Political Participation and Three Theories of Democracy: A Research Inventory and Agenda
Political Participation and Three Theories of Democracy: A Research Inventory and Agenda
Political Participation and Three Theories of Democracy: A Research Inventory and Agenda
JAN TEORELL
Lund Unversity, Sweden
Abstract. This article proposes an agenda for political participation research aimed at
providing empirical answers to questions derived from normative political theory. Based on
a threefold distinction between responsive, participatory and deliberative models of democ-
racy, the article first distinguishes three conceptions of political participation: as influencing
attempts, as direct decision making, and as political discussion. Second, it is argued that each
of the three models is associated with different desired consequences of political participa-
tion: equal protection of interests, self-development and subjective legitimacy. Third, a pro-
cedural standard is identified from which to evaluate the mechanism generating the three
types of participation. By analogy with theories of distributive justice, this mechanism should
be sensitive to incentives but insensitive to resources. The empirical questions thus implied
are finally drawn together into an integrated agenda for future participation studies.
The study of mass political participation has grown into one of the most
important subfields of political science. Originating in the early American
election studies of the 1950s, the proliferation of primarily survey-based par-
ticipation studies has reached a global scale in the last decade (see, e.g., Brady
1999; Dalton 2000; Norris 2002). Although usually inspired by normative con-
cerns, however, the field remains surprisingly loosely coupled to normative
theories of democracy. The classic reference is a simplistic notion of partici-
patory democrats urging more participation, as opposed to realist demo-
crats, who allegedly take no interest in levels of participation at all (see, e.g.,
Parry et al. 1992: 45; Norris 2002: 5). Others, like Verba and Nie (1972) in
their seminal study of participation in America, raise both normative and
empirical questions at the outset, but in the end exclusively deal with the
empirical ones leaving the suggested connection to normative theory unex-
plored. Verba et al. (1995) no doubt improved upon earlier studies by explic-
itly appealing to a normative view of the participatory process as undistorted
representation. As pointed out by critics, however, this view excludes other
important notions within democratic theory (Mansbridge 1997).
In this article, I argue there is more to the connection between normative
theory and empirical research on political participation than these examples
suggest. I shall thus be addressing the more general tendency that normative
2006 The Author(s)
Journal compilation 2006 (European Consortium for Political Research)
Published by Blackwell Publishing Ltd., 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford, OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden,
MA 02148, USA
788 jan teorell
and positive theories of democracy grow out of literatures that proceed, for
the most part, on separate tracks, largely uninformed by one another (Shapiro
2002: 235). The purpose, simply put, is to tighten the strings connecting the two
literatures on one specific theme: political participation. To this end, I explore
the existing field of empirical participation research in the light of a new
theoretical framework. Normative democratic theory plays a double role in
this framework: it suggests what questions are important to ask and it provides
the standards needed to evaluate the empirical findings. By identifying the
blind spots left by participation research in the past, I propose an agenda for
how it should be conducted in the future. Although methodological issues will
be noted in passing, I concentrate on the questions that need be answered.
In the normative realm, I focus on three models of democracy: responsive,
participatory and deliberative. While the varieties of modern democratic
theory no doubt go beyond this simple threefold division (see, e.g., Held 1987),
my argument aims to show it fruitful enough to balance the cost of generality.
The discussion is organized into three different themes: the conceptualization,
the causes and the consequences of political participation. I conclude with a
summary of the empirical research agenda suggested and a discussion of
possible reversed feedback from empirical results to normative theory.
What types of human activity fall under the category political participation?
I shall argue that the answer to this conceptual question depends on which
normative model of democracy to which one adheres. According to some
extreme elitist versions of democratic theory, such as Schumpeter (1942) and
Sartori (1987), the role of citizens is limited to that of voting their leaders out
of office. These theorists adhere to what Riker (1982) termed a liberal model
of democracy, a view with three defining constituents: citizens only hold mean-
ingful preferences over the personnel of government; these preferences are
only expressed indirectly through a system of representation; and are consid-
ered to be fixed and exogenous to the democratic process itself. With such a
thin conceptualization of participation, little is left for empirical investigation.
