Castel, Pierre-Henri. The Coming Evil
Castel, Pierre-Henri. The Coming Evil
Castel, Pierre-Henri. The Coming Evil
future. In any case, the only change we feel (before the nuclear
holocaust) is a change in the moral circumambient ether of our
everyday life. What the perspective of an ongoing apocalyptic
process implies is quite distinct: the Times of the End are a
period of unraveling material disasters piling one upon the
others (even though they may be, at the beginning, hard to
spot), all of them foreshadowing what the End will be made of.
example, the idea that between us and the last man, there will
be no more time than between us and, say, Christopher
Columbus ). It is easy to argue that consenting to our imminent
extinction would likely lead to an unprecedented outburst of
hopeless and cynical egoism, to an even more ferocious
overexploitation of all our remaining resources, and, probably,
to destructive wars waged only to postpone for a few years our
inevitable end. Actually, thinking this way amounts to a selffulfilling prophecy. But I doubt that it would be the only moral
option available. We readily foresee the Evil which comes. But
what about the good? Could the Times of the End help us to
reconsider what is good?
2
For, I do not think that we should worry about the End as such.
Were it to come, in a thousand years or in a couple of centuries,
by definition, most of the critical issues raised by this new dry
and flat apocalypse (an Apocalypse without Kingdom) would
have already been solved: there would be very few survivors,
and they would be left with very few to save. We should, then,
focus on the period before the one starting just now, and
extending to this crucial point in future history at which a more
self-conscious mankind will see in full light when and how it will
end, as clear as a fixed day on a timetable. For, in this period,
worries about the End will increasingly confer an extraordinary
intensity to the last men' s choices (the End itself being not a
choice, but the end of choice). A highly plausible option is the
following: we will witness an unbounded, a wild unleashing of
But what a modern reader of Sade could learn from the French
moralist is that people would not be long to realize that the
impending end of everything of value (life, moral virtues, love,
meaningful endeavors, etc.) can become, by a bizarre twist, the
last form of enjoyment available to us. Instead of passively
witnessing the disappearance of all what is good, generation
after generation, and then, individuals after individuals, why
not turn this sad process into a lustful, pervert, and ultimate
frenzy of self-destruction? Why not turn all that will prove to be
only worse and worse into radiant Evil? The closer the End, the
more passionate humanity would resort to the most atrocious,
the most excessive, the most demented ways to secure for the
last Sad Few the very last means to last even a few more
years... of vicious (self-)destruction. A Sadean moralist would
hold that the gist and the glamour of the Times of the End will
certainly not consist in cautiously securing the means of a
delayed ending, but in the lust attached to stealing them, and to
murder their rightful owners. Moral vices, cruelty ranking first,
and abuse would no longer be the mere side-effects of universal
6
the (indirect) hope that it will not happen is not enough. Thus,
against Jonas, the better agent must not recoil from thinking
the suicide of mankind as a tragedy in progress, so to speak.
Second, this agent will have to find the ways and means to
obtain a form of both moral and affective satisfaction in
choosing the path of good, even though it will leave no trace to
remember, nor set any example for future generations.
In the final phase of this essay, I will insist, first, on the fact
that, notwithstanding what apocalyptic philosophers have
repeatedly stated, we are perfectly able to face the eventuality
of our collective extinction (as the whole of mankind) without
any moral panic that is, without necessarily losing our
dignity, or forfeiting our reason, even though it is obviously a
deeply emotional issue.
the evildoers will do (or already do) with the idea that there is
no meaningful future, that we may turn the tables, and give
another interpretation of what is really good (in a good with no
tomorrow). The third and last paradox is a bullet against
philosophers which might ricochet and wound me as well. It is a
plea for ordinary people, or, rather, a plea for a form of
rationality which may well work undetected under the cloak of
the so-called moral insensitivity or epistemic idiocy of our
contemporaries. Actually, it seems there two options, and, of
course, they are not mutually exclusive. Either a good number
of our contemporaries are (unconscious, or self-conscious and
hidden) evildoers, well aware of our future fate, and taking
advantage as long as they still can of a situation not yet so
disastrous at the expense of the generations to come.
