Confederation.
Its task was to convince the Aetolians to come to terms with Macedonia and
end the war still raging throughout Greece. A statesman named Thrasycrates
appears to have been a Rhodian representative at the conference. Polybius
probably reproduces Thrasycrates' speech in Book 11; the identification is
not absolutely certain.33 This speaker echoes Lyciscus' criticism at Sparta of
the Romano-Aetolian alliance:
TtXckzpelTe 6' cI' Ciav6paTotYjpCp Kat KaTa(pOop& uiq 'EXa66oq. TauTa yap ai GUVOiKaL
Xk7Youctv 6jptv ai np6q 'Popaiouq . . . Kat KuptCUcYavT&q PEV auTot T6k6XCq OUT av
U3pl4ctv U1ojtcivatTc TOUR cXEUOcpOUi OUT cJITttTpaVcttTai OIi6Xt, vopiiovmTji pv&E vat
TO TOIOUTO Kat fapfaptK6v- GUVOnKai 6c irirircOc TotaUTai, 6t' XV aTtavTaq TOUR aXXoug
-EXX,vaq CK66ToUo 6C6&KaC TOS f3apfapotc ziq Taq aicxicYTa Ufpetq Kai Tapavopiaq.
[Y]ou are fighting for the enslavement and ruin of Greece. This is the story your treaty
with the Romans tells.... Did you capture a city yourselves you would not allow your-
selves to outrage freemen or to burn their towns, which you regard as a cruel proceeding
and barbarous; but you have made a treaty by which you have given up to the barbarians
the rest of the Greeks to be exposed to atrocious outrage and violence.34
The envoy goes on to warn that the Romans will throw themselves into
Greece with main force with the intention of conquering the entire land
(11.6.1-2). The pattern is clear: in three Greek ambassadorial speeches spanning a decade, Polybius represents Romans as uncouth and unprincipled bar33. Walbank 1967, 274-75 ad 11.4.1-6.10; cf. P6dech 1964, 268, Deininger 1971, 32-34.
34. Polyb. 1 1.5.1-2, 6-8; cf. 24.13.4-5, where Philopoemen refers to the Capuans and Sicilian Greeks as
slaves of Rome. For echoes of the three ambassadors' allegations about Roman intentions, see 10.25.1-5,
where the Romans are foreigners taking advantage of Greeks, with Holleaux 1921, p. 35, n. 4, p. 238, n. 2;
this fragment of a speech probably comes from the debate at Aegeon in 209 mentioned at Livy 27.30.9-10:
Walbank 1967, 15, 229. Livy (P) 39.37.9-10 (184): Lycortas, Polybius' father, refers to the Achaean relation
to Rome as in danger of becoming that of slave to master; Nissen 1863, 224, on the Polybian derivation; Livy
(P) 31.29.8-9 (199): a Macedonian orator contrasts the freedom of Aetolian assemblies with Sicilian meetings held in the presence of a Roman praetor.
This content downloaded from
128.230.234.162 on Tue, 08 Nov 2022 00:01:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
ROMANS AS BAPBAPOI 435
barians who will destroy Greek liberty. In Agelaus' prooemium, the general
reference to the perils of barbarian invasions introduces the idea of the im-
minent danger of invasion of Greece by the victor in the Second Romano-
Carthaginian War; and both Lyciscus' and [Thrasycrates'] speeches explicitly
refer to Romans as ,a3p,Bapot. In addition to these formal and highly dramatic
speeches, we also have the brief report in direct speech of Macedonian reconnaissance scouts in 197 at the decisive moment in the battle at Cynoscephalae in which, according to Polybius, Philip's scouts repeatedly referred
to the movements of the Roman ,a3p,Bapot.35 Scholars previously have ignored this passage in discussions of Polybius' views on Rome.
In a passage derived from Polybius, Livy preserves yet another example of
Romans as barbarians in Polybian speeches.36 In spring 199 a Macedonian
ambassador spoke at the Panaetolica, urging the Aetolians to remain at peace
with Philip V during his impending struggle against Rome. The ambassador
states that the mainland Greeks could expect the same brutally imperious
treatment from Romans as the Greeks of Italy and Sicily had experienced.
The Romans are an alien race, the speaker alleges, sharply separated from
Greeks by language, customs, and laws.37 He goes on to warn of the dangers
of reintroducing foreign troops (legiones externas) into Greece, and he concludes with a categorical statement on the perennial and natural enmity
existing between Greeks and barbarians: "cum alienigenis, cum barbaris
aeternum omnibus Graecis bellum est eritque; natura enim, quae perpetua
est, non mutabilibus in diem causis hostes sunt" (Livy 31.29.15-16). ProRoman Athenian envoys give a stinging riposte to the Macedonian am-
bassador's charge of the Romans as ,a3p,3apot, turning the tables in calling
the impious Philip V the real barbarian (Livy 31.30.4). These speeches
underscore the intensity of the divided nature of Greek opinions on Rome in
the early second century. In another Livian speech derived from Polybius, in
195 the Aetolian ambassador Alexander rebuked the Athenians, glorious
freedom fighters against the barbarian in their past, who were now Roman
lackeys, all too willing to support a foreign ruler.38 It is safe to assume that
Livy here reproduces an image of the Romans he found in Polybian
speeches; he is unlikely to have invented the anti-Roman sentiments himself.