As we shall see, however, by altering each of the three conditions in turn, three
models of democracy ensue with conceptions of political participation richer in
empirical content.
Consider the definition of political participation given by Verba and Nie (1972:
2): Political participation refers to those activities by private citizens
2006 The Author(s)
Journal compilation 2006 (European Consortium for Political Research)
political participation and democracy 789
process (Sartori 1987: 113). This is also the meaning assigned to the word by
adherents of the so-called participatory model of democracy (Pateman 1970:
6771). Political participation, according to Gould (1988: 259), for example, is
characterized by direct and immediate involvement in the process of decision
making by the individuals concerned. Thus, in this process, the authority of the
individuals is not delegated to some representative but is exercised directly by
them. Or, in Barbers (1984: 151) words: [P]olitics in the participatory
mode . . . is self-government by citizens rather than representative govern-
ment. In contrast to seeing participation as an attempt to influence decision
makers, then, what participatory democrats have in mind is participation in
direct decision making (Nagel 1987: 19). However, this definition should not be
interpreted as an argument to abolish all representative institutions. What
participatory democrats suggest is instead to widen the opportunities for direct
participation by providing new arenas outside the traditional representative
system, mostly in small-scale settings. In her classic defence of the participatory
model Pateman (1970) almost exclusively deals with decision making in the
workplace, whereas Gould (1988: 260) speaks of local political institutions that
have the power to decide local issues. Thus, the point is to make citizens more
involved in solving community problems, even if this take place within a larger
framework of a representative democracy.
at the decisions taken but at the formation of opinion which precedes deci-
sions. By defining participation within the deliberative model as political
discussion instead of deliberation, I believe both these contested issues can
be resolved (for a related argument, see Conover et al. 2002: 2325). As
argued by Fearon (1998: 63), while it makes sense to say, I deliberated on
the matter, it does not to say, I discussed the matter with myself. Since to
participate is to engage in some kind of collective endeavour, defining delib-
eration as discussion is more adequate as a concept of participation. More-
over, if we define deliberation as political discussion (i.e., as a process of
opinion formation rather than a procedure for decision making), we can
avoid blurring the line separating deliberative and participatory models of
democracy. This blurring partly stems from the fact that most forms of direct
decision making provide opportunities to take part in political discussions.2
The point in defining deliberation as political discussion is that discussions
aimed at forming opinions may occur even if no collective decision is to be
reached.
In sum, participation according to the responsive model is defined as an
attempt to influence those who have a say in government. According to par-
ticipatory democrats, by contrast, participation is to have a say in government
oneself. The deliberative model, finally, defines participation as a way of
finding out what to say. By defining participation in these three ways, a first
set of empirical questions drawn from democratic theory ensues. These ques-
tions are simply related to the level or amount of participation in a given
democratic polity. The more participation of each type that can be found, the
more satisfactory the result when evaluated from any of the three normative
perspectives. In order to avoid the perennial question of what level of par-
ticipation should then count as satisfactory, at least three comparative
yardsticks could be applied: comparing the amount of different types of par-
ticipation in the same polity, and comparing the amount of the same type of
participation in either different polities at the same time or in the same polity
over time.
