The Savage Mind PDF
The Savage Mind PDF
The Savage Mind PDF
95
In The Savage Mind, Claude Lévi-
Strauss, modern anthropology's
most revered thinker, takes as his
central theme the very nature of
thought itself. He demonstrates how
each culture has its own system of
concepts and categories derived
from experience and imposed by the
surrounding natural world. The per-
ception that the world is populated
by "species'" of things is a primitive
one, yet it is from a similar classifi-
cation into species and names that
the most sophisticated and abstract
thought evolves. Lévi-Strauss shows,
through the order in the naming of
plants and animais, concepts of
space and time, myths and rituals,
how primitive societies do engage in
a high level of abstract reasoning
different from but not necessarily
inferior to that involved in culti-
vated "systematic thought."
Throughout this book Lévi-
Strauss is concerned with the flux of
history and with the perpetual strug-
gle between established social sys-
tems and their history. He takes
issue with Sartre's Critique de la
raison dialectique, refuting the idea
that there is a dichotomy between
"civilized" and "primitive," non-
historic thought. The role of "his-
tory" in anthropology is constantly
debated, and Lévi-Strauss's intensely
challenging views are a brilliant con-
tribution to that debate.
Lévi-Strauss brings new vision to
the traditional problems of the social
anthropologist and to areas of
human expression such as art, ri tuai,
mythology. He shows that the most
fascinating work is still to be done
in investigating these areas which
have been hitherto neglected by
materialist anthropology.
THE NATURE OF HUMAN SOCIETY
PREFACE Xl
8 TIME REGAINED
BIBLIOGRAPHY
INDEX
ILLUSTRATIONS
XII
CHAPTER ONE
lt has long been the fashion to invoke languages which lack the
terms for expressing su ch a concept as 'tree' or 'animal', even
though they contain ail the words necessary for a detailed inventory
of species and varieties. But, to begin with, while these cases are
cited as evidence of the supposed ineptitude of 'primitive people'
for abstract thought, other cases are at the same time ignored
which make it plain that richness of abstract words is not a
monopoly of civilized languages. In Chinook, a language widely
spoken in the north-west of North America, to take one example,
man y properties and qualities are referred to by means of abstract
words: 'This method', Boas says, 'is applied to a greater extent than
in anyother language 1 know.' The proposition 'The bad mar, killed
the poor child' is rendered in Chinook: 'The man's badness killed
the child's poverty'; and for 'The woman used too small a basket'
they say: 'She put the potentilla-roots into the smallness of a clam
basket' (Boas 2, pp. 657-8).
In every language, moreover, discourse and syntax supply indis-
pensable means of supplementing deficiencies of vocabulary. And
the tendentious character of the argument referred to in the last
paragraph becomes very apparent when one observes that the
opposite state of affairs, that is, where very general terms outweigh
specific names, has also been exploited to prove the intellectual
poverty of Savages:
Among plants and animais he [the lndian] designates by name only
those which are useful or harmful, ail others are included under the
classification of bird, weed, etc. (Krause, p. 104).
A more recent observer seems in the same way to believe that the
THE SAVAGE MIND
3
THE SAVAGE l\IIND
4
THE SC'IE:\"CE OF THE COI\'CRETE
names of at lcast four hundred and fifty plants, seventy-fivc birds, most
of the snakes, fish, insccts, and animais, and of even twenty species of
ants ... • and the botanical knowlcdgc of the mananambal, the 'medicine
men and women, who use plants wnstantly in their practice, is truly
astounding (R. B. Fox, pp. 187-8).
Of a backward people of the Tyukyu archipclago, we read:
En·n a child can frcqucntly identify the kind of trcc from which a tiny
wood frag'JTlcnt has corne and, furthermore, the sex of that tree, as defined
by Kabiran notions of plant scx, by observing the appearance of its wood
and bark, its smcll, its hardncss, and similar characteristics. Fish and
shellfish by the dozcn arc known by individually diHinctive terms, and
their separatc fcaturcs and habits, as wcll as the scxual <liffcrcnccs within
each type, arc wcll rccognizcd (Smith, p. 150).
Sevcral thousand Coahuila lndians never exhausted the natural
resources of a desert region in South California, in \Vhich today
only a handful of white families manage to subsist. They lived in
a land of plenty, for in this apparently completely harren tcrritory,
they were familiar with no less than sixty kinds of cdible plants and
twenty-cight others of narcotic, stimulant or medicinal properties
(Ilarrows). A single Seminol informant could identify two hundred
and fifty species and varieties of plants (Sturtevant). Three
hundred and fifty plants known to the Hopi Indians and more than
five hundred to the ~avaho have been recorded. The botanical
vocahulary of the Subanun of the Southern Philippines greatly
exceeds a hundred tcrms (Frakc) and that of the l lanunôo
approaches two thousand.t Sillans, working with a single inform-
ant in the Gabon, recently published an ethno-botanical list of
about eight thousand terms, distributed between the languages or
dialects of twelve or thirteen neighbouring tribe& (Walker and
Sillans). The, for the most part unpublished, results of Marcel
Griaule and his co-workers in the Sudan promise tu be equally
. .
1mpress1ve.
Their extreme familiarity with their biological environment, the
passionate attentio:i. which they pay to it and their precise know-
ledge of it has often struck inquirers as an indication of attitudes
and preoccupations which distinguish the natives from their white
visitors. Among the Tewa lndians of New Mexico:
• Also at least forty-five types of edible ground-mushrooms and ear-fungi
(I.e., p. 231) and on the technological plane, more than fifty types of arrows (id.,
pp. 265-8).
t See below, pp. 138, 153.
5
THE SAVAGE MIND
Small differences are noted ... they have a name for every one of
the coniferous trees of the region; in these cases differences are not con-
spicuous. The ordinary individual among the whites does not distinguish
(them) ... lndeed, it would be possible to translate a treatise on botany
into Tewa ... (Robbins, Harrington and Freire-Marreco, pp. 9, 12).
6
THE SCIENCE OF THE CONCRETE
Conklin quotes the following extract from his field notes to illus-
trate the intimate contact between man and his environment which
the natiYe is constantly imposing ~m the ethnologist:
At o6oo and in a light rain, Langba and 1 left Parina for Binli ... At
Aresaas, Langba told me to eut off several 10 x 50 cm. strips of bark from
an anapla kilala tree (Albizzia procera (Roxb.) Benth.) for protection
against the leeches. By periodically rubbing the cambium side of the
strips of sapanceous (and poisonous: Quisumbling, 1947, 148) bark over
our ankles and legs - already wet from the rain-soaked vegetation - we
produced a most effective leech-repellent lather of pink suds. At one spot
along the trait near Aypud, Langba stopped suddenly,jabbed his walking
stick sharply into the side of the trait and pulled up a smalt weed, tawag
kugum buladlad (Buchnera urticifolia R. Br.) which he told me he will use
as a lure ... for a spring-spcar boar trap. A few minutes latcr, and we
were going at a good pace, he stopped in a similar manner to dig up a
small terrestrial orchid (hardly noticeable beneath the other foliage)
known as liyamliyam (Epipogum roseum (D. Don.) Lindl.). This herb is
useful in the magical control of insect pests which destroy cultivated
plants. At Binli, Langha was careful not to damage those herbs when
searching through the contents of his palm leaf shoulder basket for apug
'slaked lime' and tabaku (Nicotiana tabacum L.) to offer in exchange for
other betel ingredients with the Binli folk. After an evaluative discussion
about the local forms of betel pepper (Piper betle L.) Langba got per-
mission to eut swect potato (Jpomoea balatas (L.) Poir.) vines of two
vegetatively distinguishable types, kamuti inaswang and kamuti lupaw
... In the camote patch, wc eut twenty-five vine-tip sections (about
75 cm. long) of each variety, and carefully wrapped them in the broad
fresh leaves of the cultivated saging saba (iWusa sapientum compressa (Blco.
Teoforo) so that they would remain moist until we reached Langba's
place. Along the way we munched on a few stems of tubu minuma, a type
of sugar cane (Saccharum officinarum L.), stopped once to gather fallen
bunga area nuts (Areca catecl1u L.), and another time to pick and eat the
wild cherrylike fruits from some bugnay shrubs (Antidesma brunius (L.)
Spreng). 'Ve arrived at the l\lararim by mid-afternoon havingspent much
of our time on the trait discussing changes in the surrounding vegetation
in the last few decades! (Conklin 1, pp. 15-17).
This knowledge and the linguistic means which it has at its dis-
posai also extend to morphology. ln Tewa there are distinct terms
for all or almost all the parts of birds and mammals (Henderson
and Harrington, p. 9). Forty terms are employed in the morpho-
logical description of the leaves of trees or plants, and there are
fifteen distinct terms for the different parts of a maize plant.
The Hanun6o have more than a hundred and fifty terms for the
parts and properties of plants. These provide categories for the
7
THE SAVAGE l\11NI1
9
THE SAVAGE MIND
16
THE SCIENCE OF THE CONCRETE
17
THE SAVAGE MIND
use or, putting this another way and in the language of the 'bri-
coleur' himself, because the elements are collected or retained on
the principle that 'they may always corne in handy'. Such elements
are specialized up to a point, sufficiently for the 'bricoleur' not
to need the equipment and knowledge of all trades and profes-
sions, but not enough for each of them to have only one definite
and determinate use. They each represent a set of actual and
possible relations; they are 'operators' but they can be used for any
operations of the same type.
~lements Q(mythicalthought s~!J1_il~}yJi!!half-way between
P~-~_!Vl.Jld-roncep!ê.:_ It would be impossible to separate percepts
from the concrete situations in which they appeared, while recourse
to concepts would require that thought could, at least provision-
ally, put its projects (to use Husserl's expression) 'in brackets'.
~_an _intermediary _betweerL-images and concepts,
~~igns. For signs can always be defined in the way intro-
duced by Saussure in the case of the particular category of
linguistic signs, that is, as a link between images and concepts. In
the union thus brought about, images and concepts play the part
of the signifying and signified respectively.
/Signs resemble images in being concrete entities but they
resemble concepts in their powers of reference. Neither concepts
nor signs relate exclusively to themselves; either may be substi-
tuted for something else. Concepts, however, have an unlimited
,capacity in this respect, while signs have not. The example of the
'Drîèoleur' helps to bring out the differences and similarities. Con-
sider him at work and excited by his project. His first practical step
is retrospective. He has to turn back to an already existent set made
up of tools and materials, to consider or reconsider what it contains
and, finally and above all, to engage in a sort of dialogue with it
and, before choosing between them, to index the possible answers
which the whole set can offer to his problem. He interrogates all the
heterogeneous objects of which his treasury* is composed to dis-
cover what each of them could 'signify' and so contribute to the
definition of a set which has yet to materialize but which will
ultimately differ from the instrumental set only in the interna! dis-
position of its parts. A particular cube of oak could be a wedge to
make up for the inadequte length of a plank of pine or it could be a
pedestal - which would allow the grain and polish of the old wood
• Cf. 'Treasury of ideas' as Hubert and Mauss so aptly describe magic.
THE SCIENCE OF THE CONCRETE
21
THE SAVAGE MIND
22
THE SCIENCE OF THE CONCRETE
have liked to paint a t less than life-size. His paintings are therefore,
like Japanese gardens, miniature vehicles and ships in bottles, what
in the 'bricoleur's' language are called 'small-scale models' or 'min-
iatures'. Now, the question arises whether the small-scale model or
miniature, which is also the 'masterpiece' of the journeyman may
not in fact be the universal type of the work of art. All miniatures
seem to have intrinsic aesthetic quality - and from what should
they draw this constant virtue if not from the dimensions them-
selves? - and conversely the vast majority of works of art are small-
scale. It might be thought that this characteristic is principally a
matter of economy in materials and means, and one might appeal
in support of this theory to works which are incontestably artistic
but also on a grand scale. \Ve have to be clear about definitions.
The paintings of the Sistine Chapel are a small-scale model in spite
of their imposing dimensions, since the theme which they depict
is the End of Time. The same is true of the cosmic symbolism of
religious monuments. Furthcr, we may ask whether the aesthetic
effect, say, of an equestrian statue which is larger than life derives
from its enlargement of a man to the size of a rock or whether it is
not rather due to the fact that it restores what is at first from a
distance seen as a rock to the proportions of a man. Finally even
'natural sizc' implies a reduction of scale since graphie or plastic
transposition always involves giving up certain dimensions of the
object: volume in painting, colour, smell, tactile impressions in
sculpture and the temporal dimension in both cases since the whole
work represented is apprehendcd at a single moment in time.
What is the virtue of reduction either of scale or in the number
of properties? It seems to result from a sort of reversai in the pro-
cess of understanding. To understand a real object in its totalrty
we always tend to work from its parts. The resistance it off ers us is
overcome by dividing it. Reduction in scale reverses this situation.
Being smaller, the object as a whole seems less formidable. By
being quantitatively diminished, it seems tous qualitatively simpli-
fied. More exactly, this quantitative transposition extends aryd
diversifies our power over a homologue of the thing, and by means
of it the latter can be grasped, assessed and apprehended at a
glance. A child's doll is no longer an enemy, a rival or even an
interlocutor. ln it and through it a person is made into a subject.
In the case of miniatures, in contrast to what happens when we try
to understand an object or living creature of real dimensions,
23
THE SAVAGE l\llND
fact exactly the reverse of that which gives rise to works of art.
In the case of works of art, the starting point is a set of one or more
objects and one or more events which aesthetic creation unifies by
~fing a conunon structure. l\'Iyths travel the same road but
start from the other end. They use a structure to produce what is
itself an object consisting of a set of events (for all myths tell a
story). Art thus proceeds from a set (object + event) to the dis-
co1:ery of its structure. ::'vlyth starts from a structure by means of
which it constructs a set (object + event).
~ -The first point tempts one to generalize the theory. The second
might seem to lead to a restriction of it. For we may ask whether
it is in fact the case that works of art are always an integration of
structure and event. This does not on the face of it seem to be
true for instance of the cedarwood Tlingit club, used to kill fish,
which I have in front of me on my bookshelf (Plate 2 ). The artist
who carved it in the form of a sea monster intended the body of the
implement to be fosed with the body of the animal and the handle
with its tail, and that the anatomical proportions, taken from a
fabulous creature, should be such that the object could be the cruel
animal slaying helpless victims, at the same time as an easily
handled, balanced and efficient fishing utensil. Everything about
this implement - which is also a superb work of art - seems to be a
matter of structure: its mythical symbolism as well as its practical
fonction. 1\Iore accurately, the object, its fonction and its sym-
bolism seem to be inextricably bound up with each other and to
form a closed system in which there is no place for events. The
monster's position, appearance and expression owe nothing to the
historical circumstances in which the artist saw it, in the flesh or in
a dream, or conceived the idea of it. It is rather as if its immutable
being were finally fixed in the \vood whose fine grain allows the
reproduction of all its aspects and in the use for which its empirical
form seems to pre-determine it. And all this applies equally to the
other products of primitive art: an African statue or a Melanesian
mask . . . So it looks as if we have defined only one local and
historical form of aesthetic creation and not its fondamental pro-
perties or those by means of which its intelligible relations with
other forms of creation can be described.
\Ve have only to widen our explanation to overcome this diffi-
culty. \Vhat, with reference to a picture of Clouet's, was provision-
ally defined as an event or set of events now appears under a
26
THE SCIENCE OF THE CONCRETE
broader heading: events in this sense are only one mode of the
contingent whose integration (perceived as necessary) into a struc-
ture gives rise to the aesthetic emotion. This is so whatever the type
of art in question. Depending ori- the style, place and period the
contingent plays a part in three different ways or at three distinct
points in artistic creation (or in all of them). It may play a part in
the occasion for the work or in the execution of the work or in the
purpose for which it is intended. It is only in the first case that it
takes the form of an event properly speaking, that is, of conting-
ency exterior and prior to the creative act. The artist perceives it
from without as an attitude, an expression, a light effect or a
situation, whose sensible and intellectual relations to the structure
of the object affected by these modalities he grasps and incorpor-
ates in his work. But the contingent can also play an intrinsic part
in the course of execution itself, in the size or shape of the piece of
wood the sculptor lays hands on, in the direction and quality of its
grain, in the imperfections of his tools, in the resistance which his
materials or project offer to the work in the course of its accomplish-
ment, in the unforeseeable incidents arising during work. Finally,
the contingent can be extrinsic as in the first case but posterior,
instead of anterior, to the act of creation. This is the case whenever
the work is destined for a specific end, since the artist will construct
it with a view to its potential condition and successive uses in the
future and so will put himself, consciously or unconsciously, in the
place of the person for whose use it is intended. _
The rocess of artisti~.rcation therefore consists in trying~o
communicate within the immu~rk-of·a:-müfüâlcon::·
fronfat10n0f structure and accident) either with the mode! or with
the materials or with the future user as the case may be, according
to which of these the artist particularly looks to for his directions
while he is at work. Each case roughly corresponds to a readily
identifiable form of art: the first to the plastic arts of the West, the
second to so-called primitive or early art and the third to the
applied arts. But it would be an oversimplification to take these
identifications very strictly. All forms of art allow all three aspects
and they are only distinguished from one another by the relative
proportion of each. Even the most academic of painters cornes up
against problems of execution, for example. All the so-called primi-
tive arts can be called applied in a double sense: first, because many
of their productions are technical objects and, secondly, because
27
TllE SAVAGE :\llND
28
THE SCIENCE OF THE COl\"CHETE
the purposc can becomc more and more prccisc and specific and
applied art is transformed into industrial art. Wc call it peasan~
folk art if the reverse is the case. Finally, primitive art is the
opposite of profcssional or academic art. Professional or acadcmic
art internalizcs execution (which it has, or hclievcs itself to have,
mastercd) and purp~>se ('art for art's sake' being an end in itself).
As a result, it is impellcd to cxternalize the occasion (which it
requires the mode! to provide) and the latter thus becomes a part
of the signified. PrimitiYc art, on the othcr hand, internalizcs the
occasion (sincc the supcrnat ural hcings which it dclights in rcprc-
senting ha\'c a rcality which is timclcss and indcpcndcnt of circum-
stanccs) and it cxtcrnalizcs cxccution a11d purposc which thus
bccome a part of the signifying. _.,,-
On a ditfcrcnt plane wc thcrcforc find once more this dialogue
with the matcrials arid mcans of cxccution hy which we dcfincd
'bricolage'. The esscntial prohkm for the philosophy <.fart is to
know wltcthcr the artist regards th cm as intcrlocutors or not. No
doubt thcy arc always rcgardcd as such, although lcast of all in art
which is too profcssional and most of all in the raw or riaive art
which \'Crgcs on 'bricolage', to the <letrimcnt of structure in hoth
cases. :\o form of art is, howc\·er, worthy of the namc if it allows
itself to corne cntirely undcr the sway of extrancous contingencics,
whcther of occasion or purposc. If it did so it would rate as an icon
(supplementary to the modcl) or as an implement (complemcntary
with the matcrial workcd). Even the most profession;.! art succecds
in mo\·ing us only if it arrcsts in timc this dissipation of the con-
tingent in fa\'our of the prctcxt and incorporatcs it in the work,
thereby imesting it with the dig•1Ïty of hcing a'l ohject in its own
right. In so far as carly art, primitive art a•1d the 'primitive' pcriods
of profcssional painting are the only ones which do not date, thcy
owe it to this dedication of the accidentai to the service of execution
and so to the use, which thcy try to make completc, of the raw
datum as the empirical matcrial of something mcaningful. *
• Pursuing this analysis, one might dt:fine non-rt:prt:st:ntational painting by
two foaturt:s. One, which it has in common with 'case!' painting, consists in a
total rcjection of the contingency of purposc: the picture is not made for a
particular ust:. The other fcature characteristic of non-representational painting
is its methotiical exploitation of the contingcncy of cxecution, which is claimed
to afforti the extl'rnal prctext or occasion of the pictu re. ::\'on-rcprcscntational
painting adopts 'styles' as 'subjccts'. lt claims to gi\'c a concrete rt;prcscntation
of the formai conditions of ail painting. Paradoxically the result is that non-
represcntational painting docs not, as it thinks, crl·atc works which arc as rl'al as,
THE SAVAGE MIND
\Ve have seen that there are analogies between mythical thought on
the theoretical, and 'bricolage' on the practical plane and that
artistic creation lies mid-way between science and thesetwo forms of
activity. There are relations of the same type between games and
rites.
~<\U-games are defined by a set of rules which in practice allow the
playing of any numher of matches. Ritual, which is also 'played',
is on the other hand, like a favoured instance of agame, remern-
bered from among the possible ones because it is the only one
which results in a particular type of equilibrium between the two
_s~. The transposition is readily seen in the case of the Gahuku-
Gama of New Guinea who have learnt football but who will play,
several days running, as many matches as are necessary for both
if not more real than, the objects of the physical world, but rather realistic
imitations of non-existent models. It is a school of academic painting in which
each artist strives to represent the manner in which he would execu te his pictures
if by chance he were to paint any.
THE SCIENCE OF THE CONCRETE
sicles to reach the same score (Read, p. 429). This is treating agame
as a ritual.
The same can be said of the games which took place among the
Fox Indians during adoption ceremonies. Their purpose was to
replace a dead relative by a living one and so to allow the final
departure of the soul of the deceased. * The main aim of funeral rites
among the Fox seems indeed to be to get rid of the dead and to
prevent them from avenging on the living their bitterness and their
regret that they are no longer among them. For native philosophy
resolutely sicles with the living: 'Death is a hard thing. Sorrow is
especially hard'.
Death originated in the destruction by supernatural powers of
the younger of two mythical brothers who are cultural heroes
among all the Algonkin. But it was not yet final. It was made so by
the elder brother \vhen, in spite of his sorrow, he rejected the
ghost's request to be allowed to return to his place among the
living. l\'len must follow this example and be firm with the dead.
The living must make them understand that they have lost nothing
by dying since they regularly receive off erings of tobacco and food.
ln return they are expected to compensa te the living for the reality
of death which they recall to them and for the sorrow their demise
causes them by guaranteeing them long life, clothes and something
to eat. 'lt is the dead who make food increase', a native informant
explains. 'They (the Indians) must coax them that way' (Michelson
1, pp. 369, 407).
Now, the adoption rites which are necessary to make the soul of
the deceased finally decide to go where it will take on the role of a
protecting spirit are normally accompanied by competitive sports,
games of skill or chance between teams which are constituted on
the basis of an ad hoc division into two sicles, Tokan and Kicko.
It is said explicitly over and over again that it is the living and the
dead who are playing against each other. lt is as if the living off ered
the dead the consolation of a last match before finally being rid of
them. But, since the two teams are asymmetrical in what they
stand for, the outcome is inevitably determined in advance:
This is how it is when they play ball. When the man for whom the
adoption-feast is held is a Tokana, the Tokanagi win the game. The
Kickoagi cannot win. And if it is a Kicko woman for whom the adoption-
31
THE SAVAGE MIND
feast is given, the Kickoagi win, as in turn the Tokanagi <lo not wm
(:\llichelson 1, p. 385).
And what is in fact the case? It is clear that it is only the living who
·win in the great biological and social game which is constantly
taking place between the living and the dead. But, as all the North
American mythology confirms, to win a game is symbolically to
'kill' one's opponent; this is depicted as really happening in in-
numerable myths. By ruling that they should always win, the dead
are given_ the illusion that it is they who are really alive, and that
their opponents, having been 'killed' by them, are dead. Under the
guise of playing with the dead, one plays them false and commits
th,em. The formai structure of what might at first sight be taken
for a competitive game is in fact identical with that of a typical
ritual such as the Mitawit or Midewinin of these same Algonkin
peoples in which the initiates get symbolically killed by the dead
whose part is played by the initiated; they feign death in order to
obtain a further lease of life. In both cases, death is brought in but
~beduped.
~hus appear to have a disjunctive effect: they end in the
establishment of a difference between individual players or teams
where originally there was no indication of inequality. And at the
end of the game they are distinguished into winners and losers.
~!, on the other hand, is the exact inverse; it conjoins, for it
brings about a union (one might even say communion in this con-
text) or in any case an organic relation between two initially separ-
ate groups, one ideally merging with the person of the officiant and
the other with the collectivity of the faithful. In the case of games
the symmetry is thercfore preordained and it is of a structural kind
since it follows from the principle that the rules are the same for
both sicles. Asyanmetry is engendered: it follows inevitably from
the contingent nature of events, themselves due to intention, chance
or t::i.Ient. The reverse is true ofrituaL There is an asymmetrywhich
is postulated in advance between profane and sacred, faithful and
officiating, dead and living, initiated and uninitiated, etc., and the
'game' consists in making ail the participants pass to the winning
_s~-~y means of evcnts, the nature and ordering of which is
genuinely structural. Like science (though here again on both the
theoretical and the practical plane) the game produces events by
mcans of a structure; and wc can therefore understand why com-
petitive games should flourish in our industrial societies. Rites
THE SCIENCE OF THE CONCRETE
and myths, on the other hand, like 'bricolage' (which these sam
societies only tolerate as a hobby or pastime), take to pieces an
reconstruct sets of events (on a psychical, socio-historical or tech
nical plane) and use them as so many indestructible pieces fo
structural patterns in which they serve alternatively as ends c
means.
33
CHAPTER TWO
35
THE SAVAGE MIND
37
THE SAVAGE MIND
39
THE SAVAGE MIND
1
COLOURS yellow blue, green red white black multicoloured
1
(calochortus) (delphinium)
1 1 1 1 1 1 1
CORN yellow blue red white purple sweet
1 1 1 1 1 1 1
French bean Butter-bean dwarf bean lima bean vanous
...,
BEANS .....
(Î
(P haseolus (Phas. rnlg.) (Phaseolus >
ml{!.) 1 lunatus --!
.....
0
Beans were also subdivided into: z
light light white white blue en
black yellow black grey red
red brown spotted yellow pink
red etc.
black
THE SAV AGE MIND
43
THE SAVAGE .i\11.'.':D
fcct whcrc maizc will not ripcn) further than it has pcrhaps evcr
bccn donc.
ÜYcr two hundrcd and fifty varicties arc still distinguished in
nati\·c rncabuLtry and the figure was ccrtainl y higher in the past.
This taxonomy opcratcs by using a tcrm to dcsignate the variety
and adding a qualifying adjccti\'e for cach sub\'ariety. Thus the
Yaricty imilla 'girl' is subdividcd cither according to colour (black,
blue, white, rcd, blood-coloured) or according to othcr characteris-
tics such as grassy, insipid, cgg-shaped and so on. Thcre are about
twenty-two main \'arietics which arc subdiYided in this way. In
addition, thcre is a gcncral dichotomy bctwccn thosc which may
be caten after simple cooking and thosc which can only be eatcn
after bcing altcrnatcly frozen and fermcnted. A binomial taxonomy
also always uses critcria such as form (flat, thick, spiral, like cact11s
lcaf, lumpy, cgg-shapcd, in the shapc of an ox tonguc, etc.),
texture (mcaly, clastic, sticky, etc.), or 'sex' (boy or girl) (La
Barre).
It was a professional biologist who pointcd out how many
crrors and misunderst:mdings, some of which haYe only recently
bccn rcctificd, could have bcen avoided, had the older travellers
been content to rcly on nati\·c taxonomies instead of improvising
cntircly ncw <mes. The rcsult was that clevcn diffcrcnt authors
hetween thcm applicd the scicntific namc Canis azarae to thrce
distinct gcncra, cight spccies and nine differcnt sub-spccics, or
again that a single Yariety of the samc specics was rcfcrrcd to by
seYeral different names. The Guarani of Argentine and Paraguay,
on the other hand, work methodically with namcs composcd of
one, two or thrce tcrms. By this mcans they distinguish for
instance between large, small and medium felincs: the dyagua eté
is the suprcme example of the large fcline, the mharakadya eté of
the srnall wild cat. The mini (small) among the dyague (large)
correspond to the guasu (large) among the chin', that is, the
medium-sized frlines:
ln general, nati\·e tcrms can hc sai<l to constitutt' a wcll-concci\'c<l
system, and, with a pinch of salt, they can hc sai<l to hear sonH.· resem-
bbnce to our scientific nomenclature. Thcsc primitiYc lmlians <li<l not
lca\·c the naming of natural phcnomcna to chance. They asscmblc<l tribal
councils to <leci<le which tcrms best correspomle<l to the nature of spccics,
classifying groups and suh-groups with grcat precision. The preservation
of th(' indigL·nous tcm1s for tht· local fatma is not just a matter of piety and
int('grity; it is a duty to science (lknnler, pp. 2J-J. and Z-J.4).
THE LOGJC OF TOTE.MIC CLASSIFICATIONS
In the face of such accuracy and care one begins to wish that every
ethnologist were also a minerdogist, a botanist, a zoologist and
even an astronomer ... For Reichard's comment about the Navaho
applies not only to the Australians and Sudanese but to ail or
almost all native peoples:
45
THE SAVAGE MIND
Since the Navajo regard ail parts of the universe as essential to well-
being, a major problem of religious study is the classification of natural
objects, a subject that demands careful taxonomical attention. We need a
list, with English, scientific (Latin) and r'\avajo names of ail plants,
animais - especially birds, rodents, insects and worms - minerais and
rocks, shells and stars (Reichard, p. 7).
47
THE SAVAGE MIND
,,
Cfemale> cm~le)
,Artemisia
,,
,/ Chrysothamnus
, ,,
/
/ , ,/
,
,
/
,,
,, ,,
,,/ ,/I
(to assist Penstemon Chrysothamnus
,,
birthJ= (female birthJ /Cmale birthJ
,
,, ,,
o' .c:,.'
49
THE SAVAGE MIND
also from a mythical point of view (the eagle being a t the top of
the mythical hierarchy of birds).
Analysis of the ritual shows that it accords in every detail with
the hypothesis that there is a dualis~ between a celestial prey and
a subterranean hunter, which at the same time evokes the strongest
possible contrast between high and low in the sphere of hunting.
The extreme complexity of the rites which precede, accompany and
conclude an eagle hunt is the counterpart of the exceptional
position which eagle hunting occupies within a mythical typology
which makes it the concrcte expression of the widest possible
distance between a hunter and his game.
Sorne obscure features of the ritual become clear at the same
time, in particular the significance and meaning of the myths
which are told du ring hunting expeditions. They ref er to cultural
heroes, capable of being transformed into arrows and masters of
the art of hunting with bows and arrows; and thercforc, in their
guise of wild cats and racoons, doubly inappropriatc for the role
of hait in eagle hunting. Hunting with bows and arrows involves
the region or space immediatdy above the earth, that is, the
atmospheric or middle sky: the hunter and his game meet in the
intermediate space. Eagle hunting, on the other hand, separates
them by giving them opposite positions: the hunter below the
ground and the game close to the cmpyrean sky.
Another striking feature of eagle hunting is that women have a
beneficial effect during their periods. This is contrary to the
belief held almost universally by hunting peoples, including the
Hidatsa themselves in the case of ail except eagle hunting. What
has just been said explains this detail also, when it is remembered
that in eagle hunting, conceived as the narrowing of a wide gulf
between hunter and game, mediation is effected, from the technical
point of view, by means of the hait, a piece of meat or small piece
of game, the bloodstained carcass of which is destined to rapid
decay. A first hunt to procure the bait is necessary in order for
the second hunt to take place. One hunt involves the shedding of
blood (by means of bows and arrows), the other does not (eagles
are strangled without any effusion of blood). The one hunt, which
consists in a close union of hunter and game, fumishes the means
of effecting a union between what is so distant that it looks
at first as if there is a gulf which cannot be bridged - except,
precisely, by means of blood.
SI
THE SAVAGE :\11:\D
• The Hidatsa seem to have lived at various points in the state of N"orth
Dakota for as long as their traditions go back.
As for the wolverine: it 'is a circumpolar species belonging to the northern
forested areas of both continents. In North America it fonnerly ranged from the
northern limit of trees south to New England and New York, and down the
Rocky :\fountains to Colorado, and down the Sierra Nevada to near Mount
\Vhitney, California' (Nelson, p. 427). The Common Wolverine is found 'from
the Arctic Ocean and Baffin Bay southward and from the Pacifie to the Atlantic,
reaching the extreme north-eastern United States, Wisconsin, Michigan, Minne-
sota, North Dakota, and down the Rocky Mountains into Utah and Colorado'
(Anthony, p. III). Species which appear to be synonymous have been reported
in the mountains of California and at Fort Union, North Dakota (id.).
53
THE SAVAGE ::\11ND
54
THE LOGIC OF TOTEMIC CLASSIFICATIONS
55
THE SAVAGE MIND
'*' 'Among the \Vinnebago, a number of other Siouan, and Central Algonquain
tribes, there was a fivefold classification; earth animais, sky animais, empyrean
animais, aquatic animais, and subaquatic animais. Among the Winnebago the
thunderbird belong to the empyrean; the eagle, hawk, and pigeon, to the sky;
the bear and wolf, to the earth; the fish, to the water and the water spirit, bclow
the water' (Radin I, p. 186).
57
THE SAVAGE MIND
Petican
The available data are certainly fragmentary, but one cannot fail
to :10tice a rough system, which, indeed, only looks rough to the
onlooker because the ethnographie background necessary for its
interpretation is almost entirely missing. The white cockatoo,
'diurnal', is next to the sun, and the black cockatoo, which is
almost directly opposite, is itself next to the tubers, 'chthoni<in'
plants, and on the same axis as the cave, which is also 'chthonian'.
Snakes are on one axis, and the 'sea' creatures, pelican, sea, hot
wind, also seem to be grouped according to axes. But does this
wind belong to land or sea? W e do not know and, as so often, we
must go to a geographer or meteorologist or to a botanist, zoologist
or geologist, for the solution to this ethnographie problem.
The truth of the matter is that the principle underlying a classifi-
cation can never be postulated in advance. It can only be discovered
a posteriori by ethnographie investigation, that is, by experience. *
• 1 hcrc includc scvcral pages of a paper intended for the Mélanges Alexandre
Koyré.
58
THE LOGIC OF TOTEJ\1IC CLASSIFICATIONS
59
THE SAVAGE MIND
60
THE LOGIC OF TOTEMIC CLASSIFICATIONS
Parrots and squirrels are famous fruiteaters ... and men about to go
headhunting feel a relationship to these beings and call themselves their
brothers ... (because of the) parallelism between the human body and a
tree, the human head and its fruit (~egwaard, p. 1034).
61
THE SAVAGE MIND
of the term, but, as among the Bemba and the Ambo, joking
relationships link them in pairs. The reasoning behind this has,
from our point of view, the same interest. As 1 showed in an
earlier book and am continuing to establish here, so-called
totemism is in fact only a particular case of the general problem of
classification and one of many examples of the part which specific
terms often play in the working out of a social classification.
The following clans stand in a joking relationship to each other
among the Luapula: the Leopard and Goat clans bccause the
leopards eat goats, the Mushroom and Anthill clans because
mushrooms grow on anthills, the :\Iush and Goat clans because
men like meat in their mush, the Elephant and Clay clans because
women in the old days used to carve elephants' footprints in the
ground and use these natural shapes as receptacles instead of
fashioning pots. The Anthill clan is linked with the Snake clan
and also with the Grass clan because grass grows tall on anthills
and snakes hide there. The Iron clan jokes with ail clans with
animal names because animais are killed by metal spears and
bullets. Reasoning of this kind allows the definition of a hierarchy
of clans: the Leopard clan is superior to the Goat clan, the Iron
clan to the animal clans and the Rain clan to the 1ron clan because
rain rusts iron. l\foreover the rain clan is superior to ail the other
clans because animais would die without it, one cannot make mush
(a clan name) without it, clay (a clan name) cannot be worked
without it, and so on (Cunnison, pp. 62-5).
The Navaho give man y different justifications of the virtues they
ascribe to medicinal plants and their modes of employing them:
the plant grows near a more important medicinal plant; one of the
plant's organs looks like a part of the body; the odour (or feel or
taste) of the plant is 'right'; the plant makes water the 'right' colour;
the plant is associated with an animal (as food, or in habitat, or by
contact); the knowledge was revealed by the gods; its uses were
learnt from someone else without any explanation: the plant is
found near a tree struck by lightning; it is good for a certain ailment
in that part of the body or an ailment with similar effects, etc.
(Vesta!, p. 58). The terms used to differentiate plant names among
the Hanunôo belong to the following categories: leaf shape, colour,
habitat, size/dimension, sex, habit of growth, plant host, growing
time, taste, smell (Conklin 1, p. 131 ).
These examples, together with those given earlier, make it clear
62
THE LOGIC OF TOTEMIC CLASSIFICATIONS
that such systems of logic work on several axes at the same time.
The relations which the y set u p between the terms are most
commonly based on contiguity (snake and anthill among the
Luapula and also the Toreya of South India)* or on resemblance
(red ants and cobras which, according to the Nuer, resemble each
other in 'colour'). In this they are not formally distinct from other
taxonomies, e\·en modern ones, in which contiguity and resem-
blance also play a fondamental part: contiguity for discovering
things which 'belong both structurally and fonctionally ... to a
single system' and resemblance, which does not require member-
ship of the same system and is based simply on the possession by
abjects of one or more common characteristics, such as ail being
'yellow or ail smooth, or ail with wings or ail ten feet high (Simpson,
pp. 3-+).
But other types of relation intervene in the examples we have
just examined. Relations may be established, in effect, on either
the sensible Ie,·el (the bodily markings of the bee and the pythons)
or on the intelligible level (the fonction of construction common
to the bce and the carpentcr): the samc animal, the bec, fonctions,
as it were, at diff erent levcls of abstraction in two cultures. Again,
the connection can be close or distant, synchronie or diachronie
(the relation between squirrels and cedars for instance on the one
hand, and that between pottery and elephants' footprints on the
other), static (mush and goat) or dynamic (fire kills animals, rain
'kills' fire; the flowering of a plant indicates that it is time to
return to the village), etc.