From this time, the beginning of the second century, the sources are silent on
formal Greek diplomatic references to the Romans as barbarians, but, as I
suggest in my final section, there is no reason to believe that that perception
had faded among Greek politicians in the decades that intervened between
these anti-Roman Greek orations and Polybius' recording of them.39 Polybius' authorial decision to record anti-Roman sentiments in such detail is
significant.
35. Polyb. 18.22.8; cf. Plut. Flam. 5.5 (Macedonian reports of the Roman aipjapot).
36. Livy 31.29.4-16; Nissen 1863, 126-27, on the Polybian derivation; Walbank 1940, 138-85, Gruen
1984, 382-98, and Errington 1989, 261-74, on the events of the Second Macedonian War.
37. Livy 31.29.12: alienigenae homines, plus lingua et moribus et legibus quam maris terrarumque spatio
discreti.
38. Livy 34.23.5-11, with Habicht 1997, 206-7.
39. Deininger 1971, 34-37, on the disappearance during the Second Macedonian War in official Gree
political propaganda of Panhellenic appeals to a common defense against the Romans as adpjapot.
This content downloaded from
128.230.234.162 on Tue, 08 Nov 2022 00:01:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
436 CRAIGE CHAMPION
As we have seen, except for one passage, which scholars have previously
misinterpreted, Polybius makes the charge that Romans were barbarians in-
directly, usually through the medium of the reported speech of historical
characters. There is no reason to discount the historicity of the Greek antipathy against Romans in these speeches. Polybius has deservedly enjoyed a
reputation through the centuries as a painstaking and scrupulous researcher
for whom truth (adiijOFta) is the paramount concern.40 In these speeches Polybius most certainly is relaying orally transmitted reports of actual Greek
charges against Romans, and therefore we should view them as historical evidence for a Greek politics of cultural alienation from Rome. Yet, since they
derived from a predominantly oral culture, such speeches necessarily required the historian to reconstitute them through his own memory, reports
from eyewitnesses, or even his own knowledge of the political context of the
speech, as written transcripts of speeches were rare. Verbatim reproduction
of historical agents' speeches most frequently would be an impossibility, and
the historian perforce exercised a certain amount of invention in reproducing
speeches. This situation would have been especially true in the case of battle
exhortations of field commanders to their troops.41 Polybius himself provides an illustration of this point. He states that Achaean soldiers could not
hear what Philopoemen had to say before the battle against Machanidas at
Mantinea, yet the historian gives the "gist," just the same.42 Another illustration, more significant for our discussion, is 18.22.8, where we have the
Macedonian reports in direct speech on the Roman barbarians' position in
the midst of the battle at Cynoscephalae.
Polybius' historiographical practice in recording speeches, then, of neces-
sity leads the historian not only to select exclusively what he believes to be
the most historically significant portions of a given speech, but also to shape
the material of an historical agent's speech according to his own understanding of the events.43 These references to Romans as ,a3p,3apot were most
likely integral, passionately felt parts of these Greek orations. Yet, as Walbank has also suggested, anything that we find in Polybian speeches is the
result of the author's "subjective operations."44 And the inclusion of references to Romans as barbarians seems to run counter to some modern scholars' position that Polybius minimizes the differences between Greeks and
Romans; we may view these passages as prime evidence for the historian's
honesty and integrity.45 In the case of the passages under consideration, we
may point to the famous cloud metaphor, which Polybius attributes to Age40. On Polybius' rigorous historiographical principles and posthumous reputation, see assembled references at Champion 1996, pp. 315-16, nn. 2-4; on his use of oral testimony, see P6dech 1964, 356-77.
41. See Hansen 1993, Ehrhardt 1995.
42. Polyb. 1.12.1-3; it is indeed difficult to reconcile the evidence of this passage with Polybius' criticism of Timaeus' practice with historical agents' speeches at 12.25a.3-5.
43. See now Champion 1997, 112-17.
44. Walbank 1985, 249.
45. See now Eckstein 1997 for Polybius' stress on differences in institutions, rather than innate differences, between Greeks and Romans. I do not wish to contest this assimilationist aspect of Polybius' representation of Romans; indeed, we have already seen a remarkable example of it (Polyb. 2.35). Rather, I want to
argue for complexity, ambiguity, and tension within Polybius' image of Romans. For scholarly opinion that
Polybius emphasizes the differences between Greeks and Romans, see assembled references at Eckstein 1997,
p. 175, n. 1; cf. p. 176, n. 4.