The three models of democracy, however, are not only probably not even
primarily interested in the levels or amount of participation. We can derive
a further set of empirical questions by interpreting each of the three models as
a best result theory of democracy. A best result theory holds that fair terms
of political participation are those that are likely to produce the most desirable
result (Beitz 1989: 20). This view of democratic theory is outcome-oriented. It
2006 The Author(s)
Journal compilation 2006 (European Consortium for Political Research)
792 jan teorell
deal with those priorities, or in successfully dealing with those priorities. For
reasons of data accessibility, Verba and Nie relied on the first three meanings
of responsiveness mentioned. In the only other study of the impact of partici-
pation known to me, responsiveness in the second sense was measured (Parry
et al. 1992: Chapter 17). From the perspective of normative democratic theory,
however, I would argue that the fourth meaning is what really matters. True,
the first three meanings may be regarded as important in some cases perhaps
even necessary conditions required for bringing about responsiveness in the
latter respect. All things considered, however, a democratic system could
hardly be considered responsive if it never successfully deals with the priorities
of its citizens.
In sum, the responsive model of democracy puts two questions on our
proposed research agenda. The first concerns the representativeness to the
general public of those who engage in influencing attempts. The second
relates to the impact of those influencing attempts on the actions taken by the
government or other institutions in society. In terms of research design,
answers to these questions would require data on preferences, needs and
activity at the level of individual citizens, supplemented with elite level data
from elected representatives and other key decision makers. Since respon-
siveness is an aggregate-level phenomenon, it must then be measured either
across time within the same democratic system, or simultaneously across
several systems. This would allow the necessary evaluation of the entire
linkage chain running from citizens needs and preferences, over preferences
expressed through participation, to preferences perceived, acted upon and
dealt with by the elites.
Apart from their focus on direct decision making, the distinguishing feature of
participatory democrats is their argument that this kind of participation fosters
desirable personal and social qualities in democratic citizens (Dahl 1989: 92;
Warren 1992: 9, 11). According to Kaufman (1960), credited with being the one
who first coined the term participatory democracy, citizen participation is
crucial because it contributes to the development of human powers of
thought, feeling and action. Similarly, Pateman (1970: 42) argues that: One
might characterize the participatory model as one where maximum input
(participation) is required and where output includes not just policies (deci-
sions) but also the development of the social and political capacities of each
individual, so that there is feedback from output to input. Thus, self-
realization or self-development is the primary consequentialist criterion prof-
fered by participatory democrats (Macpherson 1977: 2; Gould 1988: 4042,
2006 The Author(s)
Journal compilation 2006 (European Consortium for Political Research)
political participation and democracy 795
4651, 287). The exact definitions of the concept of self-development vary, but
they all share an idea of a not fully realized potential in the human self that
could be transformed or even perfected through political participation
(Warren 1992).
Thus, there is again a straightforward causal proposition involved that is
derived from democratic theory. Does participation in direct decision making
foster self-development? Following Pateman (1970: Chapter 3), most
research in this regard has focused on the effects of participation on the
sense of political efficacy. However, some of the tests that have been per-
formed look at the effects of political participation defined as influencing
attempts (Finkel 1985, 1987; Stenner-Day & Fischle 1992). This misses the
point of the participatory argument. What is needed, of course, is an empirical
assessment of the alleged effects of direct decision making. In this respect,
there is some evidence that curbs the hopes of participatory democrats, but,
most importantly, this evidence is scarce (Sniderman 1975; Pedersen 1982). To
remedy this situation, experimental and case study research would most
likely be preferable in the future (Mansbridge 1997: 424; cf. Pedersen 1982:
558569). The reason is that we are dealing with propositions on the potential
nature of certain relationships. Participatory democrats argue that if oppor-
tunities for participation in direct decision making were widespread at the
workplace, in the neighborhood, in the local community or elsewhere then
self-development would ensue. It could be argued, however, that no demo-
cratic country in the world provides such widespread opportunities to the
population at large or at least that the cross-country variation is not large
enough to allow meaningful impact assessment. Controlled experiments or
well-designed case studies of participatory initiatives at the local or organi-
zational level, by contrast, could enable researchers to explore whether par-
ticipation in direct decision making really pays the psychological dividends
that participatory theorists claim.
Let us now turn to the other side of participation: the question of its causes.
