Plato and The Painters
Plato and The Painters
Plato and The Painters
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
https://www.jstor.org/stable/1087580?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Classical Association of Canada is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to Phoenix
This content downloaded from 146.95.253.17 on Wed, 12 Dec 2018 19:17:14 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
PLATO AND THE PAINTERS
NANCY DEMAND
This content downloaded from 146.95.253.17 on Wed, 12 Dec 2018 19:17:14 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
2 PHOENIX
This content downloaded from 146.95.253.17 on Wed, 12 Dec 2018 19:17:14 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
PLATO AND THE PAINTERS 3
This content downloaded from 146.95.253.17 on Wed, 12 Dec 2018 19:17:14 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
4 PHOENIX
brother Aristoph
dorus, the creato
Plato will soon co
In the Cratylus,
extended analogy
The analogy is ex
to the nature of
picture" (430e). F
truth:
These passages m
painting, yet the
about painting in
may call true pai
color and shape an
recurs in the Sop
also compares pic
the writer in the
pictures of false
Laws, this notion
its subject correc
have the arrange
proper respective
maintained in po
may occur under
and deliberate di
This content downloaded from 146.95.253.17 on Wed, 12 Dec 2018 19:17:14 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
PLATO AND THE PAINTERS 5
This content downloaded from 146.95.253.17 on Wed, 12 Dec 2018 19:17:14 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
6 PHOENIX
Ancient paintings were done with simple coloring, with no dappled mixtures (Aiylyaa
7roLKIXlav) of pigments, and with precisely drawn lines, all of which made these wo
very pleasing. Later paintings were less well drawn, but more elaborately worked
with the dappled effects of light and shade (MK^ re Kal 4wl rOLKLroXXM6/peva), and
their strength in the very preponderance of these methods. (de Isaeo iudic. 4)
It is just as in a shadow painting, in which the parts appear to be all one and the same
and alike to someone standing far away, but, to someone approaching, these same parts
appear to be many and varied, and, owing to the visual effects (0av'r&Arara) of con-
trasting colors, the colors appear changed and unlike themselves. (Prm. 165c-d)
This content downloaded from 146.95.253.17 on Wed, 12 Dec 2018 19:17:14 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
PLATO AND THE PAINTERS 7
This content downloaded from 146.95.253.17 on Wed, 12 Dec 2018 19:17:14 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
8 PHOENIX
was a posthumou
clear that exper
quarter of the fi
mentation. He m
name, and yet w
had any real aw
painters experim
demonstrates a c
see in these earli
nation which he
Zeuxis the innov
respect in Plato's
Yet, by the time
painter in full sw
29Rumpf (above, note 16) 10-21. Pfuhl also dates the discovery t
fifth century, although he would give credit for the discovery to
3) 676, but see also Pfuhl and Sch6ne (above, note 27).
This content downloaded from 146.95.253.17 on Wed, 12 Dec 2018 19:17:14 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
PLATO AND THE PAINTERS 9
(6) 6.488a: Socrates says, of his own use of imagery, "it is necessary to
combine many things... as painters do when they paint goat-stags and
such creatures."
(7) 6.500e-501c: The legislator's work is likened to the work of the
painter:
No city could ever prosper unless painters using a divine pattern drew its lines ....
Taking the city and the habits of men like a tablet, first they will wipe it clean .... And
then, after this, wouldn't they sketch out (Owroyp&daOae0a) the outline (aXija) of the
constitution? ... And then, in completing their work they would look frequently in both
directions, towards the just and noble and wise in nature (4ait), and again towards
what they were creating in men, mixing and blending the image of man (7"b -rVpeLKfXov)
from customs and usages .... And they would wipe away portions, and paint them
again, until they had rendered human ways as pleasing to the gods as possible ....
And that would be the noblest painting.
(8) 7.523b: A remark about perceptions which "call the mind to reflection
because the perception makes nothing clear," draws the response, "It's
clear that you mean things seen from a distance, and shadow painting."
(9) 7.529b: It is absurd to expect to find truth in diagrams drawn by a
Daedalus or by some other painter.
(10) 9.583b: "The pleasure of things other than intelligence is not com-
pletely real or pure, but is a kind of shadow painting."
(11) 9.586b: Such pleasures (those other than intelligence) are "phantoms
of true pleasure and shadow paintings, their colors taking their tone
(&roxpalvetv) from their placement beside each other so that each seems
intense."
This content downloaded from 146.95.253.17 on Wed, 12 Dec 2018 19:17:14 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
10 PHOENIX
toward painting ar
Plato's strongest an
in 4, 5, and 7 we fin
painter, for he is
painting as a craf
compares the fanta
imagery. One can
toward painting i
demn the painter
skiagraphia while o
pre-Phaedo dialog
or conventional (Po
morally acceptable
Two other points
between the poet/
of these passages d
poet to the painter
ate than that in Bo
poets are to be ba
the gods), and the
the painter who fa
on the other hand,
painter per se, rat
in Book 10 it is th
condemns him: it
Although the treat
necessary supplem
at the time when
two passages as ear
30Paul Friedlander, P
(New York 1967) 14-31
31R. E. Nettleship, Le
F. M. Cornford, The R
differed in Books 3 and
tion and in Book 10 h
or he may be operati
([above, note 30] 132-1
analogies with paintin
topic shows a degree o
judgment arbitrarily as
painter as vicious impo
he was expressing his
not carefully revise his
clear not only from his
I am convinced that co
intentioned scholarly e
This content downloaded from 146.95.253.17 on Wed, 12 Dec 2018 19:17:14 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
PLATO AND THE PAINTERS 11
32Nettleship (above, note 31) 47-66; Max Pohlenz, Aus Platos Werdezeit (Berlin
1913) 209; H. von Arnim, Platos 7ugenddialoge (Leipzig 1914) 73 ff.