This content downloaded from
128.230.234.162 on Tue, 08 Nov 2022 00:01:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
ROMANS AS BAPBAPOI 437
laus and then has Lyciscus repeat, as a demonstration of the historian's shaping of the material in his speeches.46 We also may note that close to half a
century had elapsed between the delivery of these speeches and Polybius' recording of them, for Polybius began composing his work sometime after his
extradition to Italy in the aftermath of the battle at Pydna in summer 168.47
Polybius, then, has faithfully reported historical speeches with the degree
of accuracy that his historiographical conventions allowed, but the conditions in which he worked entailed a good deal of what we should call authorial license. If Polybius' reports of the anti-Roman sentiments in recorded
speeches show him to be a good historian, relaying what actually happened
as he received it from his informants, his inclusion and shaping of this
material also constituted an historiographical and a political choice. Polybius did not have to relate these speeches in extenso. In doing so he provided
a platform for detailed Greek attacks against the Romans. In the following
section I examine the historical background to the political dimension of
these Polybian speeches, the detailed reporting of Greek charges of Roman
barbarism, as a Polybian engagement of the politics of cultural alienation.
III. ROMANS AS BARBARIANS AND ACHAEAN POLITICS
A contextualist reading of these anti-Roman speeches in Polybius accommodates the two diametrically opposed representations according to which
Romans emerge both as "honorary Greeks" and as ,a3p,Bapot. I shall first
discuss the time of composition as it bears on this inquiry. Attempts to date
particular parts of the Histories are fraught with difficulties.48 The problem
of later insertions, for example, runs throughout the work.49 Yet such inser-
tions predominantly concern Polybius' personal experiences,50 whereas the
orations under consideration took place before Polybius' birth. It is highly
likely, on this evidence, that these speeches are integral parts of the original
text of the books in which they occur. Now, Polybius makes several references to Carthage as still being in existence down to Book 15; the Romans
destroyed Carthage, of course, in 146.51 During his travels circa 151-46
Polybius most likely did not have time for extensive writing.52 These observations yield a terminus ante quem for the composition of the speeches of
Agelaus, Lyciscus, and [Thrasycrates], in Books 5, 9, and 11, respectively, of
circa 151; indeed, considering their placement in the text, Polybius probably
wrote them earlier in the 150s.
Polybius composed the books in which these speeches occur, therefore,
while he was still technically a political prisoner at Rome. He wrote for
46. 5.104.10, 9.37.10. Polybius employs the cloud figure in his own voice at 38.16.3.
47. See Walbank 1972, 16-31.
48. Weil 1988 maintains that we can know almost nothing about the time of composition, an ex
pessimistic view.
49. See Walbank 1977, 140-45.
50. E.g., Demetrius I Soter's escape from Rome in 162 at 31.11.1-15.12, perhaps the most famous exam
51. 1.73.4, 6.52.1-3 and 56.1-3, 9.9.9-10, 14.10.5, 15.30.10; cf. 31.12.12. Erbse 1951 and 1957 argued
that these are "achronistic" present tenses; rightly rejected by Brink and Walbank 1954, 99; Walbank 1963,
204-6; Musti 1965, 383-84; cf. Mioni 1949, 36-37. On the redaction generally, see Pedech 1964, 563-73.
52. See Pedech 1964, 532-34, 555-96.
This content downloaded from
128.230.234.162 on Tue, 08 Nov 2022 00:01:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
438 CRAIGE CHAMPION
both Roman and Greek audiences.53 We have seen that he draws on an established Greek tradition of cultural assimilation of Romans to Hellenism,
and cynics might say that Polybius' position as political prisoner makes it
easy to understand his representations of "Hellenic" Romans: they were
congenial to his Roman readership. But I have also suggested that Polybius
indirectly engages another established Greek practice, a politics of cultural
alienation from Rome. This Polybian image of Romans as barbarians is
more mysterious. I suggest that allegations of Roman barbarism, as evidenced in these speeches, take on meaning in the context of Achaean political interactions with Rome and Polybius' stance as Achaean patriot
regarding the Roman dominion.
In the collective historical conscience of the Achaean Confederation,
discomfiture and embarrassment concerning Achaean relations with Rome
reached back to 198. Achaea's relationship with the Macedonian monarchy
lay at the root of these collective pangs of conscience, and Polybius and
Livian passages derived from Polybius provide the bulk of the evidence for
them. Many Achaean poleis owed debts of gratitude to Macedonia. In 210/
9, the Achaeans and other Greeks had beseeched Philip V for aid against
the depredations of Aetolians, Attalus I of Pergamum, and the Romans
(Polyb. 10.41.1-2). In the early stages of the First Macedonian War, Philip
had defended Sicyon and Corinth from Roman attacks.54 During his second war against Rome, Philip actually returned cities to the KOlVoV in order
to ensure merely Achaea's benevolent neutrality in the coming struggle.55
Achaea suddenly severed its ties with Macedonia in autumn 198, joining
Rome against Philip. Indeed, Polybius states that the Achaeans accomplished many of their most brilliant achievements in league with the Romans.56 Yet some Achaean statesmen viewed the volte-face of 198 as a
political betrayal, and there are indications in Polybius' account relating to
this event that seem to belie the proud statement at 2.42.5.57 No Achaean
patriot could look back on the Achaean support for Rome resulting from the
divisive Achaean meeting at Sicyon in 198 without some reservation. The
(tpYTPW7y Aristaenus pushed through the resolution to join Rome only with
the greatest difficulty; a certain Memnon of Pellene broke the deadlock of the
Achaean damiurgi to put the proposal to assist Rome before the Achaean
assembly only after having been threatened with death by his father (Livy
53. Mioni 1949, 32. Walbank (1972, pp. 3-6 and nn. 16-19) assembles the references, stressing Polybius' Greek readership, to which add 1.42.1-2 (Sicily to Italy as Peloponnesus to Greece). But I cannot
accept his dismissal of 31.22.8, where Polybius states that his work will be read above all by Romans; see
Dubuisson 1985, 266-67.
54. Livy 27.31.1-3; cf. Polyb. 22.8.9-11: in 210 Galba stormed Achaean Aegina, sold all its inhabit
into slavery, and passed it on to the Aetolians, who in tum sold it to Attalus of Pergamum for thirty ta
Many Aeginetans were able to purchase their freedom, despite Galba's blustering (Polyb. 9.42.5-8).
55. Livy 32.5.4-5; cf. Polyb. 4.9.4; Livy 32.5.4 (Achaean oath of allegiance to Macedonia), with Aym
1938b, 50-57. But see Errington 1989, 262-63, for consideration of Philip's tactlessness regarding A
before the outbreak of the war. On Macedonian and, later, Roman encumbrances on Achaean autonomy,
Aymard 1938a, 200-204; further discussion of close Macedonian/Achaean relations at Eckstein 1
140-42.
56. Polyb. 2.42.5; on the subsequent formal Romano-Achaean treaty, probably of 192/91, see Ba
57. Cf. Polyb. 30.7.3-4 with Nottmeyer 1995, 94, for Polybius' sympathies for those who ha
loyal to King Perseus.
This content downloaded from
128.230.234.162 on Tue, 08 Nov 2022 00:01:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
ROMANS AS BAPBAPOI 439
32.22.5-8). When it became clear that the assembly would vote for assistance to Rome, the representatives from Dyme, Argos, and Polybius' own
hometown, Megalopolis, left the council rather than participate in the decision. The Argives shortly thereafter seceded from the Achaean KOlVOV in
declaring allegiance to Philip. According to Appian's account, the Achaean
majority favored Philip's cause.58 Later in the war Philip publicly accused
the Achaeans of ingratitude; after all his benefactions they had betrayed him
to his enemy.59 The Achaean statesman Archon, with whom Polybius had
close political connections, could look back on the decision of 198 from a
quarter-century remove with regret, in light of Macedonian services to the
Achaeans.60
Aristaenus was the foremost proponent in 198 for a reversal of traditional
Achaean policy towards Macedonia. He apparently enjoyed close relations
with Flamininus and, at least insofar as we can reconstruct the Polybian narrative of the lost Book 17 from Livy, Polybius represented Aristaenus himself as the source for the Roman commander Flamininus' policy of the "freedom of the Greeks."6' And Polybius takes great pains to present Aristaenus
and his policies in a most positive light. In his comparison of Aristaenus and
Philopoemen (24.11.1-13.10), Polybius represents Aristaenus as a politically astute politician who knew that political realities forced Achaea to look
to its own advantage (-o GuJtpEpov) when honor (-o6 Kakov) ceased to be a
possibility. And indeed Achaea had benefited greatly from its association
with Rome: regaining Corinth from Macedonia; recovering Argos; and being
allowed to absorb Sparta and Messene. But in 24.11-13 the historian also
praises the opposing policy of Philopoemen, who took a harder line, stressing the letter of the law in Achaean relations with Rome in order to stave off
the inevitable Achaean subservience to the Romans for as long as possible.
Polybius also took care to preserve Lycortas' hard-line speech against the
Roman hegemony (Livy [P] 39.36.6-37.18), and he reviles the excessively
pro-Roman Callicrates (Polyb. 24.8.1-10.15, 30.29.1-7).
The ambiguity in these passages is suggestive of the tensions that must
have arisen concerning Polybius' own cautiously ambivalent policies towards Rome in 170-68. In autumn 170 Polybius, about to enter upon the
office of Yiuapxog, opposed his father Lycortas' neutrality with a more p
Roman policy, and in his account the historian does not conceal the fact that
Lycortas and many other Achaeans, political heirs of the policies of the
58. Livy 32.19.1-23.3, 24.1-7 (Elateia), 25.1-12 (Argos and Corinth); Achaean majority favors Macedonia: App. Mac. 7; cf. Paus. 7.8.2; extensive discussion of the Achaean assembly of 198 at Aymard 1938b,
79-102, at pp. 80-81, n. 49 of the date; concise treatments at Deininger 1971, 42-46; Gruen 1984, 44446.
59. Polyb. 18.6.5-8; Livy 32.34.11-13; Aymard 1938b, pp. 53-54 and nn. 27-28; Eckstein 1990,
pp. 68-69 and n. 74; cf. Livy 34.23.6-7 (Alexander the Aetolian in 195): Achaeans as transfugas from Phi
who received Corinth and sought after Argos.
60. Livy 41.24.12-15; Polyb. 28.6.1-7.15 for Polybius and Archon.
61. See Livy 32.21.36 (libertas); for ?XcuOcpia as a constant, underlying principle of Achaean policy in
Polybius, see 2.37.9-11, 42.6-7, 43.8-9 (Aratus), 58.1-3 (Mantinea), 69.1-2 (Sellasia). Aristaenus himself
probably stressed the Achaean principle of freedom, as suggested by his dedication to Flamininus at Corinth:
SEG 22, no. 214 (1967), with Eckstein 1990, 62-63. See Ferrary 1988, 83-88 for a brief account of the
Greek diplomatic antecedents of Flamininus' ?XuOcpia theme.
This content downloaded from
128.230.234.162 on Tue, 08 Nov 2022 00:01:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
440 CRAIGE CHAMPION
Achaean hero Philopoemen, took a dim view of any unnecessary collaboration with the Romans.62 Upon entering office, Polybius supported the restoration of Achaean honors to the pro-Roman Eumenes of Pergamum-but
he rejected those he considered to be excessive (28.7.3-15). He later delayed
the full Achaean levy's support of the Roman commander Q. Marcius Philippus; but he himself shared Marcius' dangers (28.13.1-7). Polybius became
unwillingly involved in Roman factional politics between Philippus and the
legate Ap. Claudius Cento. Cento had requested support from the Achaeans
for operations in Epirus, but Marcius instructed Polybius to see to it that the
Achaeans not comply with Cento's request. Polybius was in a delicate posi-
tion (6uGXpiJcyou Kaci notKiXrl dro0'cY, 28.13.11): he could not reveal
Marcius' imperative to the Achaeans assembled at Sicyon, but opposing the
request in public brought its own dangers. In the end he appealed to Achaean
legalities, taking up the position of Philopoemen and Lycortas, arguing that
the KOtVoV could honor only such requests as had the sanction of a senatus
consultum.63 After leaving office, Polybius joined Archon and Lycortas in
supporting an Achaean military mission on behalf of the Ptolemaic kingdom
against Seleucid aggression, but he withdrew his support for this measure
after Marcius Philippus urged the Achaeans to adopt the Roman policy of
mediation (29.25.5-6). Polybius' independent political agency, then, had
already been compromised before Pydna, for even on his own interpretation
of events, he had had to steer a middle course between Achaean patriotism and politically necessary cooperation with Rome. Moreover, he had
had first-hand experience of Roman duplicity. These events suggest that
early on Polybius' political interactions with Romans, while he was still an
important politician in the Achaean Confederation, were filled with complexity, discomfort, and embarrassment.64 And it is worth remembering that
none of Polybius' careful measures prevented his political exile to Rome.
It is therefore reasonable to see the defenses of Aristaenus as in part a
defense of Polybius' own cautious policies. Another well-known passage,
the "Fragment on Traitors," as a retrospective defense in Book 18 of Aristaenus' policy in 198, provides further evidence for both Polybius' apparent
need to justify his own middle-of-the-road policy towards Rome and the
presence of a persistent Achaean belief that the decision of 198 had somehow betrayed Achaean principles.65 Dissident Achaean voices showed the
continued popularity of Philopoemen over against the pro-Roman Aristaenus in 185; many Achaeans were deeply suspicious of Aristaenus and
Diophanes for working in the Roman interest (Polyb. 22.10.14-15, 24.13.10).
62. Polyb. 28.6.1-9 with Pedech 1969, 255-58; Musti 1978, 77-78, Walbank 1985, 282-83.
63. On Achaean observation of legalities in relations with Rome, cf. Polyb. 22.12.5-10, 23.4.12-14;
Livy (P) 38.32.8 (foedus with Rome or Sparta? -the evidence does not permit a certain conclusion: Badian 1952, p. 78 and n. 20), 39.37.9-10.
64. On these events, see Eckstein 1995, 5-6. The negative remarks on Roman nova sapientia in the
170s in a Polybian passage in Livy perhaps further reflect Polybius' discomfiture. See Livy (P) 42.47.
with Briscoe 1964; Nissen 1863, 249-54, esp. 252 on the Polybian derivation.
65. Polyb. 18.13.1-15.17 (explicit mention of Aristaenus at 13.8-11), with the analysis of Eckstein
1987b; already Nissen 1863, p. 326, n. 2.
This content downloaded from
128.230.234.162 on fff:ffff on Thu, 01 Jan 1976 12:34:56 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
ROMANS AS BAPBAPOI 441
The Senate's vagueness and temporizing on the Spartan question dating from
189 and Roman irresolution regarding the repatriation of the exiles of 168,
of whom Polybius was of course one, ensured continued hostility towards
the Romans in some Achaean circles.66
In this context, one may well wonder how an Achaean readership would
have read the passages in the Histories in which Romans emerge as prac-
titioners of Hellenic koyl7ti6. On the basis of the long-standing Acha
reservations regarding the decision to join the Romans in 198 and Roman
temporizing over both the Achaean exiles and the Spartan question, we have
good reason to believe that Polybius' warm praise of the Roman achievement and his assimilationist treatment of Romans as "honorary Greeks"
in such passages as 2.35 would hardly have been well received by some
Achaean politicians. Further suspicions would have arisen from the fact
that in a roughly twenty-year period the historian himself had moved
from Achaean statesman to political prisoner at Rome to mentor of Scipio
Aemilianus. And after the debacle of 146, he would serve as a mediator in
the resettlement of Greece.67
Regarding Polybius' Greek, and especially Achaean, audiences, therefore,
authorial motivations for indirectly (and occasionally directly) subverting
the image of Romans as "honorary Greeks" and for demonstrating independent political agency are patent. Yet in light of Polybius' political predicament, there obviously would have been dangers in attempting to assert any
such independence containing seeds of dissidence in blatantly overt terms.
For this reason it may be best to reject a passage in Diodorus stating that
the Romans hold onto their empire through the exercise of terror as Poly-
bian.68 On the other hand, Polybius overtly condemns Rome's theft
(&patipcGl, 3.30.4) of Sardinia in the aftermath of the First RomanoCarthaginian War as an injustice (3.28.1-2, cf. 3.15.10) that led to the cataclysm of the Hannibalic War. He therefore seems to judge the Romans and
their actions, by his own lights, independently.
Suggestions of Roman barbarism in Polybius' text take on meaning in
this political context. Polybius believed that small states must sometimes
make difficult and uncomfortable decisions, as Achaea had had to do in 198.
Polybius clearly admired many qualities in the Romans, but the Achaean
patriot was also able to assert his independence in giving voice to the negative aspects of Roman behavior. His representations of Romans as both
66. See conveniently Gruen 1984, 119-23 and literature cited there on Achaea's conflict with Spar
(p. 123: "The senate made a virtual science of ambiguity"); cf. P6dech 1969, 252-55 for a concise acco
of the frictions down to Polybius' hipparchy. For Polybius' own anger and disappointment over the host
issue, see 30.32.1-12, 33.1.3-8 and 3.1-2.
67. For honors to Polybius throughout Greece for his role as mediator between Greece and R
Paus. 8.9.2, 30.8-9, 37.2, 44.5, 48.9, with Ziegler 1952, cols. 1462-64; Polyb. 39.3.11-4.4, 5.2-6, 8.1-2,
with Walbank 1977, 160-61; Schwertfeger 1974, passim, on the settlement of Achaea and its aftermath.
See also the self-proclaimed patriotic services to Greece in the most parlous of times at 38.4.7-8.
68. Diod. 32.2, 4.4-5; Walbank 1985, 289-90; Eckstein 1995, 225-29; cf. Shimron 1979/80, pp. 106-7
and n. 46, and Ferrary 1988, 334-39, and p. 335, n. 217, for modem arguments, for and against. Shimron
(1979/80, p. 101, n. 26) suggests that Polybius hints at censorship at 31.22.11. For Diodorus' use of Polybius,
see Schwartz 1903, cols. 689-90; for an independent anti-Roman strain in Diodorus, see Sacks 1990 and
1994, passim.
This content downloaded from
128.230.234.162 on Tue, 08 Nov 2022 00:01:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
442 CRAIGE CHAMPION
"honorary Greeks" and as barbarians leave the Romans in an indeterminate
cultural position.69 In his engagement of a politics of cultural indeterminacy
regarding Rome, the medium of the reported speech provided Polybius with
a vehicle for practicing the art of relatively safe criticism. And in these
speeches the pragmatic and realistic Achaean statesman of "the politics of
the possible" also reveals an emotional allegiance to the impossible dream
of complete and total Greek XkeuOcpia from the western barbarian.
Syracuse University
69. Cf. Musti 1978, 79: Polybius as "un uomo politico gia sospettato di doppio giuoco."
LITERATURE CITED
Aymard, A. 1938a. Les Assemblies de la Confederation achaienne. Bordeaux.
. 1938b. Les Premiers Rapports de Rome et de la Confederation achaienn
avant J. C.). Bordeaux.
Badian, E. 1952. The Treaty Between Rome and the Achaean League. JRS 42:76-80.
Brandstaeter, F. A. 1844. Die Geschichten des dtolischen Landes, Volkes und Bundes, nebst einer
historiographischen Abhandlung uber Polybios. Berlin.