Most empirical approaches to political participation have sought to explain
why some people engage in politics whereas others do not. The underlying
standard from which these explanatory models are assessed is their overall
predictive performance (see, e.g., Leighley 1995; Whiteley 1995). Seen from the
viewpoint of positive science, this is a perfectly justified way of proceeding;
however, if we are to take normative democratic theory as our point of depar-
ture, the perspective changes. In this section I shall argue that instead of
seeking to attain maximum overall explanatory power in our assessment of
what causes participation, we should try to ascertain whether certain specific
causes are supported by empirical evidence. More precisely, the evaluative
standard I shall propose involves determining whether political participation is
primarily driven by incentives or resources.
This view follows from a procedural interpretation of our three models of
democracy, rather than the best result version adhered to in the last section.
We are now no longer interested in the outcome of participation. What the
2006 The Author(s)
Journal compilation 2006 (European Consortium for Political Research)
798 jan teorell
procedural view entails is instead the idea that the terms of participation in
democratic procedures should themselves be fair (Beitz 1989: 22; emphasis
added). To identify the conditions under which the terms of participation can
be regarded as fair, we must make a critical distinction between opportunity
and realization; or, in Sens (1992) words, between the actual achievement
and the freedom to achieve. Achievement is concerned with what we
manage to accomplish, and freedom with the real opportunity that we have to
accomplish what we value. The two need not be congruent (Sen 1992: 31). In
other words, one could picture a situation where the rates of participation
were unequally distributed, and yet there were equal opportunities to par-
ticipate. This would be the case, for example, if those who did not participate
remained passive out of a free choice and not as a consequence of structural
constraints. Given the same incentives, they could have chosen to act just as
easily as the participants did; thus, if some citizens do not participate because
they freely choose not to be active . . . then participatory inequalities do not
compromise democracy (Verba et al. 1995: 2627).
By analogy with theories of justice, we could think of the causes that enable
citizens to participate as a distributive mechanism an allocation scheme
according to which some are entitled to the social goods called participation,
while others are not. What fairness in the terms of participation then requires
is a constraint on the design of this distributive mechanism (Beitz 1989: 17).
Following Dworkin (1981: 311), we could say that ideally the mechanism
generating political participation should be endowment-insensitive but
ambition-sensitive that is, whether people end up as participants or not
should depend on their ambitions (in the broad sense of goals and projects
about life), but should not depend on their natural and social endowments (the
circumstances in which they pursue their ambitions) (Kymlicka 1990: 75).
Although I prefer the terms resources instead of endowments and incen-
tives instead of ambition, this means we have two rival explanations for
political participation to assess. Are resources or incentives the prime mover?
What follows from this, then, is another normative standard from which to
evaluate the empirical world of political participation. This time the standard
is common to all three models of democracy.What differs between them is only
what kind of participation is being explained: influencing attempts, direct
decision making or political discussion. I will now discuss the two generic types
of causes resources and incentives in turn.
Broadly speaking, resources come in three forms: physical, human and social
capital (Coleman 1990: 304). Physical capital covers all material assets
2006 The Author(s)
Journal compilation 2006 (European Consortium for Political Research)
political participation and democracy 799
Apart from having ample access to physical, human and social capital, people
must have a desire to take part. They must be both willing and able. More
formally, we can think of resources as the first of two successive filtering
operations. Among the full set of actions available to an individual, resources
work as a constraint that delimits a smaller set of feasible actions. Within this
smaller set, the second filter determines which action will actually be carried
out. This latter role is the one played by incentives (Elster 1989: 1314).
The literature on incentives for political action usually takes as its starting
point the provocative claim by Olson (1965) that rational actors should not
engage in activities oriented towards a common good. Since one could reap the
benefits of these general incentives even if others provide them, each individual
has a rational motive to abstain. The fact that people do engage in collective
endeavours must instead be explained with reference to selective incentives
that is, benefits that only accrue from the act of actually contributing to the
outcome oneself (Olson 1965: 51).
Whereas Olson was almost exclusively concerned with material benefits, a
range of other more psychic and less tangible selective rewards to political
participation have been suggested over the years (see, e.g., Rosenstone &
Hansen 1993: 1620; Verba et al. 1995: Chapter 4; Whiteley 1995; Finkel &
Muller 1998). One such set of factors may be termed process incentives:
people may participate out of sheer excitement, regardless of what outcomes
are at stake. A related selective reward is often called expressive incentives:
people may participate simply in order to express their support or reaffirm
their identity (Calvert 2002). Yet another set of selective incentives are
related to social norms (Elster 1989: Chapter 12; Coleman 1990: Chapters
1011). Both an internalized sense of duty to the wider community and norms
supported by the threat of social sanctions may engender citizen participation
(Knack 1992). While these selective incentives have primarily been developed
for explanatory models of participation defined as influencing attempts, they
easily translate to the other types of political participation as well. If people
were only to engage in direct decision making or join political discussion for
the pursuit of collective goals, then again any single individual seen in isola-
tion would be better off remaining inactive. Selective incentives such as
2006 The Author(s)
Journal compilation 2006 (European Consortium for Political Research)
political participation and democracy 801
Some three decades ago Robert Salisbury (1975: 337) noted that: There are so
many good questions arising under the heading of political participation that
it would be foolish even to attempt a summary listing. Nevertheless, I shall
make such an attempt. In Figure 1, I summarize the theoretical framework
underlying this article, bringing together the empirical research questions
derived from all three normative models of democracy. In the central box, the
three conceptions of participation are located, bringing descriptive questions
pertaining to the distribution of political participation to the fore. Arrows then
signify the causal relationships that need to be assessed in order to evaluate the
state of political participation in a given collective entity abiding to democratic
principles. These arrows are either running to or from political participation
(capturing either its causes or its effects).
Common to all three models, when given a procedural interpretation, is
their definition of fairness in the terms of participation. Irrespective of whether
participation as influencing attempts, direct decision making or political dis-
cussion is being considered, incentives should be the causal force, not
Resources
Incentives
Political discussion Subjective legitimacy
resources. Even if this was found to be the case in terms of direct effects on
participation, however, the possibility that resources have an indirect effect
must be taken into consideration, with incentives merely acting as an inter-
vening variable. For this reason, the possibility of a reciprocal relationship
between resources and incentives has been indicated. In a similar vein, the
causal effect running from resources and incentives to participation must be
disentangled from the effect running in the opposite direction.
In terms of the responsive model of democracy, the desired effect of politi-
cal participation is equal protection of interests. Individual needs and prefer-
ences should be translated into collectively binding decisions by means of
responsiveness to the preferences and needs expressed through participation.
These preferences and needs, moreover, should give equal weight to the inter-
est of each citizen. In contrast to all other effects indicated in the model, this is
an aggregate level proposition. Both the participatory and the deliberative
models primarily imply individuallevel effects of participation. In the case of
participatory democracy, what is required is a transformation of the personal
qualities of the human being, or self-development. Deliberative democrats, in
turn, are ultimately concerned with subjective legitimacy. They argue that only
when arguments from each contending side has been sifted through political
discussion will the outcomes of democratic decision making be morally accept-
able to the individual.
Participation studies in the past have clearly covered certain areas high-
lighted in Figure 1 better than others. In conceptual terms, political participa-
tion defined as influencing attempts have dominated the field. With respect to
consequences, the impact on equal protection of interest has attracted greater
attention than the individual-level effects on self-development and subjective
legitimacy, although, as was noted above, much work remains when it comes to
gauging the actual impact of influencing attempts on the behaviour of state
agents. By and large, the responsive model of democracy is better assessed
than both its participatory and deliberative counterparts. Both resources and
incentives loom largely in the empirical literature on the causes of participa-
tion (again concentrated on influencing attempts), but their theoretical status
has never been assessed in terms of fairness as suggested here (see, however,
Teorell, Sum & Tobiasen, forthcoming, for an attempt in this direction). This is
another important blind spot that should be addressed in the future agenda for
participation research.
