The Antitrust Paradox
The Antitrust Paradox
The Antitrust Paradox
Volume 13
Number 2
Winter 1979
Recommended Citation
Paul H. Brietzke, Robert Bork, The Antitrust Paradox: A Policy at War with Itself, 13 Val. U. L. Rev. 403 (1979).
Available at: http://scholar.valpo.edu/vulr/vol13/iss2/7
This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by the
Valparaiso University School of Law at ValpoScholar. It has been accepted
for inclusion in Valparaiso University Law Review by an authorized
administrator of ValpoScholar. For more information, please contact a
ValpoScholar staff member at scholar@valpo.edu.
pp.403-421
Brietzke: Robert Bork, The Antitrust Paradox: A Policy at War with Itself
BOOK REVIEW
The Antitrust Paradox: A Policy at War with Itself, by Robert H.
Bork. New York: Basic Books, 1978. Pp. 425, $18.00.
Except when responding to advertisements and sale promotions, the people are stupid; their indolent and fickle representatives
in Congress are no better; the courts are unable to recognize the
narrow limitations on their competence or to resist the temptations
to power provided by the antitrust statutes; FTC and Antitrust
Division bureaucrats are guilty of an untrammeled pursuit of the
pet theories of the moment at the expense of consumer welfare;
private attorneys are frustrated by a fragmentation of issues in
complex antitrust litigation; and legal academics, members of an "intellectual class" seeking to augment its power and prestige at the
expense of the "business class," bear a major share of the blame for
the decadence of contemporary antitrust law.' Strong stuff, and Professor Bork seeks to rescue the beleagured and bewildered by
deploying insights he has gleaned from neoclassical microeconomics,
as it is understood by the Chicago School. The book is uneven, bearing the stamp of having been written and revised over a period of
ten years. The content of crucial premises shifts subtly (and
sometimes not so subtly) in the course of exposition. While it is not
designed as a hornbook and cannot be used as such, given the
number of axes being ground, many of Bork's case commentaries are
original and interesting. In sum, however, they fail to meet the
burden of proof through logical argumentation incurred by anyone
who attacks most of the important Supreme Court decisions in a
particular area.
In outline, Bork contends that "the only legitimate goal of
antitrust is the maximization of consumer welfare." 2 This concept
"provides a common denominator by which gains in destruction of
monopoly power can be estimated against loss in efficiency, and
economic theory provides the means of assessing the probable sizes
of the gains and losses."' Most judges and lawyers ignore this mode
1. R. BORK, THE ANTITRUST PARADOX 16, 49, 84, 86, 318, 410, 413, 416, 423-24
(1978) [hereinafter cited as R. BORK].
2. Id. at 7.
3. Id.at 79.
404
[Vol. 13
Id at 409.
Id at 419.
Id at 418-19.
8.
Id at 10.
9.
http://scholar.valpo.edu/vulr/vol13/iss2/7
Brietzke: Robert Bork, The Antitrust Paradox: A Policy at War with Itself
19791
ANTITRUST PARADOX
liberty and equality other than his own. You will thus love the book
if Bork's prejudices confirm your own. If they don't, you-like this
reviewer-will undoubtedly remain unmoved by a rather slipshod
analysis.
Professor Bork ignores the fact that the economy of the United
States operates under far fewer regulations than the economies of
most industrialized states. Since the economic performance of
several of these states has far outstripped ours in terms of growth,
Bork's concept of efficiency and the general welfare (the mere
presence or absence of various types of regulations) cannot be the
decisive variable governing economic performance. It is a truism
that business regulations-including antitrust laws in the U.S.-accurately reflect the degree of trust a government reposes in the
nation's corporations. The economic performance of American corporations in recent years offers slender justification for expanding
upon an already abundant trust;0 certainly the political performance
of our corporations, particularly that of multinationals in the international arena, argues for a more extensive regulation. Given that
Professor Bork was one of Nixon's Solicitors General (on this topic I
shall say no more), he should, at least by now, be aware of the
political abuses which stem from the exercise of a concentrated and
undifferentiated mass of wealth and power by managers of large
corporations. Bork does discuss a "predation through governmental
processes" - sham litigation, sharp lobbying practices, influencing
local zoning board decisions, etc."-but he ignores the corruption
and diffuse corporate influence over high-level governmental decisions (the so-called clout) that make genuinely participatory
democracy at home impossible and constitute an interference in our
foreign relations and in the internal affairs of other states.