Brink, C. O., and F. W. Walbank. 1954. The Construction of the Sixth Book of Polybius. CQ
4:97-122.
Briscoe, J. 1964. Q. Marcius Philippus and Nova Sapientia. JRS 54:66-77.
Cartledge, P. 1993. The Greeks: A Portrait of Self and Others. Oxford.
Castiglioni, L. 1928. Motivi antiromani nella tradizione storica antica. RIL 61:625-39.
Champion, C. 1993. The Indirect Historian: The Depiction of Group Character in Polybius'
Histories, 1-6. Ph.D. diss., Princeton University.
. 1996. Polybius, Aetolia, and the Gallic Attack on Delphi (279 B.C.). Historia
45:315-28.
. 1997. The Nature of Authoritative Evidence in Polybius and Agelaus' Speech at
Naupactus. TAPhA 127:111-28.
Dahlheim, W. 1968. Struktur und Entwicklung des romischen Volkerrechts im dritten und zweiten
Jahrhundert v. Chr. Munich.
Dauge, Y.-A. 1981. Le Barbare: Recherches sur la conception romaine de la barbarie et de la
civilisation. Collection Latomus 176. Brussels.
Deininger, J. 1971. Derpolitische Widerstand gegen Rom in Griechenland, 217-86 v. Chr. Berlin.
Dell, H. J. 1967. Antigonus III and Rome. CP 62:94-103.
Dittenberger, W., and K. Purgold, eds. 1896. Inschriften von Olympia (IVO). Berlin.
Dubuisson, M. 1985. Le Latin de Polybe: Les Implications historiques d'un cas de bilinguisme.
Paris.
Eckstein, A. M. 1976. T. Quinctius Flamininus and the Campaign against Philip in 198 B.C.
Phoenix 30:119-42.
. 1987a. Senate and General: Individual Decision-Making and Roman Foreign
Relations, 264-194 B.C. Berkeley and Los Angeles.
. 1987b. Polybius, Aristaenus, and the Fragment On Traitors. CQ 37:140-62.
. 1990. Polybius, the Achaeans, and the "Freedom of the Greeks." GRBS 31:45-71.
. 1995. Moral Vision in the "Histories" of Polybius. Berkeley and Los Angeles.
. 1997. Physis and Nomos: Polybius, the Romans, and Cato the Elder. In Hellenistic
Constructs: Essays in Culture, History, and Historiography, ed. P. Cartledge, P. Garnsey,
and E. Gruen, 175-98. Berkeley and Los Angeles.
This content downloaded from
128.230.234.162 on Tue, 08 Nov 2022 00:01:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
ROMANS AS BAPBAPOI 443
Ehrhardt, C. 1995. Speeches Before Battle? Historia 44:120-21.
Eisen, K.-F. 1966. Polybiosinterpretationen: Beobachtungen zu Prinzipien griechischer und
romischer Historiographie bei Polybios. Heidelberg.
Erbse, H. 1951. Zur Entstehung des polybianischen Geschichtswerkes. RhM 94:157-79.
_ 1957. Polybios-Interpretationen. Philologus 101:269-97.
Errington, R. M. 1989. Rome Against Philip and Antiochus. CAH2 8:244-89.
Erskine, A. 1994. The Romans as Common Benefactors. Historia 43:70-87.
. 1997. Greekness and Uniqueness: The Cult of the Senate in the Greek East. Phoenix
51:25-35.
Ferrary, J.-L. 1988. Philh'llenisme et imperialisme: Aspects ideologiques de la conque^te romaine
du monde hellenistique. Paris and Rome.
. 1997. The Hellenistic World and Roman Political Patronage. In Hellenistic Constructs:
Essays in Culture, History, and Historiography, ed. P. Cartledge, P. Gamsey, E. Gruen,
105-19. Berkeley and Los Angeles.
Forte, B. 1972. Rome and the Romans as the Greeks Saw Them. Rome.
Fuchs, H. [1938] 1964. Der geistige Widerstand gegen Rom in der antiken Welt. Berlin.
Gabba, E. 1974. Storiografia greca e imperialismo romano (111-I sec. a. C.). RSI 86:625-42.
Gelzer, M. 1933. Romische Politik bei Fabius Pictor. Hermes 68:129-66.
. 1940a. Die Achaica im Geschichtswerk des Polybios. Abhandlungen der deutschen
Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin: 3-32.
. 1940b. Die hellenische IIPOKATAYKEYH im zweiten Buche des Polybios. Hermes
75:27-37.
Golan, D. 1971. The Problem of the Roman Presence in the Political Consciousness of the Greeks
before 229 B.C. RSI 1:93-98.
Gruen, E. S. 1984. The Hellenistic World and the Coming of Rome. Berkeley and Los Angeles.
. 1992. Culture and National Identity in Republican Rome. Ithaca.