Thus far I have only discussed how the research agenda proposes assess-
ments of the three models of democracy independent of one another. I have
also been ignoring ways to incorporate more than one evaluative dimension in
a single study. By relaxing both these constraints, we can take a first step
toward an agenda for political participation studies that integrates both
2006 The Author(s)
Journal compilation 2006 (European Consortium for Political Research)
804 jan teorell
normative models and evaluative criteria. First, whereas Figure 1 outlines the
main effects of each participation form posited in the literature, there are a
number of interesting side effects to explore that involve core concepts from
the other normative models. Some of these have been mentioned in passing
above. Thus, for example, most studies of self-development have been looking
at the effects of influencing attempts rather than direct decision making. More-
over, political discussions may have other effects than increased subjective
legitimacy, such as more informed citizens, which is a form of self-
development. Political discussions may also lead to more structured prefer-
ence orderings, which may facilitate the aggregation of interests into
collectively binding decisions. In other words, participation in political discus-
sion may promote the equal protection of interests.
Other causal propositions, never referred to above, now also present them-
selves. Through Patemans (1970: 2427) close reading of Rousseau, for
example, two new potential effects of direct decision making may be devel-
oped. One is based on the idea that the interests of individual citizens can
never be protected indirectly by elected representatives. They can only be
secured through participation in direct decision making. Thus by, for example,
comparing the representativeness of elected bodies with local boards of citizen
self-management, one could assess a causal arrow running from participation
in direct decision making to the equal protection of interests.A second hypoth-
esis is that participation in direct decision making has a legitimizing effect. This
proposition is based on the idea that citizens are only willing to accept the
outcome of decision-making processes of which they have been a part.
Whereas these steps to integrate the separate components of Figure 1 have
been taken vertically, there are also horizontal linkages to explore. Most
importantly, explorations of the causes of participation could be incorporated
into the assessment of its effects. A promising first attempt in that direction
was undertaken by Verba et al. (1995: 465) in their study of how the process
by which people come to participate affects the substance of what is commu-
nicated through their participation. A similar strategy might be employed
with respect to the development of subjective legitimacy. The deliberative
model of democracy is generally considered to suffer from a scale problem in
that most ordinary citizens will never be able to take part in the political
discussions preceding large-scale decisions (Dryzek 2001; Parkinson 2003).
Yet perhaps it is not the actual participation in political discussions that
matters for subjective legitimacy, but the causes leading to that participation?
According to this view, the outcome of political decisions are accepted as
legitimate when opportunities for participation have been provided to those
who have incentives to take part, and not in relation to their access to
resources. It could be left open for investigation, moreover, whether it is the
2006 The Author(s)
Journal compilation 2006 (European Consortium for Political Research)
political participation and democracy 805
Acknowledgements
Notes
1. In effect, Verba and Nies conception is narrower than the more general definition of
political participation as action by ordinary citizens directed toward influencing some
political outcomes (Brady 1999: 737) since political outcomes may be determined by
other than government personnel (see, e.g., Norris 2002: 193194). However, Verba and
Nie (1972: 2) were aware of this limitation in that they saw governmental decisions only
as a close approximation of the more general process of political decision making (see
Teorell, Torcal & Montero, forthcoming).
2. Barber (1984), for example, is most commonly treated as a participatory democrat,
although he also pays attention to preference formation and the importance of citizen
dialogue.
References
Barber, B. (1984). Strong democracy: Participatory politics for a new age. Berkeley, CA:
University of California Press.
Barry, B. (1979). Is democracy special? In P. Laslett & J. Fishkin (eds), Philosophy, politics
and Society. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Beitz, C. (1989). Political equality: An essay in democratic theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Becker, G. (1964). Human capital. New York: National Bureau of Economic Research.
Bohman, J. & Rehg, W. (eds), (1997). Deliberative democracy: Essays on reason and politics.
Cambridge, MA: MIT press.
Finkel, S. & Muller, E. (1998). Rational choice and the dynamics of collective political action:
Evaluating alternative models with panel data. American Political Science Review 92(1):
3749.
Fishkin, J. (1991). Democracy and deliberation: New directions for democratic reform. New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Fishkin, J. (1995). The voice of the people: Public opinion and democracy. New Haven, CT:
Yale University Press.
Gould, C. (1988). Rethinking democracy: Freedom and social cooperation in politics,
economy and society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Granovetter, M. (1973). The strength of weak ties. American Journal of Sociology 78:
13601380.
Gutmann, A. & Thompson, D. (1996). Democracy and disagreement: Why moral conflict
cannot be avoided in politics, and what should be done about it. Cambridge, MA: Belknap
Press.
Habermas, J. (1996). Between facts and norms: Contributions to a discourse theory of law and
democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Held, D. (1987). Models of democracy. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Kaase, M. & Marsh, A. (1979). Political action: A theoretical perspective. In S. Barnes et al.
(eds), Political action: Mass participation in five Western democracies. Beverly Hills, CA:
Sage.
Kaufman, A. (1960). Human nature and participatory democracy. In C. Friedrich (ed.),
Responsibility: NOMOS III. New York: Liberal Arts Press.
Knack, S. (1992). Civic norms, social sanctions and voter turnout. Rationality & Society 4:
133156.
Knight, J. & Johnson, J. (1994). Aggregation and deliberation: On the possibility of demo-
cratic legitimacy. Political Theory 22: 277296.
Knoke, D. (1990). Networks of political action: Toward theory construction. Social Forces 68:
10411063.
Kymlicka, W. (1990). Contemporary political philosophy: An introduction. Oxford: Claren-
don Press.
Leighley, J. (1995). Attitudes, opportunities and incentives: A field essay on political partici-
pation. Political Research Quarterly 48: 181209.
Lin, N. (2001). Building a network theory of social capital. In N. Lin, K. Cook & R. Burt
(eds), Social capital: Theory and research. New York: Aldine de Gruyter.
Lukes, S. (1974). Power: A radical view. London: MacMillan.
Macpherson, C.B. (1977). The life and times of liberal democracy. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Manin, B. (1987). On legitimacy and political deliberation. Political Theory 15: 338368.
Manin, B., Przeworski, A. & Stokes, S. (1999). Introduction. In Democracy, accountability
and representation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mansbridge, J. (1997). Normative theory and Voice and Equality. American Political Science
Review 91(2): 423425.
Miller, D. (1983). The competitive model of democracy. In G. Duncan (ed.), Democratic
theory and practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Miller, D. (1992). Deliberative democracy and social choice. In D. Held (ed.), Prospects for
democracy: North, South, East, West. Oxford: Polity Press.
Mutz, D. (2002). Cross-cutting social networks: Testing democratic theory in practice.
American Political Science Review 96(1): 111126.
Verba, S., Nie, N. & Kim, J. (1978). Participation and political equality: A seven-nation
comparison. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.
Verba, S., Schlozman, K.L. & Brady, H. (1995). Voice and equality: Civic voluntarism in
American politics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Warren, M. (1992). Democratic theory and self-transformation. American Political Science
Review 86: 823.
Warren, M. (1996). Deliberative democracy and authority. American Political Science
Review 90: 4660.
Weatherford, S. (1992). Measuring political legitimacy. American Political Science Review 86:
149166.
Whiteley, P. (1995). Rational choice and political participation: Evaluating the debate.
Political Research Quarterly 48: 211233.
Address for correspondence: Jan Teorell, Department of Political Science, Lund University,
Box 52, S-22100 Lund, Sweden. Sweden. E-mail: jan.teorell@svet.lu.se