Unfortunately, I think that we should worry very much about
this possibility, because, if the End is both imminent and
certain, as I hold it to be, it may lead to radically new excesses,
leaving far behind us the most outrageous manifestations of
human Evil that we have long witnessed. Or, at the other end of
a spectrum where shades likely blend smoothly into each
others, our contemporaries are people who do not see why they
should embrace for their own sake any apocalyptic anxiety, but,
rather, they just focus on life-asserting behaviors without
worrying about the day after. It might be, then, that ordinary
folk may know best; they act in a very reasonable way, to the
extent that it should bring about a serious reconsideration of
what we deem good, in the Times of the End. And philosophers,
instead of banging their heads against the non-existent
conundrum of common people' s seeming indifference to
eschatological stakes, would rather learn from them.
1K. Jaspers, The Atom Bomb and the Future of Man, The University of Chicago Press,
1963, being the English trans. of Die Atombombe und die Zukunft des Menschen.
Politische Bewusstsein in unserer Zeit; Piper Verlag, Mnchen, 1956; G.
Anders, Endzeit und Zeitenende: Gedanken ber die atomare Situation, Beck
Verlag, Mnchen, 1972; H. Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility. In search of an
Ethics for the Technological Age, The University of Chicago Press, 1985, being the
English trans. of Die Prinzip Veranwortung: Versuch einer Ethik fr die
technologische Zivilisation, Insel Verlag, Frankfurt am Main, 1972.
2In the famous last page of the Naked Man (1971, English transl. by J. and D.
Weightman, 1981, p.693), C. Lvi-Strauss reminds us that our species, and our
planet, and the solar system, and our galaxy, are all to disappear in the future,
leaving nothing behind to remember, and to nobody. But I am not speaking of
stellar eons, which are, by definition, impervious to the human quest for its own
meaning.
3J. Schell, The Fate of the Earth, and The Abolition (First edited by Knopf, 1982 and
1984), Stanford University Press, 2000.
4For a good reason, by itself, cannot entail (in the sense of trigger) any action. No
action will ever follow from the premises of a practical syllogism the way a logical
conclusion follows from the premises of a theoretical one.
5We may be witnessing a conceptual shift, in this regard. In the 2000s, people were
deemed unconscious about the actual possibility of a catastrophic termination of
humanity. They were regarded as non-believers, or not properly informed.
Nowadays, the problem seems rather that we do know, but we do nothing because
we are not anxious about what is going on the way we should. We are no longer
unconscious, we are insensitive.
6Think, for instance, of the Nazis, well aware that the war was lost (with all its
foreseeable consequences for the German people and its dignitaries), and, however,
stopping or diverting the trains headed to the frontline loaded with ammunitions in
order to let the convoys of Hungarian Jews reach Auschwitz in time.
7There is irony, here, when one thinks that Jonas was a scholar well versed in
gnosticism. One of the oddest (though marginal) expressions of this philosophy is
that men, if the prophecy of Apocalypse is true, should not refrain from their evil
deeds. On the contrary, the worse they sin, the quicker the End of Times, and the
advent of the Kingdom. Of course, sinners would be damned. But all the others
would enjoy a prompt salvation. Now, if we are heading towards an Apocalypse
without Kingdom, what are we at risk to lose, if we sin without restraint?
8Kant, Critique of Practical Reason and Other Works on the Theory of Ethics, Abbott' s
translation, Longmans, Green and Co, London, 1898, p.118.
9In Nietzsche Briefwechsel. Kritische Gesamtausgabe, G. Colli & M. Montinari (eds.),
De Gruyter, Mnchen-Berlin-New York, 1975, vol. II, 1, p. 204.
10P. Klossowski, Nietzsche and the Vicious Circle, English transl. by D.W.Smith, The
University of Chicago Press, 1997.
11The most striking distinction between the erotic life of antiquity and our own no
doubt lies in the fact that the ancients laid the stress upon the instinct itself,
whereas we emphasize its object. The ancients glorified the instinct and were
prepared on its account to honour even an inferior object; while we despise the
instinctual activity in itself, and find excuses for it only in the merits of the object.
S. Freud, Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality, SE VII, p.1476.