Habicht, C. 1997. Athens from Alexander to Antony, Translated D. L. Schneider. Cambridge, MA
and London.
Hahm, D. E. 1995. Polybius' Applied Political Theory. In Justice and Generosity: Studies in
Hellenistic Social and Political Philosophy, ed. A. Laks and M. Schofield, 7-47. Cambridge.
Hall, E. 1989. Inventing the Barbarian: Greek Self-Definition through Tragedy. Oxford.
Hansen, M. H. 1993. The Battle Exhortation in Ancient Historiography. Historia 42:161-80.
Harris, W. V. 1979. War and Imperialism in Republican Rome, 327-70 B.C. Oxford.
Holleaux, M. 1921. Rome, la Grece, et les monarchies hellenistiques au IIIe siecle avant J.-C.,
273-205. Paris.
Jones, C. P. 1999. Kinship Diplomacy in the Ancient World. Cambridge, MA, and London.
La Roche, P. 1857. Charakteristik des Polybios. Leipzig.
Lazenby, J. F. 1996. The First Punic War: A Military History. Stanford.
Lehmann, G. A. 1967. Untersuchungen zur historischen Glaubwiirdigkeit des Polybios. Munster.
MacMullen, R. 1991. Hellenizing the Romans (2nd Century B.C.). Historia 40:419-38.
Meister, K. 1975. Historische Kritik bei Polybios. Wiesbaden.
Mioni, E. 1949. Polibio. Padua.
Mohm, S. 1977. Untersuchungen zu den historiographischen Anschauungen des Polybios.
Saarbriicken.
Musti, D. 1965. Problemi polibiani. PP 20:380-426.
. 1978. Polibio e l'imperialismo romano. Naples.
Nissen, H. 1863. Kritische Untersuchungen uber die Quellen der vierten undfunften Dekade des
Livius. Berlin.
Nottmeyer, H. 1995. Polybios und das Ende des Achaierbundes: Untersuchungen zu den romischachaiischen Beziehungen ausgehend von der Mission des Kallikrates bis zur Zerstorung
Corinths. Munich.
Pedech, P. 1964. La Methode historique de Polybe. Paris.
This content downloaded from
128.230.234.162 on Tue, 08 Nov 2022 00:01:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
444 CRAIGE CHAMPION
. 1969. Polybe hipparque de la confederation acheenne (170-169 avant J.-C.). EC
37:252-59.
Petrochilos, N. 1974. Roman Attitudes to the Greeks. Athens.
Petzold, K.-E. 1969. Studien zur Methode des Polybios und zu ihrer historischen Auswertung.
Munich.
Sacks, K. S. 1981. Polybius on the Writing of History. Berkeley and Los Angeles.
. 1990. Diodorus Siculus and the First Century. Princeton.
. 1994. Diodorus and His Sources: Conformity and Creativity. In Greek Historiography,
ed. S. Homblower, 213-32. Oxford.
Schmitt, H. H. 1957/58. Hellenen, Romer, und Barbaren: Eine Studie zu Polybios. Wis-
senschaftliche Beilage zum Jahresbericht 1957/58 des Humanistischen Gymnasiums.
Aschaffenburg.
Schwartz, E. 1903. Diodoros (38). RE 5:663-704.
Schwertfeger, Th. 1974. Der achaiische Bund von 146 bis 27 v. Chr. Munich.
Shimron, B. 1979/80. Polybius on Rome: A Re-examination of the Evidence. SCI 5:94-117.
Taifacos, I. G. 1982. Tito Livio e una fonte antiromana di Polibio. Latomus 41:817-32.
Toynbee, A. J. 1965. Hannibal's Legacy, 2 vols. London, New York, and Toronto.
Volkmann, H. 1954. Griechische Rhetorik oder roimische Politik? Hermes 82:465-76.
Walbank, F. W. 1940. Philip V of Macedon. Cambridge.
1957, 1967. A Historical Commentary on Polybius. Vols. 1-2. Oxford.
. 1963. Three Notes on Polybius XII. In Miscellanea di studi alessandrini in memoria di
Augusto Rostagni, 203-13. Turin.
. 1972. Polybius. Berkeley and Los Angeles.
. 1977. Polybius' Last Ten Books. In Historiographia Antiqua: Commentationes
Lovanienses in honorem W. Peremnans, 139-62. Leuven.
. 1985. Selected Papers: Studies in Greek and Roman History and Historiography.
Cambridge.
Weil, R. 1988. La composition de l'Histoire de Polybe. JS: 185-206.
Wiedemann, Th. 1990. Rhetoric in Polybius. In Purposes of History: Studies in Greek
Historiography from the 4th to the 2nd Centuries BC, ed. H. Verdin, G. Schepens, and
E. de Keyser, 289-300. Leuven.
Ziegler, K. 1952. Polybios. RE 21.2:1440-578.
This content downloaded from
128.230.234.162 on Tue, 08 Nov Thu, 01 Jan 1976 12:34:56 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms