Bubbles and Fools
Bubbles and Fools
Bubbles and Fools
Gadi Barlevy
54
55
56
Before I discuss whether models featuring heterogeneous prior beliefs among traders can rightly be
viewed as giving rise to bubbles, let me reflect on
why dispensing with the assumption that traders begin with the same priors about their environment may
allow us to avoid Tiroles (1982) conclusion that rules
out bubbles. Let me trot out Alice and Bob again. If
Alice tries to sell her asset to Bob, then because Bob
is rational, he still realizes that there is no reason
Alice would want to sell him the asset other than that
she believes the asset is worth less than the price she
is offering. But since Bob does not start out with the
same beliefs as Alice, he will not necessarily be convinced by the evidence Alice sees. Indeed, suppose
nobody receives any new information to update their
priors. In that case, Bob would know that Alice is
trading on the basis of her priors, which he does not
agree with. Thus, he might believe the asset is selling
for less than its fundamental value even as Alice believes
the price is above the fundamental value. Alice and
Bob will agree to trade, each believing they are taking
advantage of the other. Note that in getting around
Tiroles result, I am not abandoning the assumption
that agents are rational. Indeed, I invoke rationality
throughout my analysis. This is worth pointing out,
since models with uncommon priors are sometimes
described as models in which agents are irrational,
even though they need not be.10
To show how dropping the requirement of common priors can lead to scenarios that are suggestive
of greater-fool bubbles, consider the following adaptation of the Harrison and Kreps (1978) model. Suppose there is a single asset, available in fixed supply
that is normalized to 1. Let dt denote the dividend this
asset yields in period t, which corresponds to a single
day. There are two agents, Evelyn and Odelia, who
maintain different beliefs about dividends. In particular,
Evelyn believes the asset yields one unit of consumption goods in even periods and nothing in odd periods:
1 if t is even
Evelyn believes dt =
1)
0 if t is odd.
Odelia instead believes that the asset yields one unit
of consumption goods in odd periods and nothing in
even periods, that is,
2)
0 if t is even
Odelia believes dt =
1 if t is odd.
3)
+ 3 + 5 + =
.
1 2
On the other hand, Odelia believes the asset will pay
a dividend today, two days from now, four days from
now, and so on. Hence, she would value the present
discounted dividends from the asset at
4)
1 + 2 + 4 + =
1
.
1 2
57
1
at some period t, there would
1 2
1
, the highest
1 2
1
1 + 2
1+
=
.
2
1 2
1
But since 0 < < 1, it follows that
1 + (1 )
1
>
1
.
1 2
1
in period 1,
1 2
1
at
1 2
1 + 2
in
1 2
1 + 2
in period 2, or else Evelyn could buy
1 2
1 + 2
for all t. Thus, I have established a new
1 2
1
that I started with.
1 2
1 + 2
at all dates, can it ever equal this
1 2
1 + 2
in the following
1 2
1
in the next period. She
1 2
58
1 + 2
1 + 3
1+
.
=
2
1 2
1
Since 0 < < 1, it follows that
1 + 3
1 + 2
>
.
1 2
1 2
Hence, Odelia would expect to earn strictly positive
profits from this strategy, and so she should buy as many
units of the assets as her endowment allows. To ensure
supply is equal to demand, the price in period 1 must
be at least
1 + 3
, the lowest profit Odelia can
1 2
1 + 3
for all t, a bound that is higher than
1 2
1 + n
. Since this holds for
1 2
pt lim
1 + n
1+
1
=
=
.
2
2
1
1
1
1
for all t turns out
1
1
the next day is equal to
1
1
1
1+
.
=
1 1
1
for each t
1
59
1
apples.
1
60
1 + 2 + 4 + ... =
1
.
1 2
+ 3 + 5 + ... =
.
1 2
1
, because any
1
1
+
=
from the two agents to
2
2
1
1
1
1
accurately reflects the value to
1
1
,
1
1
emerges because Evelyn and
1
1
can be rationalized using
1
61
1
if given the option to rent it out,
1
and would view accepting any price for the asset below
this one as a bad trade. The fact that traders believe
others are fools does not necessarily imply that they
must think the asset is overvalued.
Disagreement on valuation
In my example in which Evelyn and Odelia had
different beliefs, both valued holding the asset indefinitely
equally provided they could rent out the asset. This
equality in valuation is due to a particular feature of this
examplenamely, that traders agree about the distribution of the most optimistic valuation for dividends
in every period. This feature can arise in other environments. For example, Scheinkman (2014) presents a
model in which beliefs are independent across time.
Specifically, Scheinkman assumes two types of traders.
Type A traders believe the dividend in each period is
equally likely to be 0 or 1. Type B traders, independent
of their beliefs in other periods, will with probability
1 2q share the same beliefs that type A traders hold;
but with probability q, type B traders believe the dividend that period will be 1, and with probability q, these
same type B traders believe the dividend will be 0. In
this case, type A and type B agents still agree about
the expected value from holding the asset indefinitely
given they both have the option to rent it out.
62
FIGURE 1
Alices and Bobs beliefs given the number of good trees in each period
3
1
1
2
2
1
0.9
0.1
1
1
0
1
1
2
1
1
1
0
1
1
0
1
0
Number of
good trees by
period 2
Number of
good trees by
period 3
Number of
good trees by
period 4
Alices beliefs
0
Number of
good trees by
period 2
Number of
good trees by
period 3
Number of
good trees by
period 4
Bobs beliefs
63
64
65
66
knowing what beliefs any agent might have. This notion may be in line with the emerging view on bubbles
in the wake of the Great Recession: The apparent bubble
in housing might have left some better off (for example, homeowners and developers who sold houses in
the years leading up to the recession and traders such
as those profiled in Michael Lewiss book The Big Short
who managed to short housing21) and some worse off
(for example, those who bought housing or invested in
mortgages just before the recession hit); however, on
the whole, society was worse off because of misallocated
resources (for example, excess housing and workers
whose skills were specific to housing-related activities) that might have depressed subsequent economic
activity. Posner and Weyl (2013) are the most forceful in making this case. But there are two important
caveats that make this policy prescription difficult to
implement in practice. First, the extent to which the
investment in an asset (whether it be housing in the
mid-2000s or dot-com ventures in the late 1990s or
railroads in the 1800s or tulips in the Netherlands in
the seventeenth century) is excessive ex ante, before
we know how things turn out, hinges not on agents
holding different beliefs but on them holding beliefs
we know to be distorted. Many would balk at the notion that policymakers can judge when agents hold
distorted beliefs and whether agents beliefs are correct.
Referring to models featuring agents with heterogeneous
beliefs as models of bubbles can be misleading in that
regard, since evidence that people hold different beliefs
does not prove that their beliefs are distorted. And yet,
distorted beliefs, rather than heterogeneous beliefs, are
what imply asset prices are too high. Second, since
agents are eager to trade, there is strong incentive for
agents to claim they are trading because of fundamental
reasons rather than because of differences in their beliefs.
Indeed, the response to financial reform in the wake of
the financial crisis suggests market participants have
actively sought to evade restrictions on when they can
trade. Cochrane (2014) makes a similar argument.
An alternative approach: Asymmetric
information
I now turn to the other approach for modeling
greater-fool theories of bubbles. For lack of a consensus term, I will refer to these as asymmetric information
models. This is because a key feature of these theories
is that agents receive private information other agents
may not be privy to. In particular, they may receive
information that all agents would agree establishes that
the asset is overvalued. However, since agents are unsure
what other agents know, they might still buy the asset
in the hope of selling it to a less informed agent. Thus,
67
68
69
not the policy response that advocates of more forceful action against potential bubbles have in mind. They
typically argue that a central bank should raise interest
rates to head off possible bubbles. That said, Conlons
thought experiment is still informative, since it reveals
the social welfare consequences of deflating a bubble
when it can be achieved costlessly.26
To understand Conlons (2015) results, it will be
helpful to return to the key intuition behind bubbles
in asymmetric information environments: Traders are
willing to buy an asset they know to be overvalued
because they are taking a gamble. Either they will be
able to sell it at an even higher price to another less
informed trader, or else they will find out that no other
trader is willing to buy the asset and they will incur a
loss. The reason a trader may be able to sell the asset
to a greater fool is that the buyer believes he may be
entering into a mutually beneficial trade. Thus, an inherent feature of greater-fool bubbles based on asymmetric
information is that when agents trade, sometimes it is
because assets are overvalued and sometimes it is because there are mutual gains from trade. In other words,
Carol can profit at Teds expense only because there
are other situations in which both Carol and Ted gain
from trading and Ted doesnt know which state they
are in while Carol does. If a policymaker were to reveal
that the asset is overvalued, this information would
affect the price in both scenarios. In particular, it would
lead to a reduction in the price when the asset is overvalued, and it would lead to an increase in the price
when there are mutual gains from trade. The first part is
straightforward: By telling everyone the asset is overvalued, the policymaker prevents those who know the
asset is overvalued (for example, Carol) from passing
it off to less informed traders (for example, Ted), and
so the price of the asset will not exceed the fundamental
value. As for the second part, in the state of the world
where there are mutual gains from trade between Carol
and Ted, one should note that when Ted buys the asset
he remains nervous that Carol might be taking advantage of him. If this concern were mitigated, he would
be willing to pay more for the asset, and the price
would be higher.
When the asset is available in fixed supply, announcing a bubble will generally have an ambiguous effect
on social welfare. Given that the price of the asset rises
in some states of the world and falls in others, those who
sell the asset will be better off in some states but worse
off in others. We can abstract from these considerations
by assuming that the gains and losses exactly cancel
each other out. In this case, a commitment by a fully
informed policymaker to announce whenever she knows
the asset is overvalued will have no effect on welfare
70
agents believe the asset is worth less than its price, yet
they are willing to buy it because they are unsure
whether other traders are aware of this. Eventually,
uncertainty about what other traders know is resolved,
at which point the price of the asset collapses. This is
not true for other theories of bubbles. For example, in
models where bubbles arise because of asset shortages,
bubbles can in principle persist indefinitely. In models
where bubbles arise because of risk shifting, agents
who buy the asset are gambling on a risky asset that
sometimes pays off. If that happens, the price of the
asset will rise further rather than collapse. The fact that
greater-fool theories of bubbles based on asymmetric
information imply that bubbles necessarily burst makes
them of natural interest for further study, especially to
determine whether merely avoiding an eventual asset
price collapse can justify policy intervention.
Conclusion
This article described the literature on greaterfool theories of bubbles, that is, theories in which
agents are willing to buy assets they know to be overvalued because they believe they can profit from selling the assets to others. The idea behind this theory is
intuitive and seems to capture aspects of what often
happens during real episodes that are suspected to be
bubbles. This theory can also capture the unsustainable nature of a bubble that makes asset bubbles a
concern for policymakers. And yet it turns out to be a
surprisingly difficult theory to model and analyze.
What specific lessons should be taken away from
this discussion? In this article, I highlight two distinctions that are important to keep in mind to better sort
through the various results in the existing literature.
The first is the distinction between speculation and
bubbles. Speculative trading concerns why agents trade
namely, to profit at the expense of others as opposed
to intending to find mutually beneficial gains. Asset
bubbles concern features of an equilibrium price
namely, whether the price faithfully represents what
the asset is fundamentally worth. The fact that agents
engage in speculative trading does not necessarily imply
that the asset must be a bubble. In line with this, some
models that try to capture greater-fool theories of
bubbles are really models of the greater-fool theory
of trading rather than models of bubbles per se.
The second distinction that this article highlights
is one between models based on uncommon priors and
those based on asymmetric information. Any greaterfool theory requires that traders hold different beliefs.
But it matters whether these different beliefs arise because traders start out with distinct priors or because
they receive different information. This difference is
71
72
NOTES
Note that this logic concerns only how policymakers should respond
to evidence of a possible bubble. In principle, though, policy intervention might prevent bubbles from arising in the first place. Indeed,
some have argued that policies such as restricting how much agents
can borrow against an asset or taxing transactions to make trading less
profitable may prevent bubbles. These policies are also more targeted
than the interest rate rules Bernanke and Gertler (1999) considered.
1
It is not clear where the term greater fool originated, but it seems
to have been first used by market practitioners. For example, a discussion of potential broker-dealer misconduct in the Securities and
Exchange Commissions annual report for the fiscal year ending
June 30, 1963, contains the following description: What has been
colloquially referred to as the bigger fool theory ... is simply the
assurance that regardless of whether the price paid for a security is
fair and/or reflective of the intrinsic value of the security or even
reflective of a rational public evaluation of the security, the security
is still a good buy because a bigger fool will always come along
to take it off the customers hands at a higher price (Securities and
Exchange Commission, 1964, p. 74).
5
Chancellor (1999).
Milgrom and Stokey (1982) independently established similar results to those in Tirole (1982), although they framed their findings
in terms of speculative trading rather than bubbles. I therefore refer
to Tiroles work in my discussion.
7
at least one agent must be wrong whenever two agents hold different
beliefs, that agent must not be rational. But as Morris notes, rationality
restricts only how agents update their priors, not what their priors
can be.
For example, suppose dividends reflect the profits of a multiproduct
company that sold different products at each date. The fact that a
theory about how much profit the firm would earn selling apples in
Australia in period 1 was wrong may not lead us to revise our theories about how much profit the firm would earn selling bicycles in
Burundi in period 2.
11
The usual motivation for assuming agents are price takers is that
it can always be assumed there are many identical replicas of Evelyn
and Odelia in the market, in which case the actions of any one agent
have no influence on the price of the asset.
12
13
suggests
17
1
behaves somewhat like a fundamental valuea
1
15
1
+ c t for c > 0
1
can also be an equilibrium price path. If Evelyns and Odelias endowments do not grow, at some point the one who values the asset
more could not afford the asset, yet the other party would want to
sell all of her holdings. Hence, in this case, such a path cannot be
an equilibrium. Harrison and Kreps refer to ct as a bubble, although
they use this term in the sense of an explosive solution of a difference
equation rather than the way I use the term. Still, their terminology
73
Lewis (2010).
21
27
REFERENCES
74
Cogley, Timothy, 1999, Should the Fed take deliberate steps to deflate asset price bubbles?, Economic
Review, Federal Reserve Bank of San Francisco, No. 1,
pp. 4252.
Conlon, John R., 2015, Should central banks burst
bubbles? Some microeconomic issues, Economic
Journal, Vol. 125, No. 582, February, pp. 141161.
__________, 2004, Simple finite horizon bubbles
robust to higher order knowledge, Econometrica,
Vol. 72, No. 3, May, pp. 927936.
Doblas-Madrid, Antonio, 2012, A robust model
of bubbles with multidimensional uncertainty,
Econometrica, Vol. 80, No. 5, September, pp. 18451893.
Doblas-Madrid, Antonio, and Kevin Lansing, 2014,
Credit-fuelled bubbles, Michigan State University
and Federal Reserve Bank of San Francisco, mimeo,
May, available at http://www.bostonfed.org/MacroFinance-2014/Doblas-Madrid-Lansing.pdf.
Farhi, Emmanuel, and Jean Tirole, 2012, Bubbly
liquidity, Review of Economic Studies, Vol. 79, No. 2,
April, pp. 678706.
Gilboa, Itzhak, Larry Samuelson, and David
Schmeidler, 2014, No-betting-Pareto dominance,
Econometrica, Vol. 82, No. 4, July, pp. 14051442.
Samuelson, Paul A., 1958, An exact consumptionloan model of interest with or without the social contrivance of money, Journal of Political Economy,
Vol. 66, No. 6, December, pp. 467482.
Scheinkman, Jos A., and Wei Xiong, 2003, Overconfidence and speculative bubbles, Journal of Political
Economy, Vol. 111, No. 6, December, pp. 11831219.
75
76