33It has been suggested that the variety in attitude reflects the art scene current at the
dramatic date of the dialogue, rather than the situation current at the time of com-
position (Webster, "Greek Theories of Art and Literature Down to 400 B.C.," C 33
[1939] 166). However, the dialogue with the earliest dramatic date (the Parmenides)
clearly (and anachronistically) mentions skiagraphia, which seems to refute this sug-
gestion.
34Alberto Diaz Tejera, "Ensayo de un metodo lingiiistico para la cronologia de
Plat6n," Emerita 29 (1961) 241-286; "Die Chronologie der Dialoge Platons," Altertum
11 (1965) 79-83.
35The same method was used by U. Fleischer, Untersuchungen zu den pseudo-hippo-
kratischen Schriften (Berlin 1939) and by R. Andrados Francisco, Estudios sobre el
lixico de lasfdbulas es6picas (Salamanca 1948).
36Diaz's ordering of the dialogues is as follows (each group is also arranged in chrono-
logical order): Group 1: Meno, Protagoras, Gorgias, Republic 1; Group 2: Republic 2-6,
Cratylus, Symposium, Phaedo, Republic 7-10, Phaedrus, Theaetetus, Parmenides;
Group 3: Philebus, Sophist, Politicus, Timaeus, Critias, Laws.
This content downloaded from 146.95.253.17 on Wed, 12 Dec 2018 19:17:14 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
12 PHOENIX
group of dialogue
consists of the Cr
suggests that Pla
(Book 1 being eve
interrupting his w
around 384, and re
sequence agrees wi
which deal with pa
The results of othe
this point. Lutosla
the Phaedo next be
than Books 2-10.38
that some work pr
time of writing th
Phaedo.39 Similarly
Republic 2-10, find
also many peculiar
there is great simi
of two editions.41
for the earlier par
that linguistic diff
as the Lysis and th
span. On the other
period after the Si
experience which c
ences between it an
This content downloaded from 146.95.253.17 on Wed, 12 Dec 2018 19:17:14 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
PLATO AND THE PAINTERS 13
This content downloaded from 146.95.253.17 on Wed, 12 Dec 2018 19:17:14 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
14 PHOENIX
closer relationship
For if they reproduced the true proportions of beautiful figures, you know that the upper
parts would look smaller than they should, and the lower parts larger, because the one is
seen from a distance and the other at close range. And so artists, abandoning the truth,
incorporate into their works not the true proportions but those which appear beautiful.
(Sophist 235e-236a)
The first type of mimesis is the art of creating likenesses (ELKIs), the
second type can create only appearances (4avrrcduara).43
Later in the Sophist, as the division is completed, the relationship
between the analyses of the Republic and the Sophist is made clear. The
Sophist makes a further division of the copies at three removes from
reality-some of these are true copies (likenesses) while others are in-
correct copies (appearances). The analysis in the Sophist is thus a further
refinement upon the analysis of the Republic. The emphasis in the
Sophist is on the right side of the division (appearances), and for the time
being no real interest is taken in the possibilities latent on the left side,
the category "likenesses." Nevertheless, the way seems to be opened to a
return of at least certain painters to favor, as a concept implicit in the
Cratylus (true painting) begins to be developed.
The Statesman contains two references to painting. The first is an
incidental analogy which nonetheless clearly expresses Plato's opinion
of painting. It is obvious that he does not subscribe to the saying that a
picture is worth a thousand words:
Our definition is rudimentary, like an outline sketch of a figure, which is sufficient to be
a likeness but has not yet received its full brilliance through the application of pigments
and the blending together of colors (77 a crvKprtcr T(WV XPWA'rwV). But a description of
a figure in words and discussion is more suitable, for those able to follow it, than a com-
pleted painting--although for those unable to follow such discussions, a drawing will
suffice. (Statesman 277c-d)
4'Quintilian (Inst. 12.10.6) reports that Theon of Samos was noted for his depiction
of imaginary scenes, known as aavratfal. Pollitt interprets 4avra'ia here as "a very
lifelike appearance" ([above, note 13] 220 n. 2). Theon cannot be dated closely; Pollitt
considers him early Hellenistic, and he is associated by Quintilian with Pamphilus, who
may have influenced Plato as Steven suggests (above, note 3). Thus there is a possibility
that Plato's term kavr7arLK~i was borrowed from actual usage (as against G. S6rbom,
Mimesis and Art [Stockholm 1966] 158-159).