This kind of authoritarianism is probably more of a clear and
present danger than the one Bork worries about, but his narrow
approach to the subject matter makes the neglect of corporate
political abuses inevitable: "It is only the fact that the simple ideas
of economics are powerful and entirely adequate to this field that
10. The law's approach has changed, but the basic policy bias has not. The
field is still open to private forms of ingenuity. There has been no sustained policy of
fragmenting markets through law, and law did little to hinder the initial growth of
large concentrations of economic power where overt collusion was absent. J. HURST,
LAW AND SOCIAL ORDER IN THE UNITED STATES
business can prosper under rules and institutions which differ considerably, "at least
from a juridical point of view ....
L. FRIEDMAN, THE LEGAL SYSTEM 208 (1975).
11. R. BORK, supra note 1, at 347-64.
406
[Vol. 13
12. Id at 90.
13. Id. at 72.
14. Id. at 92, 96, 117, 191, 392. Joan Robinson adds that economists often treat
circular statements as though they had a factual content and dress up imprecise ideas
in the language of infinitesimal calculus. J. ROBINSON, FREEDOM AND NECESSITY 119-20
(1970).
15. R. BORE, supra note 1, at 117.
http://scholar.valpo.edu/vulr/vol13/iss2/7
Brietzke: Robert Bork, The Antitrust Paradox: A Policy at War with Itself
19791
ANTITRUST PARADOX
[Vol. 13
sort out complicated situations. Social sin in the legal sciences consists in failing to work out logicially a complicated set of rules." 7
The defects inherent in Bork's economic logic become more evident when we take a closer look at his seemingly monolithic antitrust goal of maximizing consumer welfare. According to Bork, this
is the sole aim embodied in the Sherman Act. Seeking to free us
from "a falsely imagined past,""i he ignores the difficulties inherent
in reducing congressional intent in the antitrust area to so simple a
proposition. 9 The Supreme Court has occasionally utilized an approach similar to Bork's, finding Congress' major goal to have been
the maintenance of competition." The Justices' arguments are more
persuasive than Bork's, however, and his neglect of the maintenance
of competition gives rise to a badly distorted perspective.2 For
example, he suggests that competition "may be read as ...a term of
art . . .designating any state of affairs in which consumer welfare
cannot be increased . . .through judicial decree."22 This is an unduly
narrow and legalistic fusion of two complex concepts, particularly in
light of the high levels of incompetence Bork finds reflected in
judicial decrees.
Other definitions are piled on top of these rather indigestible
bits of information. Consumer welfare is found to be wholly
synonymous with efficiency and "is merely another term for the
180-85, 226-69
(1955); Letwin, Congress and the Sherman Antitrust Law, 23 U. CHI. L. REV. 221
(1956). There is nothing in the record which unequivocally contradicts Bork's position,
nor is there much support for his tenuous analysis.
20. E.g., United States v. Philadelphia National Bank, 374 U.S. 321, 338 (1963);
Northern Pac. R.R. v. United States, 356 U.S. 1,4 (1958); Standard Oil Co. of N.J. v.
United States, 221 U.S. 1 (1911).
21. See, e.g., note 24, infra.
22. R. BORK, supra note 1, at 61. This contention only makes sense if it is
treated as a gross oversimplification of the economics theory of workable competition,
http://scholar.valpo.edu/vulr/vol13/iss2/7
Brietzke: Robert Bork, The Antitrust Paradox: A Policy at War with Itself
1979]
ANTITRUST PARADOX
wealth of the nation."2 Efficiency is then defined in a fairly conventional fashion but applied in some fairly suspect ways, while Bork's
concept of wealth remains decidedly murky. This is not surprising:
most contemporary economists avoid using the notion of wealth
because of its emotive imprecision. These facile equationspresumably, some of Bork's "simple ideas of economics" - give rise
to numerous contradictions throughout the book.24
Maximizing consumer welfare is, of course, a goal commonly
assigned to competitive price systems by economists. Congress and
the courts are, however, charged by the Constitution and processes
of judicial review with maintaining and advancing a broader
goal-the general welfare. Differences between these types of
welfare are significant. For example, a contemporary
microeconomics text asserts that, while individuals can determine
their own preferences and canons of happiness, society cannot:
"[Tihe terms 'public' and 'society' are a bit too broad and vague to
have much scientific meaning in rational discourse."2 Constitutional
law and politics are based on totally different sets of premises, and
an economic atomism could never form the basis for political inaction in the area of antitrust or elsewhere.2" While neoclassical
microeconomics is unable to distinguish between types of consumers
and consumption, Congress has proved abundantly capable of doing
so. The whole is greater than the sum of those parts explored
through the economics of industrial organization- individuals, firms
and industries-and the paucity of sensible policy prescriptions offered by those economists and philosophers who attempt to link the
23. Id. at 7. See also id. at 90.
24. E.g., "The integration of economic activities, which is indispensible to productive efficiency, always involves the implicit elimination of ... competition. We...
should encourage it... because the integration creates wealth for the community." Id.
at 28; see id. at 98 and the text accompanying notes 66-67, infra. Even if efficiency and
wealth are synonymous with consumer welfare, how can they justify the elimination of
another synonym, competition? Bork also argues that there should be a time limit
within which a merger can be challenged because of "the question of equity, of settled
expectation." Id. at 223. What does this "equity" have to do with his universal goal of
consumer welfare? While he is probably making a valid point, Bork should not plead
the equities while execrating others for introducing their equitable notions into what
should, in his view, be a "pure" antitrust analysis. See also the text accompanying
notes 29-32, infra.
25. R. MILLER, INTERMEDIATE MICROECONoMICs 6 (1978).
26. If the individual's interest is posited as sovereign, taking adequate account of group, public and state interests becomes impossible, as does the technique of
social engineering (for want of a better term). Roscoe Pound's confused thinking
dominates American legal thought on this topic, rendering it incapable of a reasoned
response to Bork's arguments which would command a consensus.
410
[Vol. 13
http://scholar.valpo.edu/vulr/vol13/iss2/7
Brietzke: Robert Bork, The Antitrust Paradox: A Policy at War with Itself
ANTITRUST PARADOX
19791
vitality for granted while applying contemporary economic analyses
to a simpler and less alloyed laissez faire than is found in the United
States today."0 Inevitably, the maintenance of competition gets
neglected in the course of his exposition. His legal arguments
harken back to when the earliest antitrust cases were decided, prior
to the accretion of a concentrated corporate power. He seeks to
return us to a preregulatory Arcadia which bears little resemblance
to the realities chronicled by Frank Norris and Upton Sinclair and
which ignores the withering of Adam Smith's Invisible Hand which
has occurred in the interim."'
The justifications Bork offers for his heavy emphasis on productive efficiency are that "it necessarily benefits consumers by
lowering the costs of goods and services or by increasing the value
of the product or service offered," and that the Supreme Court's
failure to take adequate account of productive efficiency "has skewed
legal doctrine disastrously." 2 This is all well and good, save that the
Supreme Court almost invariably favors efficiency when faced
squarely with a choice between it and a competing policy.M Further,
Bork's concept of efficiency relies heavily on the suspect assumption
of almost limitless economies of scale. While the Chicago School
typically regards available scale economies as negligible beyond
very small scales, Bork, in his only significant departure from their
postulates, adopts the assumption of the British School that large
scale economies exist, especially within large multiplant firms. This
theoretical, almost theological, dispute cannot be resolved until problems inherent in calculating long run average cost curves are overcome; few practical generalizations can be made at this stage." The
30. E.g., id at 394: "Price discrimination is, on balance, probably better for
consumers than any rule enforcing nondiscrimination, and ... law cannot satisfactorily
deal with the phenomenon in any event." While this assertion is supported by some interesting arguments, and while the law is far from satisfactory in this area, the extent
of consumer benefit must surely depend on the particular discriminator's market
power and the purposes for which it is exercised. See i at 415; note 31, infra. For
Bork's Economic Darwinism, see text accompanying note 59, infra.
31. 1& at 425. "The regime of capitalism brings with it not merely unexampled economic performance and a social and cultural atomosphere that stresses the
worth of the individual but, because of the bourgeois class it creates, trains, and raises
to power, the possibility of stable, liberal, and democratic government."
32. Id at 7.
33. P. AREEDA & D. TURNER, 1 ANTITRUST LAW 9 (1978). From this perspective, the real dispute concerns whether courts regularly destroy efficiencies without
realizing it; it is clearly not the conscious process Bork makes it out to be.
34. See D. DEWEY, MONOPOLY IN ECONOMICS AND LAW 30-41 (1951); J. KOCH, IN.
DUSTRIAL ORGANIZATION AND PRICES 101 (1974).
412
[Vol.13
35.
See
F.
HIRSCH,
supra note
http://scholar.valpo.edu/vulr/vol13/iss2/7
Brietzke: Robert Bork, The Antitrust Paradox: A Policy at War with Itself
ANTITRUST PARADOX
19791
41.
42.
43.
44.
45.
Id. at 318.
Id. at 274, 295-97, 373.
R. DAHL & C. LINDBLOOM, POLITICS, ECONOMICS AND WELFARE 415 (1976).
F. HIRSCH, supra note 28, at 82-83.
[Vol. 13
Id.at 61.
R. BORK, supra note 1, at 143. He criticizes this "prophylactic rule,"
a fortuitious double entendre: it may be annoying and inconvenient, but it
be there if it is needed. See id
R. BORK, supra note 1, at 379.
Id. at 365-66, 380-81. For an example of a more sensible judicial approach,
v. Chicken Delight, Inc., 448 F.2d 43 (9th Cir. 1971), cerL denied, 405 U.S.
http://scholar.valpo.edu/vulr/vol13/iss2/7
Brietzke: Robert Bork, The Antitrust Paradox: A Policy at War with Itself
ANTITRUST PARADOX
1979]
United States v. Joint Traffic Ass'n, 171 U.S. 505, 567-68 (1898). See R..
R.
BORK,
[Vol.13
http://scholar.valpo.edu/vulr/vol13/iss2/7
Brietzke: Robert Bork, The Antitrust Paradox: A Policy at War with Itself
19791
ANTITRUST PARADOX
418
[Vol. 13
See M. EDELMAN, THE SYMBOLIC USES OF POLITICS 1, 14, 49, 114 (1964).
R. DAHL & C. LINDBLOOM, supra note 44, at 482.
http://scholar.valpo.edu/vulr/vol13/iss2/7
Brietzke: Robert Bork, The Antitrust Paradox: A Policy at War with Itself
19791
ANTITRUST PARADOX
218, 223 (E. Mason ed. 1970); L. FRIEDMAN, supra note 10, at 180-81.
[Vol. 13
70.
structures or procedures" which are endowed with the prestige of "exemplariness and
obligatoriness." L. FRIEDMAN, supra note 10, at 112.
73. See, e.g., note 31, supra.
http://scholar.valpo.edu/vulr/vol13/iss2/7
Brietzke: Robert Bork, The Antitrust Paradox: A Policy at War with Itself
19791
ANTITRUST PARADOX
74. Brewster, The Corporation and Economic Federalism, in THE CORPORATION IN MODERN SOCIETY 72, 73 (E. Mason ed. 1970). See A. BERLE, JR., ECONOMIC
POWER AND THE FREE SOCIETY 16 (1958); J. HURST supra note 10, at 242-45. Hurst
argues that the regulation of labor relations, product safety, advertising and finance
show that the public is unprepared to accept corporate management as selflegitimizing.
75. See R. DAHL & C. LINDBLOOM, supra note 44, at 480; J. HURST, supra note
10, at 45, 68-69, 209.
76. R. BORK, supra note 1, at 417.
*Associate Professor of Law, Valparaiso University.