It is probable that the number, nature and 'quality' of these
logical axes is not the same in every culture, and that cultures could
be classified into richer and poorer on the basis of the formai
properties of the systems of reference to which they appeal in the
construction of their classifications. However, even those which
are the least well endowed in this respect employ logics of several
dimensions, the listing, analysis and interpretation of which would
require a wealth of ethnographie and general information which
is all too often lacking.
•'The members of the sept, at times of marriage, worship anthills, which are
the homes of snakes' (Thurston, vol. VII, p. 176). Similarly in l\"ew Guinea:
'certain types of plants, as well as the animais and plants parasitic on them, are
thought of as belonging to the same mythical and totemic unit' (Wirz, vol. II,
p. 21).
THE SAVAGE MIND
redis the colour of life and fertility (C. M. N. White 1, pp. 46-7).*'
White represents the 'unstressed' situation in both cases, while
red - the chromatic pole of th~_ opposition - is associated with
death in one case and with life in the other. ln the Forrest River
district of Australia, members of a deceased person's own genera-
tion paint themselves black and white and keep away from the
corpse while those of other generations do not paint themselves
and approach the corpse. The opposition white/red is thus re-
placed, without any change of semantic load, by an opposition
black+ white/O. Insteadof the values given to white and red being
reversed, as in the previous case, the value of white (here associated
with black, a non-:hromatic colour) remains constant, and it is the
content of the opposite pole which is reversed, changing from the
'super-colour' red to the total absence of colour. Finally, another
Australian tribe, the Bard, constructs its symbolism by means of
the opposition black/red. Black is the colour of mourning for even
generations (grandfather, Ego, grandson) and red the colour of
mourning for uneven generations (father, son), that is, those which
are not assimilated with the generation of the deceased (Elkin 4,
pp. 298-9). The opposition between two differently stressed terms
- life and deathamong the Luvale, 'someone else's deathand ''my''
death' in Australia - is thus expressed by pairs of elements taken
from the same symbolic chain; absence of colour, black, white,
black + white, red (as the supreme presence of colour), etc.
The same fundamental opposition is found among the Fox, but
transposed from colour to sound. While the burial ceremony is in
progress 'those burying (the dead) talked to each other. But the
others did not say a thing to each other' (Michelson 1, p. 411). The
opposition between speech and silence, between noise and the
absence of noise, corresponds to that between colour and the
absence of colour or between two chromatisms of different
degrees. These observations seem to make it possible to dispose of
theories making use of the concepts of 'archetypes' or a 'collective
unconscious'. It is only forms and not contents which can be
common. If there are common contents the reason must be sought
either in the objective properties of particular nature or artificial
entities or in diffusion and borrowing, in either case, that is,
outside the mind.
• As in China, where white is the colour of mouming and red the colour of
marriage.
65
THE SAVAGE MIND
language disappears with the men who speak it. Nevertheless the
connection between synchrony and diachrony is not rigid. For, in
the first place, all the speakers are, taken as a whole, equivalent
(though this would cease to be s~ if one were to consider specific
cases), and secondly, and more important, the structure of the
language is to some extent protected by its practical purpose, which
is to ensure communication. Language is therefore sensitiYe to the
influence of demographic ernlution only up to a point and in so
far as its fonction is not impaired. But the conceptual systems
we are studying here are not, or are not primarily, means of
communication. They are means of thinking, an activity which is
governed by Yery much less stringent conditions. One either
succeeds or not in making oneself understood, but one can think
more or less well. Thinking admits of degrecs and a way of thinking
can degenerate imperceptibly into a way of remembering. This
explains why the synchronie structures of so-called totemic sys-
tems should be so extremely Yulnerable to the effects of diachrony:
a mnemotechnic procedure is less trouble to operate than a
speculati\·e one which in turn is less exacting than a device for
communication.
This point can be illustrated by an only slightly imaginary
example. Suppose that a tribe was once divided into three clans,
each of which had the name of an animal symbolizing a natural
element:
1 1 1
bear eagle turtle
(land) (sky) (water)
Suppose further that demographic changes led to the extinction of
the bear clan and an increase in the population of the turtle clan,
and that as a result the turtle clan split into two sub-clans, each of
which subsequently gained the status of clans. The old structure
will disappear completely and be replaced by a structure of this
type:
1
eagle
1 1
yellow turtle grey turtle
its parts like a motor with a feed-back device: governed (in both
senses of the word) by its previous harmony, it will direct the dis-
cordant mechanism towards an .equilibrium which will be at any
rate a compromise between the old state of affairs and the confusion
brought in from outside.
Whether they are historically correct or not, the traditional
legends of the Osage show that native thought itself may well
envisage this sort of interpretation, based on the hypothesis of a
structural adjustment of the historical process. When the ancestors
emerged from the bowds of the earth they were, according to
Osage tradition, divided into two groups, one peace-loving, vege-
tarian and associated with the left side and the other warlike,
carnivorous and associated with the right. The two groups resolved
to ally themseh·es and to exchange their respective foods. In the
course of their wanderings, they met a third group, which was
ferocious and lived entirely on carrion, with whom they eventually
united. Each of the three groups was originally composed of seven
clans, making a total of twenty-one clans. In spite of the symmetry
of this three-clan division, the system was in disequilibrium since
the newcomers belonged to the side of war and there were fourteen
clans on one side and seven on the other. In order to remedy this
defect and to preserve the balance between the side of war and the
side of peace, the number of clans in one of the groups of warriors
was reduced to five and that in the other to two. Since then the
Osage camps, which are circular in shape with the entrance facing
east, consist of seven clans of peace occupying the northern half on
the left of the entrance and seven clans of war occupying the
southern half on the right of the entrance (J.O. Dorsey /, 2 ). The
legend suggests twin processes. One is purely structural, passing
from a dual to a three-fold system and then returning to the earlier
dualism; the other, both structural and historical at the same time,
consists in undoing the effects of an overthrow of the primitive
structure::, resulting from historical events, or events thought of as
such: migrations, war, alliance. Now, the social organization of the
Osage, as it was to be seen in the nineteenth century, in fact
integrated both aspects. Although they were each composed of the
same number of clans, the side of peace and the side of war were
in disequilibrium since one was simply 'sky' while the other, also
referred to as 'of the earth', consisted of two groups of clans
associated respectively with dry land and water. The system was
THE SAVAGE MIND
ZUNI HOPI
(Walpi and Sichurnovi)
(Kroeber, /, p. 149)
500 Zuni
400
450
300
,/\
\
250 1\ I \
1' \ I \
, \ I \
\ I \
c: 200 I ' I \
"' V \
,,
I
ü \
t;; \
,,
a. 150
V>
c:
0
"....
\ -~
\
\
V>
t;; 100
a. .. \
\
\
ë \
t;; 50
.0
\
E \
:::J \
z 0
2 3 5 6 7 8 9 10 12
Clan "
Figure 3. Distribution of the population at Zuni and among the Hopi of
the first mesa according to clan.
72
THE LOGIC OF TOTEMIC CLASSIFICATIONS
73
THE SAVAGE MIND
the aesthetic and the logical, and those who have tried to define
them in terms of only one or the other aspect have therefore
necessarily failed to understand their nature. Between the basic
absurdity Frazer attributed to primitive practices and beliefs and
the specious validation of them in terms of a supposed common
sense invoked by Malinowski, there is scope for a whole science
and a whole philosophy.
74
CHAPTER THREE
SYSTEMS OF TRANSFORMATIONS
75
THE SAVAGE .MIND
.yaumako
0 .•N1filole
en•c?s!• Cruz I~
'•Vanikoro
Tikopia•
. ..,0
Banks I~ !~ Motla11 ..,
Ureparapara49 ~Mota :Il
Vanua Lava Merig >
S~• Marial> •,Merlav z
cri
C\J\ &Aurora ..,.,
Espiritu Santo~ ca!-Aoba 0
New Hebrides ('.... .1Wentecost :Il
MalekulauQ Ambrym
\$:Epi
::::
>
Tongoa::emae
0 Efate
...0
-!
Eromangao
z
cri
AUSTRALIA .Aniwa
Tanna Il •Futuna
20·
0 250miles
150• 160'
Fig 4 Partial map of Melanesia (Centre documentaire sur l'Oceanie de !'Ecole Pratique des Hautes Etudes).
THF. SAVAGE MIND
which was found, then the child may not even touch the tree on
which it grows. Ingestion or contact are regarded as a sort of
auto-cannibalism. The relation between the person and the object
is so close that the person possesses the characteristics of the object
with which he is identified. If, for example, it was an eel or sea-
snake which was found, the child will, like these, be weak and
indolent, if a hermit crab, it will be hot-tempered; or again, it will
be gentle and sweet-natured like the lizard, thoughtless, hasty and
intemperate like the rat or, if it was a wild apple which was found,
it will have a big belly the shape of an apple. These identifications
are also to be found at Motlav (the name of a part of Saddle Island)
(Rivers, p. 462). The connection between an individual on the one
hand and a plant, animal or object on the other is not general; it
only affects some people. It is not hereditary and it does not in volve
exogamous prohibitions between the men and women who happen
to be associated with creatures of the same species (Frazer vol. II,
pp. 81-3, pp. 89-91 (quoting Rivers), and vol. IV, pp. 286-7).
Frazer regards these beliefs as the origin and explanation of those
found at Lifu in the Loyalty Islands and at Ulawa and Malaita in
the Solomon Islands. At Lifu a man before he dies sometimes
indicates the animal (or bird or butterfly) in whose form he will be
reincarnated. All his descendants are then forbidden to eat or kill
this animal. 'It is our ancestor', they say, and offerings are made to
it. Similarly Codrington observed that in the Solomon Islands
(Ulawa) the inhabitants refused to plant banana trees or eat
bananas because an important person, so he could be reincarnated
in them, had once forbidden it before his death.* In Central
Mclanesia the origin of food taboos must therefore be sought in the
fanciful imaginations of particular ancestors. Frazer believed that
they were the indirect result and distant repercussions of the
cravings and sickly imaginings common among pregnant women.
He held that this psychological trait, which he elevated to the status
of a natural and universal phenomenon, was the ultimate origin of
all totemic bcliefs and practices (Frazer, vol. II, pp. 106-7 et
passim).
The fact that the women of his period and circle of society
• This fact is confirmcd by Ivens, pp. 269-70, who puts forward a somewhat
different interprctation. However, he cites other prohibitions originating in
reincarnation of an ancestor. Cf. pp. 272, 468 and passim. Cf. also C.E. Fox for
heliefs of the same type at San Cri,;to,·al.
SYSTEMS OF TRANSFORMATIONS
experienced cravings when they were pregnant and that the savage
Australian and :\Ielanesian women also did so was enough to
convince Frazer of the universality and natural origin of the
phenomenon. He would have had otherwise to dissociate it from
nature and attribute it to culture, thus admitting that there could
in some way be direct, and so alarming, resemblances between late
nineteenth century European societies and those of the cannibals.
~ow, apart from the fact that there is no evidence that pregnant
women the world over have cravings, their incidence has dimin-
ished considerably in Europe in the last fifty years and they may
even have disappeared altogether in some sections of society. They
certainly occurred in Australia and :.Vlelanesia but in the form of an
institutional means of defining in advance certain aspects of the
status of persons or groups. And in Europe itself, it is unlikcly that
the cravings of pregnant women will survive the disappearance of
a similar type of belief which fosters them - on the pretext of
referring to them - in order to diagnose (not predict) certain
physical or psychological peculiarities noticed after (not before) a
child's birth. Even if it were the case that the cravings of pregnant
women had a natural basis, this latter could not account for beliefs
and practices which, as \Ve have seen, arc far from being general
and which can take different forms in diffcrcnt societies.
Further, it is not clear what made Frazer give the 'sick fancies' of
pregnant women priority over those of old men at death's door,
except perhaps the fact that people must be born before they can
die. But by this reasoning ail social institutions should have corne
into existence in the course of a single generation. Finally, had the
system of Ulawa, l\Ialaita and Lifu been derived from that of
:\Iotlav, Mota and Aurora, the remains or survivais of the latter
should be found in the former. What is striking, however, is thatthe
two systems are exact counterparts of each other. There is nothing
to suggest that one is chronologically prior to the other. Their
relation is not that of an original to a derivative form. I t is rather
that between forms symmetrically the reverse of each other, as if
system represented a transformation of the same group.
Instead of trying to discern the priorities, let us think in terms of
groups and attempt to define their properties. W e can summarize
these properties as a triple opposition: between birth and death on
the one hand, and between the individual or collective nature
either of a diagnosis or of a prohibition on the other. It is worth
79
THE SAVAGE MIND
is, at least in theory, left to chance. For this double reason, these
systems belong immediately beside the Australian systems of the
Aranda type, as Frazer saw althm,igh he misunderstood the nature
of the relationship - logical and not genetic - which unîtes them
while at the same time recognizing the distinctiveness of each. The
Aranda systems are also of a statistical nature but their rule of
application is universal since the domain they govern is coextensive
with the whole society.
Matnlineal moiety 1
\
\
\ Female cycles
'
1
}' A man Al
(!rom matrilineal moiety 1)
marries
(te::::)~)
-,c2 a woman C2
...
The children are:
Cl= B2
'~{
Boys A2 (continuous line)
Dl=A2 who marry women 01 (broken
line. outer circle)
A2
Social structure and
marriage rules of
the Aranda type
A2! Girls A2 (broken line. inner
circle) married by men
.~ Dl (cont1nuous line)
Fig 5 Social structure and marriage rules of the Aranda type (Laboratoire
de cartographie de !'Ecole Pratique des Hautes Etudes).
THE SA V AGE MIN D
• Among the Aranda 'there was no set order ... each separate ceremony is the
property of some special individual' but among the \Varramunga 'the cere-
monies connected with a given totem are perfonned in a regular sequence: A,
B, C, D' (Spencer and Gillen, p. 192-3).
86
SYSTEMS OF TRANSFORMATIONS
SOUTH NORTH
\Ve see therefore that going from the Aranda to the \Varramunga,
one passes from a system with a collective mythology (multiplicity
of ancestors) but an individualized ritual to the reverse system of
an individualized mythology but a collective ritual. Similarly the
properties ascribed to the earth are religious (associated with
totems) among the Aranda and social among the \Varramunga
(territory is divided between the moietics). Finally, the churinga
progressively disappears as one goes north. \Vhat has already been
said might almost have led one to expect this, since in the Aranda
context the churinga serves to bring unity into multiplicity: it
represents the physical body of an ancestor and is held by a series
of successive individuals as proof of their genealogical descent, and
THE SAVAGE MIND
88
SYSTEMS OF TRANSFORMATIONS
laws. The greater our knowledge, the more obscure the overall
scheme. The dimensions multiply, and the growth of axes of
reference beyond a certain point- paralyses intuitive methods: it
becomes impossible to visualize a system when its representation
requires a continuum of more than three or four dimensions. But
the day may corne when all the available documentation on Austra-
lian tribes is transferred to punched cards and with the help of a
computer their entire techno-economic, social and religious
structures can be shown to be like a vast group of transformations.
The idea is the more attractive since it is at least possible to
see why Australia should be a particularly favourable field for such
an experiment, more so than any other continent. In spite of the
contact and inter-change with the outside world which has also
taken place in Australia, Australian societies have probably
developed in isolation more than appears to have been the case
elsewhere. :\foreover, this development was not undergone
passively. It was desired and conceptualized, for few civilizations
seem to equal the Australians in their taste for erudition and
speculation and what sometimes looks like intellectual dandyism,
odd as this expression may appear when it is applied to people
with so rudimentary a level of material life. But lest there be any
mistake about it: these shaggy and corpulent savages whose
physical resemblance to adipose bureaucrats or veterans of the
Empire makes their nudity yet more incongruous, these meticulous
adepts in practices which seem to us to display an infantile perver-
sity - manipulation and handling of the genitals, tortures, the
industrious use of their own blood and their own excretions and
secretions (like our own more discreet and unreflecting habit of
moistening postage stamps with saliva)- were, in various respects,
real snobs. They have indeed been referred to as such by a special-
ist, born and brought up among them and speaking their language
(T. G. H. Strehlow, p. 82). When one considers them in this light,
it seems less surprising that as soon as they were taught accom-
plishments of leisure, they prided themsdves on painting the dull
and studied water-colours one might expect of an old maid (Plate 8).
Granting that Australia has been turned in on itself for hundreds
of thousands of years, • that theorizing and discussion was all the
• With the undoubted exception of the northern regions and these were not
without contact with the rest of the continent. This is therefore only an approxi-
mation.
THE SAVAGE MIND
rage in this closed world and the influence of fashion often para-
mount, it is easy to understand the emergence of a sort of common
philosophical and sociological style along with methodically
studied variations on it, even the most minor of which were
pointed out for favourahle or adverse comment. Each group was
no doubt actuated by the only apparently contradictory incentives
of being like others, as good as others, better than others and
different from others, that is, of constantly elaborating themes only
the general outlines of which were fixed by tradition and custom.
In short, in the field of social organization and religious thought,
the Australian communities behaved like the peasant societies of
Europe in their manner of dressing in the la te eighteenth and early
nineteenth centuries. That each community had its own dress and
that this was composed of roughly the same elements for men and
women respectively was never callcd in question. It was in wealth
or ingenuity of detail alone that people tried to distinguish them-
selves from, and to outdo, the neighbouring village. Ali women
wore coifs but they were different in different regions. ln France
marriage rules of an endogamous kind were expressed in terms of
coifs (':\Iarry within the coif') just as Australian rules (of an
exogamous kind) were expressed in terms of sections or totemism.
Here, as elsewhere, among the Australian aborigines as in our own
peasant societies the combination of general conformity (which is
a feature of a closed world) with the particularism of the parish
results in culture being treated like thcmes and variations in music.
It is therefore conceivable that the favourable historical and geo-
graphical conditions outlined have led to Australian cultures stand-
ing in a relation of transformation with each other, possibly more
completely and systematically than those of other regions of the
world. But this external relation must not make us neglect the
same relation, this time internai, which exists, in a very much more
general fashion, between the different levels of a single culture.
As 1 have already suggestcd, ideas and beliefs of the 'totemic' type
particularly merit attention because, for the societies which have
constructed or adopted them, they constitute codes making it
possible to ensure, in the form of conceptual systems, the con-
vertibility of messages appertaining to each level, even of those
which are so remotc from each other that they apparently relate
solely to culture or solely to society, that is, to men's relations with
each other, on the one hand, or, on the other, to phenomena of a
90
SYSTEMS OF TRANSFORMATIONS
::1 1 1 1
1.4
1 11H 1111
13 1 1 1 1 1 1 t-]-f1. 1
1
1
1
1
1
1
I~
1 1 1
~
1 1
12
[
1
::r_l
1
::rJ_
1
I
1
::r
1
I
1111
:I I 1 :.I:
1 :I
11
10
L
1
1
1
1
1
1
1
1
1
J_
1
1
1
1
1
1
J_
1
1
1
1 J_
II
I
7.1
1
1
1
1
1
1
,
.11 1
1
1
1
1
1
1
1
1
J_ .1
9
1
8 -1:I
7
1
1
1
1
1
1
1
1
1
1
1 J_I
1 I..1
1
1
1
1
t _li11, .1
1
1
1
1
1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1
1
1
1 1 1 1 1111 1 1 1 1\ 1
1
1
1
1
1
1
1
1
1
1
1
11t 1
1
1
1
1
1
1 +! 1
1
1
+--1 I~
1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1
1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1
L J_ J_ J_ J_
±1
1Z
J_ \
1
L
1
J_
1 1
J_
1
J_
1 1
1
1
1
1
1
1
1 "
1\
1
1
~
L J_ J_ / J_ 1 1 1 1
I ::r I ::r
June July Aug. Sept. Oct. Nov. Dec. Jan. Feb. March April May
Fig 6 Rain chart for Port Darwin (forty-six-year record) (from Warner,
Chart XI, p. 380).
The rainy season forces the :\1urngin to disperse and take refuge in
small groups in the areas which have not been submerged. Here
they carry on a precarious existence, threatened by famine and
inundation. A few days after the floods have receded the vegetation
is lush again and animais reappear. Collective life begins once
more and abundance reigns. None ofthis would however have been
possible had the floods not swamped and fertilized the plains.
Just as the seasons and winds are divided between the two
moieties (the rainy season together with the west and northwest
winds are Dua while the dry season and southeast wind are Yiritja),
so the protagonists of the great mythical drama, the snake and the
Wawilak sisters, are associated with the rainy and the dry season
respectively. The former represents the male and initiated element,
the latter the female and uninitiated. They must collaborate if
there is to be life. As the myth explains: had the Wawilak sisters
92
SYSTE:\tS OF TRANSFORMATIONS
93
THE SAVAGE MIND
state of affairs. There are two seasons just as there are two sexes,
t\vo societies, two degrees of culture (the 'high' - that of the
initiated - and the 'low'; cf. Stanner 1, p. 77 for this distinction).
On the natural plane, however, the good season is subordinate to
the bad, while on the social plane the relation between the corres-
ponding terms is reversed. I t is therefore necessary to decide how
to interpret the contradiction. If the good season is said to be male
on the grounds that it is superior to the bad season and that men
and the initiated are superior to women and the uninitiated (a
category to which women also belong) then not only power and
efficacy but sterility as well would have to be attributed to the
profane and female element. This would be doubly absurd since
social power belongs to men and natural fertility to women. The
other alternative is equally contradictory but its inconsistency can
at least be disguised by the double division of the whole society
into the t\rn classes of men and women (now ritually as well as
naturally differentiated) and the group of men into the two classes
of old and young, initiated and uninitiated, according to tfi.e
principle that the uninitiated stand in the same relation to the inia-
ted in the society of men as women do to men within the society as
a whole. But in consequence men forego embodying the happy sicle
of existence for they cannot both rule and personify it. Irrevocably
committed to the role of gloomy owners of a happiness accessible
only through an intermcdiary, they fashion an image of themselves
on the mode! of their sages and old men; and it is striking that two
types of people, women on the one hand and old men on the other,
constitute, as the mcans to and the masters of happiness respec-
tively, the two poles of Australian society and that to attain full
masculinity young men must temporarily renounce the former and
lastingly subm1t to the latter.
The sexual privileges which old men enjoy, the contrai they
exercise over an esoteric culture and sinister and mysterious
initiation rites are undoubtedly general features of Australian
societies, and examples could also be found in other parts of the
world. 1 do not wish to daim that these phenomena are attributable
to what are obviously local natural conditions. ln order to avoid
misunderstandings and in particular the charge of reviving an old
geographical determinism, this needs to be explained.
The first point is that natural conditions are not just passively
accepted. \Vhat is more they do not exist in their own right for
94
SYSTEMS OF TRANSFORMATIONS
they are a fonction of the techniques and way of life of the people
who define and give them a meaning by developing them in a
particular direction. Nature is n«>t: in itself contradictory. It can
become so only in terms of some specific human activity which
takes part in it; and the characteristics of the environment take on
a different meaning according to the particular historical and
technical form assumed in it by this or that type of activity. On
the other hand, even when raised to that human level which alone
can make them intelligible, man's relations with his natural
environment remain objects of thought: man never perccives them
passively; having reduced them to concepts, he compounds them
in order to arrive at a system which is never determined in
advance: the same situation can always be systematized in various
ways. The mistake of Mannhardt and the Naturalist School was to
think that natural phenomena are what myths seek to explain, when
they are rather the medium through which myths try to explain
facts which are themseh-cs not of a natural but a logical order.
The sense in which infrastructures are primary is this: first, man
is like a player who, as he takes his place at the table, picks up cards
which he has not invented, for the cardgame is a datum of history
and civilization. Second, each deal is the result of a contingent
distribution of the cards, unknown to the players at the time. One
must accept the cards which one is given, but each society, like
each player, makes its intcrprctations in terms of several systems.
These may be common to them ail or individual: rules of the game
or rules of tactics. And we are well aware that different players will
not play the same game with the same hand even though the rules
set limits on the games that can be played with any given one.
To explain the noticeable frequency of certain sociological
solutions, not attributable to particular objective conditions, appeal
must be made to form and not content. The substance of contra-
dictions is much less important than the fact that they exist, and
it would be a remarkable coïncidence if a harmonious synthesis of
the social and natural order were to be achieved at once. Now, the
form contradictions take varies very much less than their empirical
content. The poverty of religious thought can never be over-
estimated. It accounts for the fact that men have so often had
recourse to the same means for solving problems whose concrete
elements may be very different but which share the feature of ail
belonging to 'structures of contradiction'.
95
THE SAVAGE MIND
To return to the Murngin: one can see clearly how the system
of totemic symbols permits the unification of heterogeneous
semantic fields, at the cost of contradictions which it is the fonction
of ritual to surmount by 'acting' them: the rainy season literally
engulfs the dry season as men 'possess' women, and the initiated
'swallow up' the uninitiated, as famine destroys plenty, etc. The
example of the Murngin is not however unique. There are sugges-
tive indications of a 'coding' of a natural situation in totemic terms
in other parts of the world also. A specialist on the Ojibwa, reflect-
ing on the symbolization of thunder as a bird which is so common
in North America, makes the following remark:
According to meteorological observations, the average number of days
with thunder begins with one in April, increases to a total of five in mid-
summer (July) and then declines to one in October. And if a bird calendar
is consulted, the facts show that species wintering in the South begin to
appear in April and disappear for the most part not later than October ...
The avian character of the Thunder Birds can be rationalized to some
degree with reference to natural facts and their observation (Hallowell, p.
32).
One must refer to meteorological data, as Warner did in the case
of Australia, to give a correct account of the personification of
natural phenomena, common in the Hawaiian pantheon. The gods
Kane-hekili (Male-in-the-form-of-gentle-rain), Ka-poha-Ka-a
(Male [= sky]-the-rock-roller) who is the same as Ka'uila-
nuimakeha (Male- [ = sky]-lightning-flash-great-streaking), etc.,
cannot be distinguished and accurately placed without certain
relevant information:
The downpours, which corne in late January, February and March
predominantly and with greatest frequency and violence, develop in the
following sequences of meteorological phenomena; lowering dark cumu-
lus over sea and uplands, with atmospheric stillness inducing an increasing
sense of ominous oppression; 'dry' thunder, sharp and threatening if near,
like distant cannon if far away: followed very soon by slow, gentle pre-
cipitation, which increases rapidly to a downpour; with continuing heavy
thunder, then, in the cloud and rain shrouded uplands, resounding and
thudding, slowly passing along the ridges or round the mountain's fiank
and often then out to sea, where it resounds in dull thuds, and may return
in a direction opposite to that along the ridge, a phenomenon produced
by the miniature cyclonic action of winds, and by convection (Handy and
Pukui, part IV, p. 125 n).
97
THE SAVAGE MIND
skin symbolizes difficulty in the healing of the scar; the genet whose
spotted skin symbolizes leprosy; the hare with his sharp teeth and
'hot' chillies which symbolize painful healing, etc. Female
initiates are subject to analogous prohibitions (C. M. N. White, 1,
2).
These prohibitions have been mentioned because they are
specialized, well-defined and rationalized. with precision. They can
readily be distinguished from totemic prohibitions within the
gcneral category of eating prohibitions and contrasted with them.
But Tessman's list of the very large number of prohibitions of the
Fang of the Gabon includes examples of intermediate as well as
extreme types - which explains why the question of whether the
Fang are totemic has been so hotly contested even by those
believing in the concept of totemism.
The prohibitions which the Fang call by the gcneral term beki
may apply to men or to women, to the initiated to the uninitiated,
to adolescents or adults, to households in which a child is expected
or to those in which it is not. The reasons given for them are m6re-
over of very different kinds. The inside of elephants' tusks may not
be eaten because it is a soft and bitter substance. The trunk of the
elephant may not be eaten for fear of softening limbs, sheep and
goats lest they communicate their panting. Squirrels are forbidden
to pregnant women because they make childbirth difficult (cf.
above [p. 6r]). Mice are specially forbidden to girls because they
shamelessly steal manioc while it is being washed and the girls
would run the risk of being 'stolen' in the same way. Mice are
however also more generally forbidden because they live near
homesteads and are regarded as members of the family. Sorne
birds are avoidecl for such reasons as their ugly cry or their physical
appearance. Children may not eat the larvae of dragonfly because
it might make them unable to hold thcir urine.
The idea of a dietetic experiment envisaged by Tessman has
recently been taken up by Fischer with respect to the natives of
Ponapy who believe that the violation of food taboos results in
physiological disorders very like allergies. Fischer shows that
allergie disorders often have a psychosomatic origin even among
ourselves: in man y patients they result from the violation of a
taboo of a psychological or moral kind. This apparently natural
symptom derives, then, from a cultural diagnosis.
Among the Fang, of whose prohibitions I have mentioned only
SYSTEMS OF TRANSFORMATIONS
99
THE SAVAGE MIND
harm to birds. The members of the Eagle clan are forbidden to put
feathers on their heads. The members of the 'Chief' clan should
never say anything against a human being, those of the Beaver clan
should not swim across rivers and those of the White Wolf should
not shout (:Vlichelson 2, pp. 64-5).
Even in the areas where there is the best evidence of eating
prohibitions it is striking that they are rarely distributed evenly.
A dozen neighbouring cultures (consisting of a hundred tribes) have
been described and analysed in the well-circumscribed region of
the Cape York Peninsula. They ail have one or more forms of
totemism, of moiety, section, clan or cuit group, but only some of
them have eating prohibitions. Clan totemism involves prohibitions
among the patrilineal Kauralaig. The Yathaikeno, on the contrary,
who are also patrilineal, only forbid initiation totems which are
transmitted in the maternai line. The Koko Yao have moiety
clan totems which are patrilineally transmitted and permitted, and
initiation totems which are matrilineally transmitted and forbidden
initiation totems which are matrilineally transmitted and for-
bidden. The Tjongandji have only patrilineal clan totems which
are not subject to any prohibition. The Okerkila are divided into
two groups, east and west, one of which has prohibitions while the
other does not. The Maithakudi abstain from eating the clan
totems, which in their case are matrilineal. The Laierdila have
the same rule although they are patrilineal (Sharp) (figure 7).
As Sharp says:
Eating and killing tabus on edible group totems are invariably associ-
ated with maternai cuit and matrilineal social totemism. Tabus are more
variable in connection with patrilineal cult totemism, being present more
commonly for moiety than clan totems (Sharp, p. 70).
The findings within a particular region confirm the general relation
between eating prohibitions and matrilineal institutions which
Elkin held to exist throughout the continent. As social institutions
are the work of men - as a general rule and especially in Australia -
what this amounts to is that there is a connection between the male
and the consumer and between the f emale and the thing consumed.
1 shall return to this later.
Finally there are cases where the idea of eating prohibitions is
as it were turned inside out. The prohibition is turned into an
obligation and applies not to Ego himself but to someone else; and
it no longer relates to the totemic animal thought of as food but to
100
SYSTEMS OF TRANSFORMATIONS
,,
I
VI .
1
' ..,
''
' ...\
, I
1
1
-.
VII
' \
'\.
\
\
'\
I
,,
IX I Vil 1
1
'
1
l
'\.
'
',
', ,'
/
,
l
,' --
..... ....
.. ,
, ... ____ ___ .,
' , '..,~,' ; ' Vlll '
, ,
,,
,,
Fig 7 Types of totemic organization in the Cape York Peninsula (following
Sharp). 1. Kauralaig Type; Il. Yaithaikeno Type; Ill. Koko Yao Type;
IV. Tjongandji Type; V. Yir Yoront Type; VI. Oikol Type; VII.
Okerkila Type; VIII. Maithakudi Type; IX. Laierdila Type.
IOI
THE SAVAGE :>'IlND
104
SYSTEMS OF TRANSFORMATIONS
105
THE SAVAGE MIND
the sexes and the union of eater and eaten is that they both effect a
conjuncti on by corn plementarity:
\Vhat is destitute of motion is the food of those endowed with locomo-
tion; (animais) without fangs (are the food) of those with fangs, those
without hands of those who possess hands, and the timid of the bold (The
Laws of 1\fanu, v, 29).
The equation of male with devourer and female with devoured is
the more familiar to us and certainly also the more prevalent in the
world but one must not forget that the inverse equivalence is often
found at a mythological level in the theme of the vagina dentata.
Significantly enough this is 'coded' in terms of eating, that is,
directly (thus confirming the law of mythical thought that the
transformation of a metaphor is achieved in a metonymy). It may
also be the case that the thème of the vagina d enta ta corresponds to
a point of view, no longer inverted but direct, in the sexual
philosophy of the Far East where, as the works of Van Gulik show,
for a man the art of love-making consists essentially in avoiding
having his vital force absorbed by the women and in turning this
risk to his ad\·antage.
This logical subordination of resemblance to contrast is clearly
illustrated in the complex attitude of some so-called totemic
peoples toward the parts of body of eponymous animais. The
Tikuna of the High Solimoes, who practise 'hypertotemic'
exogamy (the members of the Toucan clan cannot inter-marry
either among themselves or with the members of any clan called by
a bird name, etc.), freely eat the eponymous animal but they respect
and preserve a sacred part of it and use others as distinctive
ornaments (Alviano). The totemic animal is thus resolved into an
edible part, a part to be respected and an emblematic part. The
Elema of Southern New Guinea observe a very strict prohibition
on eating their totems. Each clan however retains the exclusive
prerogatiœ of using the beak, feathers, tail, etc. of its totem animal
for ornamental purposes (Frazer, vol. II, p. 41). There is thus in
both cases an opposition between edible and non-edible parts,
homologous to that between the categories of food and emblem. In
the case of the Elema it is expressed through a two-fold exclusivism
which may be either negative or positive: in relation to the totemic
species, each clan abstains /rom its meat but retains those parts of it
which display the characteristics of its species. The Tikuna are
equally exclusive with respect to the distinctive parts of the
106
SYSTEMS OF TRANSFORMATIONS
\ \
Tikuna: non-exèlusive exclusive
\ \
\ \
\ \
\ \
\ \
\ \
\ \
\ \
\ \
\
\ \
\ \
\ \
\ \
'\ \
The fur, feathers, beak and teeth can be mine because they are that
in which the eponymous animal and I differ from each other: this
difference is assumed by man as an emblcm and to assert his
symbolic relation with the animal. The parts which are edible and
so can be assimilated are the sign of genuine consubstantiality but
which, contrary to what one might suppose, it is the real aim of
the prohibition on eating them to deny. Ethnologists have made
the mistake of taking only this second aspect into account and this
has led them to conceive the relation between man and animal to
be of a single kind: identity, affinity or participation. l\Iatters are in
fact infinitely more complex: there is an exchange of similarities
and differences between culture and nature, sometimes as amongst
animais on the one sicle and man on the other and sometimes as
between animais and men.
The differences between animais, which man can extract from
nature and transfer to culture ( ei ther by describing them in terms
of opposites and contrasts and thus conceptualizing them or by
taking over concrete, non-perishable parts: feathers, beaks, teeth -
which equally constitutes an 'abstraction') are adopted as emblems
by groups of men in order to do away with their own resemblances.
And the same animais are rejected as food by the same group of
men, in other words the resemblance between man and animal
resulting from the fact that the former can assimilate the flesh of
107
THE SAVAGE MIND
108
CHAPTER FOUR
Both the exchange of women and the ex change of food are means
of securing or of displaying the interlocking of social groups with
one another. This being so, we can see why they may be found
either together or separately. They are procedures of the same type
and are indeed generally thought of as two aspects of the same
procedure. They may reinforce each other, both performing the
actual function, or one performing it and the other representing it
symbolically. Or they may be alternatives, a single one fulfilling the
whole function or if that is otherwise discharged, as it can be even
in the absence of both procedures, then the symbolic representation
of it:
If ... a people combines exogamy with totemism, this is because it has
chosen to reinforce the social cohesion already established by totemism
by superimposing on it yet another system which is connected with the
first by its reference to physical and social kioship and is distinguished
from, though not opposed toit, by its Jack of reference to cosmic kinship.
Exogamy can play this same part in types of society which are built on
foundations other than totemism; and the geographical distribution of
the two institutions coïncides only at certain points in the world.
(Van Gennep, pp. 351).
However exogamy, as we know, is never entirely absent. This is due
to the fact that the perpetuation of the group can only be effected
by means of women, and although varying degrees cf symbolic
content can be introduced by the particular way in which a society
organizes them or thinks of their operation, marriage exchanges
always have real substance, and they are alone in this. The exchange
of food is a different matter. Aranda women really bear children.
But Aranda men confine themselves to imagining that their rites
THE SAVAGE MIND
who has known how to persuade his neighbours' yams to move and
establish themselves in his garden. A man who has a good harvest
is reckoned a lucky thief (Fortune 2).
Beliefs of the same type were to be found even in France until
recently. In the middle ages there was a penalty of death for 'the
sorceress who defiled and injured crops; who, by reciting the
psalm Super aspidem ambulabis, emptied the fields of their corn to
fill her own granary with this goodly produce'. Not so long ago at
Cubjac in the Perigord a magical invocation was supposed to
assure the person using it of a good crop of turnips: 'May our
neighbours' be as big as millet seed, our relations' as big as grains
of corn and our own as big as the head of Fauve the ox !' (Rocal,
pp. 164-5).
Apart from the modicum of exogamy resulting from the pro-
hibited degrees, European peasant societies practised strict local
endogamy. And it is significant that at Do bu extreme endo-agricul-
ture can act as the symbolic compensation for lineage and village
exogamy which is practised with repugnance and even f ear. In
spite of the fact that endogamy within the locality - which consists
of between four and twenty villages - is generally assured, marriage
even into the next village is looked on as putting a man at the mercy
of assassins and sorcerers and he himself always regards his wife
as a powerful magician, ready to decei\'e him with her childhood
friends and to destroy him and his (Fortune 2). In a case like this,
endo-agriculture reinforces a latent tendency towards endogamy,
if indeed it does not express symbolically the hostility to the
unwillingly practised rules of a precarious exogamy. The situation
is symmetrically the reverse of that prevailing in Australia where
food prohibitions and rules of exogamy reinforce one another, as
we ha\·e seen in a more symbolic and clearly conceptual way in the
patrilineal societies (where the food prohibitions are flexible and
tend to be formulated in terms of moieties, that is, at a level which
is already abstract and lends itself to a binary coding by pairs of
oppositions) and in a more literai and concrete fashion in the
matrilineal societies (where the prohibitions are rigid anrl stated in
terms of clans which one might often be hesitant to regard as
members of systematic sets, given the determining part of demo-
graphic and historie factors in their genesis ).
Apart from these cases of positive or negative parallelism, there
are others in which reciprocity between social groups is expressed
III
THE SAVAGE MIND
112
TOTEM AND CASTE
his own may not touch an cmu. But if, on the othcr hand, he is in
company he is permitted and even supposed to kill it and offer it
to hunters of other clans. Conversely, when he is alone a man of
the Water clan may drink if hc is thirsty but when he is with others
he must receive the water from a member of the other moiety,
prefcrably from a brother-in-law (Spencer and Gillen, pp.
159-60). Among the \Varramunga each totemic group is respons-
ible for the increase and a vailability to other groups of a particular
plant or animal species: 'The members of one moiety ... take
charge ... of the ceremonies of the other moiety which are des-
tined to secure the increase of their own food suppl y'. Among the
\Valpari as well as the \Varramunga the secondary totemic prohi-
bitions (applying to the maternai totem) are waived if the food in
question is obtained through the agency of a man of the other
moiety. l\1ore generally and for any totem, therc is a distinction
between the groups which never eat it (because it is their own
totem), those which eat it only if it is procured through the agency
of another group (as in the case of the maternai totems), and those
which eat it freely in any circumstances. Similarly in the case of
the sacred water-holes, women may never approach them, uniniti-
ated men may approach but not drink from them, while some
groups drink from them on the condition that the water is given
to them by members of other groups who can themselves drink
freely from them (Spencer and Gillen, pp. 164, 167). This mutual
interdependence is already to be seen in marriage which, as
Radcliffe-Brown has shown in the case of Australia (but the same
could equally well be said of other clan societies such as the
Iroquois), was based on reciprocal gifts of vegetable food (fem-
inine) and animal food (masculine): the conjugal family in these
cases was like a miniature society with two castes.
There is thus Jess difference than would appear between
societies which, like some Australian tribes, assign a distinctive
magico-cconomic fonction to totemic groups and, for instance,
the Bororo of Central Brazil, among whom specialists are in charge
of the same fonction of 'liberating' the food production - whether
animal or vegctable - for the whole group (Colbacchini). This
leads one to doubt whether the opposition between endogamous
castes and exogamous totcmic groups is really radical. There seem
to be connections between these two extreme types, whose nature
114
TOTEM AND CASTE
sisters and daughters with them since it will tend to think of them
as being of a particular 'species'. Two images, one social and the
other natural, and each articulated ~eparately, will be replaced by a
socio-natural image, single but fragmented :*
::-;ATl"RE:
species r species 2 species 3 species n
Cl"LTL'RE:
group group 2 group 3 group n
I 17
THE SAVAGE MIND
(the tribes of the plains and of the south west) and societies such
as the Natchez which afford one of the rare examples of genuine
castes known in ~ orth America.
W e have thus established that in the two classical territories of
so-called totemism, the institutions defined with ref erence to this
misleading notion can either also be characterized from the point
of view of their function, as in Australia or, as in America, make
way for forms which are still conceived on the model of totemic
groups although they operate more like castes.
Let us now turn to India, also classical territory but of castes.
I shall try to show that through their influence institutions tradi-
tionally thought of as totemic undergo a transformation exactly the
reverse of that in America: instead of castes conceived in terms of
a natural model we have here totemic groups conceived in terms
of a cultural mode!.
l\Iost of the totemic names found among certain tribes in Bengal
derive from animals or plants. This is the case with some sixty-
seven totems recorded among the Oraon of Chota Nagput with
the exception of iron which, as there is little point in proscribing
its consumption, is forbidden to corne into contact with lips or
tongue. This prohibition is thus still formulated in terms that
make it approximate to an eating prohibition. Among the Munda
of the same region, the majority of the three hundred and forty
exogamous clans recorded have animal or plant totems, the
consumption of \vhich is forbidden. Totems of a different kind are
however already noticeable: full moon, moonlight, rainbow,
months of the year, days of the week, copper bracelet, verandah,
umbrella, professions or castes such as that of basket-maker and
torch-bearer (Risley, vol. II and Appendix). Further west, the
forty-three names of the Bhil clans are divided into nineteen plant
and seventeen animal names and seven relate to objects: dagger,
broken pot, village, thorny stick, bracelet, ankle ring, piece of bread
(Koppers, pp. 118-19).
It is towards the south that the reversa! in the relation of natural
specits and objects or manufactured goods becomes particularly
conspicuous. Few plants and scarcely any animais figure in the
names of the clans of the Devanga, a caste of weavers in the
:\Iadras area. On the other hand, the following names are found:
buttermilk, cattle-pen, money, dam, house, collyrium, knife,
scissors, boat, lamp, cloths, female clothing, ropes for hanging pots,
120
TOTE:\I A:-ID CASTE
endogamy exogamy
1 1
restricted generalized
ex change ex change
the cultural plane. In the same way that women who are homo-
geneousso far as nature is concernedare declared to be heterogeneous
from the point of \'Îew of culture, so natural species, which are
heterogeneous so far as nature is concerned are proclaimed to be
homogeneous from the point of Yiew of culture: culture asserts
them ail to be subject to the same type of beliefs and practices since
in the eyes of culture, they han the comrnon feature that man has
the power to contrai and increase them. Consequently, men by
cultural means exchange women who perpetuate these same men
by natural means and they claim to perpetuate species by cultural
means and exchange them sub specie naturae: in the form of food-
stuffs which are substitutable for each othcr since they ail provide
nourishment and since, as with women also, a man can satisfy
himself by means of some foods and go without others in so far as
any women or any foods are equally suitable to achieYe the ends
of procreation or subsistence.
128
TOTE~ AND CASTE
129
THE SAVAGE MIND
130
TOTEM AND CASTE
II uma n bcings however soon got tired of this monotonous 'di et',
so the son of the couple AB took the female product of CD and
so on for EF and G Il etc.:
ABD CDB EFII GIIF IJL KLJ
En:n thcn they were not satisfied and so the fisherman made war
<'n the hunter, the hunter on the farmer and the farmer on the
fisherman, and each appropriated the other's product. The result
was that from then on the fisherman ate flesh, the hunter the
products of the soil and the farmer fish:
ABDF CDBH EFHJ GHFL IJLB KLJD
1 33
CHAPTER FIVE
institution, when like all levels of classification it i sin fact only one
among others and there is no reason to regard it as more important
than, say, the level operating by means of abstract categories or
that using nominal classes. What is significant is not so much the
prescnce - or absence - of this or that level of classification as the
existence of a classification with, as it were, an adjustable thread
which givcs the group adopting it the means of 'focusing' on ail
planes, from the most abstract to the most concrete, the most
cultural to the most natural, without changing its intellectual
instrument.
In the work referred to above, Boas was doubtful whether the
predilection which is so frequent for classification based on a
natural mode! could be adequately explained by the 'distinctness
and individualization of species of animais ... [which] set them
off more clearly as characters of a tale than the undifferentiated
members of mankind' (!oc. cit.). Boas did, however, touch on an
important truth here. To have recognized it he need only, contrary
to a commonly held position, have been prepared, instead of
reducing the story or myth to a mere narrative, to try to discover
the scheme of discontinuous oppositions governing its organization
behind the mythical 'discourse'. Furthermore, the natural 'dis-
tinctiveness' of biological species does not furnish thought with a
means of access to other distinctive systems which have their own
repercussions on it. Ali things considered, if it is the case that zoo-
logical and botanical typologies are employed more often and more
readily than other typologies, this can only be by reason of their
intermediate position as logically equidistant from the extreme
forms of classification: categorical and singular. There is a balance
bctween the point of view of extension and that of comprehension
in the notion of a species: considered in isolation, a species is a
collection of individuals; in relation to other species, however, it is
a system of definitions. Moreover each of these individuals, the
theoretically unlimited collection of which makes up the species, is
indefinable in extension since it forms an organism which is a
system of functions. The notion of species thus possesses an in-
ternai dynamic: bcing a collection poised between two systems, the
species is the operator which allows (and even makes obligatory)
the passage from the unity of a multiplicity to the diversity of a
unity.
CATEGORIES, ELEMENTS, SPECIES, NUMBERS
1 37
THE SAVAGE MIND
• Of which 500 to 600 are only edible (I.e., p. 14 l) and 406 of purely medicinal
use (l.c., p. r88). These l ,625 types, grouped into 890 categories by indigenous
thought, correspond to 650 genera and about l,100 species in scientific botany
... (I.e., pp. 122-3).
CATEGORIES, ELEMENTS, SPECIES, NUMBERS
1
HERBACEOUS PLANT (not a woody plant, etc.)
1
1
PEPPER PLANT (not a rice plant, etc.)
(Capsicum sp.)
1
1
HOUSEYARD (not a ·wild pepper plant, ~
Capsicum f rutescens L., ~
PEPPER PLANT
(Capsicum annum L.) etc.) -
tTl
r:n
1
z
1 c::
HOUSEYARD CHI LLI (not a houseyard green ::
PEPPER PLANT pepper plant, etc.) l:t!
tTl
1
:>:!
r:n
1
'CAT-PENIS' (not one of the five other
terminal taxa)
(Conklin 4, p. 13 1)
THE SAVAGE MIND
apparently the right and left hands rather than feet, but we have
already noticed the particular attention which the Osage pays to
the lower extremities). A Kaguru man uses his lef t hand for making
love and a woman her right hand (that is, the hands which are
impure for each sex respectively). The first payment which has to
be made to a healer, before treatment can begin, is made with the
right hand, the last with the left, etc. The nomadic Fulani of the
Sahel zone of the Niger, the Bororo of Africa, seem, like the Kaguru,
to associate the right side with men and - in the temporal order -
with what cornes first, the lef t si de with women and what cornes
after.• Symmetrically, the masculine hierarchy goes from south to
north and the feminine from north to south, so that, in the camp,
the woman places her calabashes in order of decreasing sizc, with
the largest to the south, while a man fastens his calves in the reverse
or der (Du pire).
To return to the Osage: the number thirteen, as we have seen, is
first of ail the sum of the two social groups, right and left, north and
south, winter and summer; thereafter it is specified concretely and
developed logically. In the image of the rising sun, in which the
beholder venerates the source of ail lifc (thus facing east, which
means that the south is on his right and the north on his left),t the
number thirteen can symbolize the union of two terms: six and
seven, sky and land, etc. But when it relates to a star the solar sym-
bolism is particularly attached to the sky moiety. Hence there corne
to be other concrete specifications of the number thirteen, in this
case reserved to sub-groups of the other moiety: thirteen foot-
prints of the black bear to represent the notable actions of the land
clans and thirteen willow trees to represent those of the water clans
(La Flesche 3, p. 147).
Thirteen is thus the expression of a double human totality: collec-
tive, since the tribe is made up of two asymmetrical moieties (quanti-
tatively: one is single, the other divided; and qualitatively: one in
• Cf. Diamond for an analogous spatio-temporal system in the same region.
t The officiant is painted red 'to express his craving that through the sun his
life may be made fruitful and that he may be blessed with a long line of descend-
ants'. \Vhen his whole body has been painted red, 'a dark line is drawn on his
face running upward from one cheek to the forehead, then across to the opposite
side and downward to the middle of the other cheek. This line represents the
dark horizon line of the earth and is called a "snare" or an enclosure into which
all life is drawn and held captive'. (La Flesche 3, p. 73).
145
THE SA VAGE MIND
charge of peace, the other of war) and individual but equally asym-
metrical (the right and the left). As a totality, this union of even and
odd, of collective and individual, social and organic, is geared to the
ternary cosmological schcme: there is a 'thirteen' of sky, a 'thirteen'
of land, a 'thirteen' of water. Finally, added to this coding by
elements, there is a coding by species where the two groups com-
posed respectively of seven and six 'animais' are duplicated by the
appearance of antagonists, thus (as might be foreseen) bringing the
number of units of the system at the most concrete level to twenty-
six. The seven animais and their antagonists are shown in the
following table :
ANIMALS ANT AGONISTS
lynx young male deer, with curved horns
grey wold young male deer, with grey horns
male puma full grown male deer, with dark homs
male black bear hummock full of little bugs (insects?)
buffalo bull high bank
elk a plant whose blossoms always look up to the sun
(Silphium laciniatum)
deer• no antagonist: his strength lies in fiight
not fall into inertia but continues to progress through new detotal-
izations and retotalizations which can take place on several planes.
Each clan possesses a 'symbol of life' - a totem or divinity-whose
name it adopts: puma, black bear, golden eagle, young deer, etc.
The clans are thus defined, in relation to each other, by means of
differentiating features. Nevertheless, the ritual texts found each
distinctive choice on a system of invariant characteristics, assumed
to be common to ail species: each affirms of itself what the puma, for
instance, declares on its own account:
'Behold the soles of my feet, that are black in colour.
I have made the skin of the soles of my feet to be as my charcoal.
\Vhen the little ones [men] also make the skin of the soles of my feet
to be as their charcoal,
They shall always have charcoal that will easily sink into their skin as
they travel the path of life.
Behold the tip of my nose, that is black in color, etc.
Behold the tips of my ears, that are black in color, etc.
Behold the tip of my tail, that is black in color, etc.'
(La Flesche 2, pp. 106-'7)
Each animal is thus decomposed into parts, according to a law of
correspondence (muzzle = beak, etc.) and the equivalent parts are
regrouped among themseh·es and then all together in terms of the
same relevant characteristic: the presence of 'charcoaled' parts, on
account of the protective raie which the Osage attribute to fire and
its product, charcoal, and finally, and by way of consequence, to
the colour black. The 'black thing', charcoal, is the abject of a
special rite which warriors have to perform before going into battle.
If they neglect to blacken their faces, they will Jose the right to
recount their notable actions and to claim military honours (La
Flesche 3, p. 327 seq.). We therefore already have a system on two
axes, one devoted to diversities and the other to similarities:
CHARCOAL ANIMAL
1 1
black paws black muzzle black tail etc.
~ s -puma-___,l,__~~~+-~~~-lc--~~~+1 ~~~~
a
u
:
s
-eagle -1
p -bear----+-------+------+------+-----
ec - deer---------1-----
~ -swan - -
--etc.---~------'-----~-----'-------
FI -----
1 47
TllF. SAVAGE MIND
As media! classifier (and therefore the one with the greatest yield
and the most frequently employed) the species level can widen its
net upwards, that is, in the direction of elements, categories, and
numbers, or contract downwards, in the direction of proper names.
This last aspect will be considered in detail in the next chapter. The
network to which this twofold movement gives rise is itself cross-eut
at every level, for there are a great many different manners in which
these levels and their ramifications can be signified: nomenclature,
differences of clothing, bodily paintings or tattoos, ways of being or
behaviour, privileges and prohibitions. Each system is therefore
defined with reference to two axes, one horizontal and one vertical,
which correspond up to a point with Saussure's distinction between
syntagmatic and associative relations. But 'totemic' thought, unlike
speech, has this in common with mythical and poetical thought
that, as Jakobson has established for the latter, the principle of
equivalence acts on both planes. The social group can code the
message without any alteration in its content by means of different
• 'We do not believe', as an Osage explained 'that our ancestors were really
animais, birds, etc., as told in traditions. These things are only wa-u:i-k11-ska'-ye
(symbols) of something higher' (J.O. Dorsey, 1, p. 396).
1 49
THE SAVAGE MIND
150
CATEGORIES, ELEMENTS, SPECIES, NUMBERS
• 'It appears that a totem may be any enduring element of the physical or
mental environment, either unique conceptual entities, or, more frequently,
classes or species of things, activities, states, or qualities which are constantly
recurring and are thus considered to be perdurable' (Sharp, p. 69).
THE SAVAGE MIND
SPECIES
0
INDIVIDUAL
... which apportions to each of the 2100 species, of plants for in-
stance, a presiding angel in heaven, and assigns this as the motive of the
Levitical prohibition of mixtures among animals and plants (Tylor, ,-ol.
II, p. 246).
In the present state of knowledge, the figure of two thousand
appears to correspond well, in order of magnitude, to a sort of
threshold corresponding roughly to the capacity of memory and
power of definition of ethnozoologies or ethnobotanies reliant on
oral tradition. 1t would be interesting to know if this threshold has
any significant properties from the point of view of Information
Theory.
1 57
THE SAVAGE MIND
they invariably reasoned along these lines: trees and the birds which made
their nests in them were in the same moiety; trees which grew alongside
creeks or in water-holes and swamps were in the same moiety as water,
fishes, water-fowl, lily-roots. 'Eaglehawk, plain turkey, everything that
flies ail work together. Carpet snake [Python variegatus] and ground
goanna [Varanus Gould?] ail work together - they travel together in olden
time' (Kelly, p. 465).
160
CHAPTER SIX
UNIVERSALIZATION AND
PARTICULARIZATION
• But this disillusioned reflection on the part of one of the champions of pu rel y
historical ethnology is enough to convince one that these two notions are of value
only as limiting cases: 'The present state of Zande clans and that of their totemic
affiliations can only be understood in the light of the political development of
Zande society, even though it can be for us only a glimmering light. Hundreds
of thousands of people of different ethnie origin ail jumbled up - the ethnologist
in Africa may sc.metimes sigh for some neat little Polynesian or Melanesian
island community!' (Evans-Pritchard, 2, p. 121).
161
THE SAVAGE MIND
point with the set of local logics inserted in it. This general logic
can be of a different order. lt is then definable by the number and
nature of the axes employed, by the ru les of transformation making
it possible to pass from one to another, and finally by the relative
inertia of the system, that is, its greater or Jess receptiveness to
unmotivated factors.
The so-called totemic classifications, the beliefs and practices
connected with them, are only one aspect or mode of this general
systematic activity. From this point of view 1 have so far done
little more than develop and deepen some comments of Van
Gennep's:
Every ordered society necessarily classes not only its human members,
but also the objects and creatures of nature, sometimes according to their
extemal form, sometimes according to their dominant psychic character-
istic, sometimes according to their utility as food, in agriculture or in
industry, or for the producer or consumer ... Nothing entitles us to
regard any one system of classification, say the zoological system of
toternism or the cosmographie system or the occupational system (castes)
as prior to the others (Van Gennep, pp. 345--6).
A footnote makes it clear that Van Gennep was fully conscious of
the boldness and novelty of this passage:
It will be seen that 1 do not accept Durkheim's view (Formes, p. 318)
that the cosmic classification of living creatures (including man) and
material objects is a consequence of totemism. In my own view, the
special form of cosmic classification found in totemism is not even a
nuance of it but one of its primitive and essential components. For
peoples without totemism also possess a system of classification which in
this case too is one of the primordial elements of their general system of
social organization and as such reacts on their Jay and magico-religious
institutions. Examples are the oriental systems, Chinese and Persian
dualism, Assyro-Babylonian cosmographism, the so-called magical
system of syrnpathetic correspondences, etc.
Van Gennep's demonstration is inadequate, however, in spite of
these sound views, for he continued to believe in totemism as an
institutional reality. He no longer tried to make it into a classi-
ficatory system from which ail others derived, but he still attempted
to preserve a distinctiveness for it comparable to that of a species
objectively identifiable within a genus:
The notion of totemic kinship is th us composed of three elements:
physiological kinship ... social kinship ... and cosmic, classificatory
kinship which links al! the men of a single group to creatures or objects
theoretically belonging to the group. What characterizes totemism •.•
UNIVERSALIZATION AND PARTICULARIZATION
and somnolence from owls, pain in the joints from rattle-snakes, etc.
(Swanton, 2).
Similar beliefs are found among the Pima of Arizona. They attri-
bute throat diseases to the badgei,- swellings, headaches and fever to
the bear, diseases of the throat and lungs to the deer, children's
diseases to the dog and coyote, stomach trouble to the gopher or
prairie-rat, ulcers to the jack-rabbit, constipation to the mouse,
nose-bleed to the ground-squirrel, haemorrhages to the hawk and
eagle, syphilitic sores to the vulture, children's fevers to the Gila
monster, rheumatism to the horned toad,* 'white fever to the !izard,
kidney and stomach troubles to the rattle-snake, ulcers and paralysis
to the turtle, internai pains to the butterfly, etc. (Russcll).t Among
the Hopi, who are a day's march from the Pima, an analogous classi-
fication is based on the organization into religious orders, each of
which can inflict a punishment in the form of a particular discase:
abdominal swelling, sore cars, horn-like swelling on the top of the
head, deafness, cczcma on the upper part of the body, twisting and
twitching of the face and neck, soreness in the bronchial tubes, bad
knee (Voth 2, p. io9 n.). The problem of classifications could un-
doubtedly be tackled from this angle and some curious resem-
blances, symptomatic of logical connections which could be of
considerable importance, might be found between distant groups
(the association of the squirre! and nose-blceding, for instance,
seems to recur in a large number of North Amcrican peoples).
The spccific categories and the myths connccted with them can
also serve to organize space, and the classificatory system is thcn
extended on a territorial and geographical basis. A classic example
is the totemic geography of the Aranda, but there are other people
equally exacting and subtle in this respect. ln Aluridja territory a
rocky site measuring five miles round the base was recently dis-
covered and described in which every accident of relief corresponds
to a phase of ritual in such a way that this natural rock illustrates the
structure of their myths and the order of the ceremonies for the
natives. Its north sicle is the sicle of the moiety of the sun and of the
• It may be noted, in support of the considerations adduced earlier (pp. 64-5)
that it is probably the same behaviour on the part of this animal which suggests
entirely different associations to the American Indians and the Chinese. The
Chinese ascribe aphrodisiac virtues to the flesh of the phrynosoma or to the wine
in which it has been macerated because the male holds on to the female so hard
during copulation that he does not let go even when caught.
t For closely related ideas among the Papago, cf. Densmore.
7-TSM
THE SAVAGE MIND
ritual cycle Kerungera, its sou th side that of the moiety of the shade
and the ritual Arangulta. Thirty-eight points on the base üf the
plateau are named and annotated (Harney).
North America also furnishes examples of mythical geography
and totemic topography, from Alaska to California as well as in the
south-west and north-east of the continent. ln this respect the
Pcnobscot of ~faine exemplify a general tendency on the part of the
northern Algonkin to interpret all the physiographic aspects of the
tribal territory in terms of the peregrinations of the civilizing hero
Gluskabe and other mythical personage or incidents. An elongated
rock is the hero's canoe, a streak of white rock represents the entrails
of the moose he killed, Kineo mountain is the overturned cooking
pot in which he cooked the meat, etc. (Speck 2, p. 7).
Again, in the Sudan, a mytho-geographical system has been dis-
covered which covers the entire Niger valley, and thus extends over
more than the territory of any single group, and in which is trans-
lated down to the minutest detail a conception of the relations
between diff erent cultural and linguistic groups which is at once
diachronie and synchronie.
This last example shows that the systems of classification not
only permit the 'furnishing', as it were, of social time (by means of
myths) and of tribal space (with the help of a conceptualized topo-
graphy). The filling in of the territorial framework is accompanied
by enlargement. In the same way that, on the logical plane, the
specific operator effects the transition to the concrete and individual
on the one hand and the abstract and systems of categories on the
other, so, on the sociological plane, totemic classifications make it
possible both to define the status of persons within a group and to
expand the group beyond its traditional confines.
Primitive socit:Lic:-. have, and not without justification, been said
to treat the limits of their tribal group as the f rontiers of humanity
and to regard everyone outside them as foreigners, that is, as dirty,
coarse sub-mcn or even non-men: dangerous beasts or ghosts. This
is often true, but what is overlooked when this is said is that one of
the essential fonctions of totemic classifications is to break down
this closing in of the group into itself and to promote an idea some-
thing like that of a humanity without frontiers. There is evidence of
this phenomenon in all the classical areas of so-called totemic organ-
ization. ln a region in \Vest Australia the clans and theirtotems 'are
grouped together into a number of what may be called inter-tribal
166
UNIVERSALIZATION AND PARTICULARIZATION
• Among the Wik Munkan a dog is called Yatut 'extracting bones of •.. the
totem fish' if his master is of the Bone-fish clan, Owun 'illicit or stolen meeting'
if his master is of the Ghost clan (Thomson, pp. 161-2).
THE SAVAGE MIND
1 have given a brief indication of how the mcshes of the net can
stretch indefinitely in accordance with the dimensions and gener-
ality of the field. 1t remains to be shown how they can also shrink
to filter and imprison reality but this time at the lower limit of the
system by extending its action beyond the threshold which one
would be inclined to assign to ail classification, that beyond which
it is no longer possible to class, but only fo name. These extreme
operations are in fact Jess widely separated than they might appear
and, when seen in the perspective of the systems we are studying,
they may even be superposed. Space is a society of particular places
as people are landmarks within the group. Places and individuals
alike are designated by proper names, which can be substituted for
each other in many circumstances common to many societies. The
Yurok of Ca!ifornia provide one example among others of this
personified geography, where trails are conceived of as animated
beings, each house is named, and the names of places replace
persona! names in current usage (\Vaterman).
An Aranda myth well expresses this feeling of correspondence
between geographical and biological individuation: the earliest
divine beings are shapeless, without limbs, and welded together
until the coming of the god Mangarkunjerkunja (the fi.y-catcher
!izard), who proceeded to separate them and fashion them indivi-
dually. At the same time (and is this not indeed the same thing ?) he
taught them the arts of civilization and the system of sections anJ
sub-sections. The eight sub-sections were originally divided into
two main groups: four land ones and four water ones. lt was the god
who 'territorialized' them by allotting each site to a pair of sub-
sections. Now, this individuation of territory corresponded to bio-
logical individuation in another way as well, in that the totemic
mode of fertilizing the mother explains the anatomie differences
observable among children. Those with fine features were con-
ceived by the operation of a ratapa, embryo-spirit; those with large
features by magical projection of a rhomb into a woman's body;
children with fair haïr were direct reincarnations of totemic
ancestors (C. Strehlow). The Australian tribes of the Drysdale
River, in Northern Kimberley, divide ail kinship relations, which
together compose the social 'body', into five categories named after
a part of the body or a muscle. Since a stranger must not be ques-
tioned, he announces his kinship by moving the relevant muscle
(Hernandez, pp. 228-9). In this case, too, therefore, the total system
168
u:-;rvERSALIZATION AND PARTICULARIZATION
of the other levels. We showed a moment ago that the Aranda attri-
bute empirically established morphological differences to hypothetic
differences in modes of totemic conception. But the examples of the
Omaha and Osage furnish evidence of a correlative tendency which
consists in introducing symbolically expressed specific differences
into empirical and individual morphology. The children of each
clan wear their haïr eut in a characteristic Style evoking a distinctive
feature or aspect of the animal or natural phenomenon which serves
as an eponym (La Flesche 4, pp. 87-9).
This modelling of the appearance according to specific, elemental,
or categorical schemes has psychological as well as physical conse-
quences. A society which defines its segments in terms of hi gh and
low, sky and land, day and night, can incorporate social or moral
attitudes, such as conciliation and aggression, peace and war,justice
and policing, good and bad, order and disorder, etc., into the same
structure of opposition. In consequence, it does not confine itself
to abstract contemplation of a system of corresponder.ce but rather
furnishes the individual members of these segments with a pretext
and sometimes even a provocation to distinguish themselves by their
behaviour. Radin (I, p. 187), referring to the Winnebago, very
rightly insists on the reciprocal influence of religious and mythical
conceptions of animais on the one hand and the political fonctions
of social units on the other.
The Sauk Indians provide a particularly instructive example by
reason of their individuating rule for determining membership of a
moiety. The moieties werc not exogamous and their role, which was
pureiy ceremonial, was principally manifested at feasts. It is
important, from our point of view, to notice that these were con-
nected with rites for the giving of names. Membership of moieties
was determined by a rule of alternation: the first born was affiliated
to the moiety of which his father was nota membcr, the next child to
themoietyof which hisfatherwas amember, andsoon. Now, at least
in theory, these affiliations determined behaviour which one might
call 'dispositional': members of the Oskûsh moiety ('the Blacks')
had to complete all their enterprises, those of the Kishko moiety
('the Whites') might give up or turn back. In theory, if not in prac-
tice, an opposition in terms of categories thus directly influenced
everyone's temperament and vocation, and the institutional scheme
which made it possible for this to happen testifies to the link between
UNIVERSALIZATION AND PARTICULARIZATION
11 12
Fig 9 Cut of Osage and Omaha boys' hair according to clan. I. Head and
tail of elk; 2. Head, tail and horns of buffalo; w, Homs of buffalo;
3. Line of buffalo's back as seen against the sky; 4b. Head of bear; 4c.
Head, tail and body of small birds; 4d. Shell of the turtle with the head,
feet and tail of the animal; 4e. Head, wings and tail of the eagle; 5. Four
points of the compass; 6. Shaggy side of the wolf; 7. Homs and tail of the
buffalo; 8. Head and tail of the deer; 9. Head, tail and knobs of the grow-
ing horn of the buffalo calf; xo. Reptile teeth; xx. Petals of the cone ftower;
12. Rock with algae floating round (following La Flesche 4, pp. 87, 89).
171
THE SAVAGE MIND
• Everything, except the existence of what exists, which is not one of its
properties (cf. below, p. 255).
1 73
THE SAVAGE MIND
use of the names of the dead which 'contaminate' any words with a
phonetic resemblance to these names. The Tiwi of the Melville and
Bathurst islands taboo not only the proper name 'IV1ulankina' but
also the word 'mulikina' which means: full, filled, enough (Hart).
This usage finds a parallel in that of the Yurok of California: 'When
Tegis died, the common word tsis, "woodpecker scalps", was not
uttered in the hearingofhis relatives or by them' (Kroeber 2, p. 48). •
The Dobu islanders forbid the use of proper names between
individuals temporarily or permanently connected by a 'species' tie
through being companions on a voyage, eating together, or sharing
the favours of the same woman, as the case may be (Bateson).
Such facts have a double daim on our interest. In the first place,
they :tfford an indisputable analogy with food prohibitions, which
have been wrongly associated with totemism alone. In the same
way that at Mota a woman is 'contaminated' by a plant or animal, as
a result of which she gives birth to a child subject to the correspond-
ing eating prohibition, and at Ulawa it is the dying man who 'con-
taminates' by his incarnation in an animal or plant species which his
descendants are then forbidden to consume, so, by homophony, a
name 'contaminates' other words, the use of which then cornes to be
forbidden. Secondly, this homophony defines a class of words, to
which the prohibition applies because they belong ta the same
'species', and which th us acquires an ad hoc reality comparable ta
that of animal or plant species. These 'species' of words 'stressed' by
the same prohibition bring together both proper names and common
names. And this is a further reason for suspecting that the diff erence
between the two types of words is not as great as we were near to
admitting at first.
The customs and procedures which 1 have just mentioned are no!
found in all exotic societies nor even in all those which designate
their segments by animal and plant names. The Iroquois, who are
an instance of the latter, seem to have a system of proper names
entirely distinct from the system of clan appellations. Their names
most commonly consist of a verb with an incorporated noun or a
noun followed by an adjective: In-the-Centre-of-the-Sky, He-
raises-the-Sky, Beyond-the-Sky, etc.; Hanging-Flower, Beautiful-
Flower, Beyond-the-Flowers; He-announces-Defeat (or Victory),
• There are other examples in Elmendorf and Kroeber 1960, which was not
available tome at the tÏine of writing this section.
177
THE SAVAGE MIND
180
C);I\"ERS.-\LIZATIO.N A~D P.-\RTICCLARIZATIO.N
181
THE SAVAGE MIND
Although I have called them 'persona! names' they are really group
names and signify membership of, and solidarity with, a totemic group
(Thomson, p. r 59).
These resen·ations are due to the fact that the list of names which
are the property and prerogatiœ of each clan is often restricted and
that two people cannot bear the same name simultaneously. The
Iroquois have 'guardians' to whom they entrust the task of remem-
bering the repertoire of clan names and who always know which
i88
u:-:1vERSALIZATION AND PARTICULARIZATION'
GIRLS BOYS
!. \Vino'ne Tcaske'
2. Ha'pe Hepo'
3. Ha'psti Hepi'
4. \Viha'ki \Vatca'to
5. Hapo'nA Hake'
6. HapstinA 'l 'atco'
7. Wihakc'da
(\\'allis, p. 39).
Terms which replace propcr namcs at different stages of initiation
can be put in the same category. The Australian tribes in the north
Dampier Land have a series of ninc names gi\'en to novices hefore
the extraction of tceth, thcn bcfore circumcision, before the ritual
bleeding, etc. The Ti,vi of the ~Ielville and Bathurst islands off
.i\ orth Australia give novices special namcs according to thcir grade.
Thcre arc scven mcn's names covering the pcriod from the fifteenth
to the twenty-sixth year and seven women's names going from the
tenth to the t\venty-first ycar (Hart, pp. 286-7 ).
However, the problcms which arise in thesc cases are no different
from that raised by the custom with which wc arc acquainted in our
society whcreby an eldest son is giYCn his patcrnal grandfather's
christian namc. 'Grandfathcr's name' can also be regarded as a title
which is both obligatory and exclusive. There is an imperceptible
transition from namcs to titles, which is connected not with any
intrinsic property of the terms in question but with their structural
rolc in a classificatory system from which it would be vain to claim
to separate them.
CHAPTE.R SEVEN
The naming system of the Penan, who are nomads of the interior of
Borneo, enablcs us to givc a more precisc account of the relation
betwcen the terms to which wc should be inclined to reserve the
title of propcr namc and othcrs which scem at first sight to be of a
differcnt kind. Dcpcnding on his age and family situation, a Penan
may be dcsignatcd by thrcc sorts of tcrms: a persona! name, a
tcknonym ('father of so-and-so', 'mothcr of so-and-so') and, finally,
what one feels like calling a necronym, which expresses the kinship
relation of a deceascd relative to the subjcct: 'father dead', 'niece
de::ad', etc. The western Penan have no Jess than twcnty-six distinct
necronyms, corresponding to the degrcc of kinship, relative age
of the deceased, sex and the order of birth of children up to the ninth.
The ru les gO\·erning the use of thesc names are of surprising com-
plexity. Simplifying a great deal, we can say that a child is known by
its propername until one of his ascendants dies. If it is a grandfather
who dies, the child is then called Tupou. If his father's brother dies
he becomes Ilun and remains so until another relative dies. He then
receives a new name. A Penan may th us pass through a series of six
or se,·en or more necronyms before he marries and has children.
At the birth of their first child a father and mother adopt a
Teknonym expressing their relation to the child whose name forms
part of it. Thus: Tama Awing, Tinen Awing, 'father (or mother) of
Awing'. Should the child die, the teknonym is replaced by a nec-
r0nym: 'Eldest child dead.' When the next child is born a new
teknonym takes the place of the necronym, and so on.
The position is further complicated by the special rules relating
to s!blings. A child is called by his O\Vn name if ail his brothers and
191
THE SAVAGE MIND
AUTONY'.\1 NECROl'YM
_ _ _ _ __I
1
relation
present ( +) or 1
absent(-): +
opposition
between self
( +) and other
(-): +
THE INDIVIDUAL AS A SPEC!ES
husband) to presen·e the par aile! but there i s little point in this as the
identity of structure is immediately apparent without recourse to
neologism. In French usage the right to a necronym thus depends
on the possession of a name analogous to a teknonym: because my
self is ddined by my relation to an other self my identity can be
presen·ed at this other's death oniy by retaining this relation, un-
changed in form but governed from now on by a negative sign.
'\Vidow Smith' is the \Vife of a Smith who is not extinct but who
now exists only in his relation to that other who defines herself
through him.
I twill be objected that in this example bath terms are constructed
in the samc way, by adding a kinship relation to a patronymic deter-
minant, while, as I have pointed out, the necronym among the
Penan contains no propcr name. Before resolving this difficulty, let
us consider the series of siblings where autonym and necronym
alternate. \Vhy autonym and not a term analogous to t'!knonym,
say a 'fratronym' of the type 'brother (or sister) of so-and-so'? The
answer is easy: the persona! name of the child who has just been
barn (whose brothers and sisters are thereby reliend of their nec-
ronyms) is brought into play elsewhere. It is used to form the
parents' teknonym and they have in some way appropriated it for
inclusion in the particular system by which they are defined. The
name of the last-born is thus scparated off from the series of siblings
anc!, as the othcr siblings can be defined neither through it nor
through that of their dead brother or sister (since one is no longer
in the 'key of death', as it were, but in the 'key of life'), they fall back
on the only course left open to them: the resumption of their own
name which is also their proper name. But, it must be emphasized,
this is only in default of 'other' relations which haœ either become
unavailable because they are turned to adifferent use ornotrelevant
becausc the sign governing the system has changed.
The clarification of this point !caves us with only two problcms:
the use of teknonyms by parents, and the absence of proper names
in necronyms, a problem wc came across just now. At first sight the
former seems to raise a question of content and the second one of
form. But they are in fact a single problem amenable to one and the
same solution. T lie names of the dead are never mentioned, and this
sufficcs to cxplain the structure of the necronym. So far as the
teknonym is concerned, the inference is clear: the reason why
parents may no longer be called by their namc when a child is barn
1 94
THE INDIVIDUAL AS A SPECIES
is that they are 'dead' and that procreation is conccivcd not as the
addition of a ncw being to those who exist already but as the substi-
tution of the one for the others. ,.
The Tiwi custom of forbidding the use of proper names during
initiation and child-birth is also to be understood in this way:
The hirth of a child is, to a native, a most mysterious affair and the
woman is regar<led as being intimately in touch with the spirit world.
Hence her name as part of hersclf is investe<l with a ghostly character and
this is expressed hy the tribe in treating her husband as if she did not
cxist, as if she were dead in fact and for the time being no longer his wife.
Shc is in touch with the spirits and the result will be a child for her
husband (Hart, pp. 288-9).
A remark of::-\eedham's suggcsts a similar intcrprctation in the case
of the Penan. The teknonym, hc says, is not honorific and not to have
a child is nota matter of shame.
If you have no child, infonnants say, ... it is not your fault. You arc
sorry because thcrc is no one to replace you, no one to remember your
namc ... Ilut you arc not ashamcd. \\"hy should you be? (l.c., p. 417).
The couvade can be explained in the samc way for it 'vould be a
mistakc to suppose that a man is taking the place of the woman in
labour. The husband and wifc somctimcs have to takc the samc
precautions because they arc idcntificd with the child who is subject
to great dangers during the first wecks or months of its life. Some-
times, frcqucntly for instance in South America, the husband has to
take cven greater prccautions than his wife because, according to
native thcorics of conception and gestation it is particularly his
person which is identificd with that of the child. In ncithcr cvcnt
docs the father play the part of the mother. He plays the part of the
child. Anthropologists arc rarely mistaken on the first point; but
they yct more rarcly grasp the second.
Thrcc conclusions can be drawn from this analysis. In the first
place, proper names, far from constituting a catcgory apart, form a
group with othcr tcrms which differ from thcm evcn though thcy
arc unitcd with thcm by structural relations. The Penan themselvcs
think of these terms as class indicators: they speak of 'cntering into'
a necron ym, not of taking or receiving it.
Sccondly, propcr namcs occupy a subordinate position in this
complcx system. It is really only children who overtly bear their
names, either because thcy are too young to be structurally qualified
by the family and social system or becausc the mcans of qualification
1 95
THE SAVAGE l\llND
ha \·e, for the time hcing, been suspended in favour of their parents.
P;-oper namcs thus undergo a truly logical devaluation. They are
the mark of being 'unclassed' as candidates for a class, of being
temporarily obliged to definc themseh-es either as unclassed (as in
the case of siblings resuming the use of their autonyms) or alter-
nati,-cly by their relation to an unclassed person (like parents when
they assume a teknonym). \Vhen, however, death causes a breach in
the social fabric, the individual is, as it ,.,,·ere drawn in. Thanks to
the nccronym, which has an absolute logical priority over other
forms, his proper name, a mere place in the queue, is replaced by a
position in the system, which from the most general point of view,
can thcreforc be considered as formed of discrete quantified classes.
The proper name is the reverse of d.e necronym, of which the
teknonym in turn presents an inverted image. The case of the Penan
is to ail appearanccs the opposite of that of the Algonkin, froquois
and Yurok. Among the former a person must await a relative's
death to be rid of the na me he bears, white often among the latter
he must await it to succeed to his name. But in fact there is as great a
logical devaluation of names in the latter case as there is in the
former:
The individual name is never used in either direct address or indirect
reference to relatives, the relationship term doing service in all such cases.
Even when addressing a non-relative, the individual name is very seldom
used, the form of address consisting in a relationship term, according to
the relative age of the speaker and the person addressed. Only when non·
relatives are referred to in conversation is it customary to use the indi-
vidual name, which even then will not be used if the context plainly
indicates the person referred to ((ioldenweiser, p. 367).
So, among the Iroquois too, and in spite of the differences pointed
out, a person is left uncla5sed only when there is no alternative.•
•Ta avoid using propcr names, the Yurok of California have conccived a
system or appellations composed of a root corresponding to a place of residence -
a village or house - and a suffix, which differs for men and women, describing
their marital status. The men's names refer to the wife's place of birth and the
women's to the husband 's place of hirth. The suffix of the name indicates whether
it is a case of a patrilocal marriage hy purchase, a matrilocal one or a f ree union,
whcther the marriage has hcen dissoked through the dcath of hushand or wife
or hy divorce, etc. Other affixes, entering into the names of children and the
unmarried, refer to the place of hirth of their Ji,·ing or deceased mother, or their
deceascd father. Thus the only names employe<l arc of one of the following types:
:\1arried to a woman of---; ::\Iarried to a man of--; Has a 'simi' husband in
the house of hirth o f - - ; Is 'half' married to a woman o f - - ; Widower
belonging t a - - ; Divorccd from a woman (or man) o f - - ; \Voman o f - -
THE 1:-;DIVIDUAL AS A SPECIES
Ali sorts of beliefs have been invoked to explain the very common
prohibition on pronouncing the names of the dead. These beliefs
are real and well authenticated 1?-ut the question is whether they
should be regarded as the origin of the custom, as one of the factors
which have contributed to reinforce it or perhaps even as one of its
consequences. If the explanations 1 have given are correct, the pro-
hibition on the names of the dead is a structural property of certain
systems of naming. Proper names are either already class operators
of alternatively they provide a temporary solution for those awaiting
classification. They always represent classes at their most modest.
In the limiting case, as among the Penan, they are no more than the
means, temporarily unclassed, of forming classes or again, as it were,
bills drawn on the logical solvency of the system, that is on i1s
rliscounted capacity to suppl y the crcditor with a class in due course.
Only newcomers, that is, the children who are born, raise a problem:
there they are. Any system which treats individuation as classifica-
tion (and 1 have tried to show that this is always so) risks having its
structure called in question every time a new member is admitted.
There arc two types of solution to this problem, and intermediate
forms between them. If the system in question consists of classes of
positions, it has only to command a reserve of unoccupied p9sitions
sufficient to accommodate ail the children born. The available
positions bcing always more numerous than the population, syn-
chrony is protected against the vagaries of diachrony, at least in
theory. This is the Iroquois solution. The Yurok are Jess farsighted.
Among them, children have to wait their turn; but as thcy are
nevertheless assured of being classified after a few years, they can
remain temporarily undifferentiated while awaiting a position in a
class, which the structure of the system guarantees them.
Everything is different when the system consists of classes of
relations. It is then no longer the case that one individual ceases to
exist and another replaces him in a position labelled by means of a
proper name which outlasts any particular person. For the relation
itself to become a class term, proper names, which present the terms
related as so many distinct entitles, have to be eliminated. The ulti-
mate units of the system are no longer single member classes with a
train of successive living occupants, but classed relations between
who allows a man to li\e with her, has a lover or illegitimate children; His father
was o f - - ; Their late mother was - - ; Unmarried person o f - - ; etc.
(\\'aterman, pp. 214-18; Kroeber in: Elmcndorf and Kroeber, pp. 372-4, n. 1)
1 97
S-TSM
THE SA\'AGE ;-.11:-;n
the dead or even those who are soin effect (parents are described as
deaJ by contrast with the life they have created) and the living,
whether really li\·ing or in etfect so (new born children who have a
proper name so that their parents may be defined in relation to them
until the real death of an ascendant allows them in turn to be
defined in relation to him). In these systems, the classes arc thus
composed of different types of dynamic relations associating entries
and departures, while among the Iroquois and other societies of the
same sort, they are founded on a collection of static positions which
may be vacant or occupied.*
The prohibition on the names of the dead does not therefore raise
a separate problcm for anthropology. A dead persan !oses his name
for the same reason that - among the Penan - a living persan !oses
his; \\·hen the living Penan enters the system he assumes a nec-
ronym, that is te say, he becomes one of the terms in a relationship,
of which the other - since he is dead - no longer exists save in that
relation which defines a li\·ing persan with reference to him. Finally,
for the same reason as the dead !ose their names a mother and father
Jose theirs also whe:n they assume a teknonym, resolving in this way
(until the dcath of one oftheir children) the difficulty created for the
system by the procreation of a supernumerary member. The latter
rnust wait 'outside the door' as a named persan until someone's
departure allows him to make his entrance. Then two beings of
whom rme did not previous!y belong within the system and the
• ln the Fox myth of the origin of de a th, the persan in mouming is told: Now
this is what you are to do. You, i.e. you and the deceased, must always rclease
each other (i.e. hold an adoption feast). Then the soul of the dead will safely and
speedily go yondcr. Y ou must adopt somL"One. And you must think exactly the
same of that toward them. And you will be related to him exactly (as you were to
the dead). That is the only way the soul of your relative may depart safely and
speedily (!Vlichelson, I, p. 411 ). The text is eloquent about the fact that, in this
case too, the quick drive out the dead.
THE SAVAGE MIND
200
THE IXDIVIDUAL AS A SPECIES
201
THE SAVAGE MINU
,. [Ed. note.] The usage of capitals and articles in the tcxt is quite haphazard
and corresponds neither to any fcaturc in the :\avaho languagc nor to any prin-
ciplc of English usage. ln this regard English is similar to French usage and the
text has thereforc bccn adaptcd for the sakc of the clarity of the illustration.
203
THE SAVAGE l\IlND
205
THE SAVAGE :\IIND
1 1
_bird~----------------------_h9rses
--... --- ---
--------- __ ... ---
--- ---
------ ____ ... -~::::. -:.:: ----
___ ...
--- ... ____ _
--- ---
_dogs.;;...·_--_-_ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ _ cattle_ ------
1 1
The systematic relations between these usages are not their only
interesting feature from our point of view.* Although borrowed
from our civilization where their place is a minor one, they off er
ready access to other usages which-are given extreme importance by
the societies which employ them. The attention we have paid to
certain aspects of our customs which some may consider futile is
justified for two reasons. ln the first place, we hope thereby to gain
a clearer and more general idea of the nature of proper names.
Secondly and above ail, we are led to inquire into the hidden
motives underlying ethnographie curiosity: the fascination exer-
cised over us by customs apparently far removcd from ours, the
contradictory feeling of proximity and strangeness with which they
affect us, stem perhaps from the fact these customs are very much
closer to our own than they appear and present us with an enigmatic
image which needs deciphering. ln any case this is what seems to be
shown by a comparison of the facts just analysed with some features
of the Tiwi naming systems which were provisionally left on one
side.
1twill be remembered that the Tiwi have an inordinate consump-
tion of na mes: first, because each person has several names;
secondly, because ail the names have to be distinct; thirdly, because
every re-marriage (and we have seen that they are frequent) in volves
giving new namcs to ail the children a woman already has; and
finally, because a pen;on's death results in a prohibition not only
of the names he has borne but also of ail those which he may have
been led to bestow in the course of this life.t How, one may ask, do
the Tiwi constantly manage to fabricate new names in these
circumstances?
Several cases have to be distinguished. A proper name can be put
back into circulation by the son of the deceased if he decides to take
it after the period during which its use is forbidden. Many names
are thus put in reserve and constitute a sort of onomastic fond which
can be drawn on at will. N evertheless, if one assumes a constant
rate ofbirths and deaths, the pool is likely to diminish on account of
the prolonged duration of the taboo, unless a sudden demographic
•This book was already completed when M.M. Houis kindly drew my atten-
tion to the work of V. Larock. Although I have not made use of it bccause its
context is so different from my own, l feel it right to pay tribute to it as the first
tentative account of names of people from an ethnographie point of view.
t Cf. abo\·e, p. 199.
THE SAVAGE :\IIND
That this is so seems eyen more certain when one notices that the
Tiwi system has striking analogies, on the human plane, \\·ith the
system in our own society, to which I dre\\. attention in analysing
the various ways of naming animals·, where, it is hardly necessary to
say, fear of the dead plays no part. Among the Tiwi also, the system
rests on a sort of arbitrage, exercised by means of proper names,
between a syntagmatic chain (that of ordinary language) and a para-
digmatic set (the sacred language, which is esscntially of this nature
since the words there become progressiYely unfitted to forma syn-
tagmatic chain as they Jose their meaning). In addition, proper
names are metaphorically connected with common nouns through
a positive phonetic resemblance, white sacred \rnrds are metonym-
ically connected with proper names (as means or ends) through a
negative resemblance, based on the absence or pm·erty of semantic
content.
Even if one defines it, on the most general level, as consisting in
an exchange of words between the profane and the sacred language,
through the medium of proper names, the Tiwi system clarifies
phenomena which minor aspects of our culture allowed us only to
do so muchas broach. \\"e arc better able to un<lerstand how terms
likc Brassica rapa which belong to a language 'sacred' in two respects
(being Latin and scientific) can have the charactcr of proper names,
not, as Gardiner suggests and Hart seems prepared to admit,
because they are deYoid of mcaning but because, in spi te of appear-
ances, they arc part of a whole system in which mcaning is neYer
entirely lost. \Vere this not so, the sacred language of the Tiwi
would not be a language but a conglomeration of oral gestures.
Therecan, however, be no doubt that even an obscure sacred langu-
age retains potential meaning. I shall corne back to this aspect of the
question later.
For the moment we must distinguish another type of 'sacrcd'
language which we employ, in the manncr of the Tiwi, to introduce
proper names into ordinary language, even transforming the
common nouns from the domain in question into proper names.
Thus, as we have already seen, we use flo\ver names as proper n amcs
for girls, but we do not stop at this, since the inventivc11ess of horti-
culturalists provides newly introduced flowers \vith proper names
taken over from h uman beings. This chassé-croisé has some notable
peculiarities. The names we take from flowers and give (mainly to
persons of the female sex) are common nouns belonging to ordinary
211
THE SAVA<;E :\HNIJ
language (a girl may perhaps be called Rosa but definitely not Rosa
centrfolia); those we give them in return, however, corne from a
'sacred' language: a title is added to the patronym or christian name
and )ends it a mysterious dignity. A new flower is not usually called
'Elizabeth', 'Doumer', or 'Brigitte' but 'Queen-Elizabeth', 'Presi-
dent-Paul-Doumer', ''.\Iadame-Brigitte-Bardot'. '*' Moreover, no
account is taken of the bearer's sex (in this case the grammatical
gender of the name of the flower) in naming it: a rose or a gladiolus
(fcminine and masculine respectively in French) can be given either
a man's or a woman's name indifferently. This recalls one of the
rules for the attribution of 'umbilical' names among the Wik
'.\Iunkan.t
.:\ow, these usages, whether also taken from our mvn culture or
from that of Australian islanders, clearly derive from the same group
as ail those we have been considering; we observe the same equiva-
lence between metonymical and metaphorical relations which has
seemed to play the part of common denominator between them
from the start. The names we take over from flowers to make into
proper names have the force of metaphors: fair as a rose, modest
as a violet, etc. But the names drawn from 'sacred' language which
flowers receive in exchange have the force of metonymy, in two
ways: Brassica rapa removes the self-sufficiency of cabbage-turnip
to make it a species of a genus, part of a whole. The name 'Impéra-
trice-Eugénie', given to a new variety of flower, performs a converse
transformation, since it takes place at the levcl of the signifying
instead of at that of the signified: this time the flower is designated
by means of part of a whole; not any Eugénie but a particular
Eugénie; Eugénie de .i\Tontijo not before her marriage but after it;
nota biological indiYidual but a person in a determined social raie,
etc.:j: One type of'sacred' name is thus 'metonymizing' and the other
212
THE I.'."DIVIDl"AL AS A 5PECIE5
lanll'uage fumishes the common name rose which first becomes Rose, a woman's
christian name and then retums to ordinary language through the imermediary
of the sacred language in the form: Princess ~1argarer-Rose, naming a variery
of rose of which (if the f\ower is a success) it will ra;iidly become the common
na me.
•The alphabetical cycle refers to the system "'hereby the initial lener of a
pedigree animal should correspond to the year of its bi:rth, and th.at the le!!ers
succeed one another in alphabetical order [trans. note).
213
extrinsic detennination that a certain Jeye) of classification requires
appellations, which can be common nouns or proper namcs accord-
ing to the circumstances. But this does not, howevcr, bring us back
to the Durkheimian thesis of the social origin of logical thought.
Although there is undoubtedly a dialectical relation between the
social structure and systems of categories, the latter are not an effect
or result of the former: each, at the cost of laborious mutual adjust-
ments, translates certain historical and local modalities of the
relations between man and the world, which form their common
substratum.
These clarifications were necessary to enable us to emphasize,
without risk of misunderstanding, the sociological and at the same
time relative nature of the notion of a species as well as of an indiù-
dual. From the biological point of view, men who belong to the same
race (assuming that a precise sense can be given to this term) are
comparable to the indiYidual flowers which blossom, open and
wither on the same tree: they are so many specimens of a variety or
sub-nriety. Similarly, ail the members of the species Homo sapiens
are logically comparable to the members of any other animal or
plant species. Howeyer, social life effects a strange transformation
in this system, for it encourages each biological individual to
deYelop a personality; and this is a notion no longer recalling speci-
mens within a nriety but rather types of varieties or of species,
probably not found in nature (although there is a suggestion of it
now and again in the tropical environment) and which could be
termed 'mono-indn·idual'. '\'hat disappears with the death of a
personality is a synthesis of ideas and modes of behaviour as exclu-
sive and irreplaceable as the one a iloral species develops out of the
simple chemical suhstances common to ail species. "'hen the Joss
of someone dear to us or of some public personage such as a poli-
tician or writer or artist moves us, we suffer much the same sense of
irreparable printion that wc should expericnce were Rosa centzfolia
to bccomc extinct and itsscent to disappear for ever. From this point
of view it seems not untrue to say that some modes of classing,
arbitrarily isolated under the title of totemism, are universally
employed: among ourselves this 'totemism' has merely been
humanized. EYerything takes place as if in our civilization every
individual's own personality were his totem: it is the signifier of
his signified being.
214
THE INDIVIDUAL AS A SPECIES
215
THE SAVAGE MIND
216
CHAPTER,EIGHT
TIME REGAINED
2r8
TI:\lE REGAINED
The error of judgment of which Comte was guilty in the last pro-
position explains why he was so entirely mistaken about the
219
THE SAVAGE MIND
220
Tll\IE REGAINED
This is not ail. Once the relation between man and the deity is
secured by sacralization of the victim, the sacrifice breaks it by
destroying this same victim. Human action thus brings about a
solution of continuity, and, as it had pre\"Ïously established com-
munication between the human reservoir and the divine reservoir,
the latter will automatically fi.Il the gap by discharging the antici-
pated benefi.t. The scheme of sacrifice consists in an irreversibk
operation (the destruction of the victim) with a view to setting off
an equally irreversible operation on another plane (the granting of
divine grace), which is required by the fact that two 'recipients',
situated a t different levels, have previously been brought into
communication.
So sacrifice is an absolute or extreme operation which relates to
an intermediary object. From this point of view, it resembles,
though it is at the same time opposed to them, the rites termed
'sacrilegious', such as incest, bestiality, etc., which are intermediary
operations relating to extreme objects. This was shown in an earlier
chapter in the case of a minor sacrilege: the appearance of a
menstruating woman while the rites of eagle hunting are in pro-
gress, among the Hidatsa lndians.* Sacrifice seeks to establish a
desired connection between two initially separate domains. As
•Cf. abO\·e, p. 51 seq.
225
THE SAVAGE MIND
a b c d e .......... 11
227
THE SAVAGE l\llND
228
TL\IE REG:\10:ED
mustard kan:s and a branch of oak, gathered and eut on the way.
After this, they met the cock and then the warrior. The badger and
butterflv clan is so-called because its ancestors took with them a
man-badger whose acquaintance they had made a short time before
they caught a butterfly to amuse a child; but the child was ill and
it was Badger who curcd him with simples. The ancestors of the
rab bit and tobacco clan found the plant and met the animal. Those
0î the Patki clan took the names of lake, cloud, rain, snow, and fog
as a result of various incidents on their journey. Somewhere
h;:tweer~ ihe actual site of Phoenix (Arizona) and the Little Colora-
do, the ancestors of the bear clan came upon a dead bear, whence
their name; but another band founcl the skin, from which small
rodcnts had taken the hair to line their hales. They made hide
straps out of the skin, and sin ce then the hide strap and bear clans
haYe been associated. A third band took the name of the rodents
and \\·as allied to the former clans (Yoth 4, Parsons, pp. 26-30).
Let us now turn to South America. The Bororo say that the sun
and moon belong to the Badedgeba clan of the Cera moiety on
account of a dispute bet\\·een a father and son, who both wanted to
appropriate the names of these hea\·cnly bodies. A compromise
gaYe the father the names of Sun and Bath-of-the-Sun. Tobacco
belongs to the Paiwe clan because an Indian belonging to it hap-
pened by chance to discovcr its leaves in the innards of a fish he was
gutting in order to cook. The chief of the 'black' Badedgeba clan
at one time possessed somc black and some red birds ( Phimosus
infuscatus and Ibis ruhra respecti\·ely), but his colleague 'red'
Babedgeba stole them from him and he had to agree to a division
according to colour (Colbacchini).
Ali thesc myths of origin of clan appellations are so similar that
it is unnecessary to cite examples from other parts of the world,
such as Africa where they also abound. \Vhat, then, are their com-
mon characteristics? In the first place, they ail haYe in common a
breYÏty leaYing room for none of those apparent digressions which
often haYe a wealth of concealcd meaning. A story reduced to its
essential outlines has no surprises in store for the analyst. Secondly,
thcsc myths are falsely acticlogical (supposing that a myth could be
genuinely so) in as muchas the kind of explanation they give Ï5
reducible to a scarcely modified statement of the initial position;
from this point of \·iew they appear redundant. Their raie seems
to be demarcative, rather than aetiological; they do not really
230
TI:\IE REGAINED
232
TIME REGAINED
The two series exist in time but under an atemporal regime, since,
being both real, they sa il through time together, remaining such as
they were at the moment of s~_paration. The original series is
always there, ready to serve as a system of reference for the inter-
pretation and rectification of the changes taking place in the
derivative series. In theory, if not in practice, history is subordi-
nated to system.
\Yhen, however, a society sicles with history, classification into
finite groups becomes impossible because the derivative series,
instead of reproducing the original series, merges with it to form
a single series in which each term is derivative in relation to the
one preceding it and original in relation to the one coming aftcr it.
Jnstead of a once-for-all homology het\\·een two series each fini te
and discontinuous in its own right, a continuous evolution is postu-
lated within a single serics that accepts an unlimited number of
terms.
Sorne Polynesian mythologies are at the critical point where
diachrony irrerncably prevails on:~r synchrony, making it impos-
sible to interpret the human order as a fixed projection of the
natural order hy which it is cngcndcrcd; it is prolongation, rather
than a rcflcction, of the natural order:
Firc and ·water married, and from them sprung the earth, rocks, trees,
and eYerything. The cuttle-fi.sh fought with the fi.re and was beaten. The
fire fought with the rocks, and the rocks conquered. The large stones
fought ..,,·ith the small ones; the small ones conquered. The small stones
fought with the grass, and the grass conquered. The trees fought with the
creepers, the trecs wcre heaten :iml the creeper> conquen·d. Tlw creepers
roCCt"d, ~"·arrnl'd \\'llh 1nc1lLl{nts, <:ltH~ fnnn tn;1~\!<•t!'i they ~•«·"· tu 1u_· 111t·n
(C. Turnrr. pp. (1 7).
234
TIME REGAI:\"ED
1 select this in prefercnce to ail the other evidence to the samc pur-
pose available from other parts of the world because it emanatcs
from an ethnologist born and brought up among the natives,
speaking their language fluently and remaining deeply attached to
life and development'. After which hc describes, in \'Cry pertinent fashion more-
over, institutions whose object is, to use his own terms, to 'regroup' lineages
threatened with dispersion; to 'allay' their crumbling; to 'recall' their solidarity,
'establish' communication with the ancestors, 'prc,·cnt scparatcd members of the
clan from becoming strangers to each other', furnish 'an instrument of protection
against conAicts', 'control' and 'master' antagonisms and subversions by means
of a 'minutely regulated' ritual which is 'a factor reinforcing social and political
structures'. One is easily in agreement with him (while, however, questioning
whether he is so with his own premises), th:it the institutions he began by deny-
ing to ha,·e been founded on 'logical relations' and 'fixed structures' (p. 23)
demonstrate in fact the 'prevalence of traditional social logic' (p. JJ), and that
'the classical system thus reveals, over a long pcriod, a surprising capacity for
"assimilating" ... ' (p. J4). The only surprising thing in ail this is the author's
own surprise.
235
THE SA\'AGE :'vll:-;'D
DREA:\I
past- present
/~ DEA TH
present-.. past
historical rites / ""' mourning rites
( _;_) /
DIACHRONY
""' ( )
239
THE SA \'AGE M IND
1
TL\lE REGAINED
Fig r r Churinga of an Aranda man of the Frog totem. The large concentric
circles (a) represent three celebrated trees which mark the totemic site
near the Hugh River. The straight lines betwcen them (b) depict their
large roots, and the curved lines (c) their smaller roots. The small con-
centric circles (d) represent Jess important trees with their roots, and the
dotted lines (e) are the tracks of the frogs as they hop about in the sand
of the river bed. The frogs themselves are represented on one side of the
churinga (see the left) by the complicated network of lines (their limbs)
linking small concentric circles (their bodies) (from B. Spencer and
F. J. Gillen, The Native Tribes of Central Australia, new e<l., London,
1938, pp. 145-7).
THE SAVAGE MIND
\ Vhen i t i s noted that these events and sites are the samc as th ose
which furnished the materials of the symbolic systems to which the
pre,·ious chapters were devoted, it must be acknowledged that so-
called primitive peoples have managed to evolve not unreasonable
methods for inserting irrationality, in its dual aspect of logical
contingence and emotional turbulence, into rationality. Classifica-
tory systems thus allow the incorporation of history, even and
particularly that which might be thought to defy the system. For
make no mistake: the totemic myths which solemnly relate futile
incidents and sentimentalize over particular places are comparable
only to minor, lesser history: that of the dimmest chroniclers. Those
same societies, whose social organization and marriage rules
require the efforts of mathematicians for their interpretation, and
whose cosmology astonishes philosophers, see no solution which
would maintain continuity between the lofty theorizing to which
they devote themselves in these domains and a history which is
243
THE SAVAGE MINIJ
247
THE SAVAGE MIND
inert matter, it will be to discover that the latter has properties very
different from those previously attributed toit. Levels of reduction
cannot therefore be classed as superior and inferior, for the level
taken as superior must, through the reduction, be expected to com-
municate retroactively some of its richness to the inferior level to
which it will have been assimilated. Scientific explanation consists
not in moving from the complex to the simple but in the replacement
of a less intelligible complexity by one which is more so.
Se en in this light, therefore, my self is no more opposed to others
than man is opposed to the world: the truths learnt through man
are 'of the world', and they are important for this reason.* This
explains why I regard anthropology as the principle of all research,
\vhile for Sartre it raises a problem in the shape of a constraint to
overcome or a resistance to reduce. And indeed what can one make
of peoples 'without history' when one has defined man in terms of
dialectic and dialectic in terms of history? Sometimes Sartre seems
tempted to distinguish two dialectics: the 'true' one which is sup-
posed to be that of historical societies, and a repetitive, short-term
dialectic, which he grants so-called primitive societies whilst at the
same time placing it very near biology. This imperils his whole
system, for the bridge between man and nature which he has taken
such pains to destroy would turn out to be surreptitiously re-estab-
lished through ethnography, which is indisputably a human science
and derntes itself to the study of these societies. Alternatively Sartre
resigns himself to putting a 'stunted and deformed' humanity on
man's sicle (p. 203), but not without implying that its place in
humanity does not belong toit in its own right and is a fonction only
of its adoption by historical humanity: either because it has
begun to internalize the latter's history in the colonial context,
or because, thanks to anthropology itself, historical humanity has
given the blessing of meaning to an original humanity which was
"This enn holds for mathematical truths of which a contemporary logician,
however, says that 'The characteristic of mathematical thought is that it does not
convey truth about the external world' (Heyting, pp. 8-9). But mathematical
thought at any rate reflects the free functioning of the mind, that is, the activity
of the cells of the cerebral cortex, relatively emancipated from any external
constraint and obeying only its own laws. As the mind too is a thing, the func-
tioning of this thing tcaches us something about the nature of things: even pure
reflection is in the last analvsis an interna-lization of the cosmos. Tt illustrates the
structure of what lies ou;side in a symbolic form: 'Logic and logistics are
empirical sciences belonging to ethnography rather than psychology' (Beth,
p. I 51).
HISTORY AND DIALECTIC
without it. Either way the prodigious wealth and diversity of habits,
beliefs and eus toms is allowed to escape; and it is forgotten that
each of the tens or hundreds of t):iousands of societies which have
existed sicle by sicle in the world or succeeded one another since
man's first appearance, has claimed that it contains the essence of
all the meaning and dignity of which human society is capable and,
reduced though it may have been to a small nomad band or a hamlet
lost in the depths of the forest, its daim has in its own eyes rested on
a moral certainty comparable to that which we can invoke in OUT
own case. But whether in their case or OUT own, a good deal of ego-
centricity and naïvety is necessary to believe that man has taken
refuge in a single one of the historical or geographical modes of his
existence, when the truth about man resides in the system of their
differences and common properties.
He who begins by steeping himself in the allegedly self-evident
truths of introspection never emerges from them. Knowledge of
men sometimes seems easier to those who allow themselves to be
caught up in the snare of persona) identity. But they thus shut the
door on knowledge of man: written or unavowed 'confessions' form
the basis of all ethnographie research. Sartre in fact becomes the
prisoner of his Cogito: Descartes made it possible to attain univers-
ality, but conditionally on remaining psychological and individual;
by sociologizing the Cogito, Sartre merely exchanges one prison for
another. Each subject's group and period now take the place of time-
less consciousness. Moreover, Sartre's view of the world and man
has the narrowness which has been traditionally creditcd to closed
societies. His insistence on tracing a distinction hetween the primi-
ti,·e and the civilized with the aid of gratuitons contrasts reflects, in
a scarcely more subtle form, the fondamental opposition he postu-
la tes between myself and others. Y et there is little difference
between the way in which this opposition is formulated in Sartre's
work and the way it would have been formulated by a Melanesian
savage, while the analysis of the practico-inert quite simply revives
the language of animism. *
Descartes, who wanted to found a physics, separated Man from
*lt is precisely because ail these aspects of the savage mind can be discovered
in Sartre's philosophy, that the latter is in my view unqualified to pass judgment
on it: he is prevented from doing so by the very fact of furnishing its equivalent.
To the anthropologist, on the contrary, this philosophy (like ail the others) affords
a first-class ethnographie document, the study of which is essential to an under-
standing of the mythology of our own time.
2 49
THE SAVAGE MIND
253
THE SAVAGE MIND
the right one: superstructures are faulty acts which have 'made it'
socially. Hence it is vain to go to historical consciousness for the
truest meaning. \Vhat Sartre catis dialectical reason is only a recon-
struction, by what he catis analytical reason, of hypothetical moves
about which it is impossible to know - unless one should perform
them without thinking them -whether they bear any relation at ail to
what he tells us about them and which, if so, would be definable in
terms of analytical reason atone. And so we end up in the paradox
of a system which invokes the criterion of historical consciousness to
distinguish the 'primitive' from the 'civilized' but - contrary toits
claim - is itself ahistorical. I t offers not a concrete image of history
but an abstract schema of men making history of such a kind that
it can manifest itself in the trend of their lives as a synchronie
totality. lts position in relation to history is therefore the same as that
of primitives to the eternal past: in Sartre's system, history plays
exactly the part of a myth.
Indeed, the problem raised by the Critique de la raison dialectique
is reducible to the question: under what conditions is the myth of
the French Revolution possible? And 1 am prepared to grant that
the contemporary Frenchman must believe in this myth in order
fully to play the part of an historical agent and also that Sartre's
analysis admirably extracts the set of formai conditions necessary
if this result is to be secured. But it does not follow that his meaning,
just because it is the richest (and so most suited to inspire practical
action), should be the truest. Here the dialectic turns against itself.
This truth is a matter of context, and if we place ourselves outside
it - as the man of science is bound to do -what appeared as an experi-
enced tru th first becomes confused and finally disappears altogether.
The so-called men of the Left still cling to a period of contemporary
history which btstowed the blessing of a congruence between prac-
tical imperati ves and schemes of interpretation. Perhaps this golden
age of historical consciousness has already passed; and that this
eventuality can at any rate be envisaged proves that what we have
here is only a contingent context like the fortuitous 'focusing' of an
optical instrument when its object-glass and eye-piece move in
relation to each other. \Ve are still 'in focus' so far as the French
Revolution is concerned, but so we should have been in relation to
the Fronde had we lived earlier. The former will rapidly cease to
afford a coherent image on which our action can be modelled, just
as the latter has already clone. \Vhat we leam from reading Retz is
HISTORY AND DIALECTIC
257
THE SAVAGE MIND
biased cven when it daims not to be, for it inevitably remains partial
- that is, incomplete - and this is itself a form of partiality. When one
proposes to write a history of the French Revolution one knows (or
ought to know) that it cannot, simultaneously and under the same
heading, be that of the Jacobin and that of the aristocrat. Ex hypo-
thesi, their respective totalizations (each of which is anti-symmetric
to the other) are equally true. One must therefore choose between
two alternatives. One must select as the principal either one or a
third (for there are an infinite number of them) and give up the
attempt to find in history a totalization of the set of partial totaliza-
tions; or alternatively one must recognize them all as equally real:
but only to discover that the French Revolution as commonly con-
ceived never took place.
History does not therefore escape the common obligation of all
knowledge, to employa code to analyse its object, even (and especi-
ally) if a continuous reality is attributed to that object. «<The distinc-
tive features of historical knowledge are due not to the absence of a
code, which is illusory, but toits particular nature: the code consists
in a chronology. There is no history without dates. To be convinced
of this it is sufficient to consider how a pupil succeeds in learning
history: he reduces it to an emaciated body, the skeleton of which is
formed by dates. Not without reason, there has been a reaction
against this dry method, but one which often runs to the opposite
extreme. Dates may not be the whole of history, nor what is most
interesting about it, but they are its sine qua non, for history's entire
originality and distinctive nature lie in apprehending the relation
between be/ore and a/ter, which would perforce dissolve if its terms
could not, at least in principle, be dated.
Now, this chronological coding conceals a very much more com-
plex nature than one supposes when one thinks of historical dates
illusion of having overcome the insoluble antinomy (in such a system) between
my self and others, consists of the assignation, by historical consciousness, of
the metaphysical fonction of Other to the Papuans. By reducing the latter to the
state of means, barely sufficient for its philosophical appetite, historical reason
abandons itself to a sort of intellectual cannibalism much more revolting to the
anthropologist than real cannibalism.
• In this sense tao, one can speak of an antinomy of historical knowledge: if it
daims to reach the continuous it is impossible, being condemned to an infinite
regress; but to render it possible, events must be quantified and thereafter
temporality ceases to be the privileged dimension ofhistorical knowledge because
as soon as it is quantified each event can, for ail useful purposes, be treated as
if it were the result of a choice between possible pre-existents.
HISTORY AND DIALECTIC
259
THE SAVAGE MIND
261
THE SAVAGE :\1INU
262
HISTORY AND DIALECTIC
world is not merely coherent but the very one demanded in the
case of an object whose elementary structure presents the picture of
a discontinuous complexity.
The false antinomy between logical and prelogical mentality was
surmounted at the same time. The savage mind is logical in the
samc sense and the same fashion as ours, though as our own is only
when it is applied to knowledge of a universe in which it recognizes
physical and semantic properties simultancously. This misunder-
standing once dispelled, it remains no less true that, contrary to
Levy-Bruhl's opinion, its thought proceeds through understanding,
not affectivity, with the aid of distinctions and oppositions, not by
confusion and participation. Although the term had not yet corne
into use, numerous texts of Durkheim and Mauss show that they
understood that so-called primitive thought is a quantified form of
thought.
It will be objected that there remains a major difference between
the thought of primitives and our own: Information Theory is con-
cerned with genuine messages whereas primitives mistake mere
manifestations of physical determinism for messages. Two con-
siderations, however, deprive this argument of any weight. In the
first place, Information Theory has been generalized, and it extends
to phenomena not intrinsically possessing the character of messages,
notably to those of biology; the illusions of totemism have had at
least the merit of illuminating the fondamental place belonging to
phenomena of this order, in the internai economy of systems of
classification. In treating the sensible properties of the animal and
plant kingdoms as if they were the elements of a message, and m
discovering 'signatures' - and so signs - in them, men have made
mistakes of identification: the meaningful element was not always
the one they supposed. But, without perfected instruments which
would have permitted them to place it where it most often is -
namely, at the microscopie level-theyalready discerned 'as through
a glass darkly' principles of interpretation whose heuristic value and
accordance with reality have been revealed tous only through very
recent inventions: telecommunications, computers and electron
m1croscopes.
Above all, during the period of their transmission, when they
have an objective existence outside the consciousness oftransmitters
and receivers, messages display properties which they have in
common with the physical world. Hence, despite their mistakes
268
HISTORY AND DIALECTIC
272
BIBLIOGRAPHY
273
TITE SAVAGE MI'.'iD
274
BIBLIOGRAPHY
275
THE SAVAGE MIND
279
THE SAVAGE MIND
285
TIIE SA\'AGE l\II;-.;D
288
INDEX
289
THE SAVAGE MIND
Wik Munkan, 45, 167 n., 174, 183, WYMAN, L.C., 40, 204
186-8, 212
WILLIAMS, M.L.W., 56 Yathaikeno, 100-1
WILSON, G.L., 48, 50 Yoruba, 105, 131-3
Winnebago, 57, 140, 142, 167, 170 Yuma, 180
WIRz, P., 63 n. Yurlunggur (snake), 91-3
WITKOWSKI, G.J., 201 Yurok, 168, 177, 189, 196-7
W OENSDREGT, J., 169
Wolverine, 50-3 ZAHAN, D., 39, 163
Wormwood. See Artemisia ZEGWAARD, G.A., 61
WORSLEY, P., 156 ZELENINE, D., 9
Wotjobaluk, 57, 105 Zuni, 40, 71-2