This content downloaded from 146.95.253.17 on Wed, 12 Dec 2018 19:17:14 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
PLATO AND THE PAINTERS 15
And finally art, last born of these, mortal offspring of mortal parents, bears certain
pastimes possessing little of truth, phantoms resembling the arts themselves, such as
those which painting produces, and music and all the arts which are fellow-workers with
these. Those of the arts which create something serious are those which join their power
with that of nature, such as medicine, and farming, and gymnastic. (Laws 889d)
In the Philebus there is a return to the hint given in the Sophist that
there may be a respectable form of painting. There is said to be a painter
in the soul who paints true pictures of true opinions and false pictures of
false opinions about pleasures and pains (39b-e). The powers of pleasure
to deceive are explained through a continuation of the analogy with
painting:
In the case of sight, looking at magnitudes from a distance or at very close range obscures
the truth and falsifies their appearance; wouldn't, then, the same thing happen in the
case of pains and pleasures? (Phlb. 41e-42a)
This recalls the earlier passages in the Republic in which Plato likened the
pleasures of the senses to shadow paintings (Resp. 583b, 586b), but there
is a difference between the two dialogues in this respect, for the Philebus
calls some pictures in the soul true pictures, allowing for the possibility
that some of the pictures painted by human painters might also be
"true" pictures, while this possibility is not mentioned in the Republic.
The Critias contains an interesting reference to skiagraphia which
suggests possible areas in which its use was especially marked:
We observe that in the case of earth, mountains, rivers, and woods, the whole sky and the
bodies revolving in it, we would be pleased if anyone were able to copy them with some
slight likeness; and, moreover, since we know nothing definite about such things, we
neither question nor find fault with the painting, but accept a vague and deceptive shadow
This content downloaded from 146.95.253.17 on Wed, 12 Dec 2018 19:17:14 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
16 PHOENIX
painting (aKLaypaqLq
attempts to make a co
missing, because of co
anyone who does not
This description ca
bine realistically
impressionistic bac
story that Alcibia
coverer of skenogr
such techniques m
of the more elabor
used in wall painti
There are several
are introduced in o
passage, it is almo
the legislator's une
painter. It is only
of familiarity with
Athenian: You know th
involved in each figur
adroxpaiv rv), or what
embellishments, or to
becoming clearer or mo
Clinias: I've heard some
I'm not really acquain
Athenian: You're just as
clarify a point. Suppos
picture possible, and,
its excellence for all tim
to leave behind him some successor to restore his work when it suffered from the effects
of time-and a successor who was able to correct his own shortcomings in the work as
well? (Laws 769a-d)
In another passage, the painter, rather than being compared with the
44See note 17 above.
45A. M. G. Little, Roman Perspective Painting and the Ancient Stage (Kennebu
Maine 1971) 1-2. Steven also suggests that a connection may exist between the use
the term oKtraypa4la in Republic 356c and wall paintings, resting his conjecture up
the words 7rp6Ovpa Kat 7aX^ja which he thinks suggest illusionistic architecture (abov
note 3) 150. See also note 17 above.
46I have not discussed the color theory of the Timaeus (67c-68d), because its links
with earlier color theories, going back to Empedocles, rather than with the act
activities of painters, as Plato makes clear when he warns that anyone who tries to
his statements by putting them into practice is forgetting the difference between hum
and divine nature: God alone has the power to combine different things into one.
color theory, see Walter Kranz, "Die iltesten Farbenlehren der Griechen," Hermes
(1912) 126-140.
This content downloaded from 146.95.253.17 on Wed, 12 Dec 2018 19:17:14 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
PLATO AND THE PAINTERS 17
CONCLUSIONS
This content downloaded from 146.95.253.17 on Wed, 12 Dec 2018 19:17:14 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
18 PHOENIX
as Schweitzer sugg
Plato looked upon
respectable memb
techne (Ion, Gorg
passages reflect bot
illusionistic paintin
painter (Phaedo, R
a period in which
persists, but in wh
true painting whic
However, if one rec
to skiagraphic refe
seems that one is le
Despite the strong
exist, this does no
no one would mai
instant, and it seem
which the composi
have had experien
reflected in his wo
in his composition
Can anything be
influence which m
and attitude? In o
Schuhl, Steven, an
tion, two aspects o
the negative aspec
(Plato's allusions to
that this attack wa
case, how are we t
existed peacefully w
such vehemence? T
would be some grea
voice raised in oppo
istic painting, a vo
ous nature of ski
candidates: Schweit
introduction of Sic
suggests that the S
painting and as po
us the archaizing p
As far as Schuhl's
the actual existenc
This content downloaded from 146.95.253.17 on Wed, 12 Dec 2018 19:17:14 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
PLATO AND THE PAINTERS 19
This content downloaded from 146.95.253.17 on Wed, 12 Dec 2018 19:17:14 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
20 PHOENIX
481 should like to express my appreciation to Philip Ambrose, Jean Davison, Robin
Schlunk, and George Bryan for helpful comments and suggestions on an earlier version of
this paper.
This content downloaded from 146.95.253.17 on Wed, 12 Dec 2018 19:17:14 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms