(Bernard Hoose) Christian Ethics (BookFi)
(Bernard Hoose) Christian Ethics (BookFi)
(Bernard Hoose) Christian Ethics (BookFi)
continuum
L O N D O N • NEW Y O R K
Continuum
The Tower Building, 11 York Road, London SE1 7NX
370 Lexington Avenue, New York, NY10017 - 6503
ISBN 0-304-70263-3
ISBN 0-8264-4968-9
5 Virtue ethics 84
James F. Keenan
7 Conscience 110
Richard M. Gula
8 The theory of the fundamental option and moral action 123
Thomas R. Kopfensteiner
v
Christian ethics
Social ethics
11 Justice 163
Karen Lebacqz
12 Property 173
Timothy J. Gorringe
Medical ethics
19 Euthanasia 277
Richard M. Gula
20 Ethical problems arising from new reproductive techniques 290
Joyce Poole
21 Organ transplantation 304
David F. Kelly
vi
Contents
Index 331
vii
The contributors
viii
The contributors
Debate and Its European Roots and Received Wisdom? Reviewing the Role of
Tradition in Christian Ethics.
Kevin T. Kelly combines his pastoral work as a priest with writing and
lecturing. He is part-time Senior Research Fellow in Moral Theology at
Liverpool Hope University College. His writings include Divorce and
Second Marriage, New Directions in Moral Theology and Life and Love: Towards
a Christian Dialogue on Bioethical Questions.
ix
Christian ethics
Joyce Poole initially trained in paediatric surgery but moved into family
practice. Her professional involvement with seriously ill and handicapped
children kindled an interest in medical ethics. She is the author of The
Harm We Do: A Catholic Doctor Confronts Church, Moral and Medical
Teaching and of numerous articles on medical ethics.
X
Introduction
xi
Christian ethics
xii
Introduction
Bernard Hoose
xiii
This page intentionally left blank
PART I
Most Christians believe that the Bible has, or should have, a special role
in Christian living. Ethicists in the Protestant tradition have generally
been more alert than Roman Catholic moralists to the need to take this
belief seriously in the conduct of their discipline. However, since the
decades leading up to Vatican II, and especially after that Council's call
for moral theology to be revitalized through more contact with the Bible,
Roman Catholic moralists have increasingly acknowledged the need to
give the Bible a higher profile in their reflections. In a 1971 article 1
Charles Curran was able to review several significant benefits brought to
Catholic moral theology in the 1960s by what he called the 'Scriptural
renewal'.
However, it is sobering to note that Curran then went on to warn about
certain 'limitations' or difficulties inherent in the use of the Bible in moral
theology - limitations and difficulties relating especially to the Bible's
diversity and to its historical and cultural distance. More sobering still is
the thought that the 'Scriptural renewal' whose benefits Curran applauded
had owed its success largely to its failure to notice such difficulties. It was,
in fact, the tail-end of a movement (the so-called 'Biblical theology
movement' in its 1940s/1950s form), whose scientific naivety had already
been amply exposed by the time Catholic theology began enjoying its
benefits.2 This is not to say that these benefits were not real as far as moral
theology was concerned; only that they appear to have been made possible
by methods of biblical interpretation which are now widely regarded as
inadequate for scientific purposes. Hence, the 'Scriptural renewal', while
it may have prevented Roman Catholic moral theology from ever reverting
to its traditional mould, offers no satisfactory way forward today.
My aim in this chapter is not to add substantially to what Curran wrote
3
Tom Deidun
in 1971 but only to describe in more detail, for the benefit of students
who are new to the discussion, the problems that may arise from the
standpoint of biblical scholarship when Christian ethicists look to it for
some contribution to their discipline. Only by way of postscript, as it
were, do I venture a suggestion for a possibly constructive 'use' of the
Bible in Christian ethics which respects the nature of the biblical writings.
If we are to apply 'what the Bible says' to our own ethical concerns (that
is, if we are to pass from text to life), then we must first do our best to
establish 'what the Bible says'. This prior task involves trying to discover
what a given biblical writer understood himself to be saying. There are
two distinct steps, therefore, in any attempt to apply biblical material in
Christian ethics: interpretation of biblical texts and some kind of
appropriation or contemporization.
Obvious as that last remark may sound, many modern hermeneutical
theorists would argue that far from these two steps being distinguishable,
the merging of the interpreter's horizons with those of the text is integral
to any act of interpretation. There is no such thing as a 'presuppositionless'
interpretation. Interpretation involves a circular, or spiral, movement of
interaction between interpreter and text, and this interaction is itself
constructive of meaning. In that sense, the reader is the text's co-author.
But it is one thing to say that there is no interpretation without some
involvement of the interpreter, and quite another to make the interpreter's
involvement a methodological imperative. It may be true at some level
that 'the theologian is . . . an exegete simultaneously of Scripture and
existence';3 but in what follows I take the old-fashioned view that in so far
as the theologian is an exegete of biblical texts, his or her only remit is to
explain the text in its historical and literary context. This entails doing
one's utmost to prevent one's 'exegesis of existence' colouring one's
interpretation of biblical texts. Experience surely teaches us (if common
sense failed to do so) that interpreters who turn to biblical texts in search
of 'relevance' will surely find what they are looking for, but only after
imposing on the texts their own notions of what counts as relevant.
This is not to say that interpretations of biblical texts which operate on
modern hermeneutical theories will have nothing to contribute to Chris-
tian ethicists' appropriation of biblical texts. Quite the opposite, for such
interpretations might, given certain conditions, turn out to be peculiarly
enriching, not least because of their inevitable pluralism and their ability
to bring to the ethicist's use of the Bible a faculty which often remains
unexercised in biblical interpretation, namely, imagination.4
4
The Bible and Christian ethics
Interpretation
Historical-critical exegesis
The method (or cluster of methods) of interpretation which professes to
concern itself with discovering what the biblical writers understood
themselves to be saying, and which claims to provide the least fragile
defence against the imposition of gratuitously subjectivizing elements on
biblical texts, is commonly described as the 'historical-critical method'.
This operates on the principle that a prerequisite for discovering what any
given biblical writer understood himself to be saying is a careful use of all
available critical tools (historical, linguistic and literary), joined with an
honest effort to be objective and an openness to unfamiliar ideas.
As implied above in my references to current hermeneutical theories,
the historical-critical method has not gone unchallenged in recent decades,
and in some quarters has given way to, or been supplemented by, methods
which start from very different hermeneutical premisses. Still, most
biblical scholars continue to regard it as irreplaceable, and as a necessary
first step, at least, in the interpretation of all, or almost all, biblical
writings. The Roman Catholic Church, having gradually become less
fearful of it than it once notoriously was, has recently given it its official
blessing (even if that blessing perhaps evokes, in uncharitable minds,
reminiscences of the blind Isaac).
5
Tom Deidun
6
The Bible and Christian ethics
7
Tom Deidun
8
The Bible and Christian ethics
Even in cases where New Testament notions of love are not vulnerable to
such strictures, we should not assume that they coincide with ours. For
New Testament writers are typically concerned with the perfection of the
subject who loves, and only obliquely, if at all, with the interests and
needs of the one loved. From this one might infer that the New Testament
writers seem not to know of the altruism that is cherished in the best of
our own culture, and arguably, in the most really Christian souls; and that
the love they commend is in the last analysis (albeit ever so spiritually)
self-centred; 14 or, alternatively, one could take the difference in perspective
as a cue for critical self-questioning about possible deficiencies in our own
culture's evaluation of love. But all that aside, the point I am concerned
to make here is that there is a difference in perspective, and Christian
ethicists need to be aware of it.
9
Tom Deidun
10
The Bible and Christian ethics
11
Tom Deidun
Most biblical writings are contextual in a far narrower sense than their
simply being historically and culturally conditioned, for they addressed
very particular situations, or they were occasioned by very particular
circumstances. (I leave aside for now the question whether it is possible to
establish connections, parallels or analogies between the situations
addressed by particular biblical writers then, and situations which
typically confront us now — supposing that establishing such connections,
etc., might be useful.) In the case of Paul's letters, for example (with the
possible exception of Romans), and in the case of, say, the Johannine
epistles, so much is obvious. It is perhaps less obvious in relation to the
Gospels. They too, however, almost certainly had in view the circum-
stances of particular communities. (A careful study of each Evangelist's
redactional strategy suggests so much.)
So it will not do to bring to the interpretation, say, of Matthew, only
the general knowledge that he speaks out of the culture of some kind of
first-century Jewish Christianity (fatal as it would be to overlook this fact).
One would need also to establish, in so far as this is possible, what
Matthew's community's relationship was with this or that sector of
contemporary non-Christian Judaism, what the latter were up to at that
time, whether there was interaction between Matthew's community and
the non-Christian Jews in the 'synagogue over the road' (their syn-
agogues'!); whether there was debate between them, and if so, over what
issues; whether and to what extent Matthew's community still observed
the whole or part of Torah, and, if so, whether some or all of its members
interpreted it in ways which distinguished them from their non-Christian
kinsfolk, and in what ways; and whether this gave rise to problems, and
how Matthew's community appears to have handled these problems, and
whether, and how, and for what reasons their belief in Jesus messiah
aggravated such problems; then, further, whether Matthew's community
was engaged in, or was contemplating, a gentile mission, and, if so, how
this might have complicated (or even created) those problems — to say
nothing, finally, of the sociological profile of Matthew's community and
the light that this might throw on his Gospel. On historical-critical
principles, it would be illegitimate to seek to appropriate Matthew's text,
12
The Bible and Christian ethics
not to say miscellaneous bits of it, without first considering at least these
questions.
So also, regarding, say, 1 Corinthians, one would need to try to discover
the mindset, beliefs and problems of the Corinthian community, if only
to decide whether what Paul says about marriage in 1 Corinthians 7 is to
be read as timeless wisdom, or whether that chapter was not rather
addressed to very particular needs, for example, those of a community of
semi-converted Christians with hang-ups about sex and celibacy.25 It
could make all the difference.
As readers of the Bible we are first of all eavesdroppers. This means that
a proper interpretation of the biblical writers' ethical statements presup-
poses the prior task of reconstructing the situation which a given biblical
writer was addressing there and then. We may need to reconstruct the
unrecorded side of the interchange to stand any chance of understanding
what is being said in the biblical text, and with what nuances or emphases,
and in order to be reasonably sure that we are not getting the wrong end
of the stick altogether. In the case of a few biblical writings the quest for
a reconstructed dialogue partner may be misguided; in the case of others
it may be desirable, but impossible for lack of clues; but in most cases the
clues are there, and it would be disingenuous to ignore them.
Attempts at reconstruction will inevitably involve varying degrees of
conjecture and provisionality. Doubtless, the very idea of conjecture and
provisionality will cause hilarity or annoyance among those born or reborn
to see the Bible as the word of God tout court; and may be regarded with
suspicion by those who, while not holding a fervent view of biblical
inspiration, still see the Bible as a repository of straightforward truths,
and scholarly conjecture as an evasion of those truths. But the alternative
to scholarly conjecture is to risk getting it all wrong, and perhaps with
dire consequences.26
13
Tom Deidun
14
The Bible and Christian ethics
fatted calf!' There is no biblical interpreter who has wholly resisted the
temptation to bring to the text fascinations that have come to them from
elsewhere (whether from cherished dogmatic or apologetic concerns, or
some paramount life concern or some all-consuming pastoral/socio-
political commitment).30
Manifestations past and present of the fatted-calf syndrome are beyond
counting, so examples must be chosen at random. Classic are: the (second-
think) Augustine's — and then, more disturbingly, Luther's — misuse of
Romans 7:l4ff.; the Roman Catholic tradition's cultivation of the Mat-
thean 'Petrine text'; the same tradition's use of the New Testament texts
which speak of marriage and divorce (though with curious disregard for
Matthew's 'exceptive clause', cf., e.g., Veritatis Splendor, n. 22);31 the
Lutheran tradition's fascination with the verb 'to reckon' in Romans 4;
Veritatis Splendor's, refocusing of Matthew's account of the Rich Young
Man (Matt 19:16-22) on verses 17-18; and the feminist exegete Elisabeth
Schiissler Fiorenza's discovery, in those resurrection narratives which omit
mention of the women, evidence of a calculated suppression of an earlier
women-oriented tradition. 32 The little boy need not have worried, for in
one form or another the fatted calf is alive and well.
A hermeneutic of suspicion
A corollary of all this is that exegetes, by training if not by temperament,
will be suspicious of texts that look like they demand to be read at face
value.33 The wisdom of regarding 'obvious' readings as at least pro-
visionally suspect could be supported by countless illustrations taken from
the history of interpretation. Here are just two, the first 'doctrinal' and
the second more directly 'ethical'.
(1) In Galatians 4:4—5 Paul wrote: 'When the fullness of time came,
God sent his son, born of woman, born under Torah, to redeem those
under Torah, [and] so that we might receive adoption as sons.' Now no
one doubts that by 'born of woman' Paul meant that Jesus was human.
The question is, why he drew attention to the fact. Interpreters have
normally assumed that he wanted to say that Jesus was human as well as
divine. Is it not just possible, though, that he meant, rather, that Jesus was
human and not just a Jew (and because he was human and not just a Jew,
people have direct access to his blessings just because they are human, i.e.,
they do not have to become Jews first)? The literary context of these
verses, and the situational context of Galatians (where Paul was opposing
rival missionaries who sought to persuade his converts to embrace elements
of Judaism as a precondition of access to Jesus) overwhelmingly support
this latter interpretation. Yet traditionally interpreters, doubtless assum-
ing that New Testament writers shared their doctrinal preoccupations,
15
Tom Deidun
have taken it for granted that Paul's intention in this passage was to assert
the doctrine of incarnation and the two natures of Christ. (Never mind
that any preoccupation with the idea of incarnation, and, arguably, even
the idea itself, arose several decades later than Paul.34)
(2) In 1 Corinthians 7 Paul writes about marriage and sex. He seems to
be saying that whereas celibacy is preferable ('it is good for a man not to
touch a woman'), marriage and normal conjugal relations are advisable for
most Christians as a safeguard against the temptation to engage in non-
marital sex. Throughout the centuries Christian interpreters have assumed
that Paul in this chapter is calling his own tunes, and that a straight-
forward reading conveys his considered assessment of marriage, viz., that
marriage is a regrettable necessity for those Christians who cannot control
themselves; and that the best that can be said of it is that it is no sin. A
very common view of interpreters nowadays is that Paul's agenda in this
chapter was determined not by himself but by those in Corinth whose
dualistic disdain of the body and pursuit of spiritual elitism had led them
to advocate (or even seek to impose) an eccentric sexual asceticism. If this
view is correct, then 1 Corinthians 7 tells us more about the Corinthians'
evaluation of marriage (which Paul vigorously opposed) than it does about
Paul's.
The pitfall of the 'obvious meaning' claims most victims from among
those who are ignorant of the connotations of words in biblical texts — as
is often the case when these texts are approached through translation. For
example, it is wrong to suppose that the Hebrew terms generally translated
'holy', 'sin' or 'abomination' have the same semantic resonance as their
'equivalents' in modern languages; or that mysterion in Ephesians 5:32
(translated as sacramentum in the Latin versions) says anything at all about
marriage being 'a sacrament'. Then: it is wrong to equate Paul's sarx with
'the flesh' as this term is used in later ethical discourse; or to interpret his
soma ('body') in the light of anthropological perspectives which were not
his; or to assume that his nomos ('law') has any simple equivalent in our
own conceptuality, or any necessary overlap with our own uses of 'law'
(e.g., '"natural" law'). Similarly, the RSV is wrong to translate the Greek
episkopos and diakonos (e.g., Phil 1:1) respectively as 'bishop' and 'deacon';
and is at least misleading when it renders the Greek malakoi and
arsenokoitai (1 Cor 6:9) as 'sexual perverts'. Germain Grisez has written
that according to Veritatis Splendor 'passages such as 1 Cor 6:9-10 mean
exactly what they say: those who do certain kinds of acts, such as adultery
and sexual perversion, will not inherit the Kingdom . . .V35 Whether or
not such passages mean exactly what they say, or what Grisez says they
say, one must first establish what they say. A sure way of aborting this
task ab ovo is to ignore the Greek text and to neglect to ask what the
terms used in it would have meant to Paul and his hearers.36
16
The Bible and Christian ethics
Jesus
In non-scholarly views of 'Christian morality', and in much scholarly
Christian ethical discussion as well, Jesus' ethical sayings are accorded
unique authority. (Even those who hold that the Bible's words are the
very words of God somehow manage to maintain that Jesus' words are
uniquely authoriative.) However, those who wish to appeal to Jesus'
ethical teachings are faced with a number of difficulties. There is, first, the
unsolvable problem of how to distinguish what Jesus said from what the
Evangelists, often variously, say that he said.37 Several methods have been
used in the course of this century to retrieve Jesus' words from underneath
the layers of later encrustations. None of these methods has escaped
criticism, nor have all of them together come up with more than tentative
findings, with the result that many scholars have concluded that what
Jesus actually said is now beyond retrieval (intermittent waves of scholarly
optimism notwithstanding). For New Testament scholars as such this is
not at all worrying, and in any case it does not diminish the value of the
Gospels as testimonies to traditions which were surely shaped by the
impact of the historical Jesus. But it offers no encouragement to those
whose use of the Bible in Christian ethics depends above all on an appeal
to the authority of Jesus' 'actual words'.
In spite of the difficulties of establishing Jesus' 'actual words', there is
now some measure of consensus on the core themes of Jesus' preaching,
namely, the kingdom of God; God reaching out to the alienated as never
before; the call to metanoia (repentance). But what consensus there is has
hardly brought an end to the debate. For even granted that 'the kingdom'
was a central theme in Jesus' preaching, it is still not clear what he meant
by it, or what his religious outlook was, and how, therefore, his supposed
utterances on ethical matters are to be understood. This unclarity has
given rise to a host of reconstructions, some of them more or less plausible
and all of them conjectural.38
For the 'kingdom of God' has turned out to be an endlessly debatable
concept. Did it refer to some ideal order of society for which people were
17
Tom Deidun
18
The Bible and Christian ethics
19
Tom Deidun
interpret it. In neither of these tasks will they be able to rely on any broad
consensus among New Testament scholars.
Paul
Christian ethicists have traditionally had recourse to Paul on two levels:
on the level of the content of his moral exhortations, and at a deeper
doctrinal/ethical level, where he wrestles with such questions as the
relationship between sin and the law, or the relationship between faith
and 'works'. Recent controversies in Pauline studies affect not so much
the legitimacy of appeals to his moral exhortations (though these are often
problematic enough, for other reasons), as traditional interpretations
(typically the Lutheran one) of the import of Paul's doctrinal/ethical
statements. Such interpretations have been massively challenged especially
since the 1970s by a thoroughgoing application of historical-critical
methods to Paul in the context of the Judaism of his day, motivated by a
determined effort to free the exegesis of Paul's epistles from doctrinal
presuppositions, (I refer to E. P. Sanders and what James Dunn has called
the 'new perspective' on Paul.43)
The essence of this critique of traditional interpretations is that (a)
Paul's opposition to Torah observance has been misinterpreted (it had
nothing to do with the Lutheran antithesis between gospel and law, but
concerned only the demands to be made of gentile converts), and (b) Paul's
statements linking Torah with sin reflect not a phenomenological critique
of contemporary Judaism, nor any profound theological or anthropological
analysis, as Lutheran interpreters have always supposed, but rather Paul's
own 'tortured' attempts to extricate himself from the theological difficult-
ies which arose from his 'dogmatically' motivated repudiation of Torah.
The dilemma into which the 'new perspective on Paul' has led Pauline
studies46 may dismay those Christian ethicists who look to Paul for
support in their advocacy of a gospel that is allergic to law, and, more
particularly, may challenge some theologians in the Lutheran tradition
who appeal to Paul for support not so much in this or that ethical stance
as in their aversion to ethics altogether.
I said at the beginning of this chapter that Christian ethicists intent on
'using' the Bible in their discipline must consider the two steps of exegesis
and appropriation. Having reviewed the chief difficulties which they will
need to face in relation to the first step, I now move on to the question of
appropriation, and some of the difficulties which that step involves.
20
The Bible and Christian ethics
Appropriation
Under this heading I first indicate the ways in which the Bible has
commonly been used by Christian ethicists, with some critical comments
on each of them; and then I make some tentative recommendations.
21
Tom Deidun
22
The Bible and Christian ethics
and Luke? Does Paul's injunction to 'judge those inside the church' (1 Cor
5:12) override Jesus' injunction not to judge? Should Paul's exhortation
to respect civil authorities as God's ministers (Rom 13) take priority over
his recommendation that we should consider secular courts 'unrighteous'
(1 Cor 6 [he means: in the biblical sense])? Should we take it that the
non-Christian partner in a 'mixed' marriage is 'consecrated' by the
Christian (1 Cor 7:14), or should Christians recoil from any union with
non-believers on pain of being denied (2 Cor 6:14—18)?
Then, even if there were some acceptable criteria for separating off those
biblical injunctions that are still 'valid' from those which are no longer so,
on what criteria are Christian ethicists to decide how to interpret this or
that still valid command, and to determine what its status and function
must be? Origen thought that Jesus' commendation of those who 'make
themselves eunuchs' ought to be taken literally, but afterwards (too late)
changed his mind. Others, while acknowledging that these words of Jesus,
if indeed they were his words, were meant metaphorically, still differ on
how the metaphor is to be interpreted. 54 Again, to return to a point made
above: what authorizes some to interpret Jesus' words on divorce as a non-
negotiable juridical norm, while serenely interpreting others of Jesus'
sayings as hyperbole?
As well as having to come to terms with the above difficulties, and
others not mentioned for lack of space, people who see the Bible as a
repository of divine commands run the risk of trivializing the Bible by
isolating elements of it at whim, or by arbitrarily privileging one
particular mode of biblical discourse over all others ('norm reductionism').
This can lead to a restricted number of biblical texts exerting a mantra-
like influence upon their devotees. And in so far as this kind of approach
to the Bible is typically accompanied by the conviction that the Bible is
the sole authority in ethical matters, its advocates surely suffer the evil of
having their whole ethical vision narrowed down to scattered biblical
prescriptions, being left to their own imagination, or prejudices, in those
vast areas of present-day ethical concern to which the Bible speaks not at
all. (Which, conceivably, is part of the appeal of that kind of approach.)
23
Tom Deidun
24
The Bible and Christian ethics
25
Tom Deidun
The Bible reveals not a morality but a reality: the character of the living God
Although in some respects this approach is similar to the one just
described, it differs from it in that it is not concerned with the biblical
writers' moral reactions to particular situations but with their description
of what God is like and how God acts. Gustafson described this approach
thus:
. . . The primary question became not 'How ought we to judge this
event?' nor even 'What ought we to do in the event?' But 'What is God
doing in this event?' 'What is he saying to us in this event?' Three
articles published by H. Richard Niebuhr during World War II have
titles which illustrate this: 'War as the Judgment of God', 'Is God in
the War?' and 'War as Crucifixion'.64
This approach65 looks not to biblical imperatives, interpreted in a more or
less simple fashion, but to generalized descriptions of the biblical indicative.
Christian morality is about response to a person, not a rule. The Bible
draws us away from fascination with God's laws and calls us instead to a
discerning and responsible relationship with God. According to this
approach, we are not looking to the Bible for normativity, but for partial
insights. By considering (among other things) what sort of God the Bible
reveals to us, we discern how best we can fulfil our role as responsible
moral agents responding to the living God who now acts in contemporary
events (a response that may entail more radical and more demanding
action than is ever required by the directly ethical imperatives to be found
here and there in the Bible). As the interpretative key to what God is like
and how God acts, practitioners of this approach typically rely on what
they consider to be the central or all-embracing biblical theological theme,
for example, 'liberation'; 'crucifixion and resurrection'; 'hope'; 'God's
doing humanizing work'.
The main problems with this approach are, first, the basic theological
one of whether it makes sense to say that God is 'doing' anything in this
or that event (does not Job protest against simple-mindedness in this
matter?); and, second, its over-confidence in its ability to discover in the
Bible a central theological theme, or a dominant portrayal of God. For
who is to say where in the Bible we must look to discover what God is
like and how God acts? Should we look to the jihad God of some Old
Testament passages or to a God who looks approvingly on all of creation?
To the Deuteronomist's God, or to Job's? To Paul's gospel about God's
limitless outreach to sinful humanity, or to the Book of Revelation? To
the God of Sinai or to the God of Luke 15 ? To passages which speak of
God's 'wrath', or to passages which portray God as endlessly forbearing?
The Bible simply does not give us a uniform portrayal of what God is
26
The Bible and Christian ethics
27
Tom Deidun
and of the fact that they were addressed to a variety of particular historical
situations. Ethical judgements are to be made
28
The Bible and Christian ethics
29
Tom Deidun
30
The Bible and Christian ethics
A recommended non-method
The approach to the Bible which I favour will not lend itself to any
'methodology', but will instead be free and unpredictable. Since one of its
main concerns will be to respect the principles and methods of exegesis, it
will not be vulnerable to the criticisms which show other — apparently-
more tidy — approaches to be either inconsistent in theory or unworkable
in practice. It might be more enriching than any of the methods reviewed
above, while remaining hospitable to elements of most of them. It will
seek to stimulate rather than terminate Christian-ethical discussion. Its
strength will lie in being inventive, rather than in seeking to settle issues
on its own biblical say-so. Its attention to biblical texts will be versatile
and imaginative. It will be disdainful of biblical one-liners, and suspicious
of 'favourite' biblical texts or 'themes', such as are nowadays cherished by
all manner of ideologues. Since it will make no blanket judgement about
the 'authority' of biblical texts, it will not need to be consistent; and
selectivity will be its virtue. Because it will want to take biblical writings
seriously, it will not use them woodenly. It might on occasion put forward
the opinion that the ethical insight of this or that biblical writer is
wonderfully intuitive, while accepting with perfect equanimity that this
or that other biblical writer's ethical stance is irrelevant or distasteful.
Similarly — and consistently with its refusal to be compelled to be relevant
— it will not feel that it has something special to say on every contemporary
ethical issue or ethically significant event.78 It will not feel obliged to
31
Tom Deidun
32
The Bible and Christian ethics
that nearly all of them regard the 'Sermon' as a source of law (binding on
some or all), without ever asking about the genres of Jesus' sayings, or
about Matthew's understanding of Jesus vis-a-vis Torah, or whether
Matthew considered law (and not rather the character of Jesus as wisdom -
Torah in person) to be the prism of God's will for Christians (cf., e.g.,
Matt ll:28ff., with Sirach 24:19-23; 51:23-26).
For we too are culture-bound, and where shall we turn for something to
jolt us out of our domesticity?
The kind of approach I favour might stimulate fresh discussion on
specific ethical issues, or, more generally, urge on Christian ethicists the
need to expand their horizons of relevance; or at least it might call
attention to possible imbalances in their agenda: for example, by posing
the strange question, why Christian ethical discussion is intensely con-
cerned with questions of sexual morality, social justice, bioethics, business
ethics, human rights, gender issues and the like, and not also with what
was a major preoccupation of many biblical writers — what the psalmist
calls 'truth in the heart' or what, obversely, the Fourth Gospel saw as the
hidden depths of mendacity in human behaviour (e.g., John 2:25b; 3:19f.).
Similarly, while the insights of biblical writers may be hopelessly pre-
Freudian, they might none the less invite us to query whether our post-
Freudian 'therapeutic ethos'81 has got it right in all respects.
More bittily: Such an approach might, for example, bring to bear
biblical texts about adam as steward of creation (also in the Christological
sense) on environmental ethics and the 'futurity problem'; 82 or some
prophetic texts which condemn the practice of 'religion' without social
justice on current social-justice issues (perhaps a useful point of encounter
between the Judaeo-Christian tradition and humanists); or a consideration
of the thrust of Romans to a discussion of religious (including Christian)
particularism; or an analysis of the dialogue between Paul and the
Corinthians (in 1 Corinthians) to a discussion of contemporary inner-
Church issues, for example, pluralism, conflicting rights, the dangers of
33
Tom Deidun
spiritual elitism, the co-equal sharing of spiritual gifts and the correlative
functions of community members (e.g., magisterium/theologians; lay/
ordained; males/females) in 'building up' the Christian (and wider)
community; or, say, a consideration of the situation which occasioned
Galatians to a discussion of the relationship between faith and behavioural
conformity; or the implications of Hebrews to a critical discussion of the
place of cult in religion. Or, it might draw on this or that psalm, this or
that section of wisdom literature, this or that parable of Jesus, to suggest
to us unfamiliar insights.
This is not to say that the Bible will be able to contribute to Christian
ethics only when it is presented as 'foreign', or only when its interpreters
come visibly armed with historical-critical tools. Doubtless, to dispense
with such tools would be 'to create an illusion'. But even when we have
heeded the strictest caveats of historical criticism, we cannot ignore certain
recurrent emphases in most New Testament writings which surely go to
the heart of their authors' perception of what we still regard as central
Christian values: for example, the emphasis on innocence, love, compas-
sion, forbearance, humility, and so forth. Even while acknowledging even
here the danger of arbitrary selectivity, we can hardly deny that there is a
recognizable set of ethical attitudes (seen as profoundly Christian and
authentically human) which span the gap between then and now. Scholars
who spend their days poring over the Bible, for all their technical
sophistication, must surely think it part of their contribution to Christian
ethics to recall to its practitioners such central Christian values, in case
their technical sophistication causes them to lose sight of them.
Further: an approach to the Bible that wants to be free and creative will
welcome every insight, even those not born of historical-critical parentage.
The approach I favour would be warmly welcoming of modern hermeneut-
ical insights, such as those which highlight the importance of the reader's
involvement in the interpretation of texts, or the transformative potency
of story, or which seek to go behind the text to unmask negative
ideologies. At the same time, there must be some means of identifying and
excluding the plainly aberrant. Dennis Nineham spoke of the distinction
between 'insight' and 'vagary', and took comfort in the assurance of
Graham Hough that 'the consensus of those qualified to judge seldom has
much difficulty in deciding where the area of legitimate and illuminating
interpretation ends and the lunatic fringe begins'.83 Nineham must have
written that in one of his rare trusting moments; at all events, our own
day has surely taught us that consensus is not necessarily a safeguard
against lunacy. Still, in order for hermeneutically sophisticated interpreters
of biblical texts to contribute, and to contribute richly, to Christian
ethical reflection, it will be sufficient that they include in their point of
departure a consideration of what can be known of the original authors'
34
The Bible and Christian ethics
35
Tom Deidun
36
The Bible and Christian ethics
37
Tom Deidun
Progressivity
I recalled above a common ploy of canonically-minded Bible interpreters
in handling the problem of the (to us) obvious provisionality of much Old
Testament moral teaching. To be consistent with the logic of canonicity,
it was enough to assert that God was educating God's people through a
progressive pedagogy, whose earlier stages were to be revealed as merely
provisional at the time of New Testament graduation. We saw then that
this did not work, for even within New Testament ethical teachings we
need to separate off the obsolete from the potentially enduring; so that it
appears that the progressive divine pedagogy continues into the New
Testament period.
But this is not to say that some notion of progressivity (or at least of
provisionality or corrigibility) might not encourage useful reflection
38
The Bible and Christian ethics
Summary
39
Tom Deidun
Notes
1 Charles E. Curran,The role and function of the Scriptures in moral theology', first
published in Proceedings of the Catholic Theological Society of America (1971); reprinted
in Charles E. Curran and Richard A. McCormick, SJ (eds), The Use of Scripture in
Moral Theology (Readings in Moral Theology, no. 4; Ramsey, NJ: Paulist Press,
1984), pp. 178-212.
2 'In academic circles, this ephemeral movement was by I960 in a state of terminal
decline': Robert Morgan, 'Biblical theology' in R. Coggins and J. L. Houlden
(eds), A Dictionary of Biblical Interpretation (London: SCM Press, 1990), p. 89. See
Brevard Childs, Biblical Theology in Crisis (Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1970).
This is by no means to deny that many Catholic exegetes at that time were
employing proper scientific methods in their study of the Bible. Some of them
paid for it dearly.
3 James H. Cone, God of the Oppressed (London: SPCK, 1977), p. 8.
4 See, e.g., Robert Murray, Exegesis and Imagination (University of London, The
Ethel M. Wood Lecture, 1988).
5 ET and commentary in Joseph A. Fitzmyer, The Biblical Commission's Document 'The
Interpretation of the Bible in the Church' (Rome: Pontifical Biblical Institute, 1995).
6 After vigorously commending the historical-critical method ('which implies of
itself no a priori), the Biblical Commission's Statement went on to speak of
'Catholic exegesis'. I cannot understand this incongruity. Fitzmyer, who was a
member of the Commission, tries hard to explain it (The Biblical Commission's
Document, p. 47), but, as it seems to me, makes matters worse when he speaks of
'the way the Bible must be interpreted in the Church'. On p. 133, with reference
to 'Catholic exegesis', Fitzmyer speaks of 'risks', 'dangers' and the need for
'caution', especially regarding the temptation to 'attribute to the Bible what is
only a product of a later development'. Thirteen months after Pope John Paul had
blessed the Commission's Statement, the Apostolic Letter Ordinatio Sacerdotalis
put forward the (ostensibly historical) judgement that 'the Blessed Virgin Mary
{did not receive] . . . the ministerial priesthood' (n. 3).
7 The Biblical Commission's Statement sees a denial of this as a failure to accept
fully the 'consequences of the Incarnation' (Conclusion).
8 See Dennis Nineham, The Use and Abuse of the Bible (London and Basingstoke:
Macmillan, 1976), esp. ch. 1.
9 The point being made in this paragraph does not depend entirely on the view that
Jesus and the New Testament writers believed that the End was imminent (pace
Nigel Biggar and Donald Hay, The Bible, Christian ethics and the provision of
Social Security', Studies m Christian Ethics 7.2 [1994], pp. 43-64 [44f.]). I
personally think that Jesus and some New Testament writers did. But even if they
did not, it seems certain that their negative evaluation of the world was influenced
by apocalyptic elements in Judaism. Cf. J. L. Houlden, Ethics and the New Testament
(London and Oxford: Mowbray, 1975), pp. 8ff.
10 Cf. Eduard Schweizer, The Good News According to Matthew (London: SPCK, 1976),
pp. 117—36; E. P. Sanders, The Question of Uniqueness in the Teaching of Jesus
(University of London, The Ethel M. Wood Lecture, 1990).
11 Edouard Hamel is confident that the Bible presents 'a fundamental sexual
anthropology' and 'the fundamental significance of sexuality': 'Scripture: the soul
of moral theology?' in Curran and McCormick, Use, pp. 105-32 (p. 113).
40
The Bible and Christian ethics
41
Tom Deidun
or to reject the normative claims of both' (Hays, art. cit., p. 47). Why not both
choose between them and reject the normative claims of both?
25 Cf. H. Chadwick, '"All things to all men": (1 Cor. 9:22)', New Testament Studies 1
(1954-55), pp. 261-75; W. E. Phipps, 'Is Paul's attitude towards sexual relations
contained in 1 Cor. 7:1?', New Testament Studies 28 (1982), pp. 125ff.
26 For an example, see the articles referred to in note 25 above, and Peter Brown,
The Body and Society: Men, Women and Sexual Renunciation in Early Christianity
(New York: Columbia University Press, 1988), pp. 53ff.
27 Pope John Paul, in his address on the occasion of the presentation of the Biblical
Commission's Statement (see Fitzmyer, The Biblical Commission's Document, note 5
above, pp. 5f.), reminded his audience that Pius XII's Divino Afflante Spiritu laid
particular emphasis on Bible interpreters' need to understand literary genres. See
also Vatican II, Dei Verbum, n. 12. The papal magisterium's interest in literary
genres, and its criticism of the 'illusion' of those who refuse to 'make distinctions
that would relativize the significance of the words (of biblical texts}' (Pope John
Paul in Fitzmyer, p. 5), seem not to envisage the biblical writers' ethical language.
28 Cf. A. N. Wilder, cited by Nineham, Use, p. 206: 'the stultifying axiom that
genuine truth or insight or wisdom must be limited to that which can be stated
in discursive prose'.
29 Cf. Nineham, Use, pp. 47ff.
30 Cf. Houlden, Ethics, p. 11: 'Even the most biblically-minded Christian makes
artificial patterns with the texts.' (Did he mean especially the most biblically-
minded?)
31 Cf. Gareth Moore, 'Some remarks on the use of Scripture in Veritatis Splendor in
Joe Selling and Jan Jans (eds), The Splendor of Accuracy: An Examination of the
Assertions Made by 'Veritatis Splendor' (Kampen: Kok/Pharos, 1994), pp. 71-98.
Moore argues that the encyclical's preoccupation with a commandment-centred
ethic induced it to home in on the text's transitional reference to 'the command-
ments', thus missing the whole point of the passage, which is about the
'inadequacy of thinking of a person's relationship to God in terms of law and
commandment' (p. 80).
32 Cf. Anthony C. Thiselton, New Horizons in Hermeneutics: The Theory and Practice of
Transforming Biblical Reading (London: HarperCollins, 1992), pp. 444ff. See also
Thiselton's comments on Rowland and Corner's assessment of the use of biblical
material in liberationist communities in Brazil, and on Cardenal's research into
comparable groups in Nicaragua (the Magnificat shows that '[the Virgin] was a
communist. . . . That is the Revolution'): New Horizons, pp. 41 If.
33 Feminist and liberationist exegetes, in the wake of Gadamer, claim a 'hermeneutic
of suspicion' as their preserve. In fact, most second-term students in biblical
studies work on the principle that they can't trust anyone. (This is by no means
to discourage feminist and liberationist exegetes from becoming even more
hermeneutically suspicious.)
34 Cf. J. D. G. Dunn, Christology in the Making: A New Testament Enquiry into the
Origins of the Doctrine of the Incarnation (London: SCM Press, 1980). (On Gal 4:4,
see pp. 38ff.)
35 The Tablet (16 October 1993), p. 1331. Grisez continues: ' . . . assuming, that is,
that the sin, committed with full awareness and deliberate consent, remains
unrepented'. From the list of types who, according to 1 Cor 6:9f., will not inherit
the kingdom, Grisez picks out those characterized by sexual misbehaviour and
then directs his attention to particular acts. This preoccupation with certain
(intrinsically evil) sexual acts he shares with the encyclical: cf. Nicholas Lash,
42
The Bible and Christian ethics
'Crisis and tradition in Veritatis Splendor, Studies in Christian Ethics 7.2 (1994),
pp. 22-8.
36 For examples of such an enquiry, see Countryman, Dirt, pp. 117ff. and Robin
Scroggs, The New Testament and Homosexuality (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1983).
37 Even the 'Sermon on the Mount' - often regarded as Jesus' answer to Sinai, or at
least as the classic compendium of his ethical teaching - was never a sermon of
Jesus, but is rather a Veritable chorus of voices, some bearing the stamp of Jesus,
the others assembled by the evangelist to form a single whole that makes certain
specific points' (Schweizer, Good News, p. 197).
38 On the wide range of views, see, e.g., Allen Verhey, The Great Reversal (Grand
Rapids: Eerdmans, 1984), ch. 1; or Tom Wright in Stephen Neil and Tom
Wright, The Interpretation of the New Testament 1861-1986 (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1988), ch. 9- Perhaps we should bear in mind Henry Cadbury's
observation that the idea that Jesus will have worked out any overall plan for his
'ministry', and that the 'kingdom of God' was a single, thought-out conception,
may well be anachronistic. If this is true, then any attempt at a (to us) plausible
'reconstruction' will be misguided from the start.
39 '. . • the thrust of Jesus' life and teaching was at most oblique to anything that
could reasonably be called morality and not infrequently subversive of it. ... The
view that Jesus offers distinctive and superior moral teaching, and the notion that
he confirms and expands the highest agreed moral wisdom, are different forms of
the attempt to say the best we can of him in terms of the prior assumption that
morality is all-important. This assumption is being allowed to dictate the
interpretation of Jesus': Nicholas Peter Harvey, The Morals of Jesus (London:
Darton, Longman and Todd, 1991), pp. 32f.
40 Cf. Thomas W. Ogletree, The Use of the Bible in Christian Ethics (Oxford: Blackwell,
1984), pp. 177ff.; E. Clinton Gardner, 'Eschatological ethics' in John Macquarrie
and James Childress (eds), A New Dictionary of Christian Ethics (London: SCM
Press, 1986), pp. 201-5.
41 Jack T. Sanders, Ethics in the New Testament (London: SCM Press 1975, 2nd edn
1986): '[Jesus'] ethical teaching is interwoven with his imminent eschatology to
such a degree that every attempt to separate the two and to draw out only the
ethical thread invariably and inevitably draws out strands of the eschatology, so
that both yarns only lie in a heap. Better to leave the tapestry intact' (p. 29).
42 'The underlying message of the New Testament is that the emergency is now, for
us all': J. L. Houlden, Bible and Belief (London: SPCK, 199D, p. 171. Cf. Richard
Hiers, 'Jesus, ethics and the present situation' in Curran and McCormick, Use,
pp. 1-20.
43 Cf. Jack Sanders's appraisal of Bultmann's attempt to reinterpret Jesus' imminen-
tist eschatology in terms of existential urgency (Ethics, pp. 11-14).
44 'Whereas twenty-five years ago a consensus had emerged, there appears now to be
only confusion': Morna D. Hooker, 'Kingdom of God' in Coggins and Houlden,
Dictionary, pp. 374-7 (p. 377).
45 See E. P. Sanders, Paul and Palestinian Judaism: A Comparison of Patterns of Religion
(London: SCM Press, 1977); Paul, The Law and the Jewish People (see note 18
above). This challenge has not yet been effectively answered. At least, the only
extended response to it I have seen from the Lutheran tradition (Timo Laato,
Paulus und das Judentum [Abo: Abo Akademis forlag, 1991]) goes no further than
an unabashed rehearsal of standard Lutheran exegesis.
46 Cf. Tom Deidun, 'James Dunn and John Ziesler on Romans in new perspective',
The Hey throp journal XXXIII (1992), pp. 79-84.
43
Tom Deidun
47 Edward LeRoy Long Jr, 'The use of the Bible in Christian ethics', Interpretation 19
(1965), pp. 149-62; Charles E. Curran, art. cit., note 1 above, pp. 178-212.
48 James F. Gustafson, 'Christian ethics' in Paul Ramsey (ed.), Religion (Englewood
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1965); see also Curran and McCormick, Use,
pp. 133-50.
49 In a later article (1974), reprinted in Curran and McCormick, Use, pp. 151-77,
Gustafson suggested some specifications of his earlier classification.
50 Verhey, Great Reversal (see note 38 above).
51 John Murray, quoted by LeRoy Long Jr, 'The use of the Bible', p. 150.
52 To typical practitioners of this use of the Bible, this is no problem.
53 Cf. Moore, art. cit., note 31 above, p. 86.
54 Especially in Roman Catholic tradition these words of Jesus are interpreted as a
commendation of celibacy. But they are open to other quite plausible interpreta-
tions: cf., e.g., A. E. Harvey, Eunuchs for the Sake of the Kingdom (University of
London, The Ethel M. Wood Lecture, 1995).
55 Long locates its origin in Harnack, with his 'infinite value of the human soul', and
in Albert Knudson, who did much to perpetuate Harnack's view. He also cites,
more recently, Paul Ramsey, Andrew Osborne and Reinhold Niebuhr.
56 Cf. Charles Robert, 'Morale et Ecriture: Nouveau Testament', Seminarium NS 11
(1971), pp. 596-622. This kind of approach influenced Bernard Haring's The
Law of Christ (German original 1954), commonly acknowledged to have marked a
turning-point in Catholic moral theology; and it appears to be what Vatican II
had in mind when it recommended that 'biblical themes should have first place' in
dogmatic theology (Optatam Totius, n. 16; my italics).
57 '. . . the canonizing and harmonizing impulse which longs to produce "the New
Testament view'" (Houlden, Ethics, p. 121). Even such (supposed) 'master themes'
as the 'kingdom' or the imitation of Jesus leave most of the New Testament out
of account.
58 John H. Yoder, The Politics of Jesus (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1972), p. 250; cited
by Verhey in Curran and McCormick, Use, p. 226.
59 In any case, it is questionable whether the New Testament references to non-
violence can be so easily generalized, either into a principle of personal conduct
(for we simply do not know what action Jesus or the New Testament writers
might have taken had they chanced on a rape or a mugging), or into a socio-
political programme (for we do not know what advice they might give to, say,
British conscripts when war was declared on Hitler's Germany).
60 Here re-enters the whole problem of the historical Jesus. In Mark's Gospel, at
least, neighbour love is mentioned in only one passage; and Matthew's Jesus is
capable of a long tirade on the question of ethical priorities without once
mentioning love (Matt 23). Regarding Paul: notwithstanding those texts which
speak of the paramountcy of love, he is quite capable of bringing to moral
questions criteria which have nothing obviously to do with love (cf., e.g., 1 Cor
6:12-20; 1 Cor 7; Rom 13:1-7).
61 See pp. 8-9 above.
62 Richard B. Hays, art. cit., note 23 above, p. 44.
63 Gustafson in Curran and McCormick, Use, pp. I63f.
64 Gustafson in Curran and McCormick, Use, p. 166.
65 Its origins are attributed especially to Earth. As well as in H. R. Niebuhr it is
exemplified in Paul Lehmann, Joseph Sittler, Jiirgen Moltmann and others.
Curran, art. cit., note 1 above, p. 182, judged that it had beneficial influence in
the 'Scriptural renewal' in Roman Catholic circles. It is still at the heart of
44
The Bible and Christian ethics
liberation theologians' use of the Bible. Cf. Gustafson in Curran and McCormick,
Use, pp. I66f.
66 E.g., some biblically-minded people 'know' what God is 'doing' in the AIDS
crisis.
67 Bruce Birch and Larry Rasmussen, 'The use of the Bible in Christian ethics' in
Ronald P. Hamel and Kenneth R. Himes OFM (eds), Christian Ethics: A Reader
(New York: Paulist Press, 1989), pp. 322-32 (p. 324), extracted from their The
Bible and Ethics in Christian Life (Minneapolis: Augsburg, 1976). For the place of
character and virtue in contemporary Christian-ethical discussion, see Chapter 5
in this book.
68 A similar caveat must apply to those who insist that 'the believing community' is
the indispensable context for the appropriation of the Bible in Christian ethics.
Cf. Verhey in Curran and McCormick, Use, p. 216: ' . . . the importance of the
believing community as the context for the authority and appropriation of biblical
materials seems to be part of a developing consensus'. But which believing
community? The Bob Jones University (which still, on biblical grounds, prohibits
interracial dating)? The Nederduitsch Hervormde Kerk (which still, on biblical
grounds, limits its membership to whites)?
69 Gustafson in Curran and McCormick, Use, p. 165.
70 Curran, art. cit., pp. 198, 206; Gerard J. Hughes in The Heythrop Journal XIII
(1972), pp. 27—43; Gustafson in Curran and McCormick, Use, p. 172.
71 For starting-points for reflection on the Bible's 'authority', see, for example, L.
William Countryman, Biblical Authority or Biblical Tyranny? Scripture and the
Christian Pilgrimage (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1981); and John Barton, People
of the Book? The Authority of the Bible in Christianity (London: SPCK, 1988).
72 '. . . the revelatory canon for theological evaluation of biblical androcentric
traditions . . . cannot be derived from the Bible itself but can only be formulated
in and through women's struggle for liberation from all patriarchal oppression': E.
Schiissler Fiorenza, In Memory of Her (New York: Crossroad, 1983), p. 32; quoted
by Hays, art. cit., note 23 above, p. 51.
73 For the magisterium as authentic interpreter of the Bible in Roman Catholic
thinking, see Vatican II, Dei Verbum n. 10, quoted by Veritatis Splendor, n. 27. For
reflections on the relationship between this claim and the commitment of Roman
Catholic exegetes to historical critical exegesis, see R. E. Brown in R. E. Brown et
al. (eds), The New Jerome Biblical Commentary (London: Geoffrey Chapman, 1990),
pp. 1163F.
74 Cf. Hughes's discussion (art. cit., note 70 above, pp. 37f.) of Keith Ward's Ethics
and Christianity (London, 1970); Hamel, art. cit., note 11 above, pp. 109f.:
'Human reason is not infallible. . . . The light provided by Scripture will be added
to the light of human reason, supporting it, guiding its reflections, keeping it out
of impasses and indicating to it the sure paths to be followed.'
75 Similarly, it appears to be a preoccupation with biblical normativity that has
prompted Christian ethicists to speak of the 'function' of the Bible in Christian
ethics, or of an appropriate 'methodology' for using the Bible in Christian ethics.
76 Nineham, Use, p. 268.
77 See the splendid quotation from Chrysostom in Veritatis Splendor, n. 24; cf. also
Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, I-II, q. 106, a. 1, also quoted there. Aquinas (ibid., a.
2) also made the point, citing Augustine, that 2 Cor 3:6 was as applicable to the
New Testament as it was to any other writing. Cf., among moderns, Houlden,
Ethics, p. 120: 'It is arguable that to be true to the deepest convictions of the
leading New Testament writers, and more, to be faithful to the Lord who lay
45
Tom Deidun
behind them, we need to be emancipated from the letter of their writings.' All
this means, surely, that Christians are not in any nomistic sense a 'people of the
Book'. Cf. Barton, People of the Book?
78 I second Nineham's wish when he says: 'I should like to see Christians nowadays
approach the Bible in an altogether more relaxed spirit, not anxiously asking
"What has it to say to me immediately?", but distancing it, allowing fully for its
"pastness" . . .' (Use, p. 196).
79 Catechism of the Catholic Church (London: Geoffrey Chapman, 1994), Part 3, Section
2.
80 Countryman, Dirt, p. 237. His discussion in this book is an excellent example of
what I mean here.
81 The phrase is Brian Mahon's: Dictionary of Ethics, Theology and Society (London and
New York: Routledge, 1996), p. 59.
82 The phrase is Gregory Kavka's: 'The futurity problem' in Ernest Partridge (ed.),
Responsibilities to Future Generations (Buffalo: Prometheus Books, 1981),
pp. 109—22. For a Christian-ethical discussion of some of the issues involved, see
William P. George, 'Thomas Aquinas and concern for posterity', The Heythrop
Journal XXXIII (1992), pp. 283-306.
83 Nineham, Use, pp. 195ff.
84 Admittedly, the first of the following examples is not derivable only from modern
exegesis; though the point would certainly be missed by ethicists who turned to
the Bible on the look-out for directly ethical concerns.
85 Nineham saw fit to conclude his Use with a homily on prayer (p. 269).
86 Leonard Hodgson, Sex and Christian Freedom: An Enquiry (London: SCM Press,
1967), p. 42; quoted by Nineham, Use, p. 75.
87 The image is cribbed from J. L. Houlden's 'The status of origins in Christianity'
in his Bible and Belief (London: SPCK, 1991), pp. 74-81 (pp. 80-81), used there
in connection with the relationship between historical studies and systematics.
46
2
Natural law
Gerard J. Hughes
(1) Different views about the use of reason to discover God's designs for
human beings.
(2) Different accounts of what human nature is, and about how, or
indeed whether, there is any way of deriving morality from such an
account.
In a broad sense it would be fair to say that almost all the classical
Western philosophers, from Aristotle to Bentham, tried in some way to
show that morality had its basis in human nature. Many of them would
contrast morality as derived from human nature itself with the moral
customs and legislation of particular groups of human beings, and would
on occasion appeal to the natural law as a basis for assessing and on
occasions rejecting the legitimacy of particular customs or laws. In our
own day, documents like the United Nations Declaration on Human
Rights propose a set of rights which belong to human beings because of
what human beings are, and which ought to be respected for that reason.
It can be appealed to precisely to challenge the customs or legislation of
particular countries. The many difficulties encountered in attempting to
elaborate what the natural law is have at least until comparatively recent
times not deterred philosophers from holding that some such basis for
47
Gerard J. Hughes
morality there must be. However, the difficulties are serious enough. I
shall in this chapter try to outline and assess them by elaborating on the
two types of issue mentioned above.
48
Natural law
the theological doctrine of the Fall. They would argue that human nature,
as we know it now, is very far indeed from expressing the way God
intended us to be; it has been distorted by our own wrongdoing at every
period in human history. Theologians did, and to some extent still do,
differ considerably in their estimate of the extent of this moral distortion
of human nature. Views range widely. Some would argue that while
indeed we are weakened, both in our minds and in our constancy in
seeking the good, this weakness is not such as to invalidate the view that,
reflecting on ourselves even as we are, we can still see how God intends us
to live. The most they would concede is that this reflection might be more
difficult than it ideally should have been. At the other extreme, it has
been held that we are so weakened that, left to our own devices, we are
simply not capable of seeing in ourselves anything but our own distortions;
there is therefore no secure way in which reflection on ourselves as we are
can tell us anything about how God intends us to be.
To give a proper account of these differences would take us too far into
issues which are more properly the concern of systematic theology. But
perhaps some brief points can be made which might at least help to
pinpoint where the real disagreements lie. A convenient place to start is
with the famous slogan of the sixteenth-century reformers, sola fide, sola
gratia, sola Scriptura, 'only by faith, only by grace, only from Scripture'. It
is the last two of these which are of immediate importance. Going back to
the time of Augustine, there was a controversy in the Christian churches
about the need for divine assistance, 'grace', to enable us to know what
God's will is and to follow it. Pelagius and his followers were thought to
deny this, and to say that with our own unaided powers we could do a
great deal; and this view (whether Pelagius really did hold it or not) was
rejected as heretical. It remains a further, and separate question, to whom
and how God's grace becomes available. Is God's grace in fact available to
everyone who sincerely seeks God, whether they are Christian believers or
not? It is possible to hold that God's grace will always assist the sincere
moral reflections of human beings, so that in practice human reason need
never be unaided human reason, while still maintaining that the natural
law can be known without appeal to the specifically Christian revelation
in Jesus, as interpreted in the biblical and later Christian tradition. One
might, therefore, accept sola gratia, without accepting sola Scriptura. Those
theologians who insist upon sola Scriptura will generally reject the
usefulness of a natural law approach to Christian ethics.
In any event, theologians have often found it difficult to be consistent,
either in their proclaimed trust in, or in their clear distrust of, the use of
reason in ethics. Reformed theologians like Karl Earth, despite their
rejection of a natural law approach, have in practice used reason to reflect
on human nature as we know it, partly in order to interpret Scripture
49
Gerard J. Hughes
itself, and partly to supplement its moral teachings to deal with issues
which are not mentioned in Scripture at all. At the other end of the
theological spectrum, some Catholic theologians, despite their theoretical
insistence that we can in principle discover God's designs by using our
reason to reflect upon human nature, have in practice shown a good deal
of distrust for such purely philosophical reflections, and have insisted that
they be corrected or supplemented by revelation, or by the Church as the
proper interpreter of revelation.
50
Natural law
Human nature has been understood in many different ways. In the opinion
of Plato, of Augustine and of Kant, human reason, or the human rational
soul, was regarded as defining what a human being essentially was, and
the human body was regarded either as an unavoidable hindrance, or at
least as an irrelevance so far as the moral self was concerned. The British
philosophers from Hobbes to Mill believed that ethics depended on human
psychology, and that human psychology could be explained in terms of
51
Gerard J. Hughes
52
Natural law
try to understand the world around us, and God. But, as he somewhat
ruefully says, a life devoted entirely to such speculative activity is 'too
high for man'. But something of this vision of the grasp of all truth being
the pinnacle of human fulfilment was taken over by Aquinas and
interpreted in terms of the Christian doctrine of the beatific vision. In
practice, though, Aristotle accepted that human beings must also live a
life of contribution to the community; and this requires us to turn our
reason to practical decisions.
We will, if we have been well brought up, have already grasped
connections between actions which have been described to us as wrong, or
as cowardly, or dishonest, generous or mean. We can formulate general
rules about what it takes to be brave, or dishonest, or generous. But, says
Aristotle, practical wisdom (we might say, 'moral discernment'; his term
is phronesis) requires that we be able to read individual situations in a
morally correct way, since morality requires us to make particular
decisions. We already have at our disposal many moral concepts which we
have learnt to use: but we have simply to see what is required of us here
and now: whether, for example, to say 'That's very good' to someone
would be a lie, or a proper piece of encouragement, or a raising of false
expectations of progress. There are no rules which will tell us how to do
this, no arguments which can be used: what we need is long experience of
life, and emotional balance.
Aristotle points out that being liable to over-react, or under-react,
emotionally does not destroy someone's ability to do theoretical math-
ematics; but, in his view, it certainly does undermine one's judgement in
making moral decisions. To make good moral decisions, and to be able
also to trust our moral insight, we need to come to individual decisions
with a solid emotional balance; and that, in turn, requires that our
emotional responses have been properly trained. (Here, the contrast with
Plato is evident.) To have appropriate emotional responses is to have all
the moral virtues.
All this Aquinas takes over. He speaks, as does Aristotle, of the first
principles of practical reasoning. What are these? They include two
different types of principle: (1) purely formal principles: The most basic
of these is the principle of Non-contradiction, which should govern all
our reasoning, whether speculative or practical: another purely formal
principle is 'Good is to be done and evil avoided', which should govern all
practical reasoning. These formal principles as it were set the ground rules
for how we should think, in science or in ethics; but they do not in
themselves tell us what to think. (2) Other 'first principles' have
substantive content. In science, they contain fundamental truths about the
natures of things in the physical world; and in ethics, such truths as that
life and health are good things, as are education, and honesty, and the
53
Gerard J. Hughes
virtues generally. He also points out that there are many other more
detailed 'good things'; examples might be open heart surgery, or nursery
schools, or confidentiality, or giving to Oxfam. I have chosen these more
specific examples as indicative of ways in which we might seek to promote
health, or education, or honesty; but Aquinas points out that these more
detailed good things are less clear, and less likely to be truly good in all
cases, than the more fundamental ones. He, like Aristotle, does not believe
that it is possible in ethics to have anything like the precision one might
hope for in the natural sciences. And, just as Aristotle appeals in the end
to the insight of the person of practical wisdom and emotional balance, so
Aquinas stresses the importance of prudentia (his translation of Aristotle's
phronesis}, which presupposes fortitude and temperance (the balanced
emotional response in the areas of aggression and desire).
What neither Aristotle nor Aquinas believes is that from general moral
principles we can simply deduce what we ought to do in individual cases.
Part of the reason for this is that there is no way of logically deducing the
desirability of open heart surgery from the desirability of health, even
though the desirability of open heart surgery may be based upon the
desirability of health; and, second, though it is true in all cases that health
is a good thing, it is not true that open heart surgery will be a good thing
in every case. There is no substitute for seeing, in the circumstances of
each situation, what is to be done. Of course, one can explain one's
decision afterwards, by stating the good ends at which it was aimed. But
that does not in itself justify one's decision. For example, I could decide
to say 'That's very good!' to someone, and explain that by saying that they
needed encouragement at this point; but equally, I could decide to say
'Really, that could be a lot better' by saying that what was required was
honest criticism. Each decision can thus be explained in terms of the good
at which it aimed. But the explanation does nothing to justify one decision
rather than the other. Aristotle and Aquinas agree that the person of
practical wisdom will just have to see what is to be said to the person; and
that 'seeing' cannot be further justified by argument. And were someone
to object that saying 'Well done!' was simply a lie, and therefore wrong,
the reply would be that in the circumstances, it was an act of kindness,
not a lie, and if the critic does not see that then he is simply lacking in
practical wisdom.
As will be seen, then, Aquinas's view of natural law combines the
conviction that what one ought to do is based upon what is good for
human beings given how human nature functions, with a remarkably
flexible account of what people ought to do in practice. Consistency
requires that we treat similar situations in the same way, and the
injunction that we should do good and avoid evil requires that in
explaining our choices we have to be able to explain the good at which we
54
Natural law
were aiming. But neither these requirements, nor any of the more specific
statements about what things are good for human beings, will of
themselves settle how particular decisions have to be taken.
Therein lies both the strength and the weakness of natural law theories,
whether those of Aquinas and Aristotle, or the views of such writers as
Kant, or Hobbes, Hume and Bentham.
Their strength lies in the basic contention which is common to them
all, that ethics ought to be firmly rooted in what human beings are like,
and how they interact with their various environments. Although in more
recent times views of ethics have been propounded which are explicitly
value-neutral, it is perhaps more generally accepted that we cannot just
decide what we will count as a human good. What is good for us depends
upon our natures, not upon our decisions. And, in theological terms, it
seems more consonant with the wisdom of God that he wills us to be
fulfilled individuals, fulfilled according to the nature with which we have
been created. Moreover, natural law theories have always been committed
to the view that there is room in ethics for truth and falsity: we can be
mistaken, less easily with regard to very general aims like health, or
education, or freedom, but more and more easily in more specific types of
case, about what genuinely is fulfilling for ourselves or others. We can get
things right, but also get things wrong. We have to discover what truly
fulfils a person, we cannot simply decide what we will count as fulfilment.
Moreover, these theories all insist on the connection between ethics and
the human sciences. Aristotle and Aquinas were no exceptions to this,
despite their lack of modern scientific knowledge, and despite the
strictures of the Enlightenment critics. What has changed is the concep-
tion of scientific method, rather than the basic view that in order to
understand ethics, let alone to make good ethical decisions, one has to
understand human beings in a scientific way. The more we can understand
medicine, or psychology, or sociology, the better placed we will be to
understand what we are actually doing to ourselves and one another, and
hence the better placed to see what we ought to be doing.
Their weakness, if weakness it is, lies in the difficulty of relating
complex decisions to basic principles. For example, whether to spend more
money on the health service than on education, or whether to insist on
doctor—patient confidentiality where minors are concerned, or whether to
allow genetic research, and if so under what limitations. These decisions
obviously affect different people, for good and for ill, and at least often
make it only too clear that it is just not possible to achieve everything we
would wish all the time. Philosophers and theologians have wrestled with
these issues, and have tried to give theoretically consistent accounts of
why they advocate looking at them one way rather than in some other, as
indeed they are intellectually bound to do. It has often been said, with
55
Gerard J. Hughes
Select bibliography
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, I-II, qq. 91-94; II-II, qq. 47-52.
Karl Earth, Church Dogmatics, II, 2 (Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1957).
John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980).
Paul Helm (ed.), Divine Commands and Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1981).
Richard Kraut, Aristotle on the Human Good (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1989).
56
3
Authority and moral teaching in a
Catholic Christian context
Joseph Selling
The issue of authority and the sources of morality is a far-ranging one that
will inevitably be treated differently by the different Christian churches.
Some churches regard the Scriptures as the sole authority in every matter
religious, others recognize the role played by philosophy and/or consensus
in the formation of fundamental principles. Since there is a great deal of
literature dealing with each of these perspectives, I will limit myself here
to treating the issue of authority and moral teaching as it is perceived
within the Roman Catholic community.
The question of authority and its role in the lives of individuals and
groups of persons is not an exclusively ecclesiastical one. This simple
observation points immediately to a rather significant problem that will
plague any attempt to write about authority from a theological or moral
perspective, namely that differing concepts of authority will be confusingly
mingled in the mind of the reader. Police authority and parental authority
might be posed as examples of different concepts of authority that most of
us take for granted in our daily speech (although far too many parents
exercise their authority as if they were police officers). We can add to these
examples the notions of scientific authority (competence), judicial author-
ity and political authority, none of which necessarily connote moral
authority.
Using the word 'authority' will inevitably conjure up associations that
can obscure moral theological discussion. When that discussion is carried
out within the specific ecclesiological context of the Roman Catholic
Church, we must exercise further caution for, although moral teaching
certainly occupies an important place in church offices, this particular
exercise of authority does not function in exactly the same way as other
offices in the ecclesial body.
57
Joseph Selling
I suggest that the traditional distinction that has been made between the
primary and secondary objects of authoritative teaching3 should be
extended to encompass a third category. What has generally been referred
to as the primary object of authoritative teaching is held to be coextensive
with revelation, that is, the deposit of faith contained in Scripture and
(apostolic) tradition. These constitute dogmas and they are essential to the
faith, pertaining to salvation, and frequently put forth with a christological
focus. With the Orthodox churches we could easily extend this general
body of truths to the teachings of the first seven ecumenical councils and
to the creeds, most of which are synonymous with conciliar teaching.
The secondary objects of authoritative teaching constitute a more
problematic area that was not clearly defined either at Vatican I or Vatican
58
Authority and moral teaching
II. There is a general consensus, however, that this 'class of truths' includes
those things which are indispensable for the maintenance of revelation,
such as the condemnation of propositions that would contradict revelation
or a statement of those things that would necessarily flow from revelation/*
It seems rather clear that there are a great number of items that would
fall into neither of these categories and which, up until now, have been
given no clear designation. Whereas dogmas are understood to be the
object of authoritative definitions and must be accepted by one who
considers oneself to be a member of the Church, and doctrines are
generally considered to be 'theologically certain' if not actually irreforma-
ble, there are a significant number of 'teachings' that may be more or less
important but for which there is no clear measure. My suggestion is that
we attempt to delineate a category of teachings that would not so much
seek to exhaust what should be contained in this body of statements or
propositions as it would, by default, exclude an entire range of things that
have nothing to do with ecclesiastical pronouncement. 5
I propose that the majority of church teaching that fits this category
has traditionally been referred to as discipline, meaning practices, habits or
a manner of living, sometimes associated with the Latin term mores. In a
theological context, these practices or disciplines frequently have an
explicitly religious character. One thinks, for instance, of sacramental and
liturgical practice. Sacramental discipline would include factors ranging
from the time, style and manner of celebrating a sacrament to the
determination of conditions necessary for its reception. Most of these
elements have little or nothing to do with revelation, yet they do enjoy a
certain level of importance, for both the individual and the community,
and are thus the object of authoritative teaching. That said, it is clear that
being the object of authoritative teaching does not ipso facto imply
absoluteness, certainty or unchangeability.
There is also an entire range of things, however, which are not explicitly
or evidently religious in character but which are relevant to what we could
call the object of authoritative teaching (i.e., that which falls within the
competence of the office to teach). This encompasses that broad field we
call 'morality' and, at first sight, touches upon just about every facet of
our lives.
Some aspects of the moral life enjoy virtually universal consensus among
Christians and are thus taken for granted. It is not merely coincidental
that these areas of consensus are congruent with Christian dogmas and
church doctrine, intimately tied up with revelation. The most obvious
59
Joseph Selling
example are the dictates of the Decalogue. Most people would be startled
to hear us say that the Church teaches the Ten Commandments authori-
tatively, even infallibly. Yet the fact is that even the Decalogue needs to
be taught, something that constitutes a primary function of the Church,
exercised not only by the hierarchy but by every member of the faithful.
Less obvious examples of moral teaching that would constitute church
doctrines are those things that are essential to, flow from or are necessary
to protect revelation. The doctrine of free will, for example, is not
explicitly stated in revelation, nor is the doctrine of grace, and the entire
question of justification remains a lively debate among the Christian
churches. The rejection of predestination is a doctrine that has great, if
subtle, significance for Christian morality. Yet few of us ever think about
any of these issues that continue to be taught — authoritatively — by the
Church. We take for granted that the pastors of the Church, the hierarchy,
can, do, and must continue to exercise this teaching office, lest the
community of the People of God drift away from the truth (integrity) of
revelation.
Church doctrine in the area of morality, therefore, contains statements,
propositions, or more accurately convictions that are widely, if uncon-
sciously, taken for granted among the faithful and are even frequently
recognized by non-members as characteristic of the Christian community.
Christians, for instance, are expected to pray together and worship at some
fairly predictable regularity, although how and when this is actually done
is a matter of practice (discipline). Christians are the kind of people who
marry for life, although again how this doctrine is applied to particular
situations is again a matter of practice. It is Christian doctrine that
forgiveness and reconciliation are essential aspects of justice, but how this
is worked out in practice remains very much under the influence of social,
cultural, political, economic and ideological factors.6
All these aspects of Christian (church) doctrine contribute to the very
character of the community and hence to its individual members who are
expected to be attentive to and to accept what we might here call the
basic tenets of that community. While these tenets together define the
community, or more properly describe the community we call the Church,
they are not necessarily exclusive to the Christian churches, especially as
individual elements. There are those, for instance, who would subscribe to
the notion that marriage is a life-long commitment but who would
experience no tendency or compulsion to pray in community. That is,
even in the area of doctrine, Christians do not have an exclusive claim to
the individual aspects of what may constitute moral life.
60
Authority and moral teaching
Natural morality
The idea that persons can live morally without having an explicit
knowledge of revelation comes as no surprise to the Christian who already
has the benefit of that revelation. Following Jesus' own teaching, St Paul
observes that all persons are capable of doing what is prescribed 'in the
law' even if they have never known 'the law', because what is essential to
the law is written in their hearts (Rom 2:14-15). It is part of Christian
doctrine that human persons are capable of coming to a knowledge of
what is true and what is good, that they can recognize truth and goodness
because of their very being.7
This is sometimes referred to as natural morality because it is available
to all human beings, regardless of their culture, faith or religious
convictions. The leaders of the Catholic community have always claimed a
competence to teach about natural morality or the conviction that there is a
natural morality. Some have even gone so far as to claim a competence to
expound upon the content of natural morality. This, however, appears to be
taking a step too far, and the countless historical examples of the
overextension of such claims should make us very cautious. What has been
'taught' (as a matter of discipline, not doctrine, according to the
distinction proposed) about slavery, usury, or the divine right of kings is
now recognized as being culturally and historically specific. At some time,
it was important for everyone, including institutions such as the church,
to have some position on these issues. Taking a position on something,
however, was not equivalent to, nor should it be confused with, incorpo-
rating that position into the essence of what it means to be a believing
person (dogma and doctrine). Even more fundamentally, as long as any
given position with respect to natural morality has no demonstrable
connection with revelation, there is no guarantee that such a position
exhibits any inherent truth value. In most areas of natural morality,
church leaders enjoy no more — or less — competence than any other
intelligent or wise persons on most issues.
The exception to this observation rests in any possible connection that
an issue of natural morality might have with revelation. There are some
who hypothesize that the Decalogue represents the specific revelation of
(the) propositions of natural morality that a fortiori now enjoy the status
of certain truth. This is a convenient argument for those who are wedded
to the notion that morality must be deductive in argumentation from
some set of first principles. Nevertheless, the burden of proof still rests
with those who claim that their conclusions are contained in the principles
themselves.
At various times in history, claims have been made for virtually absolute
61
Joseph Selling
62
Authority and moral teaching
Only slowly did 'the natural law' become a repository for moral norms.
As stated above, the content usually assigned to this 'law' very much
resembled dominant ethnic practices. This does not disqualify the validity
or even the normative character of that content, because the aggregate of
social expectations within which we live more or less constitutes, or at
least reflects, the concrete material (descriptive) norms that are operative
on the moral level. What is distressing about assigning these things to
the 'natural' law is that it invests these norms with a character of
unchangeability and absoluteness that is not only inappropriate but
actually antithetical to their purpose. This is compounded by the
assignment of authoritative status when these norms are taken up into a
body of 'official' teaching, such as that proposed by the hierarchical
magisterium of the Church.
The problem of the relationship between authoritative teaching and
natural morality remains a delicate one. It is, furthermore, a problem that
will not be solved by 'authoritative pronouncement'. 13
Especially since the first Vatican Council in 1870, there has been a
tendency to think of the exercise of authority in the Church as concentrated
in the hands of the hierarchy alone, the pope and the bishops. This is so
pervasive that even the term 'magisterium', a term that was traditionally
used of learned persons and teachers,11 has come to be virtually identified
with membership in the hierarchy. Some correction to this idea was
accomplished at Vatican II which restored a more balanced understanding
of the Church as the 'People of God'. The Church is first and foremost a
community; God relates to and reveals to a community. Therefore, no
amount of papal or episcopal hegemony can claim exclusive access to the
truth about God and the mystery of the relationship of God to humankind,
an experience that is primarily set in the context of the entire People of
God.
The exercise of authority in the Church as the People of God, therefore,
does not rest solely in the hands of the episcopacy, although as we shall
see the bishops remain the only persons in the Church who can lay claim
to being official teachers. The authoritativeness of any deed or statement,
furthermore, is inextricably tied up with the nature and the mission of the
Church as the People of God, formed by the Word of God and shaped by
apostolic tradition. Therefore, any claim to authoritative action or teaching
in the Church is bound up with revelation. It 'extends as far as extends
the deposit of divine revelation, which must be religiously guarded and
faithfully expounded' (L(7, n. 25).
63
Joseph Selling
64
Authority and moral teaching
65
Joseph Selling
concrete, behavioural norms that describe human activity and signal the
real or potential presence of good and evil. The authority of the formal or
fundamental norms is the most certain because of its link with the core of
Christian faith itself that specifically addresses attitude or disposition.
Called to love God and love our neighbour as ourselves, we recognize this
call to love being applied in the many facets of human life, especially life
in community. Love applied to human relations is commonly referred to
as justice; love applied to human sexuality is chastity. Love applied to
communication is called honesty and a loving attitude toward commit-
ment is called faithfulness. In other words, love applied to all sorts of
human endeavour reveals the virtues: be kind, generous, patient, and so
forth (1 Cor 13). The authority of the fundamental norms is the authority
of revelation itself and those who pronounce such statements can claim
this authority with confidence, knowing that they are servants of the
source and not its creator. Those who hear the exhortation to a virtuous
life respond not to the speaker but to the source itself, for 'God is love' (1
John 4:7-8).
It is quite a different story for the more explicit, concrete norms that
describe specific human behaviour which always takes place in a cultural
and historical context. Exactly what authority such statements might carry
is dependent not simply on a demonstrable connection with the faith but
also upon a consensus within the (Christian) community about the
appropriateness of various forms of behaviour. Here it is clear that we need
to use the utmost caution lest we overextend the claims to authoritative
pronouncement or underestimate the importance of some behaviours
purely on the basis of their representing cultural conventions. These are
two of the dangers to be avoided in elaborating material norms.
On the first count, we could offer the example of some interpretations
of the so-called natural law that claimed a hierarchy of persons based upon
non-specifying differences within the human condition. As we read in
Gaudium et Spes, 'every type of discrimination, whether social or cultural,
whether based on sex, race, colour, social condition, language or religion,
is to be overcome and eradicated as contrary to God's intent' (GS, n. 29).
There have been some instances in the past in which the pretence of
religious authority was used to enforce discriminatory practices as though
they were willed by God.
On the other side, we should be wary of complacency toward some form
of behaviour simply because it constitutes 'common practice'. One could
again refer to many forms of discrimination in social living, but a good
alternative would be the way in which various societies tolerate the
violation of social expectations. Tolerance shown to political corruption,
the practice of avoiding reasonable taxes, or the negligent breaking of
traffic laws all constitute specific forms of behaviour that have an important
66
Authority and moral teaching
Clearly, however, it is neither realistic nor possible for each and every
member of the faithful - not to mention every member of society - to
assess every possible form of behaviour or even come to grips with the
appropriateness of a given attitude or disposition. (How, for instance, does
one distinguish righteous anger from revenge, especially when one is the
victim of injustice?) Fortunately, it is not necessary for us to approach the
vast majority of moral issues from scratch, as it were, because we have
available to us a tremendous heritage of moral wisdom. This wisdom
contains insights, observations, practical rules, and tools for moral
assessment and calculation that help us develop lifestyles and guide us in
making moral decisions that are appropriate for living out the faith.
A person who considers himself or herself to be Christian will define
their life at the most fundamental level as being a child of God, redeemed
by Christ and participant in the entire People of God. A Catholic Christian
(NB: not to the exclusion of others) further recognizes that the means for
encounter with God encompass not only the written Scriptures but also
the apostolic — episcopal — tradition, transmitted through the ages via the
entire community of believers.
It resides in the office of the bishop as apostolic successor in communion
with all other bishops to safeguard and teach the faith. To the extent that
the bishops teach the faith on behalf of the community of the People of
God, this teaching is rightly referred to as authoritative. The authority
that this teaching carries is not the personal authority of the individual
exercising the office but rather the authority of the source of this teaching.
Insofar as various teachings can be related to the (deposit of) faith, 15 they
call upon the faithful to accept these teachings as essential for membership
in the community of the People of God.
When the bishops teach dogma, the very essentials of the faith itself, the
authority they exercise is the same as the dogmas: every member of the
faithful must accept these dogmas if they are to count themself as members
of the faithful. When the bishops teach doctrines, they enunciate items that
have been found to be dependent upon, flowing from or necessary for the
protection of the faith, and the authority of these teachings is proportion-
ate to their essential connection with the faith.
However, when the bishops teach about discipline or the practices of
67
Joseph Selling
68
Authority and moral teaching
69
Joseph Selling
Notes
70
Authority and moral teaching
14 Very important work has been done in this area by Yves Congar OP, who has
written two virtually classic articles on the subject in Revue des sciences philosophiques
et theologiques 60 (1976): 'Pour une histoire semantique du term "Magisterium"',
pp. 85-98, and 'Bref historique des formes du "magistere" et de ses relations avec
les docteurs', pp. 99-112. These have been translated into English in Charles E.
Curran and Richard A. McCormick (eds), Readings in Moral Theology, no. 3: The
Magisterium and Morality (New York: Paulist Press, 1982) as 'A semantic history
of the term "Magisterium"', pp. 297-313, and 'A brief history of the forms of the
"Magisterium" and its relations with scholars', pp. 314-31. For a wider back-
ground to these studies, see also Congar's Tradition and Traditions: An Historical
and Theological Essay (London: Burns & Gates, 1966), originally published in two
parts as La Tradition et les Traditions: Essai Historique (I960), Essai Theologique
(1963).
15 The classical phrase 'deposit of faith' refers to the totality of what we as the People
of God believe. As it stands, this expression gives the impression of being almost
entirely prepositional and hence not entirely apt for a description of the moral life
which includes more 'gestures' than statements.
Select bibliography
Charles E. Curran and Richard A. McCormick (eds), Readings in Moral Theology, no. 3:
The Magisterium and Morality (New York: Paulist Press, 1982), especially articles
by Yves Congar, 'A semantic history of the term "Magisterium"', pp. 297-313,
and 'A brief history of the forms of the "Magisterium" and its relations with
scholars', pp. 314-31.
Piet F. Fransen, 'A short history of the meaning of the formula fides et mores', Louvain
Studies 1 (1979), pp. 270-301.
Joseph A. Selling, 'The authority of church teaching in matters of morality' in F.
Vosman and K. Merks (eds), Aiming at Happiness: The Moral Teaching of the Catechism
(Kampen: Kok/Pharos 1996).
Francis A. Sullivan, Magisterium: Teaching Authority m the Catholic Church (New York:
Paulist Press, 1983), pp. 127-52.
71
4
Absolute moral norms
Charles E. Curran
Are there moral norms that are always and everywhere obligatory? Human
beings in general and Christians, as well as philosophers and theologians,
have continuously grappled with this issue but the question has become
more intense in the last decades as some previously accepted moral norms
have been questioned.
The question needs to be nuanced and put into proper perspective.
Almost all would agree that some absolute and universally binding norms
exist. For example, those against murder, lack of respect for persons,
cheating, harming another merely to indulge one's own sense of superior-
ity. Such absolute norms are either formal (murder by definition is
unjustified killing) or very general (justice is to be done) or quite qualified
and include relatively few actions (harming others to indulge one's own
sense of superiority is unacceptable). The controversy today in the churches
often involves concrete, specific, unqualified absolute norms.
Most often ethicians discuss this question of absolute norms from the
perspective of personal morality but this study will also consider the social
dimensions of the issue. However, these two aspects should never be
totally separated.
The Christian approach has generally recognized four different sources
of moral wisdom and knowledge - Scripture, tradition, reason and
experience. Norms have been grounded in these sources with most
emphasis going to the Scriptures and human reason. Protestant approaches
have given greater emphasis to the role of Scripture whereas Roman
Catholic authors have appealed primarily to reason, with the Anglican
tradition often appealing to both Scripture and reason.
72
Absolute moral norms
Personal perspectives
The Scriptures have often served as the basis for absolute moral norms and
laws for Christians. The Ten Commandments constitute the best known
moral teaching found in the Bible. Many catechisms and discussions of
Christian morality have followed the schema of the Ten Commandments.
Although all Christians accept the Ten Commandments, diversity exists
in the numbering of the individual commandments. The differences
concern the first commandments and the last commandments. The Greek
tradition and most Protestants make the prohibition of false gods the first
commandment and the prohibition of false images the second command-
ment while combining in the tenth commandment the coveting of the
neighbour's wife and goods. The Catholic and Lutheran traditions follow
a slightly different version putting the prohibition of false images under
the first commandment's prohibition of false gods and making the
coveting of the neighbour's wife the ninth commandment and the coveting
of the neighbour's goods the tenth commandment. Not all the Ten
Commandments constitute absolute prohibitions as illustrated in the
commandment against killing. Christians generally recognize some cir-
cumstances in which killing can be accepted albeit reluctantly. However,
some absolute norms such as the prohibition of adultery have been based
on Scripture.
Before the critical study of the Bible in the nineteenth century most
Christians understood the moral teaching of the Bible as the commands of
God for all times and places. Fundamentalists still interpret the Bible in
this way. Scripture scholars and moral theologians in the mainstream
Protestant and Catholic churches today recognize that the teachings of the
Bible are historically, culturally and socially conditioned. We live in
different circumstances and situations and consequently what was accepted
as true in a particular book of the Bible written in different times and
places might not be true in our changed situation today.
One good illustration concerns the submission and obedience of wives
to husbands as found in the 'household codes' best illustrated in Galatians
3:18 — 4:1 and Ephesians 5:22 — 6:9- Fundamentalists and some
conservative Christians still see the obedience and submission of the wife
as a biblical norm continuing to be true in our day. Those who accept the
more critical approach to the Scriptures see these household codes as
expressions of the patriarchy of the time and no longer binding in the
changed circumstances of our times.
The present controversy about homosexuality in practically all the
Christian churches illustrates the different ways in which Christians
interpret the Scriptures. Until the late 1960s Christian churches were
73
Charles E. Curran
74
Absolute moral norms
75
Charles E. Curran
Christian moral traditions has not identified the physical structure of the
act with the moral act. Killing is a physical act. But not every killing is
wrong. Not every act of false speech is a lie. The lying example provides
helpful insight into the question under discussion. In this century some
theologians began to question the accepted understanding of the malice of
lying and proposed a solution which actually has roots in an even earlier
Christian tradition. The accepted understanding in the beginning of the
twentieth century understood the malice of lying to consist in the violation
of the God-given purpose of the faculty of speech. The purpose of the
faculty of speech is to put on my lips what is in my mind. To put on my
lips what is in contradiction to what is in my mind is perverting the
faculty of speech and is therefore going against its God-given purpose.
Such an approach developed an elaborate casuistry of mental reservations
to deal with conflict situations where telling the truth might be harmful.
The problem of needing to conceal the truth from someone who has no
right to it or was going to abuse it occasioned a rethinking of the criterion
of the malice of lying. The faculty of speech should not be isolated and
considered in itself but rather seen as part of the human person who is
related to other human persons. The malice of lying consists in the
violation of my neighbour's right to truth. But if the neighbour has no
right to truth then one may speak a falsehood which is not a lie. The
'physical' falsehood is not always a moral lie. The example not only
illustrates the fact that the moral reality differs from the physical reality
but underscores the problem with a moral criterion based on the nature
and purpose of the faculty as seen in isolation from the person and the
person's relationship with other persons.
The official Catholic teaching on sexuality also employs an approach
based on the nature and purpose of the sexual faculty or power. Human
sexuality exists for the twofold purpose of love union and procreation and
consequently every sexual act must be both open to procreation and
expressive of love union. Such an understanding grounds the condem-
nation of artificial contraception for spouses.
A word of caution is in order. Sometimes the physical and the moral
are the same. The only human beings we know are physical and bodily
human beings. However, one cannot a priori identify the human and the
moral with the physical. The physical is only one aspect of the human and
the moral. The ultimate moral or human judgement (I am using these
two terms synonymously) must be inclusive of all aspects — the physical,
the psychological, the social, the eugenic, the hygienic, and so forth. The
moral or human judgement is the ultimate judgement which must balance
off all the particular aspects of the human act such as the physical or the
biological. Human nature cannot be reduced only to the physical or the
biological.
76
Absolute moral norms
77
Charles E. Curran
78
Absolute moral norms
ing. A second approach identified with Germain Grisez and John Finnis
develops a different natural law approach based on human flourishing or
integral human fulfilment. According to this approach there are certain
basic human goods which human beings can never directly go against.
While the theory disagrees with the emphasis on the nature of the faculty
in the natural law theory of the hierarchical magisterium it comes to the
same basic conclusions in practice.
A third approach, often called revisionist or proportionalist, disagrees
to some extent with both the theory and the conclusions of the natural
law theory proposed by the hierarchical magisterium. This theory dis-
tinguishes between moral evil and premoral (or physical or ontic) evil thus
trying to avoid the danger of physicalism that seems to be present in the
official hierarchical teaching. One can never intend premoral evil as an end
but one can intend and do premoral evil as a means to an end provided
there is a proportionate reason. Much discussion has ensued about the
exact meaning of proportionate reason. Proponents of Catholic revisionism
maintain they avoid the dangers of physicalism on the one hand and of
total consequentialism on the other. I personally accept the Catholic
revisionist position.
In conclusion the question of absolute moral norms is not the most
important question for basic Christian ethics. Law in my judgement is not
the most significant moral category. Morality should never be seen
primarily in terms of a legal model but rather in terms of a relationality—
responsibility model which sees the individual human person in multiple
relationships with God, neighbour, world and self. In the context of this
model great emphasis is given to the conversion or basic change of heart
of the individual person together with the virtues or attitudes that should
direct the Christian in daily life. Values constitute an important consider-
ation in Christian ethics and laws should exist to protect these values. Law
thus should never play the primary role in basic Christian ethics or in the
moral life but laws do have a necessary place. Some laws will admit of
exception while others are absolute. For example, most Christians recog-
nize there are circumstances when the obligation of promise keeping is no
longer morally required while the Christian community generally main-
tains an absolute prohibition of adultery.
The previous considerations have laid the groundwork for an under-
standing of absolute moral norms in moral theology. On a more general
level there exist absolute moral values or principles or norms but as one
becomes more specific the possibility of absolute, specific, unqualified
norms decreases. Such a general understanding coheres with generally
accepted understandings of logic. The greater the complexity and the
specificity, the more difficult it is to claim that one moral value will not
conflict with another. Confidentiality, for example, is a very important
79
Charles E. Curran
80
Absolute moral norms
Social context
The discussion about absolute norms generally occurs only in the context
of personal morality. But one must also consider here the context of social
morality with the realization that no absolute dichotomy should exist
between the personal and the social.
The Christian tradition in general and the Roman Catholic approach in
particular have emphasized the importance of the common good. Human
beings are not just isolated individuals but are social beings called to live
together in civic and political community. The common good refers to
shared or public values and interests which ultimately redound to the
good of all the members of the community.
Such an understanding of society is opposed to individualism which
sees the society as the sum total of individuals and also to collectivism
which denies the legitimate needs and rights of individuals who are
submerged in the collectivity. Individualism constitutes the major prob-
lem today.
Individualists pursue their own individual good or success (often
understood in monetary terms) and have no concern for the common or
public good of the community. I should be free to do my own thing and
you should be free to do your own thing. The dangers of such an approach
are obvious. Either civil society will be torn asunder or the strong and the
fortunate will prevail.
Any theory of the common good asserts that a shared understanding of
the requirements of justice and human rights is necessary for community
and society. We must provide justice for all and ensure the basic human
rights of all. But here too one must make sure that justice and human
rights are not understood in a totally individualistic manner.
Human rights are both political or civil on the one hand, and economic
or social on the other. Political and civil rights stress freedom from — the
freedom of individuals from outside forces that are trying to restrict or
restrain them. Thus we have freedom of religion, of the press, of
association, of speech. But there are also social or economic rights. Every
individual has the right to a basic minimum necessary for truly human
existence — a right to food, clothing, shelter, and a basic level of health
care. Both types of rights are necessary.
These basic human rights or common values will by definition tend to
be somewhat broad and general. Likewise there will be much discussion
about what such values or rights entail in practice. However, even the
many particular disagreements within a given society on such issues
indicate that a basic type of shared broad agreement still exists.
Some recent developments in Christian theological ethics, however,
81
Charles E. Curran
might seem at first sight to argue against any absolute norms of justice
and rights in a given political community. Liberationist and feminist
theologies point out there is no neutral, objective, universal reason but all
of us are human subjects who are coming from different historical and
social locations. Every human being brings with himself or herself their
own experiences, to say nothing of that person's fmitude, limitations and
prejudices. The Western world and our understanding of it have been
shaped by white males of an upper-class background. Consequently, not
enough attention has been given to women or to those of other races and
economic classes. The United States with its strong declaration of
inalienable and fundamental human rights did not recognize the rights of
African Americans and accepted slavery and second-class citizenship for
Blacks for most of its history. Patriarchy dominated the Western world,
relegating women to a subordinate role in society. The poor have been
made invisible. Universal, neutral, objective reason does not really exist.
Liberation theologies begin with the location and experience of the
oppressed - the poor, people of colour, and women - and take their
subjective strivings for liberation seriously. In this light God is not an
objective, detached observer of the human scene but God too is prejudiced
and partial - in favour of the oppressed. In the liberationist perspective
truth is not an abstract reality which is applied to particular issues.
Rather, theology and ethics insist on the importance of praxis and
reflection on praxis. Truth emerges from the experience of people striving
for liberation and does not exist primarily as an abstract, objective reality.
In the light of the emphasis found in various liberation theologies one
might conclude there is no possibility for any universality. But the vast
majority of liberation theologians and ethicists while emphasizing social
location and the experience of the oppressed do not want to deny
universality. Liberation theologians in Latin America speak about a
preferential option for the poor which is not exclusive but merely shows a
preference. Feminist ethicists generally do not plead for an exclusive
feminist society but recognize the need for all to be equal and share in the
life of society.
Yes, social location and the recognition that we are not neutral, value-
free, objective observers of the human scene are important insights in
contemporary ethics of all kinds. However, most thinkers who start from
a particular social location also recognize the need for some common
morality and universal norms of justice and rights within the society.
Without such commonly accepted principles of justice and rights there
can be no true political community. Today we are much more conscious
of the pluralism and diversity within political society. In addition, our
world has witnessed the breakup of some political unities because of the
diversity of language, ethnicity and culture. In the light of the greater
82
Absolute moral norms
Select bibliography
Charles E. Curran and Richard A. McCormick (eds), Readings m Moral Theology, no. 7:
Natural Law and Theology (New York: Paulist Press, 1991).
Germain Grisez and Russell Shaw, Fulfillment in Christ: A Summary of Christian Moral
Principles (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1991).
Bernard Hoose, Proportionalism: The American Debate and Its European Roots (Washing-
ton, DC: Georgetown University Press, 1987).
Richard J. Mouw, The God Who Commands (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre
Dame Press, 1990).
Jeffrey S. Siker, Scripture and Ethics: Twentieth-Century Portraits (New York: Oxford
University Press, 1997).
83
5
Virtue ethics
James F. Keenan
Who am I?
84
Virtue ethics
85
James F. Keenan
86
Virtue ethics
In order to get to the end, one needs prudence. For many years prudence
has had a terrible reputation, being thought of as caution or self-interest.
Be prudent meant: Don't get caught. Be extra careful. Watch out!
For Aristotle and Thomas prudence is not simply caution. Prudence is
rather the virtue of a person whose feet are on the ground and who thinks
both practically and realistically. Prudence belongs to the person who not
only sets realistic ends, but sets out to attain them. The prudent person is
precisely the person who knows how to grow.7
Being prudent is no easy task. From the medieval period until today,
we believe that it is easier to get something wrong than to get it right.
For today we still assert that if only one component of an action is wrong,
the whole action is wrong. Think for instance of cooking. In order for
something to come out right, every ingredient has to be measured exactly,
prepared correctly and cooked properly. How many of us have had a
terrible meal because it was too salty, overcooked, too spicy or too bland?
Only when everything comes out right can we say that the meal tasted
well.
Prudence is even more complicated when we try to work out the
appropriate way of becoming more virtuous. It must be attentive to detail,
anticipate difficulties and measure rightly. Moreover, as any one who has
watched children knows, we are not born with prudence. Actually we
acquire it through a very Jong process.
The first sign of real prudence is finding the right person to give us
advice. When I taught at Fordham University in the Bronx, I lived in the
student dorms and noted how often university students went to one
another for advice. These students, away from home for the first time,
were looking for advice no longer from their parents, but instead from
their peers. Often they looked to people like themselves for advice; in fact,
the groups with which they associated collectively were similar to
themselves individually. Studious students stayed together, as did hard
workers, athletes, snobs, shy people, excessive party-goers, and so forth.
When they asked for advice they usually were not hearing anything new.
On occasion someone from outside the group might raise a question.
For instance, one might say to the excessive drinker that he was drinking
too much. Inevitably he sought out advice about the charge and went to
his alcoholic drinking buddy to ask if he was drinking too much and his
buddy would calm his friend's anxiety with denial. After a while, however,
87
James F. Keenan
the drinker would ask someone else, usually someone from the exact
opposite group, someone who thought drinking was always wrong. What
the student was looking for was advice, but he went from one extreme to
the other.
Finding prudence is finding the middle point. Unlike the student here,
prudence guides us to moderation, where we are not at either end of an
extreme. The student who drinks excessively will only get good advice
when he meets someone who is able to recognize the difference between
moderate and excessive drinking.
As prudence looks for the moderating advisor, it does so because it
realizes that all of prudence is precisely getting to the middle point or the
mean between extremes. As Aquinas says, virtue is the mean.
Getting the mean is not always easy. I remember a friend who was
afraid of heights. In order to grow, he needed to face his fear, but he had
to do it prudentially. That is, he needed to set a realistic goal that he
could attain. But that goal had to be the mean between extremes for him.
For instance, if he went too high, say if he went to the observation deck
of the World Trade Center, he would feel no confidence at all, only
anxiety. But if he only went to the second-storey balcony of an apartment
building, he would not feel sufficient tension. Prudence helps then find
the mean where there is adequate tension for growth, neither too little nor
too much.
That mean is not fixed. For me to get over my fear of heights requires
me to go to the height where I feel sufficient tension, a height that may
not be the same as for another with a similar fear. The mean of virtue then
is not something set in stone: rather, it is the mean by which only a
specific person can grow. This is another reason why prudence is so
difficult: no two means are the same.
But parents again know this. Though their children always cry 'Foul'
or 'That's unfair' whenever a parent treats one child differently from
another, still if a parent treated each child the same, then only one child
would grow adequately. Instead, parents appreciate the uniqueness of each
child and try to address each child as unique.
Finding the mean of the right tension depends on who the person is.
Just as in weight-lifting, one needs to determine what is the right tension
by considering the lifter's abilities, so too in most matters that pertain to
a person's growth, we cannot give prudential advice unless we have a clear
idea of who the agent is. In a manner of speaking, a virtue ought to fit a
person the way a glove fits one's hand. There is a certain tailor-made feel
to a virtue, which prompts Aquinas to call virtue one's second nature.
Virtue ethics is, therefore, a pro-active system of ethics. It invites all
people to see themselves as they really are, to assess themselves and see
who they can actually become. In order both to estimate oneself and to set
88
Virtue ethics
desired goals it proffers the virtues for both. Moreover, it invites all people
to see that they set the agenda not only of the end, but also of the means
to accomplish that end. Virtuous actions, like temperate drinking or
courageously facing one's fear of heights, are the prudential means for
achieving the end of becoming a more virtuous person. And we see those
means as moderate or prudential ones.
Virtue ethics encompasses one's entire life. It sees every moment as the
possibility for acquiring or developing a virtue. To underline this point,
Aquinas said that every human action is a moral action.8 That is, any
action that I knowingly perform is a moral action because it affects me as
a moral person. Whatever I do makes me become what I do. If I drive to
work and use that time to reflect on the day that lies before me, over time
I can become a person with a developed sense of foresight. If I drive to
work both aggressively and speedily, I eventually arrive at my office with
the same manic personality that brought me there. If I correct everyone's
mistakes at every opportunity, I am becoming more and more of a control
freak. And though my corrections may hurt a few around me, they are
basically making me progressively more and more trapped by this
disposition. While others may be affected by some of my actions, I am the
first person affected by all of my actions.
Thomas saw every human action as an exercise. The way I take
breakfast, the way I leave home, the way I drive to work, the way I greet
people in the morning are all exercises that affect me. My morning
exercises make me in part: the person I will be for the rest of the day. They
make me become what I do. Though some of us go through life never
examining the habits we engage, Thomas suggests to us that we ought to
examine our ways of acting and ask ourselves 'Are these ways making us
more just, prudent, temperate and brave?' If they are, they are virtuous
exercises.
When we think of exercise we think of athletics. The person who
exercises by running eventually becomes a runner just as the one who
dances becomes a dancer. From that insight Thomas, like Aristotle before
him, sees that intended, habitual activity in the sports arena is no different
from any other arena of life. If we can develop ourselves physically we can
develop ourselves morally by intended, habitual activity.
Virtue ethics sees, therefore, the ordinary as the terrain on which the
moral life moves. Thus, while most ethics make their considerations about
rather controversial material (genetics, abortion, war, and so forth), virtue
ethics often engages the commonplace. It is concerned with what we teach
our children and how; with the way we relate with friends, families, and
neighbours; with the way we live our lives. Moreover, it is concerned not
only with whether a physician maintains professional ethics, for instance,
whether she keeps professional secrets or observes informed consent with
89
James F. Keenan
her patients. It is equally concerned with her private life, with whether
she knows how to respect her friends' confidences or whether she respects
her family members' privacy. In a word, before the physician is a physician
she is a person. It is her life as a person with which virtue ethics is
specifically concerned.
As opposed to dilemma-based ethics, virtue ethics is pro-active,
concerned with the ordinary and all-encompassing. Dilemma-based ethics,
which captures so much of our time, imagination and energy, presents
ethics as an emergency room in which suddenly a previously unknown
person arrives in a catastrophic state: needing an organ transplant, assisted
suicide or an abortion. In that made-for-TV ethics, the agent is little more
than a reactor to other people's dilemmas.
Virtue ethics looks at the world from an entirely different vantage
point, moving ahead with less glamour and drama, but always seeing the
agent, not as reactor, but as actor: knowing oneself, setting the agenda of
personal ends and means in both the ordinary and the professional life.
90
Virtue ethics
91
James F. Keenan
the just person. Temperance and bravery exist in order to help a person to
be just; they are effectively auxiliary. Likewise prudence functions to
determine the concrete mean for justice, temperance and courage. For
Thomas then the just person is the virtuous person. The other virtues help
the person to be just.
Today, however, the image of the just person is insufficient. Almost
everyone writing on the virtues today recognizes that whereas one must
be just, that is, that one must treat everyone equally, still one must also
attend to the immediate needs of friends, family and community. Writers
like Reinhold Niebuhr, 18 Margaret Farley19 and Carol Gilligan20 insist
that the moral person cannot only be just: the demands to care for a loved
one may conflict with the call to be fair to everyone.
Paul Ricoeur adds that it is important that justice is challenged by the
affection we have for another. Rather than reducing the two claims to one,
he places them in a 'tension between two distinct and sometimes opposed
claims'.21 This insight that the virtues are distinct and at times opposing
stands in contrast with Thomas' strategy of the cardinal virtues where
justice is supported by fortitude and temperance and none contradicts,
opposes, or challenges the claims of justice.
Furthermore we recognize another difference with Thomas. Thomas
argues that virtues perfect or make better our own dispositions; each
virtue perfects a particular power in us. Justice perfects our will, prudence
our reasoning, courage and temperance perfect particular emotions. But
today we think of the person as fundamentally relational. Virtues perfect
not individual powers, but rather the ways we relate with one another.22
In this relational light let us call the two competitive demands that we
have been discussing, justice and fidelity. If justice urges us to treat all
people equally, then fidelity makes different claims. Fidelity is the virtue
that nurtures and sustains the bonds of those special relationships that we
enjoy whether by blood, marriage, love or sacrament. Fidelity requires
that we treat with special care those who are closer to us.23 If justice rests
on impartiality and universality, fidelity rests on partiality and
particularity.24
But these two are not enough; we also must perfect the unique
relationship that we have with ourselves. Thomas, through the order of
charity, demonstrates the virtuous love for self.25 Following him, Stephen
Pope26 and Edward Vacek27 argue that we have a primary task to take care
of ourselves: affectively, mentally, physically, and spiritually.
For these reasons, then, I conclude by proposing that we conceive of
ourselves as relational in three ways: generally, specifically and uniquely,
and each of these relational ways of being demands a cardinal virtue: as a
relational being in general, we are called to justice and to treat all people
fairly; as a relational being specifically, we are called to fidelity and to
92
Virtue ethics
Notes
93
James F. Keenan
13 For example, James Drane, 'Character and the moral life: a virtue approach in
biomedical ethics' in Edwin DuBose et al. (eds), A Matter of Principles? (Park
Ridge: Trinity Press, 1994), pp. 284-309; Michael Green, 'What (if anything) is
wrong with residency overwork?', Annals of Internal Medicine 123 (1995),
pp. 512-17; James F. Keenan, 'What's morally new in genetic engineering',
Human Gene Therapy 1 (1990), pp. 289-98; William Stempsey, 'Special report:
the virtuous pathologist', American Journal of Clinical Pathology 91.6 (1989),
pp. 730-8.
14 Owen Flanagan, Varieties of Moral Personality: Ethics and Psychological Realism
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991), p. 158.
15 Alasdair Maclntyre in both After Virtue and Whose Justice? Which Rationality?
(Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press, 1988).
16 Martha Nussbaum offers a helpful response to Maclntyre's warnings in 'Non-
relative virtues: an Aristotelian approach' in Midwest Studies 13, pp. 32-53.
17 I develop this at length in 'Proposing cardinal virtues', Theological Studies 56.4
(1995), pp. 709-29.
18 Reinhold Niebuhr, Love and Justice: Selections from the Shorter Writings of Reinhold
Niebuhr, ed. D. B. Robertson (Louisville, KY: Westminster, 1957).
19 Margaret Farley, Personal Commitments: Beginning, Keeping, Changing (San Francisco:
Harper and Row, 1990).
20 Carol Gilligan, In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women's Development
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982).
21 Paul Ricoeur, 'Love and justice' in Werner G. Jeanrond and Jennifer L. Rike (eds),
Radical Pluralism and Truth: David Tracy and the Hermeneutics of Religion (New
York: Crossroad, 199D, pp. 187-202, at p. 196.
22 See Paul Lauritzen, 'The self and its discontents', Journal of Religious Ethics 22.1
(1994), pp. 189-210.
23 In Virtues for Ordinary Christians I treat each of these.
24 See a similar insight in William Spohn, 'The return of virtue ethics', Theological
Studies 53 (1992), pp. 60-75, at p. 72.
25 The concern for self-care runs throughout the Summa, from I, 5.1c and 48.1 which
describes how all nature seeks its own perfection to I-II, 27.3 that insists that it is
natural to prefer oneself over others and 29-4 that it is impossible to hate oneself.
In II-II, Aquinas argues that though inordinate self-love is the source of sin (25.4,
28.4 ad 1), self-love belongs to the order of charity and is prior to neighbour love
(25.12, 26.4). He adds that charity is the source of peace which aims at ending
conflict not only with others but also within oneself (29.1). By introducing self-
care into the constellation of the cardinal virtues I believe that I am developing
Thomas's own thoughts.
26 Stephen Pope, The Evolution of Altruism and the Ordering of Love (Washington, DC:
Georgetown University Press, 1994).
27 Edward Vacek, Love, Human and Divine: The Heart of Christian Ethics (Washington,
DC: Georgetown University Press, 1994), pp. 239-73.
94
6
The human person
Joseph Selling
Any system of moral reflection, including those which some people might
like to label 'relativistic', ultimately must have some point of reference for
denning its most fundamental terms. This remains true whether one
considers morality from the subjective perspective, the goodness or badness of
moral intention, or from the so-called objective perspective, the Tightness or
wrongness of human behaviour.
'Subjectively', for a behavioural event (act or omission) to be considered
moral, it must exhibit elements of freedom and intention. Although there
is a growing tendency to factor animals, and even 'nature', into our moral
considerations, concepts such as 'animal rights' and 'the integrity of
creation' remain passive items that are reflected upon rather than function-
ing as agents. Only human persons are considered moral agents, precisely
because they are capable of self-direction (intention) and presumably
because they enjoy the knowledge of and ability to make choices (freedom).
Random events, no matter how 'good' (bumper crops) or 'evil' (earth-
quakes) human beings might like to call them, are not of themselves
moral events. Only human events are properly referred to as moral,
although again it is necessary to qualify only certain kinds of human
events in this way.
Tradition distinguished the actus hominis, such as walking, eating or
sleeping, from the actus humanus according to whether freedom and
intention are part of the entire event. Today we might suggest that merely
describing the gestures or actions of a human being does not yet deliver us
into the moral realm. Something more is needed before we can speak of
human events as moral events, namely freedom and intentionality. Such
events are uniquely perpetrated by the human person, a term that describes
not a mere object or being but an active, existential phenomenon. The
95
Joseph Selling
96
The human person
97
Joseph Selling
98
The human person
99
Joseph Selling
make us insensitive to the fact that this language sometimes creates a wall
between people rather than a bridge. From an ethical perspective, then, it
is perhaps more ecumenical to speak of our relation with the transcendent,
with that which is on a 'higher' (more encompassing) plane than what we
would normally refer to as human experience. In our times, speaking of a
'world beyond our normal experience' is returning to popular usage,
literally and especially implicitly. There is a good deal of attention paid
to our human destiny or being caught up in a project that is universal and
greater than any individual imagination (the cosmos, the rhythms of the
'natural' world, even socio-biology); there is literature and film about
spirits, ghosts, and out-of-body experiences; there is a proliferation of
science fiction images ranging from 'the Force (be with you!)' of Star Wars
to the transient beings who people the world of the Trekkies!
Rather than demeaning this language, we should recognize it as an
expression of contemporary persons to go 'beyond' their empirical,
scientific, rational experience into a realm of different meaning. Theistic
language, unfortunately, sometimes brings with it images that are counter-
productive, making it hard to communicate the good news of the gospel.
Legalistic, paternalistic, judgemental images of God have been somewhat
dominant in Western culture, forcing people to abandon the images
without having experienced the larger reality they so narrowly attempt to
represent.
To speak of the human person, adequately considered, being in relation
to all that is, may be affirmed in theistic language by referring to our
relationship with God. In Christian tradition, we can elaborate upon this
as our relationship with a loving, affirming, forgiving God whom we
worship in thanksgiving and whose message we celebrate with joy. The
privilege that our tradition grants us to do this helps us see why our
relation with God is of fundamental ethical significance.
100
The human person
101
Joseph Selling
102
The human person
consider how the world is becoming unified and how we have the duty
to build a better world based upon truth and justice. Thus we are
witnesses of the birth of a new humanism, one in which man is defined
first of all by his responsibility toward his brothers and toward history. 9
103
Joseph Selling
104
The human person
105
Joseph Selling
106
The human person
107
Joseph Selling
Notes
108
The human person
background who they are, you are just as likely to get the answer that they are
someone's relative, a member of a particular family or tribe. Self-identity, unlike
the Western emphasis on conscious interiority and individuality, is frequently
rendered with a reference to one's membership in a group. This experience, which
has been repeated many times, over more than twenty years, has had a significant
effect upon my understanding of the human person.
8 Space does not allow me to elaborate upon this idea at this point. However, I
believe it is worth at least mentioning an important distinction. Objective culture
refers to the goods of the human environment which are offered to and
appropriated by individuals who in turn transform this into subjective culture
which is personal and, again in turn, made available to the communitarian heritage
of objective culture. Also in this connection, we should draw attention to the
definition of the common good found in GS as 'the sum to those conditions of
social life which allow social groups and their individual members relatively
thorough and ready access to their own fulfilment'.
9 Walter M. Abbott (ed.). The Documents of Vatican II (New York: America Press,
1966), pp. 260-1.
10 Reference might be made here to the famous 'wolf children' raised by animals in
the wild. Although some children raised by animals have survived, their
development not only did not exhibit human characteristics, their ability to learn
what most persons take for granted (language and other communication skills)
was seriously impaired, even obliterated.
Select bibliography
109
7
Conscience
Richard M. Gula
'Let conscience be your guide' is a reliable moral maxim. But what does it
mean and what does it demand of us? Conscience is a difficult notion to
understand and even more difficult to explain how it operates. Yet, we all
know that we have a conscience, even if we can't explain how we got it or
how it works. We know that we stand for certain things, we struggle over
deciding what to do, and we feel pangs of conscience when we do
something wrong, even petty matters like taking cookies from the cookie
jar. Questions of conscience come up regularly and not just over the big
issues like taking a stand on war, on crime and punishment, or on
euthanasia. Questions of conscience also come up on very personal matters
like whether to blow the whistle on a co-worker who is doing a sloppy
job, or whether to reveal a brother's alcoholism to his fiancee, or whether
to take more time away from the family to play another round of golf. If
we are ever going to grow in our loving relationship with God and
neighbour, then we need to discern what is truly loving. Conscience is our
capacity for making such a discernment.
The task of this chapter is to clarify the meaning of the moral
conscience. I will first distinguish the moral conscience from what it is
not — its psychological cousin, the superego. Then I will sketch in greater
detail the meaning of conscience in the moral tradition with added
emphasis to the notion of the formation of conscience, to the relation of
conscience to character and to choice, to the goal of a mature conscience,
and to the requirements for acting in conscience.
110
Conscience
Conscience/superego mixup
111
Richard M. Gula
Achieving clarity about the moral conscience has been complicated by the
way the theological tradition has spoken of it.2 What we understand today
by conscience is rooted in the biblical notion of the 'heart'. The heart is
the seat of vital decisions, for it is the centre of feeling and reason, decision
and action, intention and consciousness.3 The hope of the messianic
prophecies is for the people to receive a new heart so that their inmost
inclinations will be to live out of the gift of divine love which they receive
in the covenant (Jer 31:31-34; Ezek 11:14-21).
In the New Testament, Jesus reflects the Hebrew understanding of the
unity of the person to be centred in the heart. From a person's heart come
the evil ideas which lead one to do immoral things (Mark 7:21), whereas
a good person produces good from the goodness in the heart (Luke 6:45).
Paul is the chief New Testament author to deal with conscience. He
weaves together Hebrew and Greek thought to speak of conscience as our
fundamental awareness of the difference between good and evil, as a guide
to loving decisions, and as a judge for acting in ways unbecoming of a
Christian (Rom 2:15; 1 Tim 1). From the biblical vision of the heart as
that dimension of us which is most sensitive and open to others, especially
to God's love, we can develop our theological understanding of conscience.
The medieval debates spoke of conscience as a function of the intellect
(practical reasoning) or of the will (choosing). The manualist era made it a
rationalistic operation that functioned in a deductive way. The Second
112
Conscience
In the depths of his conscience, man detects a law which he does not
impose upon himself, but which holds him to obedience. Always
summoning him to love good and avoid evil, the voice of conscience
can when necessary speak to his heart more specifically; do this, shun
that. For man has in his heart a law written by God. To obey it is the
very dignity of man; according to it he will be judged. Conscience is
the most secret core and sanctuary of a man. There he is alone with
God, whose voice echoes in his depths. (GS, n. 16)
More recently, Pope John Paul II, in his encyclical on moral theology,
Veritatis Splendor (VS), affirms conscience as the link between human
freedom and moral truth, when he says that the relationship between
freedom and God's law 'is most deeply lived out in the "heart" of the
person, in his moral conscience' (VS, n. 54).
We can distil the wisdom of the tradition on conscience for our
contemporary understanding of it by distinguishing three dimensions of
conscience: a capacity, a process and a judgement. As a capacity, conscience is
our fundamental ability to discern good and evil. Except for those who are
seriously brain-damaged or emotionally traumatized, everyone seems to
have this raw capacity as part of our human nature. Conscience has also
been used to name the process of discovering what makes for being a good
person and what particular action is morally right or wrong. This is the
dimension of conscience which is subject to being formed and informed
through experience and critical investigation of the sources of moral
wisdom. This inquiry yields the actual judgement that concludes 'This is
what I choose to do, because this is what moral truth demands'. This is
the practical judgement that takes place in one's heart where we are alone
with God. As Veritatis Splendor puts it, 'It is the judgment which applies
to a concrete situation the rational conviction that one must love and do
good and avoid evil' (VS, n. 59). This is the judgement that fulfils the
maxim: let conscience be your guide. The guidance which this judgement
113
Richard M. Gula
114
Conscience
is the place where God speaks to us. Thus, obeying conscience is giving
witness to God. To transgress the command of conscience would be to act
contrary to what we believe that God is calling us to do in this instance.
115
Richard M. Gula
that no other teacher can rightfully claim. They believe that the moral
guidance of the magisterium helps them to check the bias of their own
sinfulness and it expands their moral awareness of how they can keep the
gospel alive from age to age. Given these convictions about the magiste-
rium, Catholics are expected to include this privileged source of moral
guidance in making moral choices.
116
Conscience
conscience, we can miss or distort some of the facts of the case and so be
mistaken in our judgement about the right thing to do. Consider the
parent who confronts a child with tough love when everyone else can see
that support is most needed now. We call this acting with an erroneous
conscience. This means that, even when we sincerely search for the truth,
we can still miss what is truly good objectively.
The dignity and inviolability of conscience do not exempt us from
making mistakes. Acting with an erroneous conscience can lead one to
doing what is wrong, but it does not necessarily make one a bad person.
Pope John Paul IFs encyclical Veritatis Splendor follows a long-standing
tradition when it speaks of the erroneous conscience as possibly resulting
from invincible ignorance, that is, the person acting is unaware of being
wrong and is unable to overcome this ignorance on his or her own. A
person who does wrong as a result of invincible ignorance commits a non-
culpable error of judgement. This error does not make what is wrong
become right, but neither does the error compromise the dignity of
conscience (VS, n. 62).
The dignity of conscience assures that the one who makes a sincere
effort to inform conscience and then lives by it will not betray his or her
integrity. It does not guarantee that one will discern what is truly good.
No one can be blamed for doing something wrong if he or she sincerely
tried to find out what is right. We say that that person did the best he or
she knew how to do. It is those who do not even try to find out what is
right that we need to worry about. As the encyclical explains, conscience
compromises its dignity when it is 'culpably erroneous', that is, when we
show little concern for seeking what is true and good (VS, n. 63).
Otherwise, we must always follow the light of our conscience in good
faith and leave the rest to God. Christian theology teaches that God will
judge us, not on the basis of our actions being objectively right or wrong,
but on the basis of the sincerity of our hearts in seeking to do what is
right, even if we make a mistake.
117
Richard M. Gula
'Why were you not Moses?' Instead, I shall be asked, 'Why were you not
Zusya?""4
If a person spends his or her life doing what he or she is told to do by
someone in authority simply because the authority says so, or because that
is the kind of behaviour expected by the group, then that person never
really makes moral decisions which are his or her own. For moral maturity
one must be one's own person. It is not enough to follow what one has
been told. The morally mature person must be able to perceive, choose,
and identify oneself with what one does. In short, we create our character
and give our lives meaning by committing our freedom, not by submitting
it to someone in authority. We cannot claim to be virtuous, to have strong
moral character, or to give direction to our lives if we act simply on the
basis that we have been told to act that way. As long as we do not direct
our own activity, we are not yet free, morally mature persons.
This note on moral maturity leads us to ask, then, 'Who can make moral
decisions of conscience?' If conscience is the whole person's commitment
to value, then to act in conscience requires some degree of knowledge,
freedom, and the affective capacity to care for others and to commit oneself
to moral values.
Knowledgee
The kind of knowledge required to act in conscience obviously includes
the capacity to reason, that is, to reflect, to analyse, or to think in
somewhat of a critical fashion. But knowledge for acting in conscience
also requires an appreciation of moral values (we call this 'evaluative
knowledge'), especially the value of persons and what contributes to their
well-being. Without a heartfelt appreciation of values, but merely
conceptual knowledge about them, we act more out of hearsay than we do
out of conviction. To reach an appreciation of value requires experience
and reflection, not just right information.
Acting in conscience also requires the capacity to be self-reflective and
to have reached some degree of self-awareness that puts us in touch with
what is going on inside us. The key to acting in conscience is to be self-
conscious. Knowledge of the self includes knowing not only one's limits,
but also one's strengths, potentials and preferences. A basic goal of
Christian morality is to live according to the graces we have received.
When we live out of our blessings, and do not try to run ahead of our
graces, we make the moral life a continuous expression of praise and
118
Conscience
Freedom
To act in conscience one must also be able to direct one's actions according
to self-chosen goals. Actions that are not under our control cannot really
be considered within the realm of conscience. For example, we cannot be
held responsible for a tree falling on our house in a wind storm. Such an
act of nature is beyond our control. But we can be held responsible for
how we respond to the destruction it brings. In our pastoral tradition we
have recognized that what we ought to do implies that we can do it. It is
unreasonable to demand that someone do what is beyond his or her
capacity of knowledge, freedom, or emotional or moral strength.
Our basic freedom is the freedom to make someone of ourselves. As
Christians, we direct our basic freedom towards becoming one with God.
But since we experience God and express our relationship to God in
mediated ways, our basic freedom of self-determination gets expressed
through the particular choices that we make in life. (We also call this 'free
will'.) Our freedom to choose must be exercised across a broad spectrum
of possibilities, but within the limits of nature and nurture. What we do
is at least partially up to us and not solely the result of genetics, the
environment, unconscious influences, or luck. If we were strictly pro-
grammed by our genes, or blinded by social sin and other environmental
conditions, then there would be no possibility for morality. If we are
beyond freedom, we are beyond morality.
The biological, psychological and social sciences have certainly made us
aware of how limited our freedom is. In fact, they have made us so aware
that the modern-day 'out' for immoral behaviour is often the claim to
being victimized by some past experience. The great temptation is to say
that, whatever my failing, it is not my fault — 'Such and such happened to
me and made me to be this way and to do these things; therefore, I can't
be held responsible.' Such a notion of determinism has profoundly
diminished our sense of responsibility and wreaked havoc on morality.
The bottom line is that, whatever has happened to us, responsibility for
our action is still possible. If we were absolutely determined, then we
would never feel unsettled or indecisive about our choices. Neither would
we ever have to deliberate about anything if we were completely free or
completely determined. Real freedom is learning to live well within
limits. Those who are free do not expect to be dealt a winning hand, but
to play well the hand they have been handed. The more we become aware
of what limits us, the more we will be able to live freely within those
limits. Our freedom to choose challenges us all the time. Each of us has to
119
Richard M. Gula
Emotions
The degree to which knowing what is right results in doing what is right
can only be understood against the flow of emotions that support a good
will. In other words, knowledge will influence behaviour to the extent
that we care about the good and are committed to seeing it come about.
For example, someone may be a whiz-kid when it comes to moral theory,
but still be morally flawed because of the lack of affective awareness and a
heartfelt commitment to the values at stake. Someone else, however, may
do what is right spontaneously from the heart because of his or her
sympathy for the values at stake, but he or she may never be able to give
any theoretical justification for acting that way. Why? Because our feelings
display our moral sensitivity. They drive us to act according to our
convictions.
Without the capacity for an affective experience of the value of persons
and what befits their well-being, we will not have the capacity for acting
in good conscience. The capacity to be loving is the beginning of moral
awareness. Research on the role of empathy shows how important this
human feeling is in the development of conscience.5 Empathy is experienc-
ing what another is experiencing. When empathy is born, care is born,
and with it, morality.
The capacity to experience an emotion like empathy is set in our genetic
endowment, but it requires the proper environment, especially in our
early years, if it is ever to emerge in full power as part of the conscience of
an adult. What is missing in a psychopath, for instance, is not the
knowledge of right or wrong, but caring commitment to do the right
thing. The psychopath has no empathy. To pour ourselves into what we
do requires an emotional capacity to care about others and to commit
ourselves to ideals and standards. Thus the emotionally traumatized, the
severely brain-damaged, the gravely mentally ill, and those suffering from
severe pathological conditions, like the sociopath or psychopath, cannot
120
Conscience
Conclusion
Notes
1 For a succinct treatment of the Freudian model of the person, see the still valuable
article by Gregory Zilboorg, 'Superego and conscience' in C. Ellis Nelson (ed.),
Conscience: Theological and Psychological Perspectives (New York: Newman Press, 1973),
pp. 210-23.
2 For a still valuable review of the ways the tradition has talked about conscience, see
Bernard Ha'ring, The Law of Christ, vol. 1: General Moral Theology, trans. Edwin G.
Kaiser (Paramus: Newman Press, 1966), pp. 135-89. Also Bernard Ha'ring, Free
121
Richard M. Gula
and Faithful in Christ, vol. 1: General Moral Theology (New York: Seabury Press,
1978), pp. 224-301.
3 Hans Walter Wolff, Anthropology of the Old Testament (Philadelphia: Fortress Press,
1974), pp. 40-55.
4 Martin Buber, The Way of Man According to the Teaching of Hasidism (New York:
Citadel Press, 1966), p. 17.
5 For a review of this research, see Sidney Callahan, In Good Conscience (New York:
HarperCollins, 1991), pp. 186-90. See also Charles M. Shelton, Morality of the
Heart (New York: Crossroad, 1990), pp. 33-59.
Select bibliography
122
8
The theory of the fundamental
option and moral action
Thomas R. Kopfensteiner
Introduction
123
Thomas R. Kopfensteiner
124
The theory of the fundamental option
of the final option. The theory of the final option holds that at death we
definitely decide for or against salvation. The theory does not mean that a
life of virtue is useless; nor is it meant to imply that we cannot reject
God's grace during our lifetime. Rather, the theory of the final option
underlines the fact that at death the nature of a decision is most vividly
manifested, and that salvation and loss do not lie on the periphery of our
lives; our daily living serves as the prehistory to our eternal destiny.
'Death issues from the whole experience of life, of which it bears the
stamp, but by affirming or revoking the past, gives life its definitive
character.'3
Though the theory of the fundamental option stands in the effective
history of personalism and transcendental philosophy, important insights
into the theory can be gained by recent developments in the hermeneutical
sciences. The appreciation of the role of prejudices in knowledge, for
instance, has undermined the traditional romantic conception of herme-
neutics that was determined by a thoroughly modern view of knowledge.
Guided by this epistemological interest, traditional hermeneutics sought
the 'determinant' meaning of a text which, it was thought, was able to be
known independently of the concerns of the interpreter or reader. This
endeavour was undermined in a radical way by the rehabilitation of the
role of prejudices in knowledge. Taking the role of prejudices seriously
means that there is no neutral or pure access to the world as in an
empirical or naive realist account of knowledge. All our knowledge of the
world is conditioned, in part, by our pre-understandings or pre-judge-
ments. Far from distorting our knowledge of reality, our pre-judgements
constitute our initial bias or openness to the world. In light of the work
of the German philosopher Hans-Georg Gadamer, it has become a
hermeneutical axiom to assert that our prejudices, far more than our
judgements, constitute our historical existence.4 In a similar way, individ-
ual decisions are only adequately understood when they are seen as
stemming from a more primordial context which directs our stance toward
life as a whole. This originating context directs freedom's striving toward
the good.
From a hermeneutical perspective we can say, then, that our inclination
toward the good is inseparable from our pre-understandings about what
constitutes the morally good life. This means that the fundamental option
is inseparable from conceptions of human flourishing, or what Gibson
Winter has labelled an 'ideology of human fulfilment'. 5 The ideology of
human fulfilment provides a normative orientation toward the realities of
the world. This normative orientation stakes out the boundaries in which
moral reasoning and freedom can function in a legitimate way. From a
hermeneutical perspective, this means that moral reasoning and freedom
are not self-sufficient realities, but they have a relational character. Our
125
Thomas R. Kopfensteiner
normative orientation toward the realities of the world also becomes the
filter through which a moral norm is read or interpreted.6 The application
of a moral norm cannot be known apart from the normative horizon that
it is meant to protect and promote; to forget this function of a moral
norm is to easily run the risk of falling into a crude voluntarism or
legalism. A moral norm, then, is like any literary text; it has a hypothetical
character; its meaning is ambivalent; its meaning emerges from a process
of interpretation or reading. In this interpretative process, the weighing
of premoral but morally relevant goods cannot be modelled on merely
technical calculation, but should be seen as the final step in a strategy of
action guaranteeing that our actions witness to our conception of the
morally good life. In this way, in all our individual decisions about
particular goods, the ideology of human fulfilment is tacitly present as the
object of our striving.
126
The theory of the fundamental option
one moment to the next. History, on the other hand, results from those
successive moments being assumed into and transformed by our life
projects. Moral actions, in other words, do not stand juxtaposed to each
other in an unrelated fashion, but they weave the story of our moral lives.
History has an autobiographical character.8
In this personalist context, the fundamental option represents the
dynamic core of our moral identities. It represents our orientation towards
the moral good as such and, though prior to any one choice, it gives
direction to our deliberations and knits our choices into our unique and
personal histories. Though no one decision will exhaust the fundamental
option, individual decisions can be seen as interpretative extensions of it.
The passage between the fundamental option and individual decisions is
not done in any mechanical or automatic way. The element of decision
cannot be subsumed under any naive scientific explanation; such a way of
thinking would belie the risks that are inherent to the moral enterprise.
The moment of decision involves what Karl Rahner has called 'the logic
of existential knowledge' which escapes the surety of deductive calculus.9
Through our decisions and actions there is a slow maturation of the
fundamental option as we realize ever more fully the meaning of our life
projects. As we make individual decisions the contours of our moral
identities take shape. All the diverse and various experiences of life become
interpreted in light of the possibilities of legitimate freedom to the point
that there emerges a profound consistency and transparency between our
identity and our actions, between who we are and what we do. We act
authentically. We develop a morally mature personality where there is
found a readiness and facility to act in a virtuous way.10
By rooting a theory of moral action in a personalist metaphysics, an
ineluctable bond is formed between the fundamental option and individual
decisions. Their inseparability creates an analogous relationship between
them. A family resemblance is created between the fundamental option
and an individual decision and, so too, among the various decisions. To
fully understand individual decisions and actions, they must be seen as
embedded in and constitutive of one's fundamental option, and they must
be seen as contributing to the greater whole of our moral personalities.
Naturally, some individual decisions will participate in the fundamental
option to a greater or lesser degree. This is no surprise when we recall that
certain decisions will involve us as subjects more than others, as and when
our life projects become the appropriate object of a moral decision. There
is, for instance, a more profound personal investment in a vocational
decision than in the peripheral choices of daily living. In this regard, there
is a convergence between metaphysical and psychological categories.
As reflective of our moral identities, there is a certain stability to the
fundamental option. For the Christian this means that there is a genuine
127
Thomas R. Kopfensteiner
and enduring orientation toward the good under the influence of grace (1
John 3:9). Nevertheless, the fundamental option can become corrupted.
Theologically speaking this occurs through mortal sin. In terms of a
psychology of sin, this kind of moral tragedy occurs over time. Our
orientation toward the good can become dulled through repeated offences
and omissions and, as we find ourselves continually failing to strive for the
moral good, our actions continually fall behind our moral potential. We
embark on a perilous journey through which the inner structure of the
fundamental option begins to decay and rot. As we become untethered
from the mainstay of our moral identities, we flounder. Because the
fundamental option and individual decisions are so intimately linked, it
becomes progressively more difficult and increasingly less probable that
we will regain our moral equilibrium. We are beset by a progressive moral
decline to the point that our orientation to fulfilment in God — still, the
end of all our knowing and acting — becomes meaningless to our self-
identities. We truly experience the death of our souls. While it is true to
say that our separation from God occurs through mortal sin understood in
terms of the traditional categories of grave matter and full knowledge and
freedom, such an act would never have its disastrous consequences had it
not already been prepared for and preceded by a prehistory of moral
decline. By uniting the sinful act with the process which leads up to it,
Klaus Demmer likens sin unto death to a whirlpool from which we will
need all our strength to escape.11 The sinful act becomes nothing other
than the confirming evidence of our moral deterioration.12
There are two positions presented on the issue of when the fundamental
option can become an object of reflection in life. The first position is
rooted in the Church's practice of baptizing infants and holds that the
fundamental option of the Christian coincides with a person's first truly
responsible decision. The second position is more speculative. It holds that
the fundamental option coincides with the infusion of the theological
virtues by sanctifying grace; they direct the moral life of the justified
person towards a life with God.
This leads to the important question as to the role of faith in moral
decision-making. What is the proper role of the content of faith in moral
reasoning? What is the relationship between the truths of faith and moral
truth? These questions are at the centre of the debate between the
proponents of an autonomous morality and an ethics of faith.13 On the one
hand, reason cannot be regarded as completely autonomous to the extent
that faith is extrinsic to the reasoning process. On the other hand, it
128
The theory of the fundamental option
129
Thomas R. Kopfensteiner
130
The theory of the fundamental option
moral object. 19 The point of departure for the determination of the moral
object was the finis opens, or the end of the act. This of course made sense
when the determination of the moral object was made within the
epistemological tradition of realism. Nevertheless, this realist tradition
was restricted by a modern notion of science and the casuistic categories
of jurisprudence. In such a state of affairs, the finis operands, or the end of
the agent, was relegated to the psychology of action. The intention of the
agent was a circumstance - albeit a principal one — and could only modify
the act in an accidental way.20
This traditional analysis of moral action had at least two important
effects, both of which are undermined by the theory of the fundamental
option. First, moral objectivity was attributed to the phenomenal structure
of the act which, in turn, circumscribed the possible interpretations of the
action. Second, while this circumspection fostered a high level of commun-
icability, the price it exacted was the impression that moral action no
longer presupposed a human subject. There was a clear line demarcating
the objective and subjective spheres of reality.
The theory of the fundamental option, however, leads to a more
nuanced determination of the moral object and revision of the relationship
between the finis operis and the finis operantis. From a moral perspective,
the phenomenal structure of the act is underdetermined and assumes its
meaning in light of the fundamental option. This means that the moral
object can no longer be limited to the phenomenal aspect of the act as in
the stark and essentialist categories of the neo-scholastic tradition, but
must be seen under the sway of the life project which predetermines
freedom and insight. The fusion between the fundamental option and the
phenomenal structure of the act is never done in an arbitrary way; the
fusion between intention and execution is always done in a way commen-
surate or proportionate to the underlying normative horizon which
conditions freedom and insight. 21 The moral object, then, is the result of
the phenomenal structure of the act being interpreted or read in light of
the ideology of human fulfilment.
The theory of the fundamental option also provides the basis from
which to reconfigure the relationship between intention and execution.
The finis operantis is no longer relegated to the psychology of action; the
agent's intention is no longer merely a circumstance answering the
question why one is acting. In light of the fundamental option, the finis
operantis plays an active and constitutive role in the determination of the
moral object. 22 What is done is always seen in light of why it is done.
From this perspective, finis operantis becomes the true finis operis of an
action.
131
Thomas R. Kopfensteiner
Conclusion
Notes
1 Piet Fransen, 'Pour une psychologic de la grace divine', Lumen vitae 12 (1957),
pp. 209-40.
2 Josef Fuchs, 'Good acts and good persons', The Tablet (6 November 1993), pp.
1444_45.
3 Jorg Splett, 'Decision' in Sacramentum Mundi, vol. 2 (London: Burns and Gates,
1969), p. 63. A more critical view of the theory of the final option is given by
Bruno Schiiller, 'Mortal sin - sin unto death?', Theology Digest 16 (1968),
pp. 232-5.
4 Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, trans. Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G.
Marshall (New York: Crossroads, 1992), pp. 216-1.
5 Gibson Winter, Liberating Creation: Foundations of Religious Social Ethics (New
York: Crossroad, 1981), p. 126.
6 Richard Gula, What Are They Saying About Moral Norms? (New York: Paulist
Press, 1982).
7 Klaus Demmer, 'Opzione fondamentale' in Nuovo dizionario enciclopedico di teologia
morale (Rome: Paoline, 1991), pp. 854-61.
8 This is the insight of recent retrievals of virtue. See for instance, James F. Keenan,
132
The theory of the fundamental option
'Virtue ethics: making a case as it comes of age', Thought 67 (1992), pp. 115-27;
Paul Wadell, Friendship and the Moral Life (South Bend, IN: Notre Dame Press,
1989).
9 Karl Rahner, 'On the question of a formal existential ethics' in Theological
Investigations, vol. 2 (London: Darton, Longman & Todd, 1975), pp. 217-34.
10 There is a connaturality between ourselves and the good: Thomas Aquinas, Summa
Theologiae: II-II, q. 45, ad 2.
11 Klaus Demmer, 'Optionalismus - Entscheidung und Grundentscheidung' in
Dietmar Mieth (ed.), Moraltheologie im AbseitsP Antwort auf die Enziklika 'Veritatis
Splendor' (Quaestiones Disputatae 153; Freiburg: Herder, 1994), pp. 83-4.
12 The same process can be detailed in terms of the conversion of our hearts and
minds. The early Church's penitential practice is based on the insight that we do
not easily pass back and forth between the state of grace and state of damnation.
13 Vincent MacNamara, Faith and Ethics: Recent Roman Catholicism (Washington, DC:
Georgetown University Press, 1985); James Walter, 'The dependence of Christian
morality on faith', Eglise et Theologie 12 (1981), pp. 237-77; Josef Fuchs, 'Moral
truths — truths of salvation?' in Christian Ethics in a Secular Arena (Washington,
DC: Georgetown University Press, 1984), pp. 48-67; idem, 'Our image of God
and the morality of innerworldly behaviour' in Christian Morality: The Word
Becomes Flesh (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 1987), pp. 28-49.
14 Hans Kiing, Global Responsibility: In Search of a New World Ethic (New York:
Crossroad, 1991), pp. 66-9.
15 Jean Ladriere, 'On the notion of criterion', Concilium 155 (1982), pp. 10—15.
16 John Paul II, Encyclical Letter The Splendour of Truth (Washington, DC: The
United States Catholic Conference/London: Catholic Truth Society (1993), para.
65.
17 Josef Fuchs, 'Morality: person and acts' in Christian Morality: The Word Becomes
Flesh, pp. 105-17; James F. Keenan, 'Distinguishing charity as goodness and
prudence as Tightness', The Thomist 56 (1992), pp. 389—411.
18 This is the criticism ol Veritatis Splendor made by Demmer, 'Optionalismus -
Entscheidung und Grundentscheidung', especially pp. 73—8.
19 The historical analysis is provided by Gerhard Stanke, Die Lehre von den 'Quellen
der Moralitat': Darstellung und Disktission der neuscholastischen Aussagen und neurer
Ansatze (Studien zur Geschichte der katholischen Moraltheologie 26; Regensburg:
Friedrich Pustet, 1984).
20 This is evident in one of the strongest critics of the fundamental option, William
E. May, Moral Absolutes: Catholic Tradition, Current Trends and the Truth (Milwau-
kee: Marquette University, 1989).
21 In this way, the theory of proportionalism can be seen as responsible for binding
all the elements of moral action into a coherent whole. See the fine study of
Bernard Hoose, Proportionalism: The American Debate and Its European Roots
(Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 1987).
22 See for instance, Klaus Demmer, Die Wahrheit leben. Theorie des Handelns (Freiburg:
Herder, 1991).
Select bibliography
Josef Fuchs, 'Basic freedom and morality' in Human Values and Christian Morality
(Dublin: Gill and Macmillan, 1970), pp. 92-111.
133
Thomas R. Kopfensteiner
Germain Grisez, The Way of the Lord Jesus, vol. 1: Christian Moral Principles (Chicago:
Franciscan Herald Press, 1983).
Bernard Raring, Sin in the Secular Age (New York: Doubleday, 1974).
John Paul II, The Encyclical Letter, The Splendour of Truth (Washington: The United
States Catholic Conference/London: Catholic Truth Society, 1993).
134
9
Feminist ethics
Susan F. Parsons
General comments
135
Susan F. Parsons
136
Feminist ethics
137
Susan F. Parsons
138
Feminist ethics
feminism, and still inspires work of liberation around the world. Many
women find that the language of liberal ethics does not quite reach to the
depths of their concerns. The growth of the social sciences and of cultural
studies has given to women new ways of understanding their situation.
The increasingly international and intercultural nature of feminism has
brought new insights and experiences onto the feminist ethical agenda.
Therefore, feminists are today concerned to investigate the structures of
domination that disempower women. In some cases, these are economic
structures that rely upon the availability of women, desperate to work for
any pay under any conditions and at any cost to their dignity. There is
evidence of increasing impoverishment of women throughout the world,
and this is disempowering. In some cases, these are political structures
that do not allow women participation in the ordering of public life. That
women continue to find it difficult to present for public debate the needs
and concerns of their lives in a serious way in their own countries is
disempowering. In some cases, these are linguistic structures configured
around the absence of woman as the hidden Other. Women find in every
area of discourse that the language they need to use to speak of themselves
and of their wisdom is not available to them, and this is disempowering.
Feminists use these realizations to encourage women to recover their
power. The means that may be required to regain lost power, or to exert
new forms of power, constitute a major part of ethical discussion amongst
feminists, who work for the liberation of women into the fullness of their
potential as human persons."*
139
Susan F. Parsons
tions, women are consenting to the loss of their full humanity. They
thereby remove themselves from the development of their own moral
potential. Feminists are committed to the affirmation of women as
distinctive moral agents.
In addition, this emphasis promises that the contributions of women's
gifts and insights may be of great significance for the reshaping of our
social and personal lives, as well as for the reformulation of ethics.
Feminists have resisted the man-centredness of traditional approaches to
ethics. They have argued that the moral emphasis upon the freedom of the
individual self may reveal an anxiety about relationships which is
characteristic of men. They suggest that women's knowledge of the
primacy of relationships in the formation of human personhood offers a
significant new approach to our understanding of humanness. Likewise,
feminists have argued that notions of rationality have typically set the
mind against, or over, the body, and in this dualism have revealed man's
mistrust of the body's knowledge. Again, it is significant that women
derive moral insight from their experiences of embodiment. Far from
being some passive material upon which a mind acts, the body itself may
also be a source of moral wisdom. Similarly, feminists have argued that
the major thrust of ethical thinking has been towards control — of personal
behaviour, of social life, of the natural world. These aims suggest a male
pride in accomplishment and in domination. Women suggest that
vulnerability, and compassion, and a rather untidy pragmatism may offer
a different, and possibly a better, picture of the moral life.
Such emphasis upon women's distinctiveness constitutes a major point
of discussion amongst feminists today. Some will argue that their
distinctive gifts are the result of women's particular embodiment, of their
physical capacities for bearing and for nursing children. This makes
women, naturally, more empathetic towards the needs of others, more
capable of caring, more sensitive to the impact of their choices upon the
welfare of others. Some find that this interpretation reinforces a simplistic
biological literalism, which binds women to their bodily functions and
keeps them socially confined to mothering or caring roles. They argue,
instead, that women's distinctive insights are the result of the activities in
which they engage, and of the positions which they occupy in social
structures. Thus, women have experiences of work, of suffering, of living
with others, of exclusion, or of creativity, all of which provide special
insights for them. By reflecting upon and learning from these experiences,
women develop the values by which they shape their own lives and their
relationships with others. To pay attention to the standpoint of women,
therefore, is to enrich our understanding of morality. Emphasis upon the
distinctiveness of women is a third major strand in feminist ethics.4
140
Feminist ethics
141
Susan F. Parsons
142
Feminist ethics
143
Susan F. Parsons
144
Feminist ethics
145
Susan F. Parsons
an adequate context for the moral life. Once again, it may be that a
fruitful way forward is to discover the ways in which they are now
inextricably linked. Thus we need to recognize that deriving moral
precepts from nature 'always takes place within a historical setting in
which the perspectives of some will be privileged over those of others and
in which the perceived need to address social and moral problems can
result in distortions of ostensibly universal values'. At the same time, we
need to be able to build 'an understanding of basic and shared human
characteristics through reflection upon human life itself.7 The more
adequate rendering of the context of the moral life is a further area for
creative theological exploration.
Conclusion
These are difficult matters on the agenda of feminist ethics as it faces the
future. A number of alternative routes lie before those involved in the
subject. To understand what these are is clearly the first important task
for feminists today. Disagreement about which one ought to be taken now
adds further to the complexity and diversity of feminism. In making these
choices, feminists are engaged in analysing their own inheritance of ideas,
in assessing their commitments to the projects that have shaped feminism
in the past, and in discerning the implications of each choice for the lives
and the well-being of women. New wisdom is needed from feminists in
this task.
Some feminists believe that a useful framework for consideration of
these issues is to be found in the theological and the philosophical
tradition of natural law ethics. Within its terms, there is potential for
developing an inclusive understanding of our shared humanness as women
and men. There is a description of the process of moral reasoning which
may overcome some of the dichotomies of relationality and autonomy, of
reason and emotion, of theory and practice, which have set women against
men in unhelpful ways. The positive way in which natural law ethics
envisions our working together for the common good of humanity, in the
midst of the realities of its sufferings and its joys, may provide the needed
mix of nature and of history together, as the context for the moral life.
The hope which it sets before us of discovering, through dialogue and
engagement with one another, not only a deeper human communion, but
also the presence of the divine intermingled with the human, is a profound
expression of the ultimate meaning of the moral life.8 Feminist ethics is
straining forward towards this flourishing of all creation in the fullness of
the divine presence.
146
Feminist ethics
Notes
Select bibliography
Barbara Hilkert Andolsen, Christine E. Gudorf and Mary D. Pellauer (eds), Women's
Consciousness. Women's Conscience: A Reader in Feminist Ethics (New York: Seabury,
1985).
Lisa Sowle Cahill, Sex, Gender and Christian Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1996).
Denise L. Carmody, Christian Feminist Theology (Oxford: Blackwell, 1995).
Elizabeth Frazer, Jennifer Hornsby and Sabina Lovibond (eds), Ethics: A Feminist Reader
(Oxford: Blackwell, 1992).
147
Susan F. Parsons
Catherine Mowry LaCugna (ed.), Freeing Theology: The Essentials of Theology in Feminist
Perspective (New York: HarperCollins, 1993).
Susan F. Parsons, Feminism and Christian Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1996).
148
10
The distinctiveness of
Christian morality
Vincent MacNamara
149
Vincent MacNamara
150
The distinctiveness of Christian morality
151
Vincent MacNamara
you are a child of God, you belong to the kingdom. Because 'your sins are
forgiven' (so Jeremias puts it) there now follows 'While you are still in the
way with your opponent, be reconciled to him quickly'. Because 'your sins
are forgiven' there now follows 'Love your enemies and pray for those who
persecute you'. And so on.2
Whatever else the revelation might or might not say about morality —
and there can be argument about morality's source, content and binding
force - there is no doubt that it sees moral commitment as the logic of
faith. The Christian religion, C. H. Dodd wrote, 'is an ethical religion in
the specific sense that it recognises no ultimate separation between the
service of God and social behaviour'.3 So closely are the two, faith and
morals, linked in the New Testament that it is difficult at times to know
whether the tradition is speaking of love of God or love of others. What
is not in doubt is that one involves the other. Not to recognize the Word
or not to love others, John's writings tell us, is to be in the dark. To
respond to the other is to respond to the offer of God's personal love to us.
There is an organic relationship between them.
So moral life is transfigured by Christian faith. It is theologal. Christian
morality has been called a covenant morality, a eucharistic morality, a
service of God, an obedience, a sharing in the mission of Christ. The
Anglican—Roman Catholic Agreed Statement characterizes it as 'the fruit
of faith in God's Word, the grace of the sacraments, and the appropriation,
in a life of forgiveness, of the gifts of the Spirit for work in God's service'.4
Faith declares the source of moral goodness — the love of God is poured
into our hearts; the Spirit is given to us. It interprets its movement
towards the final reign of God. It shows its ultimate significance: 'as long
as you did it to one of these you did it to me'. Faith offers moral life a
hope. That hope is the promise that, as goodness has a transcendent origin,
in the end, goodness, however foolish it may sometimes appear, however
defeated, will not finally be defeated. And this is because God is the
deepest mystery, the heart and soul, of every truly human liberation.
All this says something about the distinctiveness of Christian morality.
One might call it the distinctive context: the contrast is with the notion
of content. The word 'context' is a useful one. It situates morality within
the community's web of beliefs. It says something of the consciousness of
Christians as they live their moral life and reflect on it ethically. But it
leaves untouched other matters that must concern us. Two matters in
particular require attention: the source of the moral claim, and the content
of the moral call. However significantly religious considerations shape
Christian moral consciousness, it remains that the source of the moral
claim is something that is distinguishable from such considerations.
Morality has a certain autonomy. By that I mean that religious faith is not
necessary in order to experience and recognize the moral point of view:
152
The distinctiveness of Christian morality
153
Vincent MacNamara
general distribution as the need of each required. With one mind they
kept up their daily attendance at the temple, and, breaking bread in
private houses, shared their meals with unaffected joy, as they praised God
and enjoyed the favour of the whole people' (Acts 2:44ff). There is a
dynamic relationship between the liturgical recital of the good news and
moral expectations. So every liturgical celebration is a challenge to realize
the enterprise of Christ's life and mission.
James Gustafson put the question thus: 'What relationships are claimed
or assumed between religious beliefs and life grounded in Jesus Christ, on
the one hand, and the morality of the people who hold these beliefs and
share that life, on the other?'6 One could hardly hope to delineate all such
relationships: Christian engagement in the world is richly varied. Nega-
tively, one can say that there are certain kinds of acts, intentions,
dispositions and purposes that run entirely contrary to Christian sensibil-
ity. Positively, one has to say that the only total model of life is Christ
Jesus as inaugurator of the reign of God. That does not mean simply
imitating him. It means seeking to take on his core moral sensibility,
which will express itself in our struggle to realize his humanizing purposes
for society.
About this, there is a tradition. We are not the first who have sought
to discover the way: our ancestors in the faith have asked the same
question as we ask today. The Bible is the classic of that tradition. What
it gives us are impressions of the original community's experience of the
inbreak of the kingdom in Jesus and how that issued in a way of life - the
logic of faith. Moral discernment calls for dialogue between faith today
and the complex faith of the apostolic community. That is not a simple
task. The ethical material of the Bible is diverse. Its mode is indicative,
imperative, parabolic, mystical. It is more story than history, more wisdom
than law. It says what it has to say in a bewildering profusion of forms
and genres. A genuine conversation with it requires discrimination. What
one seeks is to enter into the interplay of ethos and ethic in the apostolic
community and allow it to shape consciousness. Not to engage it is not to
know our lineage, not to know the story of who we are and how we are to
be.
It would be naive to suggest that all Christians agree on the reading of
the story or on its implications. If Jesus is the key to Christian moral
consciousness much will depend on one's dominant image of Jesus. There
will be nuance of emphasis. But there is sufficient agreement, I think, to
rule certain things in and certain things out. That is what the apostolic
community did in its different forms of moral discourse. In continuity
with it, Christian morality today has to insist, for example, that each
human being is to be respected and loved, that life is sacred, that we are
to be faithful to one another and to our promises, that life is a gift and is
154
The distinctiveness of Christian morality
to be handed on, that we are to speak the truth in love, that we are to
forgive, that the poor and weak are to be protected, that unjust structures
are to be overcome, that we are to be respectful stewards of creation. Belief
in the story of God's ways with us requires such a vision of society.
Most, perhaps all, of that will be assented to by people of good will
generally — religious or not. But the distinctiveness of Christian moral life
goes beyond this. The ethico-religious vision of the early community came
to express itself — most notably in the Sermon on the Mount — as an ethic
that has suggestions about true flourishing and success, about losing and
finding one's life, about poverty of life and spirit, about making decisions
in trust in God, about seeking the interests of others and not one's own,
about giving to everyone who asks, about forgiving, about washing one
another's feet, about bearing the cross, about being prepared to lay down
one's life for others. About love, joy, peace, patience, kindness, goodness,
fidelity, gentleness and self-control (Gal 5:22). These are ideals and, again,
some of them will be shared by other traditions. That is not the point at
the moment. The point is that such ideals cohere with the faith-story and
provide a continuo to the moral journey. In Christ they have been given a
vital expression, so that he remains a living norm and challenge for all
time.
What then of specificity? If it is true that one's world-view modifies
how one reads the content of the moral claim, is it the case that the
Christian world-view leads to ethical conclusions that do not seem justified
or compelling to those who do not share that world-view? What is most
crucial for Christians, of course, is distinctiveness, that they discern and
live life in fidelity to their common, community-building story. But the
question of specificity is important for a number of reasons and has been
widely debated among theologians of the different Christian traditions. It
is important, first, for Christians to understand the methodology of moral
discernment. And it is important for them and for others to know what
kind of agreement is possible in public affairs. In fact the issue is often
raised now in the context of ethical pluralism in society.
Here are two quotations which point up the matter. The Catholic
theologian Josef Fuchs in a seminal article asked of his Church: 'Was it
Paul VFs intention to offer a specifically Catholic or Christian solution to
the problem of birth control in his encyclical Humanae Vztae? A significant
number of oral and written positions on this question . . . seem to answer
in the affirmative. Such a view implies that there is a Catholic or Christian
morality which is valid only for Catholics or other Christians and which
differs from another, a non-Christian, morality.' 7 The philosopher William
Frankena raised a concern from the point of view of public morality: 'If
morality (and hence politics) is dependent on religion, then we must look
to religion as a basis for any answer to any personal or social problem of
155
Vincent MacNamara
156
The distinctiveness of Christian morality
157
Vincent MacNamara
158
The distinctiveness of Christian morality
Schillebeeckx has the remark that the specific character of the ethic of
Christians is 'that they do not have a distinctive {sic] ethic, and thus are
open to the humanum which is sought by all men and women'. 12 If that is
saying that, at the level of material norms, there is nothing that is not per
se available to the insight of the morally sensitive non-Christian, I think I
agree. But it is well to acknowledge that every person of good will — and
every community — faces a formidable set of obstacles from within and
from without in seeking the truth. There is great difficulty not only in
doing the truth but in seeing it — the Protestant tradition has always
rightly suspected any liberal optimism about that. Objectivity is not
natural to humans: there is need for conversion. So we need constantly to
be confronted by our Christian stories and convictions to clarify for us
what we are up against in ourselves and in the world, in seeking to discern
the way. However much one might want to pay rightful tribute to the
sincerity and insight of the non-believer, we ought not to underestimate
the significance of the faith-community. Its distinctive ethos, its shaping
stories about God, humans and the cosmos, facilitate a moral sensitivity
in the pursuit of norms, even if these are per se available outside the
community.
But the issue of norms is not the whole story and perhaps not the most
important part of it. Morality cannot be adequately caught in material,
especially negative, norms. A community's vision enters into morality and
influences choice. For morality is not only public but personal. It is not
only about what one must do but what one can do. Individual choices for
a way of life — what one might roughly call vocational choices — such as
commitment to justice and peace-making, service of the marginalized,
care of the sick and handicapped, living a Christian vision of marriage,
poverty, detachment, celibacy are part of it. The judgement of faith that
one is called and enabled to give one's life for another is part of it. One
cannot easily separate content here from what some authors call motive:
does the religious motive in the choices just mentioned not enter into the
description of the act? Does it not determine just what act or purpose is
being chosen? And morality is not just a matter of doing: agape, for
example, is a virtue of attachment as well as of action and the disposition
of the heart is part of the virtue. The more attention is given to such
considerations the more arguable is the claim that there is a specific
Christian content to morality. But how much one will want to make of
that is another matter.
159
Vincent MacNamara
Notes
Select bibliography
C. Curran and R. McCormick (eds), Readings in Moral Theology, no. 2: The Distinctiveness
of Christian Ethics (New York: Paulist Press, 1980).
J. Fuchs, Christian Morality: The Word Becomes Flesh (Dublin: Gill and Macmillan,
1987).
J. M. Gustafson, Can Ethics Be Christian? (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1975).
S. Hauerwas, A Community of Character (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame
Press, 1981).
V. MacNamara, Faith and Ethics: Recent Roman Catholicism (Dublin: Gill and
Macmillan, 1995).
W. C. Spohn, What Are They Saying About Scripture and Ethics? (New York: Paulist
Press, 1995).
160
PART II
Applied ethics
This page intentionally left blank
Social ethics
11
Justice
Karen Lebacqz
Although the injunction to 'do justice' (Mic 6:8) has been a constant in
Christian tradition, understandings of what the injunction means and how
to do justice are probably as numerous as the Christians who respond to
that injunction. Some differences are notable. Roman Catholic traditions
have generally grounded the requirements of justice in natural law,
presumably accessible not only to Christians, but to all humans by virtue
of their 'nature' as reasonable creatures. Protestant traditions have focused
less on that which is common to all people and more on 'grace', locating
justice in the 'good news' of God's saving acts and in the story of a
community trying to live faithfully to that Gospel. These differences are
not unimportant. Nonetheless, some common themes and threads can be
found, from which a tapestry of justice with a distinctively Christian
texture might be woven.
Western philosophy
163
Karen Lebacqz
Liberal views
In Western philosophical traditions, the formal statement of justice is
'treat similar cases similarly' or 'give to each what is due'.1 'Treat similar
cases similarly' implies the equality of each moral agent and prevents
arbitrary discrimination. It is an empty formula, however, in that it does
not specify which cases are to be considered similar or how those cases
should be treated. Similarly, 'give to each what is due' does not specify
whether the criterion for distribution should be need (Marx), contribution
or role in society (Aristotle), the overall good (Mill), or some other
criterion or combination of criteria. The history of Western philosophy is
a history of debates about precisely these substantive issues.
Approaches to what is generally called distributive justice will thus
differ widely. Robert Nozick argues that what is 'due' to individuals
depends on the voluntary exchanges that they make and the gifts they
receive.2 Arguing explicitly against any broader notion of distributive
justice in which the state or a similar entity would redistribute goods
among individuals, Nozick proposes to substitute commutative justice
(justice in exchange) as the sole source of 'entitlements' to goods. In this
approach, there is no built-in protection for the poor or disadvantaged;
gifts given and bargains made by people determine what one rightly holds
as entitlements.
By contrast, John Rawls begins with the recognition that social
institutions position people to be in very different starting positions; these
positions impact the fairness of exchanges.1 Rational individuals choosing
under fair circumstances, he argues, would establish some shared rights
and then would require that differences in income, wealth, or status must
ultimately benefit the least advantaged. For Rawls, inequalities in wealth,
income, status, and the like are justifiable only if (a) they attach to
positions that are open to all (equal opportunity) and (b) they benefit the
least advantaged in the long run, consistent with just savings for the next
generation.
These two theories appear to give us very different understandings of
justice. In Nozick's scheme, justice derives from the voluntariness of
individual exchanges and offers no explicit protections for the poor or
disadvantaged. In Rawls' scheme, justice requires structuring the basic
institutions of society so that they benefit the disadvantaged over the long
run. Since the position of the least advantaged would appear to differ
remarkably in these two approaches, it is perhaps difficult to see how
much the approaches nonetheless share.
As different as they appear at first glance, these theories share some
liberal presuppositions. They both claim a Kantian base of respect for the
individual and individual rights. They focus on the distribution of goods,
164
Justice
Challenges to liberalism
It is precisely these presuppositions that have come under recent attack.
Communitarians such as Michael Walzer eschew the notion that an
abstract, universal standard of justice can be found. 4 Further, communitar-
ians eschew the fundamental stress on the individual that liberalism
presupposes. They propose instead that communities come to their own
understandings of justice, consistent with their particular histories. Justice
is not abstract and universal, derived by deductive logic from minimal
premises or by procedures of rational choice, but emerges out of the
complex and distinctive histories of communities.
Feminists such as Iris Marion Young,5 Susan Okin, 6 and Nancy
Hirschmann7 concur in some communitarian critiques of the liberal stress
on individual autonomy and rational choice. Hirschmann points out that
such views tend to reflect a male standpoint that cannot speak for all.
Young contends that people are not simply individuals but are organized
and oppressed as members of groups. Okin notes that if Nozick's
adaptation of Lockean property rights is taken seriously, women would be
said to 'own' their children, since they have 'mixed their labor' with raw
materials in order to 'produce' them. Hence, for feminists, the fundamental
presuppositions of liberal theory are problematic: its dependence on a
limited kind of rationality renders it absurd, its neglect of the realities of
oppression renders it impotent, and its blindness to its own biases renders
it inadequate at best and demonic at worst.
Following Carol Gilligan8 and Nancy Chodorow9, many feminists have
charged that the focus on justice and abstract principles misses an
important ethical dimension or Voice' — the voice of care, which is
particular and contextual.10 Thus, feminists have also raised a fundamental
challenge to the adequacy of justice as the rubric under which societal
arrangements should be assessed. To these communitarian and feminist
voices must be added the postmodern challenge that all knowledge reflects
power.11 Hence, the liberal view of justice will be the product of
hegemonic discourse, reflecting the powerful, middle-class position of the
advocates of liberal theory.
In sum, numerous voices are now raised questioning the entire liberal
enterprise of trying to find universal standards of justice. In the face of
such criticisms, not only liberal theory but any attempt to find a theory of
justice may be in trouble. It is partly for this reason that in his more
recent defence of liberalism John Rawls has adopted a more modest agenda
165
Karen Lebacqz
for his theory of justice, and now claims it as a political rather than a
moral theory of justice.12
Against this backdrop of liberal theory and its critics, we can see both the
distinctiveness of and the difficulties for any contemporary Christian
approach to justice. We begin with what is distinctive.
An ever/Lowing stream
Christian approaches to justice have roots in the Hebrew Scriptures. Two
words from those Scriptures are translated by our word 'justice': mishpat
and sedakah. Mishpat are particular duties and responsibilities that embody
life in covenant with God and with one another. Sedakah refers to God's
righteousness and hence brings judgement not on particular acts but on
what William Coats has called the entire 'shape of the age'.13 While
mishpat may bear some resonances with 'give to each what is due', sedakah
requires a far more expansive understanding of justice. Eloquent expression
is given to this expansiveness in the prophet Amos's denunciation of those
who trample the heads of the poor into the ground: let justice roll down
like waters and righteousness like an everflowing stream (Amos 5:24).
Christians are shaped by this understanding of fundamental covenantal
responsibilities and of an overarching righteousness that offers the vision
of God's reign. While Western philosophy defines justice formally as
'giving to each what is due', or 'treating similar cases similarly', and
Christian tradition has sometimes adopted this more narrow view,14
contemporary Christian theorists tend to follow the call of Amos in seeing
justice as an everflowing stream that will sweep away iniquities. Justice
has a much broader scope, then, than it does in the philosophical tradition.
This broad scope is both benefit and burden. Taking the broader view
enables Christians to address problems of oppression and of the treatment
of groups as well as of individuals. We shall return to this below. It also
allows Christians to refuse the division between 'care' and justice that
appears to plague contemporary philosophical feminists.15 At the same
time, taking such a broad view can dilute the power of Christian discourse
to address issues with precision and clarity.
Remembrance
For philosophers, the grounding of any demands of justice generally lies
either in a notion of the well-ordered society (Aristotle) or in an extension
166
Justice
167
Karen Lebacqz
the faces of the poor into the dust, so the early Church Fathers saw the
rich as 'robbers' who kept bread that belonged to the hungry. 25 Contem-
porary liberation theologians and feminist theologians are particularly
strong in stressing how 'the personal is political' — how individual
suffering and pain reflects structural injustices of the larger political,
economic and social systems. A Christian approach to justice therefore
begins with a recognition of structural problems and of oppression.
Dimensions of justice
Significantly, the covenantal, sweeping understanding of justice in Chris-
tian tradition yields a more complex break-down of categories than we
usually find in Western philosophy, in spite of some shared Aristotelian
168
Justice
169
Karen Lebacqz
Notes
170
Justice
171
Karen Lebacqz
Select bibliography
Joel Feinberg and Hyman Gross (eds), Justice: Selected Readings (Belmont, CA:
Wadsworth, 1977).
David Hollenbach, Claims in Conflict: Retrieving and Renewing the Catholic Human Rights
Tradition (New York: Paulist Press, 1979).
Karen Lebacqz, Justice in an Unjust World: Foundations for a Christian Approach to Justice
(Minneapolis: Augsburg, 1987).
Karen Lebacqz, Six Theories of Justice: Perspectives from Philosophical and Theological Ethics
(Minneapolis: Augsburg, 1986).
Iris Marion Young, Justice and the Politics of Difference (Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 1990).
172
12
Property
Timothy J. Gorringe
'The idea of property', wrote J. S. Mill, 'is not some one thing, identical
throughout history and incapable of alteration, but is variable, like all
other creations of the human mind; at any given time it is a brief
expression denoting the rights over things conferred by the law or custom
of some given society at that time; but neither on this point nor on any
other has the law and custom of a given time and place a claim to be
stereotyped for ever.'1 The statement needs considerable glossing but its
main point is essential to any proper understanding of the theme. Ideas of
property hang together with ideas of the state, of justice, and of human
nature and vary with different economies. Thus property has been
understood one way in a largely peasant economy where the ox plough is
the principal means of production (Scripture and the early Church Fathers),
another way when trade begins to burgeon (Aquinas), another way in the
light of the rise of the landed gentry (Locke), another way against the
background of the industrial revolution (Hegel and Marx), and another
way in late capitalism (Hayek). At the same time there is a Utopian strand
in the discussion of property, grounded in our earliest texts, which
exercises a profound gravitational pull and which is especially important
at the present time. I shall first try to outline the way in which approaches
to property have changed before sketching the contemporary situation and
the importance of the Utopian tradition.
173
Timothy J. Gorringe
174
Property
Aristotle
Whilst these developments took place in Palestine the Greek city states,
and above all Athens, rose and fell. Just past their apogee one of Plato's
pupils, and the tutor of Alexander the Great, was giving lectures of
seminal importance on politics and economics. Aristotle (384-322 BCE)
taught, of course, in the Greek city state in which sea trade was important,
but the backbone of the economy was still agriculture. Aristotle considers
in detail his teacher's proposals (in The Republic) for common ownership.
Plato is always worth reading, he notes, 'but perfection in everything can
175
Timothy J. Gorringe
176
Property
Aquinas
The need for brevity condenses the teaching of a five-hundred-year period
into one figure, and that of the thirteenth century. Thomas Aquinas
(1225—74), however, had a genius for synthesis, bringing together
Aristotle, Scripture, and the neo-platonism of Augustine, which has made
him one of the greatest oi all teachers of the Church. We discern a shift in
his teaching from that we have just reviewed and the expansion of trade
and of markets, which was a major feature of his day, is certainly part of
the reason for this. He deals with property as the presupposition of his
treatment of theft. There are no absolute rights to ownership, but there
are rights to use (Summa Tkeologiae, II—II, q. 66.1). Private property is
necessary because we care better for our own property, things are more
orderly if each looks after their own, and this situation is more conducive
to peace. However, common use always has priority if there are those in
need (66.2). What people have in superabundance is due by natural law
to the poor. In extreme cases of need we have a right to meet that need by
taking property from another either openly or secretly and this is not to
be considered theft (66.7).
In Religion and the Rise of Capitalism R. H. Tawney has rehearsed how
these pious certainties dissolved as the market economy grew. Luther, in
his rage against usury, is still pre-modern. Calvin issues a cautious
endorsement. When it comes to property, however, the first truly modern
voice is that of John Locke.
177
Timothy J. Gorringe
still something he has to reckon with. We learn from Scripture that the
earth was given to humankind in common. Whence then came private
property? In seeking an answer he formulates a new justification of
property of fundamental importance. Though the earth and all its creatures
are common to all 'yet every Man has a Property in his own Person. This
no Body has any right to but himself. The Labour of his Body, and the
Work of his Hands, we may say, are properly his. Whatsoever then he
removes out of the State that Nature hath provided . . . he hath mixed his
Labour with . . . and thereby makes it his Property.'5 This was a potentially
revolutionary argument. Locke was sixteen when Winstanley and the
Diggers challenged Cromwell on English property ownership and began
digging on St George's Hill. On his arguments they should have had
possession, and changed the face of England for ever. But Locke, whose
circle included many great landowners, hesitates. Are there limits to
property? Yes, for 'The same Law of Nature, that does . . . give us
Property, does also bound that Property too'.6 Having granted that, in
regard to the fruits of the earth, he at once becomes uncertain with regard
to land. God gave the world to men in common but did not intend it to
remain common and uncultivated. 'He gave it to the use of the Industrious
and Rational . . . not to the Fancy or Covetousness of the Quarrelsome and
Contentious.' He sees that the introduction of money as a medium of
exchange crucially affects his principle. Without money property is
limited to what a person can till. Now money is introduced by 'tacit and
voluntary consent' and so 'Men have agreed to disproportionate and
unequal Possession of the Earth'.7 America, understood as a vast tract of
uninhabited virgin territory, is constantly in the background. Even now,
Locke argues, there is land in plenty for all. But Locke has other
considerations about property, equally momentous. In his view property
(i.e., a landowning gentry) is the surest defence against tyranny. The
reason men enter society, he says, is the preservation of property and we
have laws 'to limit the Power and moderate the Dominion of every Part
and Member of the Society'. It is the attempt to take away property which
at once mobilizes resistance against tyranny. 8 Locke talks about 'the
People' establishing a Legislative, but of course only a tiny percentage of
the English population had the vote at the time. Whatever his intentions,
it is scarcely surprising that, after his death, his arguments were read as
support for the reigning oligarchy.
Rousseau
Rousseau (1712-78), like the other phtlosophes, learned from Locke, but
drew almost opposite conclusions as to property. In a famous apostrophe
in his Discourse on the Origin of Inequality he described the first man who
178
Property
179
Timothy J. Gorringe
Marx
Mill, in our opening quotation, thinks of property in terms of things, a
tendency common to most of the tradition preceding him. Marx
(1818-83), on the other hand, from the start thinks in terms of
relationships. 'An isolated individual could no more have property in land
and soil than he could speak. He could, of course, live off it as substance,
as do the animals. The relation to the earth as property is always mediated
through . . . the tribe, the commune . . . The individual can never appear
here in the dot-like isolation in which he appears as mere free worker.'14
This is his great difference from the 'bourgeois economists', who think
always of what he calls ironically 'Robinson Crusoe on his island'. One of
the reasons Marx wished to transcend capitalism was that, developing
ideas Hegel had worked out, he saw how the opposition of those who buy
and those who sell labour produces a multiply alienated society. Further-
more he saw that labour itself was a form of property, a commodity.
Earlier societies had rested on social inter-dependence. When the capitalist
acquires ownership of the means of production this is transformed into the
individual dependence of each worker on the capitalist. According to
Locke rights to property rested on a person's labour. 'Now, however,
property turns out to be the right, on the part of the capitalist, to
appropriate the unpaid labour of others or its product, and to be the
impossibility, on the part of the labourer, of appropriating his own
product.'15 All social relations are mediated by money which, Marx saw
even in 1844, creates inhuman and imaginary appetites. 'Private property
does not know how to turn crude need into human need.'16 Marx believed
that Luther, whom he quoted at length in his Theory of Surplus Value, had
a greater insight into the true nature of capital than most later commen-
tators. The answer to this problem Marx believed to be the socialization —
common ownership — of the means of production, the recovery of human
community.17 Freedom will consist in the fact that 'socialized humanity,
the associated producers, regulate their interchange with nature rationally,
bring it under their common control, instead of being ruled by it as by
some blind power'.18 In this society it will be, as Marx put it in his
Critique of the Gotha Programme (1875), 'from each according to his ability
to each according to his needs'.
180
Property
181
Timothy J. Gorringe
towards discharging our responsibility for caring for ourselves and for the
earth.' 23 The economist Herman Daly has compared the earth to a ship
with a Plimsoll line. We are on the Plimsoll line right now: the danger of
sinking is real. This could mean one of two things. It could well be that
processes of global warming are now so advanced that massive loss of
territory, including whole countries, like Bangladesh, is inevitable.
Meanwhile prominent spokesmen in the United States like Garret Hardin
have warned that we must view the earth as a lifeboat, with the Third
World poor in the water. Since our lifestyle is non-negotiable, and we
cannot keep that up if they come on board, we have to let them sink. The
possibility of systematic aggression against the burgeoning populations of
the Third World can also by no means be ruled out. There is little to
show that we have learned anything but lessons in technique from the
Holocaust. Rosa Luxemburg's stark alternative of socialism or barbarism
has already been realized many times over. The difference now is that it
could be both global and final.
The alternative to these dark prognoses is, in Sandra Postel's words, 'a
global effort to lighten humanity's load on the earth'.24 This has to be in
terms of addressing the gross disparities of wealth, of turning from a
consumption to a recycling economy, and tackling population growth. As
is well known, reaching a certain level of prosperity is the key to the
latter. As the Union of Concerned Scientists emphasized, however, a new
ethic is also crucial, and a changed attitude to property is part and parcel
of this. In the light of the present situation liberal teaching on property
since Locke is dangerous and irresponsible, an 'arid intellectualism' (to use
Hegel's phrase) if ever there was one. Let me take four points from the
founding property ethics of Western culture as an alternative.
182
Property
183
Timothy J. Gorringe
market. The 1996 Audi advertisment has only one word: 'Worship' - but
this is only to make explicit the subtext of most advertising.
Jesus' teaching about the birds of the air and the lilies of the field is
not, as generations have taken it, an outline doctrine of providence. It is
part of his satirical attack on Mammon — putting property in its place. A
much later attack on the same lines runs:
In place of the wealth and poverty of political economy, come the rich
human being and the rich human need. The rich human being is
simultaneously the human being in need of a totality of human
manifestations of life - the person in whom their own realisation exists
as an inner necessity, as need. Not only wealth, but likewise the poverty
of a person - under the assumption of socialism - receives in equal
measure a human and therefore social significance. Poverty is the passive
bond which causes the human being to experience the need of the
greatest wealth - viz, the other human being.26
Tor freedom Christ has set us free' (Gal 5:1), but that freedom is illusory
whilst we are bound by chains to Property/Mammon. A whole line of
Christians before us saw that and sought freedom in their own way. We
have to seek it in ours, but in a changed situation, and with much greater
urgency. '"Watchman, what of the night?" The watchman says: "Morning
comes, and also the night. If you will inquire, inquire; come back again'"
(Isa 21:11--12).
Notes
184
Property
Select bibliography
185
13
Morality and law
Patrick Harmon
Our lives are shaped by two forces of which often we are hardly aware: the
moral code to which we subscribe and the law of the society of which we
are part. We keep promises, or at least generally believe we ought to, we
pay our debts, respect the person and property of others; we refrain from
deceiving people, or injuring their good name, or taking what does not
belong to us. We think it 'right' to act, or refrain from acting, in such
ways, 'wrong' to deviate from the path which they mark out. We believe
that on the whole it is for our 'good' and the good of others that we
should live according to the prescriptions and proscriptions of morality
and of law.
And on the whole we don't pay much attention, nor do we need to, to
the question whether the rules by which we live are moral rules or legal.
One reason for this is that often they are both: murder is prohibited by
the moral law as well as the law of the land, as are perjury, theft and
selling defective goods. It is morally as well as legally wrong to drive at
speed on the road in front of a school playground from which a child
might emerge as we are passing. Inciting to racial hatred is an offence
against both morality and the law. The law enforces the keeping of some
of our promises, as when we sign a contract to buy or sell a house, or to
do some job or render a service.
But there are times when we become aware that, for all their similarities
and their overlap, law and morality are different fields of experience. There
are some requirements of morality which are not enjoined by the law:
there is no law which says that we ought to give to people who are in
need, or show compassion for a drug addict, or speak a kind word to
someone who is in pain. No law forbids the unilateral ending of a long-
term relationship between partners who are not married, or compels a
186
Morality and law
187
Patrick Hannon
law has been influenced by morality (and vice versa), the second is whether
some reference to morality is required in an adequate definition of law.
The third question is whether the law is open to moral criticism, and the
fourth is whether the enforcement of morality is a part of the function of
law. Hart's questions furnish a starting-point for what must here be a very
general approach to a dense and complex topic.
The first question is reasonably easily disposed of: it is not difficult to
think of examples of the reciprocal interaction between morality and law
which leads to development in one or the other. Take, for instance, laws
which aim to promote equality of opportunity for employment as between
men and women. Such laws are inspired by the moral insight that women
and men are of equal dignity and potential, and that it is wrong to give a
job to a man in preference to a woman merely because of the difference in
gender.
An employer, out of prejudice, might perpetrate such a wrong, and of
course such has been the pattern in what are usually now called patriarchal
societies. Campaigners for women's rights have therefore sought to secure
legislation which forbids discrimination on the ground of gender alone.
But of course a reformer might hope that in due course equal treatment
would become the norm, not just because the law insisted but because
people generally came to recognize that as a matter of morality it is wrong
to discriminate in this way.
One could multiply examples, from laws forbidding racial discrimina-
tion to legislation about road safety, or conditions in the workplace, or
fair trading, or due care for the environment. The point in each case is
that a moral insight generates a movement for legislation coercing people
to act for the good in ways which, left to themselves, they may not feel at
all inclined to do. But the hope is that in time they might come to the
morally more mature frame of mind in which they behave rightly, not
just for fear of punishment but rather because what the law lays down is
also the morally right thing to do.
This idea is not a new one, and in the Christian theological tradition it
was expressed by St Thomas Aquinas who saw law as having a role in
educating people in virtue: 'From being accustomed to shun what is evil
and discharge what is good on account of threat of punishment a man
sometimes comes to continue on that course from his own taste and
choice.'2 But it gives rise to questions to which we shall have to return
when we consider the issue of the enforcement of morals. For there are
difficulties and dangers in the concept of the promotion of morality
through the medium of law.
Hart's second question is whether an adequate definition of law must
include some reference to morality. At one level this is a technical
question, much discussed by legal philosophers. But it isn't a merely
188
Morality and law
189
Patrick Hannon
190
Morality and law
at least about what it does not mean. For a start, it doesn't make sense to
think of it as referring simply to the morality of acts done in private: most
murders are done in private, and privacy is virtually essential to the thief;
and it would be ludicrous to suggest that the law should never intervene
when a man beats his wife or children at home.
Nor is it helpful to think of the term 'private morality' as referring to
what is a matter of private (in the sense of personal) moral judgement. For
the question whether something is properly left to the individual's
conscience, or whether it is a claim of the moral order, is usually only the
starting-point of a debate. So, for example, the claim that women have a
moral right to choose abortion comes up against the claim that the unborn
have a moral right to life from the moment of conception.
The first claim says that it is a matter for the personal conscience of a
woman whether to have an abortion or not, the second maintains that the
moral order precludes the directly intended taking of any innocent life.
The argument cannot be settled by asserting the one right or the other,
and there remains for the legislator the question whether either of these
moral beliefs is to be 'enforced'.
Such questions are complicated nowadays by the pluralism of moral
belief and practice which is a feature of so many modern societies. For it
is a fact of modern life that societies are composed of people of a variety of
religious traditions and of none. If the law is to reflect and promote moral
values — and it must, in some sense, as we have seen — whose values? The
values of the majority religious (or other) moral tradition? What then of
minorities in the community: are they to be coerced into following
patterns of behaviour which are contrary to conscience as they experience
it, or prevented from acting according to their consciences simply because
the majority subscribes to a different world-view?
One of the reasons why it is difficult to think clearly about these
questions is that it is difficult to find a starting-point which has prospect
of common acceptance. I shall suggest that, for all that it comes from a
particular religious tradition, Roman Catholic teaching concerning reli-
gious freedom provides a starting-point, and indeed the makings of a
framework, for fruitful discussion of the issues at stake. And the reason
why it has prospect of a more general acceptance is that its basis is a
philosophical one, of a kind which resonates with the mind of our times.10
The principle is to be found in the Declaration on Religious Freedom
of the Second Vatican Council. Its genesis lay in modern consciousness of
the dignity of the human, and the growing demand that people 'should
exercise fully their own judgement and a responsible freedom in their
actions, and should not be subject to the pressure of coercion but inspired
by a sense of duty'. 11 A key influence in the drafting of the Declaration —
many would say its principal architect — was the US Jesuit theologian
191
Patrick Harmon
John Courtney Murray. It was of course not accidental that the principal
ideas embodied in the document had their roots in the experience of the
United States, pluralist in its very foundation. 12 The Council's teaching
was conceived in the context of a debate about religious freedom, and it
will be necessary to show how it may be applied to the sphere of morality
as well. But first the principle and its basis.
The principle, put shortly, is that in religious matters people should
not be made to act against their consciences, nor should they be prevented
from acting in accordance with their consciences 'within due limits', a
phrase which turns out to mean 'within the limits of the common good'.
In the context what is primarily meant is that in matters of conscience the
laws of a state should not attempt to coerce people, that there should be
freedom of conscience in matters of religious belief and practice, that there
is a right to religious freedom, within limits imposed by the requirements
of 'the common good'. The meaning of this qualification is of course
crucial, and we must return to it in a moment.
The right to religious freedom is based, the Council said, on the dignity
of the human person and the nature of the search for truth. Human
dignity consists in the twin gifts of reason and the power of choice, and it
is respected to the extent that each person is given scope for the exercise
of these gifts in the pursuit of truth and human fulfilment. And it is in
the nature of the search for truth that it 'must be carried out in a manner
that is appropriate to the dignity and social nature of the human person:
that is, by free enquiry with the help of teaching or instruction,
communication and dialogue'.13
The right here asserted is, as already mentioned, a right to religious
freedom, and its application to the field of morality probably needs to be
shown. The argument is not complicated: the dignity of the human person
and the nature of the search for truth are the same whether one is thinking
about religion or about morality. As gifted with reason and freedom we
live up to our dignity to the extent that we freely seek moral truth, and
coercion is no more at home in the quest for moral than it is for religious
value.
What I am suggesting therefore is that a starting-point and a framework
for a consideration of the issues involved in debates about the enforcement
of morals may be found by transposing Vatican II's principle concerning
religious freedom to the sphere of morality. Our starting-point then would
be that in matters of moral belief and practice people should not be
coerced into going against their consciences, nor should they be prevented
from following their consciences. But the qualifying clause has application
here too, and so we must see what is meant by 'the common good'.
This concept has its roots in classical thought and as developed by
classical and Christian thinkers is rich and complex. But for present
192
Morality and law
193
Patrick Hannon
194
Morality and law
view that there is a realm of private morality which is not the law's
business. Unless conduct involves an identifiable public harm it ought
not to be proscribed by the law. On this view the law should confine itself
to the prohibition of conduct which would injure others in their person or
property, or corrupt or exploit, or violate the public sensibility or public
order.
In making his case Hart counters Devlin's arguments, and in particular
he rejects the latter's concept of a public morality. The detail of their
exchanges (for the debate did not end with Hart's rejoinder to the
Maccabean lecture20) is beyond the scope of a short chapter. But it is
worth drawing attention to Hart's starting-point, for it sets the tone of
his contribution as a whole. And his starting-point is the contention that
the question whether morals should be enforced is itself a moral question.
For enforcement entails the curtailment of freedom, and the curtailment
of freedom requires moral justification.
In support of this way of looking at the matter Hart points out that
legal enforcement has two aspects. The first is that it involves the
punishment of offenders, and this is done through depriving them of
freedom of movement or of property or of association with family or
friends, or the infliction of physical pain or even death. But all of these are
normally regarded as evil and normally their infliction is considered
wrong. If therefore it is to escape moral censure their infliction requires
special justification.
The second aspect of enforcement is no less pertinent to the need for
justification. It is that law restricts freedom in that it coerces conformity
through threat of punishment. One's freedom is just as surely, even if
differently, inhibited when one refrains from some act for fear of being
put in jail as it is when one is jailed for doing the forbidden deed. And
this kind of restriction also needs to be justified, for freedom is valuable
both in itself and because it enables people to experiment with different
ways of living.
But there is a further reason, according to Hart, why restriction of
freedom requires to be justified from the standpoint of morality: 'interfer-
ence with individual liberty . . . is itself the infliction of a special form of
suffering - often very acute - on those whose desires are frustrated by the
fear of punishment'. 21 He observes that this is especially true of laws
which impose a sexual morality.
For all that there are differences, of vantage-point and of perspective,
between Lord Devlin's view and that of Hart they are not without common
ground. There is this much at least: that both envisage the main issue as
one of reconciling individual freedom and the public interest, in some
sense of that expression. Each requires advertence to a social dimension
in human conduct, and to a public interest in preventing social harm;
195
Patrick Harmon
and each is prepared to recognize a role for the criminal law in that
process.
Indeed one commentator has said that 'both are recognizably liberal',22
meaning no doubt that each puts a premium on freedom. In Hart's case
this is clear even in the way he frames the main question, but it is
intimated also in Devlin's assertion that 'the individual has a locus standi
too; he cannot be expected to surrender to the judgement of society the
whole conduct of his life'.23 And this insight is made concrete in the
'elastic principles' to which Devlin would have the legislator advert, and
especially in the requirements that there should be toleration of the
maximum freedom consistent with the integrity of society, and that
privacy must as far as possible be respected.
It could be that the principal difference between them is one of
emphasis; but the difference in emphasis is critical. Devlin's interest, first
and last, is in 'the integrity of society', and in that sense he is
'conservative'. Hart's concern, first and last, is with the protection of
individual freedom. Devlin's way of looking at the issues will probably
recommend itself to someone whose instinct is to preserve societal values,
Hart's will be the more congenial for someone who is inclined to a more
liberal' political view.
Of course, strictly speaking, the term 'enforcement of morals' is a
misnomer. For the law can at best ensure only external compliance,
whereas to be moral it is not enough to behave in a way which is merely
externally correct.24 From a legal point of view it does not matter with
what degree of resentment I pay my taxes; all the law requires is that I
pay them. But from the viewpoint of morality a bad attitude or unworthy
motive or perverse intention may mar what on the face of it is a good act,
as when I give money with bad grace to someone in need. Hence it seems
better to say that what the law enforces is a moral code, or the part of a
code which commands or prohibits observable conduct: that it cannot
enforce morality 'as such'. Indeed if someone refrains from misconduct
wholly out of fear of punishment it is hardly correct to speak of morality
at all.
And this provides a clue, as James Mackey has recently suggested, to
the truth that emerges from the Hart—Devlin debate, and it shows that
each of them was partly right. 'Law does, and must always, make its
business what would be morally right for people to do or refrain from
doing. That is always true of law, in any form of human society which
proposes to be essential to human living . . . This is the part of the truth
that Devlin protected so well on his side of the debate.'25 But it is the
merit of Hart's contribution that 'he has pointed unerringly to the quite
literally demoralising tendency of the apparatus of extraneous punishment
and of its ever-present threat'. 26
196
Morality and law
Notes
1 H. L. A. Hart, Law, Liberty and Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1968),
pp. 1-4.
2 Summa Theologiae, I—II, q. 92, art. 2, ad 4: Blackfriars edn, vol. 28, ed. Thomas
Gilby, 101. Cf. also q. 95, art. 2. Aquinas's approach echoes Plato's but especially
Aristotle's.
3 Augustine, De Libero Arbitno.
4 Summa Theologiae, I-II, q. 95, art. 2. Gilby translates legis corruptio as 'spoilt law'.
5 Gilby's translation of viokntiae: I-II, q. 96, art. 4, 96, 4.
6 Trans. E. F. Watling, Sophocles: The Theban Plays (Harmondsworth: Penguin
Classics, 1959), p. 138.
7 An excellent account of the history of the concept of Natural Law in legal
philosophy is in John M. Kelly, A Short History of Western Legal Theory (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1992).
8 Patrick Devlin, The Enforcement of Morals (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965).
The text of the Maccabean Lecture, entitled 'Morals and the criminal law', is in
ch. 1.
9 Hart, Law, Liberty and Morality.
10 The argument here is developed more fully in Patrick Hannon, Church, State,
Morality and Law (Dublin: Gill and Macmillan, 1992), ch. 7.
11 Dignitatis Humanae, para. 1; trans, in Austin Flannery (ed.), Vatican Council II
(revised translation of the basic documents) (Dublin: Dominican Publications,
1996), p. 551.
12 See John Courtney Murray, We Hold These Truths: Catholic Reflections on the American
Proposition (New York, I960; repr. 1988).
13 Dignitatis Humanae, para. 3; Flannery, p. 554.
14 Ibid., para. 6; Flannery, p. 556.
15 Devlin, The Enforcement of Morals, p. 2.
16 J. S. Mill, On Liberty, ed. Gertrude Himmelfarb (Harmondsworth: Penguin
Classics, 1974), p. 68.
17 Devlin, The Enforcement of Morals, p. 3.
18 Ibid., p. 15.
19 Hart, Law, Liberty and Morality.
20 See Devlin, The Enforcement of Morals, Preface, chs 5, 6, 7, and bibliography at
pp. xiii—xiv. See further Simon Lee, Law and Morals (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1986), pp. 96-8.
197
Patrick Harmon
Select bibliography
Patrick A. Devlin, The Enforcement of Morals (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965).
Patrick Hannon, Church, State, Morality and Law (Dublin: Gill and Macmillan, 1992).
H. L. A. Hart, Law, Liberty and Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1963).
John M. Kelly, A Short History of Western Legal Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1992).
Simon M. Lee, Law and Morals (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986).
Richard McBrien, Caesar's Coin: Religion and Politics in America (New York: Macmillan
and London: Collier Macmillan, 1987).
Basil Mitchell, Law, Morality and Religion in a Secular Society (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1967).
198
14
The punishment of criminals
Bernard Hoose
In recent years the prison population of the USA has exceeded one million.
In most other Western countries the figures are much smaller, but there,
as in the United States, imprisonment is merely one of several penalties
that can be imposed upon people who break the law. In other words, the
number of people punished by agents of the state in any one year is, in
most countries, considerable. Although concern has been expressed by
some about the size of the prison population in the USA and elsewhere,
most people, it seems, hold that, at least in principle, the punishment of
criminals is justifiable activity. It is not at all clear, however, that there is
general agreement among them concerning the arguments for its justifi-
cation. Three such justifications are commonly offered: deterrence, retri-
bution and reformation or rehabilitation. Some people tend to concentrate
on one of them, seeing it as the only one that is valid, but it appears that
most of those who investigate the subject see a role for all of them. We
shall begin this chapter with a brief examination of each in turn.
Punishment as deterrent
199
Bernard Hoose
200
The punishment of criminals
committed crimes but those others whom one might have expected to be
deterred from any thoughts of criminal activity through fear of receiving
like punishment. There is evidence to suggest that some such brutalizing
effects occurred in certain countries in the past when particularly gory
executions and horrific beatings were carried out in public places, and
apparently even became a source of entertainment.
A number of researchers believe that the greatest deterrent is the fear of
being caught. In places where the clear-up rate of the local police force is
poor, some people will undoubtedly be willing to risk even severe
punishments because they believe there is little chance of being appre-
hended. That single fact may explain a good deal about the widespread
failure to deter people from indulging in criminal activity. However, even
if the deterrent system worked quite successfully (and perhaps it does in
regard to certain types of criminal activity in certain parts of the world),
it would still present problems of an ethical nature. Punishing a person
merely in order to cause other people to be afraid of the same punishment
certainly seems to amount to using that person merely as a means to an
end. On the other hand, if it were possible to justify punishment in some
other way, there could surely be no objections to any deterrent effect that
resulted from an appropriate sanction administered in a truly proportionate
manner. Such deterrence might be seen as a bonus. Another problem,
however, could rear its head. If one were concerned only with the greatest
good of the greatest number and not with how the good is distributed, 2
one might be tempted to convict and punish a person known to be
innocent or whose guilt was seriously in doubt. This might occur if a
particularly serious type of crime had become all too common in a certain
place and the police had been unable to find any of the real culprits. It is
worth bearing in mind that, even in countries that have well-developed
legal systems, there have been recent cases in which false evidence has
been produced in court and so-called 'rough justice' has been administered.
Before moving on to the next section, it is worth recalling that, even if
one were a utilitarian, proof of a successful deterrent effect in one area
would not be sufficient for a justification of all punishment. Research
might reveal, for instance, that a certain kind of punishment has a
deterrent effect on certain kinds of criminals of a certain age group who
have been wont to commit certain kinds of crimes. The same kind of
research might also reveal that something other than punishment (an
educational project, for example) is more effective when dealing with a
different group of malefactors and/or a different category of crimes. The
problem is thus shown to be a very complex one. A blanket justification
of punishment could not easily be argued for using deterrence theory
alone.
201
Bernard Hoose
Retributivist theory
202
The punishment of criminals
taken for granted that it is due is simply not enough. Moreover, even if
retributivist arguments were thoroughly convincing in this regard, we
would need to bear in mind that 'what is due to a person' should not be
confined to punishment. Help in the adjustment to a new way of life after
imprisonment, for instance, may also be due, although in practice, it
would seem that it is often not forthcoming.
Another point to bear in mind is that, taken to extremes, retributivism
could lead to a situation in which consequences are simply ignored. One
way of stating that punishment is due to people who have committed
criminal offences is to say it is our duty (or at least the duty of the
appropriate organs of the state) to punish them. Somebody holding to this
point of view might be totally unmoved by the negative consequences of
such penalties. Thus we hear conversations in which the participants
appear to have no common frame of reference. Some such conversations
are about whether or not punishment should be employed at all in certain
kinds of cases. Others are about whether or not a certain penalty should
be inflicted upon perpetrators of certain types of crimes. One person
argues, for instance, that custodial sentences are counterproductive where
certain types of young offenders are concerned. She suggests that a better
course of action would be to send them off on weekend courses. There
they will learn about good citizenship and perhaps pick up one or two
useful skills. The problem with these youngsters is that nobody, including
their parents and teachers, has ever taken an interest in them or helped
them to acquire a sense of self-worth. Her interlocutor is unmoved by
such reasoning.
'They have committed serious offences. They must pay the price.'
'But giving them custodial sentences will only make matters worse.
They will return to society with even bigger chips on their shoulders,
and, moreover, they will be schooled in other kinds of criminal activity.'
'The punishment must fit the crime.'
'But punishing them in the way you suggest will only serve to make
matters worse.'
'There is a principle at stake here.'
A first point to be made here is that, in some, though certainly not all,
such conversations, the person claiming to be a retributivist may be moved
simply by a crude desire for revenge. The very existence of a system in
which organs of the state, rather than the victim(s) of the crime, are
responsible for the punishment of criminals should help us to avoid some
of the worst excesses of revenge. However, many of us feel a sense of
outrage when we hear about certain crimes, even though we ourselves are
not the victims, and this sense of outrage is often accompanied by a wish
to see the perpetrators of the crimes suffer. If they are indeed made to
203
Bernard Hoose
Reformative theory
204
The punishment of criminals
reformation can take place only when the person concerned freely embraces
the means. Quite apart from the nightmare stories one hears about coercive
'treatment' involving drugs and other questionable procedures, it is
documented that, at various times and in various places, attempts have
been made to reform prisoners by forcing them to live in an enforced
'monastic' atmosphere involving silence and obligatory prayers. It is
hardly surprising that little is heard about successes resulting from such
systems. I am not suggesting, of course, that the means to help people
achieve rehabilitation in society should not be made available to them.
We should surely rejoice if they are, but making such means available
would not normally amount to punishment. It would be something
separate from or in addition to the penalty. Various educational, psycho-
logical and religious facilities may, for instance, be made available in
prisons. It is the imprisonment, however, that is the punishment, not the
facilities which are made available. In other words, there is no proof that,
in such cases, the punishment itself is reformative. It may be necessary to
seek another justification for its existence. Having said all this, moreover,
it is worth calling to mind here what was said above concerning not the
reformative, but the possibly corrupting effects of certain forms of
punishment.
Ronald Preston notes that Christians and others who are concerned
about respect for persons realize that this concern relates in certain ways
to all three of the theories so far discussed, but also that it cannot be
satisfied by any one of them alone. Regarding retribution, he says that, if
people offend, any punishment they receive must be deserved. Afterwards,
society should wipe the slate clean. He then goes on to say: 'In certain
cases the common good of persons-in-community may require an element
of deterrence. I state this with caution because of the inveterate tendency
of the public to exaggerate the deterrent effects of punishments. In most
cases we have no deterrence except community attitudes.' Turning then to
the third theory, Preston says that there must be an intention actively to
promote the good of the person who has offended. 'This should not mean
adding a further and indeterminate length to a retributive sentence purely
for rehabilitative purposes and under coercive conditions.' He suggests
that rehabilitation should be available entirely on a voluntary basis. 'Those
who refuse to have anything to do with it would be free to ignore it.' 3
Moberly's theory
Some years ago, the British scholar Sir Walter Moberly suggested that
punishment could be seen as a ritual which represents the moral
deterioration that is taking place in the criminal. It does so by creating a
205
Bernard Hoose
206
The punishment of criminals
207
Bernard Hoose
may still be the case that, in their present state, many of these people will
not benefit from punishment. Indeed, punishment may merely make
matters worse.
It does not follow from this, however, that we should allow such people
to continue their life of crime unabated. Where persistently violent people
are concerned, drastic measures may be necessary in order to ensure
protection of the public. As the present writer suggested in a recent work,
even if such measures might not accord with Moberly's description of
justifiable punishment (given the aforementioned supposed inability of
those concerned to benefit from it), they may still be justifiable. 7 The
justification would be much the same as that invoked for self-defence or
defence of a third party. Usually, when discussing defence, we are
concerning with the morality of using violence. Here we may also be
concerned with the justification of violence, at least inasmuch as it may be
necessary to use it in the act of apprehending certain criminals. Quite
apart from this, however, we are concerned with the justification or
otherwise of taking the people concerned out of the community in which
they have been living, and detaining them in a secure place from which
we do not allow them to wander. Surely, whether we wish to call this
punishment or something else, it can be justified in much the same way
as violent defence. It is something forced upon us by those very people
who are being detained. It might be described as a lesser evil, chosen in
order to protect the public. It may, moreover, be necessary to keep some
very dangerous people in secure places, away from the general public, for
the remainder of their lives. All that, it would seem, can be justified
where there is serious danger to the public. Treating such people in an
inhumane way in addition to placing such limits on their freedom,
however, is a very different matter.
Notes
1 Ruth Morris, Crumbling Walls . . . Why Prisons Fail (London: Mosaic Press, 1989),
p. 110.
2 A common criticism of utilitarianism is that it cannot deal well with problems of
justice. Ross wrote that justice is not concerned merely with the greatest sum of
good, but rather with how the good is distributed: W. D. Ross, Foundations of
Ethics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1949), p. 319.
3 Ronald H. Preston, The Future of Christian Ethics (London: SCM Press, 1987),
pp. 231-2.
4 Sir Walter Moberly, The Ethics of Punishment (London, Faber and Faber, 1968),
pp. 199-237.
5 John Langan, 'Capital punishment', Theological Studies 54 (1993), p. 123-
6 Preston, The Future of Christian Ethics, pp. 235-6.
208
The punishment of criminals
7 Bernard Hoose, Received Wisdom? Reviewing the Role of Tradition in Christian Ethics,
(London: Geoffrey Chapman, 1994), pp. 135-43.
Select bibliography
Robert M. Baird and Stuart E. Rosenbaum (eds), Punishment and the Death Penalty: The
Current Debate (New York: Prometheus Books, 1995).
Bernard Hoose, Received Wisdom? Reviewing the Role of Tradition in Christian Ethics
(London: Geoffrey Chapman, 1994), ch. 4.
Sir Walter Moberly, The Ethics of Punishment (London: Faber and Faber, 1968).
Ronald Preston, The Future of Christian Ethics (London: SCM Press, 1987), ch. 13.
209
15
Peace, violence and war
Richard G. Jones
Many people were disturbed by the dubious moral legitimacy of the Gulf
War in 1991. The British Foreign Secretary, Douglas Hurd, called together
a group of church leaders and went to great pains to assure them that it
was indeed a 'just war' because a tyrant, Saddam Hussein, had invaded
Kuwait in a flagrant act of aggression, and Britain had a duty to support
the United Nations in repelling his forces. It was yet another instance of
the notion that some wars can be regarded by Christians as 'just', one that
has occurred throughout Christian history from about the fourth century.
From that early time some Christians — probably the majority — have seen
that although war is a monstrous evil and killing is an appalling offence
against Jesus' teaching, nevertheless it may be more evil not to take up
arms in some, but not all, wars. But in that case, which wars?
Beginning with Ambrose, strengthened by Augustine, and elaborated
by Thomas Aquinas in the thirteenth century and others later, the very
ancient notion of the 'just war' was steadily refined as the main tool with
which Christians tried to assess the morality of wars. Despite the immense
difficulty in fashioning such a tool, it remains the basic moral guide for
Christian reflection to this day. The notion is in two parts, dealing with
the decision to commence war (technically called the jus ad helium) and
then the appropriate conduct of war (the jus in hello). The former has five
requirements:
(1) There must be some just cause (e.g., to repel an aggressor).
(2) There must be just intent (e.g., to restore peace with justice, and not
to seek to devastate the other nation).
(3) The war must be a last resort, every possibility of peaceful settlement
having been exhausted.
210
Peace, violence and war
(1) The innocent must not be directly attacked, but only the armed forces
of the enemy. This provision also rules out wanton destruction and
atrocities against civilians.
(2) The means used must be in proportion to the ends in view. Huge
destructive force should not be deployed against small opponents.
But, more particularly, the harm caused by the war should not exceed
the good it aims to accomplish.
211
Richard G. Jones
war effort required immense sacrifice from every citizen and that every
possible person would be needed to bear arms.
Thus by 1915 many churchmen identified the German Kaiser as
implacably evil, the British and Allied cause as that of 'The Kingdom
of God', and the bearing of arms as the moral human equivalent of
Christ's work for our redemption. At the Primitive Methodist Conference
in 1916 a memorial service was held in which the President declared
'Never before have we thought of the Army as we think of it now. . . .
Those who have died have consecrated the Army in our thinking. Let us
go with them the way of the cross.'1 In much Christian rhetoric the
sacrifice of the Cross was equated with that of the dead soldier, as so many
village war memorials testify to this day when they carry the solemn text
'Greater love hath no man than this, that a man lay down his life for his
friends' (John 15:13), in apparent inability to notice the context in
scripture, for here Jesus was obviously talking about his own imminent
and unarmed death by which he was giving himself to his friends and the
world for God's sake.
This tendency to dignify a war by making it into a crusade has had
echoes since then but has rarely been as blatant. Christian thinking is
most prone to encourage it when a huge ideological effort has been first
made to demonize the opponents, as in the Cold War when the Russians
had become 'The Evil Empire' to the American public and communists
were the agents of Satan. Probably the horror and ineptitude of the
Vietnam War did the most to purge such lofty views about war out of the
general American mind-set. For the British, the Great War battles in
Flanders largely disabused the public of the moral grandeur of war.
Roland Bainton 2 notes four features of the crusade — belief that the
cause is God's, belief that God is directly guiding us in it, classifying our
side as godly and the enemy as ungodly, and unsparing prosecution.
Fundamentally, the crusader has never accepted that all our national causes
are ambiguous, a patchwork of the worthy and the unworthy, and has
refused to accept the humanity of the opponents who likewise are caught
up in the double-sided confusions of international politics. God is never
unequivocally 'on the side of one nation, for God's righteousness
transcends the self-interest of any one nation state. God's will is always
permeated with the demand for mercy, and never calls for ruthless
obliteration of opponents, nor the demand for unconditional surrender.
Thus the crusaders' God is too small, is a nation's desires glorified and
exalted up to divine pretensions, with the self-righteousness which always
accompanies such arrogance.
Here too we should notice that there is some value in the statements
which churches often make about the morality of wars in general — they
are not 'in Christ' and cannot be. Thus the Lambeth Conference of 1930
212
Peace, violence and war
213
Richard G. Jones
214
Peace, violence and war
215
Richard G. Jones
the problems of violence occur today. We turn now to the most pressing
contemporary problems.
216
Peace, violence and war
was the major threat to world peace but argued that negotiation from
strength is 'an unsatisfactory philosophy' because it leads to an arms race
of leapfrogging capacity for destruction. The superpowers were already too
strong. It then proposed that Britain gave up nuclear weapons in a phased
manner, whilst always working for multi-lateral disarmament, and finally
that all American nuclear weapons be removed from British soil. The
report infuriated the British government of the time, led to huge debates
within the Anglican Synod, and never succeeded in gaining agreement.
The immediate upshot was the publication of a rival series of essays The
Cross and the Bomb,16 in which the report was subject to a sharp critique
on the grounds of its lack of realism, its naivety in regard to the way
power functions in international politics and therefore its shallow theo-
logy. After some years of debate, the Synod finally passed a motion
declaring that the first use of nuclear weapons was immoral, but this too
was strongly opposed by a minority.
The Catholic Bishops consciously built their case with reference to
previous Catholic work (e.g., the Vatican II document Gaudium et Spes,
and a highly significant speech by Pope John Paul II to the United
Nations Special Session on Disarmament in 1982 in which he had said:
'In current conditions "deterrence" based on balance, certainly not as an
end in itself but as a step on the way to progressive disarmament, . . . may
still be judged morally acceptable')- The Bishops expressed deep concern
about the whole culture in which talk of nuclear war came so easily. They
accepted the need for deterrence, but said 'not all forms of deterrence are
morally acceptable' — the targeting of civilian centres, for example, and
the readiness whereby nuclear threats could escalate and, in the worst case,
for nuclear war therefore to escalate. They opposed any first-strike use,
declared a principle of 'sufficiency' in the build-up of adequate deterring
power and recommended immense energy be directed towards widespread
arms reductions, strengthening of control over nuclear weapons and the
building up of peace-making agencies, especially the UN. They believed
that 'There is a much greater potential for response . . . in the minds and
hearts of Americans than has been reflected in US policy'. Again, the
report annoyed the Reagan government, but was not as widely repudiated
as the Anglican one mentioned above.
The Methodist Bishops began with biblical study of the nature of God's
gift of shalom (peace), accepted the just war tradition as far as it is helpful,
but said that a 'theology of a just peace' must guide us. They cited twenty
features of this, including the key just war elements, but saw their task as
outlining a way of universal peace-making. They saw deterrence policy as
'idolatry'. It perpetuates 'the most distorted and most inhuman images of
our "enemy"'. They attacked the 'connection between the ideology of
deterrence and the existence of weapons', and declared roundly that
217
Richard G. Jones
At the time of writing there are mercifully no wars raging between nation
states, although the last fifty years have seen many such conflicts. But
there are numerous civil wars and wars of revolution which have been a
particular concern to the worldwide Christian conscience. The Christian
voice has not been united. Inevitably those who are pacifists have said that
there is no place whatever for Christians to take up arms, even in what
might appear to be a very legitimate cause. Those who are pacifists and
are favouring a general withdrawal from the world of politics (as with
many of the peace-churches) make their repudiation of violence an element
of that withdrawal. But the great majority of Christians accept the
obligation to work politically and socially for a just world; it is amongst
them that the debates have been most vigorous.
For the twentieth century has been one of popular uprisings, of the
overthrow of long-established colonial powers, of the widespread awareness
amongst the simplest peoples that they have a right to determine their
own existence and not be exploited by powerful oppressors. So revolution
— in the limited sense of the attempt to overthrow a government and
replace it with one more favourable to the poor majority, by arms if need
be — has been in the air that almost all of the southern half of the world
breathes. Those people have not taken kindly to established Christians in
the West who have argued that it is the primary Christian duty to obey
government because it has been instituted by God. Until recently this was
the dominant teaching of the Catholic, Orthodox and Lutheran churches
especially.
Thus a twentieth-century Lutheran (Bonhoeffer) could write in the dark
days of the beginning of the Second World War: 'According to Holy
Scripture there is no right to revolution; but there is a responsibility of
218
Peace, violence and war
every individual for preserving the purity of his office and mission in the
polis'17 (i.e., in the political order). Yet Luther recognized that there was
ultimately some ground for the forceful removal of a tyrant ruler, and
especially one who was mad.
In complete contrast to this traditional position is that which argues
that God is so involved in the processes of revolution against oppressive
rule that it is a Christian duty to bear arms and promote revolution. This
teaching first burst upon the world scene in 1966 when the World
Council of Churches gathered together a conference in Geneva on
'Christians and the Technical and Social Revolutions of Our Time'. Here
there were new sharp voices from the Third World (as it was then called)
calling for immediate and wholesale revolution in the name of Christ,
with theological warrant being provided. Thus the American theologian
Richard Shaull proclaimed
The Christian is called to be fully involved in the revolution as it
develops. It is only at its centre that we can perceive what God is doing,
understand how the struggle for humanization is being defined and
serve as agents of reconciliation. From within the struggle, we discover
that we do not bear witness in revolution by preserving our purity in
line with certain moral principles, but by freedom to be FOR MAN at
every moment. 18
The 'moral principles' he was citing were those which traditionally have
made Christians reluctant to engage in revolutionary violence against the
government of the day. He was claiming that such moral scruples were
now obsolete.
Others were taking up arms in guerrilla wars against oppressive powers,
notably the former Catholic priest Camilo Torres in Colombia, who
claimed that 'As Christians we can and we must fight against tyranny . . .
all genuine revolutionaries must see force as the only means left'. 19 Torres
was killed in an ambush, but his example was an inspiration to many.
Whilst this revolutionary fervour was gripping Latin America especially,
some theologians were claiming that Jesus had been a Zealot, a revolution-
ary fighter, too. This contention was fuelled by some eccentric scholarship
in Europe,' 0 later to be firmly repudiated by the most competent New
Testament scholarship, especially by the Reformed scholar Oscar Cull-
mann and the Lutheran scholar Martin Hengel. 21 The great classic work
of liberation theology — Gustavo Gutierrez's A Theology of Liberation — has
a key section in which he confesses that Cullmann has persuaded him to
distance Jesus from the Zealots in many significant ways, yet he is
reluctant to mention the clear implications for the practice of violence
that Jesus cannot be invoked to support it by classifying him as a Zealot.22
Others, equally committed to the immense struggle against long-
219
Richard G. Jones
220
Peace, violence and war
The echoes that can be heard here of the ancient notion of the just war are
all too clear. We have returned to where this chapter began. But that
tradition says little about the sort of peace that Christians should be
promoting. For that one must turn to the many traditions of Christian
social thought. There are however some other related issues which have
become important recently — for example, civil disobedience and the arms
trade, both of which have led to thoughtful reports by British churches.27
But that cannot be the last word. The Christian must always be asking
what sort of church life can best promote God's peace; the church should
be 'a peaceable kingdom'. 28
Notes
221
Richard G. Jones
Select bibliography
Roland Bainton, Christian Attitudes Towards War and Peace (London: Hodder and
Stoughton, 1961).
R. Bauckham and R. J. Elford (eds), The Nuclear Weapons Debate (London: SCM Press,
1989).
Norman Cohn, The Pursuit of the Millennium (London: Paladin, 1970).
J. G. Davies, Christians, Politics and Violent Revolution (London: SCM Press, ] 976).
The Challenge of Peace: God's Promise and Our Response (London: SPCK, 1983).
222
Interpersonal and sexual ethics
16
Sex, sexuality and relationships
Gareth Moore
223
Gareth Moore
Today, the old certainties are disappearing, and sex and its place in
human relationships is one of the most controversial areas of modern
Christian ethics. As ever, there is much sexual activity which does not
conform to the traditional picture of the nature and purpose of sex. But
there is also, in the West, a widespread discontent with the traditional
teaching itself, which seems to many no longer to correspond to the
realities of life and to the needs of people. The traditional ideals seem to
many not only unattainable but also unnecessary and even harmful. While
it is a normal part of human living to enter into sexual relationships —
normal because of our physical and emotional makeup - there seems,
again according to many people, to be no reason why these should always
be lifelong or exclusive. The old argument based on the needs of children
for a stable environment is no longer convincing in a world where, thanks
to the availability of efficient contraception, there is no necessary link
between sex and reproduction. Neither, given the rate at which world
population is expanding and the limited food and water sources at our
disposal, should there be regret that contraception is so readily available.
There is also an increasing recognition that homosexual acts might
sometimes be appropriate. While men and women who engaged in sexual
activity with others of the same sex were formerly (and in many places
still are) vilified and condemned as wanton perverts, it is becoming clear
to more and more people that homosexuals are capable of loving devotion
and self-giving in their personal relationships, including their sexual
relationships, and that they, as well as everybody else, should have the
chance to taste the fulfilment that such relationships can bring without
having to battle social hostility and rejection by the churches.
This change in the climate of thought about sex has multiple roots.
Since Freud, much public emphasis has been placed on the importance
of sexuality as an element of human personality. Sex is no longer seen
simply as a way of propagating the species, nor as an occasional and
potentially enjoyable necessity, but as an essential and defining aspect of
each person's character, having an all-pervasive influence on human
behaviour and attitudes. A person's sexual history and attitudes are, it is
claimed, important factors in that person's overall health, maturity and
happiness.
There has also been an increasing stress on individual liberty in Western
societies, and this, together with increasingly widespread education, has
encouraged people to think for themselves and find their own values in
sexual as in many other matters. Linked to this has been the rise of the
feminist movement and the gay movement, both of which have stimulated
much new thought about sex and have begun to undermine some more
traditional attitudes. It is not surprising that the advent of voices from
previously largely unheard sections of the community should bring to
224
Sex, sexuality and relationships
light new points of view and call into question earlier certainties; these
latter are often criticized as being, not the will of God or the reflection of
some eternal law, but merely the views of socially dominant heterosexual
males.
Historical, sociological and anthropological research (much used in gay
and feminist literature) has also had its role to play in the change of
atmosphere. In earlier ages, in a culture saturated by Christianity,
Christian attitudes to sex and relationships could seem universal and
changeless, and therefore obvious, because there was little knowledge of
how other, non-Christian, societies functioned. Modern research has made
it clear that non-Christian societies, both ancient and modern, have very
different sexual practices from those sanctioned in Christianity, and have
very different attitudes to sex. This awareness of difference has made
Christian sexual mores less self-evident, more questionable, and has even
led to a relativism which sees Christian sexual ethics merely as one option,
no better and no worse than any other. The work of Foucault has been
particularly important here, with its emphasis on the way in which the
conceptualization of sex and sexuality — the way sex and sexual relation-
ships are conceived and talked about — not only changes with time and
place but is closely linked to the social structures and wider currents of
thought within each society.1
The advent of efficient methods of contraception has meant that the
link between sex and procreation has been, if not broken, at least rendered
more tenuous, so that it is possible to think of having an active
(heterosexual) sex life without having children and the resulting responsi-
bility. For the same reason, to many it no longer seems reasonable to
confine sex within the bounds of marriage. Marriage may have been the
natural place for sex before, when sex resulted in children who needed to
be raised in a stable environment, but if, because of the use of contracep-
tion, there are no children in prospect, then it should be possible to
engage in sexual activity outside marriage, or even outside any stable
relationship. If care is taken to avoid conception, it is argued, casual sex is
no longer the irresponsible activity it once was.
Another important factor is the development of other forms of stable
relationship than marriage. Men and women openly enter into stable long-
term relationships, and have children, without going through any public
ceremony of commitment, either religious or secular, which would make
their relationship into a marriage, and they defend their right to do so.
Again, male and female homosexuals also enter into stable relationships,
more or less openly, in which they claim that sex has an appropriate place,
just as it has in heterosexual relationships.
Christians are on the whole integrated into the societies in which they
live, and so are not immune to changing currents of attitude and belief in
225
Gareth Moore
the wider society, and all the above factors have brought about changes of
thought and practice within the Church as well as outside. Christians of
most churches are happy to practise contraception, and there is increasing
(if still not widespread) acceptance of homosexual partnerships and of non-
marital heterosexual partnerships. This has been accompanied by changes
at an official level. Thus, for example, the Church of England accepted
contraception in the 1930s, and in the 1990s has come to accept the
possibility of virtuous and Christian homosexual relationships.
On the other hand, there are many Christians who view these
developments with horror and see them not as the legitimate adaptation
of Christian teaching to modern conditions in the light of new knowledge,
but as a betrayal of the clear teachings of Scripture and of Christian
tradition, an abandonment of the loving will of God. The official teaching
of the Catholic Church has been among the most steadfast voices in
defence of traditional Christian values in this area, most notably in its
opposition to contraception and homosexuality.2
In such a climate of controversy it is impossible to give a simple
summary of Christian teaching on sex and its place in human relationships.
In addition, the space available is too short to attempt a theological
treatment of the many and varied human sexual practices and the
arguments concerning them deployed by Christians. In what follows I will
try rather to indicate some (and only some) of the questions and problems
involved in any modern Christian discussion of sex. I will concentrate
particularly on the difficulties of maintaining the traditional Christian
approach in general, difficulties posed in large measure by the modern
discoveries referred to above. Whether these difficulties can be met, and
traditional attitudes rationally maintained, is a further question beyond
the scope of this chapter; but that the difficulties are there and must be
addressed seems to me undeniable.
Common to all Christians is a reliance on the Bible. In addition,
Catholics have accorded an important place to natural reason, and
arguments of a more or less philosophical nature have often found a place
in Catholic treatments of sexual ethics. Since God is seen in the Catholic
tradition as the author of human nature, including both human sexuality
and the human capacity to think, natural reflection on sexual behaviour,
even without reference to Scripture, is seen as a legitimate and indeed
important activity. One important form this reasoning has taken has been
to talk in terms of'natural law'. Fidelity to God has been seen as involving
the attempt to remain faithful to the nature that God has created, to the
natural law. This in turn involves investigation into that nature, which is
the concern not of the Bible but of our natural capacities. It is this rational
investigation, notably but not exclusively as expressed in natural law
theory, which according to the Catholic tradition makes Christian ethics
226
Sex, sexuality and relationships
Scripture
227
Gareth Moore
other people's wives (Prov 6:23-29)- In the New, we find Jesus teaching
against men coveting other men's wives (Matt 6:27-29). We also find
Paul describing same-sex passion as a punishment for idolatry (Rom
1:21-27), condemning a case of what seems to be incest (1 Cor 5: If.), and
recommending celibacy but conceding the possibility of marriage for those
who cannot exercise self-control (1 Cor 7:8f).
It used to be possible to construct a Christian sexual ethic to a large
extent by simple appeal to biblical texts. Sexual ethics was largely a
matter of finding out what kinds of sexual activity were permitted by
God, and in what circumstances; and this could be discovered by searching
through Scripture. This would normally, though not exclusively, be done
by a process of elimination, for it was for the most part sexual practices
which were not permissible which tended to be mentioned, with explicit
or implied condemnation. The legal texts of the Old Testament were a
particularly rich field here. Thus, from the sixth commandment one
learned that God forbade adultery (Exod 20:14; Deut 5:18); sexual
intercourse between men was forbidden as an abomination to God (Lev
18:22); and sex with animals was likewise prohibited (Lev 18:23). Incest
too was forbidden (Deut 22:30; Lev 18:6—18). A young woman who
marries must do so as a virgin (Deut 22:13-21). Rape is to be punished
(Deut 22:23—29). From this it appeared that the only circumstances in
which sexual activity with another3 is permissible is in marriage.
Other kinds of text, in both Testaments, reinforced this picture, and in
important respects went further. For example, the story of Sodom and
Gomorrah (Gen 19:1—29) implied a condemnation of homosexual acts, as
did Paul's remarks in Romans l:26f. and 1 Corinthians 6:9- The story of
Tobias and Sarah (Tob 6:9 — 7:18) extolled sexual purity and by
implication condemned lust. The fate of Onan (Gen 38:6—10) seemed to
imply divine condemnation of marital intercourse in which contraception
was used. Jesus himself, in the Sermon on the Mount, forbade not only
adultery but all lustful thoughts (Matt 5:27f).
Thus, by reference to Scripture one easily arrived at many of the tenets
of traditional Christian sexual morality. Sex was for married couples only,
and since Jesus forbade divorce, that meant those united in a lifelong and
indissoluble relationship. Within marriage, sexual activity must be chaste,
and not the result of lust. It must also be open to procreation. This
morality was faithful to the word of God, and therefore expressed the will
of God.
This array of biblical citations (and there are numerous others that
could be mentioned) is impressive, and for many Christians, especially
Protestants, it remains the foundation of sexual morality. In the Catholic
tradition too, while natural reason also has an important place, this
testimony of Scripture is central to sexual ethics. In the past, it seemed
228
Sex, sexuality and relationships
clear that the teaching of God in Scripture was clear and unambiguous,
and to many it still seems so.
229
Gareth Moore
law and the prophets) which makes the way a person wishes to be treated
the criterion for the way that person should treat others; in other words:
'Love your neighbour as yourself.'
This teaching, that love sums up the law, is echoed in other parts of
the New Testament. For example, 'He who loves his neighbour has
fulfilled the law . . . Love does no wrong to a neighbour; therefore love is
the fulfilling of the law' (Rom 13:8, 10); 'The whole law is fulfilled in one
word: You shall love your neighbour as yourself (Gal 5:14); 'If you really
fulfil the royal law according to the scripture — You shall love your
neighbour as yourself- you do well' (Jas 2:8).
The consistency and centrality of this teaching in the New Testament
makes impossible any insistence that scriptural precepts and prohibitions
concerning sex (or any other matter), whether from the Old Testament or
from the New, be followed simply because they are scriptural. What Christians
need to follow is not, for example, a prohibition of incest or of homosexual
acts, or a command to increase and multiply, but the injunction to love.
Whatever concrete commands may be found in Scripture must be
subordinated to this overriding principle.
230
Sex, sexuality and relationships
God, and we can thank Jesus for showing us a higher way, the way of
love, which actually does correspond to the will of God.
A second and opposite possible response is to agree that love is primary,
but to insist that the Bible is the word of God, and that the word of God
is permanent and in important ways changeless. God's word to the
Israelites of the first millennium BC is still God's word to all peoples. The
Bible must therefore always remain the source for all morality, including
sexual morality. Something like this position is the traditional and official
position of the Catholic Church. If biblical injunctions appear to be
against the law of love as preached by Jesus and the New Testament, this
should be taken to show, not that the injunctions should be jettisoned,
but that our grasp of what love demands is inadequate, that God's wisdom
is greater than ours. Though sanctioning homosexual relationships may
appear to be what love of homosexual people demands, further investi-
gation will show that such relationships only make the people in them
unhappy in the end, or endanger the overall well-being of society. There
is thus a deep wisdom in the words of Scripture which justifies our
continued adherence to them.
There are problems with both these approaches. The former can seem
to treat the word of Scripture in too cavalier a fashion. If one can simply
ignore parts of the Bible, this raises the question of the status of Scripture
in the Christian faith. Why consult Scripture at all when seeking guidance
on questions of sexual morality? The principle of love, biblically based
though it is, seems, if erected into the sole criterion for our sexual
behaviour, to render its own source obsolete. Some might accept this
consequence readily, but there is surely a problem of the status of Scripture
here which goes beyond its relevance to sexual ethics. Its whole status as
revelation, as divinely inspired, and as the word of God is put in question.
However we interpret the Bible, one might ask, does not Scripture need
to retain a privileged status of some kind within Christianity if the latter
is to be true to itself and to God?
The second, traditionalist approach, on the other hand, makes empirical
claims which are apparently untrue. To continue using the same example,
it is not clear that careful investigation does show that homosexuals in
stable sexual relationships are any worse off than they would be in non-
sexual relationships or alone; anecdotal evidence suggests the contrary.
There is some evidence that young homosexuals tend to be less happy
than their heterosexual counterparts, and this is readily understandable in
the light of the general negative image of homosexuals in society; but
there is none that suggests sexual activity within a stable partnership
tends to make them any unhappier. Further, it is difficult to think of any
plausible causal link between sexual activity in that context and a tendency
to unhappiness. Still less does it appear that the existence of such
231
Gareth Moore
232
Sex, sexuality and relationships
Non-scriptural arguments
233
Gareth Moore
we do not live in such a world. In our world, opinions are sharply divided
on contraception, as on many other issues in sexual ethics. In such a world,
the function of argument must be to convince those who doubt or who
hold a contrary opinion. A bad argument does not achieve its end; the use
of a bad argument further gives the impression that a good argument is
not available, and that those who hold the opinion in support of which
the argument is adduced are merely confused thinkers - or worse, bigots
— whose opinions cannot be rationally justified and are more likely than
not to be false.
Natural law
The natural law tradition takes its rise from Hellenistic thought, especially
Stoicism. There are two basic elements which converge in the Stoic
attitude to sex. First, for many Hellenistic thinkers the world was a
purposeful place. It was a harmonious whole in which each element
fulfilled its purpose, and each element was there so as to fulfil its natural
purpose. Proper human action was action which respected and was in
harmony with the purposes to be found in nature; it also respected the
natural purposes of human organs. The purpose of sexual activity was
clearly reproduction, since not only did normal sexual intercourse often
result in conception, but it was only by reference to reproduction that the
existence of the sexual organs could be understood at all — it is only
because people reproduce sexually that they have sexual organs in the
first place. It followed that any sexual activity which was not of a kind
such as to allow reproduction did not follow nature's purpose. So, for
instance, all masturbation, all homosexual activity and all heterosexual
intercourse where contraception was employed were against nature, and
therefore bad.
Second, if somebody did not engage in sexual activity in order to have
children, the alternative was that they were doing it for pleasure. There
was a suspicion of pleasure in the Hellenistic world, and not only among
the Stoics. To do anything simply for the sake of pleasure was, in much
Greek thought, unworthy and dangerous, and it also subverted the natural
order of things. It meant that a man (and it was usually specifically men
rather than women who were envisaged) allowed himself to be led by his
desire rather than by reason. This was contrary to nature since according
to nature it was reason, which was the distinctive mark of the human,
that should determine a man's behaviour. To act for pleasure was to act in
a less than human way. Since sex was an area where pleasure and desire
ruled, it was suspect in itself, and could only be justified by its
reproductive purpose.
It was roughly this schema that was adopted into Christianity and was
234
Sex, sexuality and relationships
235
Gareth Moore
like an animal, and also very different from blindly obeying laws simply
because they are laws.
Of course, rational thinking can be done in different ways, and it is
true that when Aquinas thinks about sexual acts, he often starts from
nature in the sense of what he takes to be biological or other empirical
facts about human beings and other animals, 'natural law' in the first
sense. But the two conceptions of natural law are not necessarily bound
together in this way. Indeed, Aquinas himself sometimes takes a different,
much more promising approach. He says that God, the author of human
nature, desires human happiness. Therefore God made human nature in
such a way as to promote human happiness. To act in accord with nature
is therefore to promote one's happiness, while to act against it is to court
unhappiness.19 This approach puts human flourishing squarely at the
centre of natural law; what is natural, what is in accordance with the
proper end of human beings, and therefore good, is what promotes well-
being and happiness, while what is unnatural, and therefore bad, what is
contrary to our true end, is what is deleterious and works against
happiness. On this account, the central question of natural law is not
'What do animals do?' or even 'What is the purpose of this or that human
organ?' but 'What, given the type of creature we are, makes for human
happiness?'
If we use this conception of natural law, natural law no longer seems to
be something which imprisons people in an impersonal system. It means
simply thinking about human action in such a way that considerations of
human happiness, well-being and flourishing — in short, of what is good
for people — are central. This is a big improvement on that: style of
thought which bases itself simply on the biological functions of organs.20
A very important aspect of this type of natural law thought, and indeed
of all types, is that it is in large measure empirically based. Those who
claimed, for instance, that the sexual organs have a certain function in
nature did so on the basis of what they or others actually observed, or
claimed to observe, about the functioning of these organs. They observed
what people and animals did with them, and what resulted. They may not
always have been good observers; they may have missed certain things,
and their preconceptions may have prevented them from taking due note
of everything they saw. But they were basically making an empirical
claim, which they then incorporated into an argument which led to a
moral conclusion. Part of the cogency of such an argument was that it
rested partly on evidence whose truth was open for all to see. Given
enough observation and scientific knowledge, it was possible to see that
the purpose of the sexual organs was reproduction (or so it seemed to those
who argued in this fashion).
In the same way, to think about what makes for human happiness is to
236
Sex, sexuality and relationships
237
Gareth Moore
238
Sex, sexuality and relationships
239
Gareth Moore
240
Sex, sexuality and relationships
241
Gareth Moore
A man may love his wife deeply, but if he has sexual intercourse with all
and sundry, his sexual activity with his wife cannot be, for him, expressive
of his deep love for her; the activity has become too ordinary. In short, for
an activity to be expressive it must be used selectively. The more
selectively it is used, the more expressive it becomes, while the more
indiscriminately it is used the less expressive it becomes.
Is it possible to argue on this basis that sexual activity should be used
very selectively? It might be possible to argue that the capacity to express
love bodily, through sex, is an important part of human well-being, and
that its loss, through less selective use of sex, is a severe impoverishment.
Those who indulge in sex other than in a context of love, one would have
to say, are — for this reason — less fulfilled and less happy than those who
only use sex for making love. I offer this as a possibility, but I admit I do
not know how such an argument would be made convincing. It involves
an empirical claim about the relative happiness of various classes of people
that would be difficult to substantiate. Even if one could show that
indiscriminate users of sex were less happy than very discriminating ones,
one would also have to show that it is the difference in their sex lives that
accounts for the difference in their happiness. Even if a successful argument
could be generated along these lines, it would tend to show only that
sexual activity is best confined to loving relationships, whether marital,
extramarital or homosexual. While that would satisfy many Christians, it
would be far from supporting the much stronger traditional Christian
claim, that sex should be confined to marriage.
242
Sex, sexuality and relationships
mutual self-giving of husband and wife; and the procreative, the ability to
generate new life. 25 These two meanings, it is claimed, can never be
separated. An act of intercourse must always have the unitive meaning
proper to it, that is to say it must take place in the context of that true
union of persons which is marriage. It must also always, as essentially
procreative, be open to new life. This is the new claim. The question is:
what reason can be given for making it — apart simply from a desire to
reinforce a ban on contraception — and can it be substantiated?
The idea of these two meanings of intercourse is at first sight
implausible. That an act might have a unitive meaning, signifying and
expressing the unity between two people, is readily understandable, but
how can an act have procreative meaning? How can an act signify or
express procreation? Procreation is surely not a possible meaning of an act,
but a possible effect. Talk of the two meanings of intercourse seems to
confuse the realm of significance with that of cause and effect. However,
this is principally a terminological problem. The doctrine does not appear
to depend on the claim that procreation can be a meaning of an act. If a
more neutral word, such as 'aspect', is used, the problem disappears. One
could then rephrase by saying that an act of intercourse has an expressive,
unitive aspect and a causal, procreative aspect, and that these two are
inseparable, in the sense that it is never legitimate to perform an act of
intercourse where one of these two aspects is deliberately suppressed.
But there still remains the problem of showing why we should believe
this, that intercourse has these two aspects, and that they are indeed
inseparable. That an act of intercourse can have these two aspects is clear:
two people can make love in a way that expresses the deep love that unites
them, and this can result in the birth of a child. But it is a much stronger
claim to say that these two aspects cannot be legitimately deliberately
separated.
It is not an implausible idea that a human act can have two such aspects
which are closely united. For example, suppose I punch you on the nose.
This is not a friendly thing to do. You will gather from it that I do not
like you. It is an expression of my hostility towards you. My act has an
expressive aspect. But it will also cause you pain. This is the physical
effect of my knuckles coming into violent contact with your nose. My act,
then, also has a causal aspect. But the two aspects are closely related. The
reason why my act has a hostile significance is that it will, if successfully
accomplished, hurt you. That is why I do it. It is the desire to produce
the painful effect that makes my act hostile. I can of course throw a punch
at you without hurting you: I can miss, or you can be wearing adequate
facial protection. I can also hurt you without intending to, by waving my
fists around carelessly and accidentally striking your nose. But I cannot
deliberately separate these two aspects of the act. I cannot throw a punch
243
Gareth Moore
244
Sex, sexuality and relationships
Conclusion
Notes
1 See Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality, vols 1-3 (Harmondsworth: Penguin,
1979-86).
2 See, for example, Pope Paul VFs encyclical Humanae Vitae (London: The Catholic
Truth Society, 1968); the document of the Congregation for the Doctrine of the
Faith published in English as Letter to the Bishops of the Catholic Church on the
Pastoral Care of Homosexual Persons (London: Catholic Truth Society, 1986); and
the same body's A Declaration on Certain Questions Concerning Sexual Ethics (London:
Catholic Truth Society, 1975).
245
Gareth Moore
246
Sex, sexuality and relationships
woman would like to have a child only with a partner whom they sincerely
esteem. The readiness of a man and a woman to unite together in the sexual act
is therefore a sign of their mutual esteem . . . Sexual acts between two persons
of the same sex however are never apt to procreate offspring. Therefore they can
also not be the expression of a love and esteem which is based on the possibility
to give life to a child. The precondition is missing which imparts to the sexual
act the quality of a sign of love. (Christian Ethics, vol.2 [Alcester and Dublin:
C. Goodliffe Neale, 1978}, p. 435)
This is unconvincing for a number of reasons, not the least of which is that it
relies on a simple logical mistake. Even if it were true that everybody would like
to have a child only with a partner they sincerely esteem, that does not imply that
you do not sincerely esteem somebody if you cannot, or even do not want to, have
a child with them. Even if love were a condition for wanting to have a child, that
would not make wanting to have a child a condition for love. Even if it were true
that only if somebody is a Scot does he like haggis, it would not follow that
somebody was a Scot only if he liked haggis.
For a more recent attempt, see Germain Grisez, Living a Christian Life. The Way
of the Lord Jesus, vol. 2 (Quincy, IL: Franciscan Press, 1993), ch. 9, esp. pp. 634-6.
Grisez's argument is too long to detail here, but it seems to me weak at many
points, in particular that it depends on Grisez's highly suspect notion of marriage
as 'one-flesh unity'. However, readers should, as in all cases, judge for themselves.
Selected bibliography
Lisa Cahill, Sex, Gender and Christian Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1996). A general survey utilizing feminist insights.
L. William Countryman, Dirt, Greed and Sex: Sexual Ethics in the New Testament and
Their Implications for Today (London: SCM, 1989)- Interesting insights into biblical
understandings of sexual relations.
Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality, vols 1—3 (Harmondsworth: Penguin,
1979—86). Essential reading.
Gareth Moore, The Body in Context: Sex and Catholicism (London: SCM, 1992). A more
thorough treatment of some of the questions raised in this chapter.
John T. Noonan, Jr, Contraception: A History of Its Treatment by the Catholic Theologians
and Canonists (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986). Much wider in
scope than its title suggests. Gives important information on traditional Christian
thought on sex in general.
Adrian Thatcher, Liberating Sex: A Christian Sexual Theology (London: SPCK, 1993).
An interesting modern Anglican view.
247
17
Divorce and remarriage
Kevin T. Kelly
In the USA today four out of ten marriages can be expected to end in
divorce. This tragic phenomenon is equally evident in Britain and the rest
of Europe. Moreover, it is not just the couples themselves who are involved
in a divorce. In the United States the lives of one out of every two children
is affected by the human tragedy of divorce. These figures need to be
transposed into the human suffering involved. Part of the tragic evil of
divorce is the terrible pain people, who once loved each other, now inflict
on each other, often unconsciously and unintentionally. It is hard to
imagine a deeper wounding of one's sense of self-esteem than to be told
by someone, who once publicly declared they could not live without you,
that now they cannot bear living with you! A relationship which it was
hoped would bring love, affirmation and healing ends up causing injury,
self-doubt and even, in some cases, mutual hostility and hatred.
The words 'plague on society', used in The Catechism of the Catholic
Church (2385), are very appropriate, even though they would be better
applied to marriage breakdown rather than to divorce. Divorce is simply a
social damage-limitation procedure for dealing with marital breakdown,
once it has become clear that reconciliation is no longer possible and
continued cohabitation would be destructive, certainly for the couple
themselves and possibly for their children too. In no way is divorce a
panacea for all the suffering caused by the breakdown of a marriage. It
operates on a different plane to the painful memories of the daily hurts
and wounds involved in the gradual disintegration of the couple's love for
each other. Sometimes it can even add to their pain when the finality of a
divorce only serves to consolidate the erosion of self-esteem of one or both
248
Divorce and remarriage
249
Kevin T. Kelly
250
Divorce and remarriage
251
Kevin T. Kelly
not imply any condemnation of those who have been through the
traumatic experience of the disintegration of their marriage. On the other
hand, personal sin, even grave personal sin in some cases, may be a factor
which contributes to the breakdown of some marriages. The adoption of a
'no fault' procedure in divorce law does not imply theologically that
marriage breakdown is always without sin. All human relationships are
affected by sin. The breakdown of a marriage relationship is no exception.
Hence, there is the same need for conversion and forgiveness as m the rest
of life. However, to acknowledge that sin can play a part in the breakdown
of a marriage is very different to saying that sin is usually the cause of a
marriage breakdown. On occasion it may be. It is just as likely, however,
that marriages fail through human incapacity to build a lasting relation-
ship despite the best of intentions, rather than through human wickedness
on the part of one or both partners.
Christians have always had to face the pastoral problem of marriage
breakdown, though never before in such numbers. Moreover, in previous
ages marriage was seen predominantly as a contract with strong patriarchal
overtones. The bride was transferred from the authority of her father and
his family to that of her husband and his family. Continuing the husband's
lineage through male offspring and guaranteeing inheritance within the
legitimate family line were key factors in such a transaction. With such
priorities the growth of a deep multi-dimensional personal relationship
did not figure largely in a marriage. The 'master' role of the husband and
the 'mother/housekeeper' role of the wife were the main consideration.
Consequently, the reasons why marriages broke down tended to focus on
alleged deficiencies on the part of the wife — her failure to produce a male
heir, her insubordination, her deficiencies in supervising the household,
suspicions about her fidelity etc.
Against such a background the absolute prohibition of divorce by Jesus
was truly good news for women. It challenged men to respect the personal
dignity of their wives and not to reject them like a piece of unsatisfactory
merchandise. Most contemporary scripture scholars hold that the radical
teaching of Jesus on divorce needs to be interpreted as gospel rather than
law. His absolute prohibition of divorce is more subversive and inspi-
rational than law can be. He is challenging the whole mind-set described
above which fails to appreciate the meaning of marriage in the mind of
the Creator and which reduces it to a social device to ensure property
rights and legitimacy of lineage and is prepared to accept divorce as a
legal corrective measure when things go wrong. Among his Jewish hearers,
these strong words of Jesus must have been particularly disturbing to men
and powerfully encouraging to women.
Scholars seem to agree that the exceptions allowing divorce found in
Matthew and Paul reflect the way the early Christian communities tried
252
Divorce and remarriage
253
Kevin T. Kelly
these exegetical findings should bear on church life and practice today.
(Kelly, pp. 226-7)
One question which has exercised Christian minds from the earliest days
has been the status of those whose marriages have broken down. Are they
still married or are they now free to embark upon a second marriage? This
question continues to be hotly debated within the Christian Churches
even today. One of the most imaginative theological contributions to this
debate is found in the Church of England Marriage Commission's 1978
report Marriage and the Church's Task. While it recognized that the
marriage commitment is 'unconditional', it interpreted the Church's task
as being one of facing the challenge of crafting 'a discipline which holds
before those who are married, and those about to marry, the challenge of
unconditional love, while offering to those who have failed in their
marriage the possibility of a new beginning' (n. 266). The marriage 'bond'
is subjected to careful scrutiny. The report argues that it is the 'personal
bond' based on 'mutual love' which unifies the various dimensions of the
marriage bond (n. 95). This personal bond can even be said to have an
'ontological character':
The marriage bond unites two flesh-blood-and-spirit persons. It makes
them the persons that they are. It binds them together, not in any
casual or peripheral fashion, but at the very centre of their being. They
become the persons they are through their relationship to each other.
Each might say to the other: 'I am I and I am you; together you and I
are we'. Since the marriage bond is in this way a bond of personal being,
it is appropriate to speak of it as having an 'ontological' character,
(n. 96)
In the eyes of the Commission, once a couple reach this level of oneness
they have created a bond between them 'which, as a matter of fact,
nothing can dissolve' (97). However, not every marriage reaches that level
of oneness. Marriage relationships often break down, as current statistics
show. The Commission interpreted such tragedies as failures in the growth
process of personal commitment in marriage. Although the commitment
is made when the marriage comes into being through their exchange of
vows — it is 'grounded in promise and obligation' — it still remains part of
the 'continuing process' of 'the making of the marriage' (n. 99). Tragically
that process can break down irretrievably with the result that the couple
fail to achieve the unbreakable character of their marriage bond. When
this occurs, God's will for this marriage is thwarted by 'human failure and
254
Divorce and remarriage
sin' even though this does not necessarily imply personal guilt on the part
of the couple themselves:
There is something radically wrong when a marriage does break down.
Marriages ought to be indissoluble! However, most of us reject the
doctrine that marriages cannot by definition be dissolved. It is only too
possible for men and women in particular cases to break the bond which
God, in principle and in general, wills to be unbreakable, and to put
asunder what God, in his original purpose, has joined together. Therein
lies the measure of human failure and sin. (n. 100)
For this approach, therefore, when the human bond has broken down
irretrievably, the marriage is no longer in existence and the two partners
are, in principle, free to embark on another union.
Although the theology and understanding undergirding it is very
different, in practice this approach is very similar to that which has been
developed in Eastern Christianity over the centuries. The Eastern tradition
and Orthodox Churches today believe that a marriage can 'die'. Such a
death is seen as tragic, but those who are left alone as a result of it can
still trust in the loving care of God, the benevolent guardian of the
Christian household (oikonomos), and may still find salvific life in the loving
union of a second marriage, even though they might be entering it
conscious of their need for healing and forgiveness as a result of their
previous failed marriage. Bernard Raring suggests that the Roman
Catholic Church might be enriched by a deeper understanding of the
Eastern tradition of 'economy' and its application to remarriage after
divorce (see Bibliography).
The theology and practice of the Latin Church, carried over in the
tradition of the Roman Catholic Church, after an uneven pastoral practice
in the early centuries has gradually hardened into a more ontological
interpretation of the bond of marriage. This bond is constituted by the
marriage covenant itself and is brought into existence by the couple's
mutual consent. Its natural indissolubility becomes absolute in the case of
a sacramental marriage since the bond now signifies the unbreakable bond
between Christ and the Church. Theoretically this interpretation leaves no
room for manoeuvre once the marriage bond has come into existence.
However, it is significant that the Council of Trent's formulation of this
seemingly absolute teaching was worded very carefully so as not to give
the impression that the Council Fathers were rejecting the more benign
Eastern Orthodox practice as incompatible with Christian faith. Moreover,
some aspects of the Roman Catholic Church's own practice are not fully
consistent with this interpretation. It is claimed, for instance, that the
Pope has the power, as the vicar of Christ on earth, to dissolve the
naturally indissoluble ontological bond in the case of marriages of the
255
Kevin T. Kelly
256
Divorce and remarriage
accounted for 94 per cent of annulments in the first instance in 1985 (cf.
Provost, pp. 600-1). Although difference of culture is certainly a partial
explanation, such a lack of functioning tribunals means that there is little
possibility of the development of a more culturally adapted tribunal
system for these countries.
The differences between the Roman Catholic position and that of the
Anglican Communion were explored in the ARCIC II Agreed Statement,
Life in Christ: Morals, Communion and the Church (1994). ARCIC was able
to conclude that 'Anglicans and Roman Catholics are at one in their
understanding of the nature and meaning of marriage' (n. 77) despite the
acknowledgement that some Anglicans believe that 'where a relationship
of mutual love and trust has clearly ceased to exist, and there is no
practical possibility of remaking it, the bond itself has also ceased to exist'
(n. 75). One can understand, therefore, why the final section of this part
of their Agreed Statement reads:
We agree that marriage is sacramental, although we do not fully agree
on how, and this affects our sacramental discipline. Thus, Roman
Catholics recognise a special kind of sacramentality in a marriage
between baptised persons, which they do not see in other marriages.
Anglicans, on the other hand, recognise a sacramentality in all valid
marriages. On the level of law and policy, neither the Roman Catholic
nor the Anglican practice regarding divorce is free from real or apparent
anomalies and ambiguities. While, therefore, there are differences
between us concerning marriage after divorce, to isolate those differ-
ences from this context of far-reaching agreement and make them into
an insuperable barrier would be a serious and sorry misrepresentation of
the true situation, (n. 77)
Mark Ellingsen, in his World Council of Churches study The Cutting Edge:
How Churches Speak on Social Issues (1993), adds an interesting gloss to this
point.
Because Orthodox practices converge with Protestantism while its
theological commitments converge with Roman Catholicism, it follows
that the disagreement it has with the Catholic Church in practice is not
theologically related. Consequently, the final conclusion can only be
that disagreements between the Roman Catholic and Protestant tra-
ditions on this matter, despite their distinct theological perspectives,
are not necessarily theologically related, (p. 85, italics in original)
Remembering how the early Christian communities were able to hold in
a kind of dialectical tension commitment to Jesus' absolute prohibition of
divorce and the acceptance of divorce by way of pastoral accommodation
in new situations in the community, it could be argued that all the
257
Kevin T. Kelly
Christian churches are, in their different ways, struggling with the same
dialectical tension. They are trying to give theological expression to the
absolute teaching of Jesus within their wider interpretation of marriage;
and, at the same time, they are to be faithful to the tradition of the early
Christian communities by trying to be pastorally accommodating and
creative in their pastoral care of those whose marriages no longer reflect
the love, peace and justice of God's kingdom.
258
Divorce and remarriage
259
Kevin T. Kelly
260
Divorce and remarriage
the priest does not pronounce any official admission in a formal sense.
(Kelly, p. 113)
To help people in this decision-making process the three bishops offer
their own version of the criteria which, as mentioned earlier, had been put
forward by various moral theologians and canon lawyers both as individ-
uals and as representing professional groupings:
Only an honest accounting can lead to a responsible decision of
conscience. An examination of the following criteria is therefore
indispensable:
• when there is serious failure involved in the collapse of the first
marriage, responsibility for it must be acknowledged and repented;
• it must be convincingly established that a return to the first partner
is really impossible and that with the best will the first marriage
cannot be restored;
• restitution must be made for wrongs committed and injuries done
insofar as this is possible;
• in the first place this restitution includes fulfilment of obligations to
the wife and children of the first marriage (cf. Code of Canon Law,
canon 1071, n.1.3),
• whether or not a partner broke his or her first marriage under great
public attention and possibly even scandal should be taken into
consideration;
• the second marital partnership must have proved itself over a long
period of time to represent a decisive and also publicly recognisable
will to live permanently together and also according to the demands
of marriage as a moral reality;
• whether or not fidelity to the second relationship has become a moral
obligation with regard to the spouse and children should be
examined;
• it ought to be sufficiently clear — though certainly not to any greater
extent than with other Christians — that the partners seek truly to
live according to the Christian faith and with true motives, i.e.
moved by genuinely religious desires, to participate in the sacramen-
tal life of the Church. The same holds true in the children's
upbringing. (Kelly, pp. 111-12)
Because of the high profile of these three bishops, the Congregation of the
Doctrine of the Faith (CDF) felt obliged to intervene and invited the three
bishops to a meeting in Rome. As mentioned above, subsequent to that
meeting, even though the German bishops were not mentioned explicitly,
the CDF sent a letter to all the bishops of the world reminding them of
the current official teaching on divorce and remarriage and insisting that
261
Kevin T. Kelly
262
Divorce and remarriage
263
Kevin T. Kelly
Conclusion
It is evident from what has been written above that doctrinal and pastoral
disagreement about divorce and remarriage exists both between and
within the Christian Churches. Nevertheless, all involved in these dis-
agreements are trying to be faithful to the mind of Christ as evidenced in
his teaching and pastoral practice. The US Catholic biblical scholar John
R. Donahue expresses this beautifully, with particular reference to his own
church, in the closing paragraph of his article referred to earlier:
In a most basic sense the New Testament does sanction what is in fact
church teaching and pastoral practice today. The Church stands in
prophetic opposition to that divorce which destroys that love and life
together which was intended by God for man and woman. At the same
time through its marriage tribunals, through continued reflection on
'the pastoral solution' and through a ministry to the divorced, the
Church is continuing that 'pastoral dimension' of the ministry of Jesus
and the missionary practice of Matthew and Paul. While bearing in its
life the prophetic teaching of Christ, the Church must also present to
the world that Christ who defended the innocent victims of different
forms of oppression and who was ever present to sinners and tax
collectors and whose offer of love was closer to the religiously marginal
than to the pious and just. Any step backwards to a simple 'adamantine
opposition' to divorce without adaptation of this opposition and the
questioning of its application would not be faithful to the New
Testament. (Kelly, p. 228)
Notes
Select bibliography
Timothy Buckley, What Binds Marriage? Roman Catholic Theology in Practice (London:
Geoffrey Chapman, 1997).
Church of England General Synod Marriage Commission, Marriage and the Church's
Task (London: Church Information Office, 1978).
264
Divorce and remarriage
Jack Dommran, Marital Pathology: An Introduction for Doctors. Counsellors and Clergy
(London: Darton, Longman and Todd, 1979).
Bernard Haring, No Way Out? Pastoral Care of the Divorced and Remarried (Slough: St
Paul Publications, 1989).
Kevin T. Kelly, Divorce and Second Marriage: Facing the Challenge (Kansas City, MO:
Sheed & Ward, new and expanded edn, 1996).
Theodore Mackin, Divorce and Remarriage (New York: Paulist Press, 1984).
James H. Provost, 'Intolerable marriage situations: a second decade', The Jurist (1990),
pp. 573-612.
265
18
Truth and lies
Bernard Hoose
The search for truth of one kind or another permeates the whole of our life
in this world. It comes to the fore when one follows courses at school or
university or when one grapples with a book on elementary physics,
anthropology, chemical engineering or Christian ethics, but it is in no
way restricted to such academic pursuits. It is involved in our watching
television news programmes, in the appreciation of art, in courtship, in
marriage, in friendship and in prayer.
In spite of the ubiquity of the search, there is often something of an
elusive quality about truth. This is especially the case when we are dealing
with the deepest senses of the term. In saying this, I am not referring only
to such matters as the truth that is God and the full meaning of that
profoundest of statements emanating from the lips of Jesus in St John's
Gospel: 'I am the Way, the Truth and the Life' (14:6). It is, for instance,
essential that we strive to know ourselves, but the truth that is each of us
is amazingly elusive. We hide a great deal about ouselves behind the
masks that we wear for the various roles we have in life. This is, no doubt,
partly a defence mechanism that prevents other people from getting too
close and hurting us too deeply — the hurt resulting from their reaction to
the discovery of truths about us that they may find unacceptable. Some
years ago, John Powell, quoting an excerpt from an actual conversation,
wrote: 'I am afraid to tell you who I am because, if I tell you who I am,
you may not like who I am, and it's all that I have.'1 The deceit, however,
affects not only those we meet. It affects us too. Strange though it may
seem, we simply do not know all that much about ourselves, and our
persisting in wearing masks is just as much a barrier to us in our quest for
knowledge about ourselves as it is to other people.
266
Truth and lies
What we have said thus far serves to illustrate the tension that we
encounter throughout our lives between the intuition that the expression
of truth is, generally speaking, good, and the seemingly commonsense
insights that a certain amount of secrecy is necessary, that some truth is
better withheld (at least from certain people), and that even the telling of
untruths may sometimes be necessary for the achievement of a greater
good.
St Augustine, however, did not consider the achievement of such a
greater good to be an option that is open to us. He taught that a lie could
never be a morally right act, not even a lie told to save the life of another
person. For him, a lie could be described as having one thing in mind and
saying another, with the intention to deceive.3 On the face of it, this
might seem to be a useful working definition. We would do well, I think,
to examine it in some detail. 4
A first point worth noting is that, if we were to take the word 'saying'
in the above description of a lie to indicate only the faculty of speech (a
combination of lungs, vocal chords, tongue, lips, etc.), we would be
ignoring numerous other ways of lying. We can also lie, for example, in
267
Bernard Hoose
writing, just as we can lie using Morse code, smoke signals, hand signs or
any other kind of body language. A second point worth noting is that a
difference between the facts and the literal meaning of what one says is
not enough to constitute a lie - even if the person doing the communicat-
ing is fully aware of that difference. There must also be an intention to
deceive. If this were not the case, much of our normal use of language
would be morally wrong. Take, for instance, our use of hyperbole. We
would also be acting in a way that is morally wrong in writing novels,
plays, poems and songs if we knew that the words written did not coincide
with known facts. This would be absurd, especially in view of the fact
that fiction can be used very effectively to communicate deep truths, as
can be seen very clearly in Jesus' use of parables in all four gospel accounts.
A third point worth bearing in mind, moreover, is that an intention to
deceive (even when accompanied by success therein) does not necessary
suffice for a lie to occur. If it were sufficient, many of the games we play
would be wrong in their very essence. In many ball games, for example, it
is normal to try to mislead members of the opposing side into thinking
you are going to execute a certain manoeuvre so that they will leave you
free to execute a very different one, and thereby, perhaps, score a goal,
point, try, run or whatever. Such misleading or deceiving of opponents, in
accordance with the rules, is, of course, part of the game. Deceit outside
those rules, as in the case of one who falls to the floor clutching an
uninjured limb whilst falsely claiming that he or she has been injured in
order to gain a penalty point or some other advantage, is, however, a very
different matter. Now it might be claimed that the difference lies in the
fact that this latter case fits Augustine's definition of a lie, whereas the
former case (deceit within the rules) does not. But is it really so? In regard
to such matters as feigning injury in order to gain a penalty point, we
could say that cheats of the kind described have one thing in mind (in the
sense that they know they have not been fouled) and are communicating
something quite different with the intention to deceive. So far so good.
However, it might also be claimed that somebody who acts within the
rules when selling a dummy, or feigning a stroke, also has one thing in
mind (knowledge that no such kick or stroke is to take place) whilst
communicating another with the intention to deceive.
It could be objected that no real deception is involved when people play
within the rules of a game. What might lead one to say this is the fact
that the words 'deceit', 'deception' and 'deceive' tend to have a ring of
moral wrongness about them in modern usage. In other words, we tend to
use those words mostly to describe activity which we have already decided
is morally wrong. In order to avoid misunderstandings, therefore, we
might decide to avoid the use of these words in this context, and use other
words to convey their essential meaning. If we consult a dictionary, we
268
Truth and lies
find that 'to deceive' means 'to lead someone to believe what is false' or 'to
purposely mislead'. This, however, changes nothing in what we have said
about selling dummies, and so forth in ball games. The fact remains that
the person selling the dummy misleads purposely, and surely it is such
misleading that we understand to be referred to in Augustine's definition
- if we take it to apply to more than just the faculty of speech as described
above.
It might seem, therefore, that, if we stay with this definition, we are
led to conclusions that are counter-intuitive, one such being that some of
the most skilful moves in ball games are unethical. Once again we need to
look at the same kind of language problem as that just discussed, but in
reference to a different word. This time the word is 'lie'. Here again we
have a word that tends to be used almost exclusively to refer to morally
wrong activity. Another such word is 'murder', which is used to refer to
acts of unjustified homicide. Using the same kind of formula, we could
say that a 'lie' is an unjustified untruth. We should note, however, that
Augustine's definition of a lie is, in fact, a definition of a purposely
misleading untruth. In other words, he appears to be saying that all
communication of purposely misleading untruths is wrong. Apparently
following his lead, various other Christian teachers over the centuries have
claimed that the telling of such untruths cannot be justified in any
circumstances. For them it matters not what the consequences may be of
taking a course other than that of telling an untruth, although, in certain
circumstances, the consequences could conceivably be disastrous. Thus we
find a deontological norm being promulgated.5
Various arguments have been used to ground this norm. One, resulting
from a particular kind of natural law thinking, is that the faculty of speech
has been given to us by God only to communicate the truth. Even if we
ignored the fact that the faculty of speech could be said to have numerous
purposes (including that of entertaining other people in various ways),
upholders of this argument would still have to show how it can be used in
some extended form to prove the wrongness of falsehoods communicated
by means of smoke signals, Morse code, and so forth. Some years ago,
John Dedek noted a couple of somewhat different arguments used in a
document called the Summa Fratris Alexandra, to show why lying, unlike
theft and homicide, could never be morally right under any circumstances.
(The word 'lying' here, it would seem, means purposely misleading by
communicating an untruth.) The first is that an evil intention is always
involved. This is so because the person telling the untruth intends to
deceive. A counter argument to this might be that analogous arguments
could be used about other kinds of acts of which Christians generally
approve. The second argument found by Dedek is that truth is more noble
than life itself and that no new good could be introduced which could
269
Bernard Hoose
270
Truth and lies
physically absent from the house, and the other that he or she is not at
home to this caller. The person speaking, he goes on to say, restricts the
meaning to one, and the hearer is deceived, not by a lie, but by his own
interpretation of the speaker's words. Davis also refers to strict mental
restriction. This he describes as 'the restriction in the mind of the speaker
of the sense of the words to a particular meaning which no one, however
wise, could understand'. Such behaviour he describes as a lie and says it is
never permissible. For the use of broad mental reservation to be legitimate,
says Davis, there must be a sufficiently good reason for its use, and the
person being addressed must have no right to the information. 9 Some
theologians, both Protestant and Catholic, see no need to resort to such
complications, which, generally speaking, are possible only if the person
to whom the question is addressed is quick-witted. They hold that, if the
questioner has no right to the information, it can be legitimate to tell an
untruth.
Those who take a teleological approach to the subject of truth and lying
would see a difference between justified and unjustified misleading of
another person through the communication of an untruth. They would see
this as analogous to the distinction between justified homicide and
murder. In determining which of the two categories a particular episode
falls into, they would take into account such matters as harm done, or
likely to be done, to the person deceived and/or the person telling the
untruth, and, indeed, anybody else who is likely to be affected. They
would also take into account any reduction in trust that might result. In
the case of the person who cheats in a ball game, it is clear that a reduction
in trust is likely to occur and that harm could result for both the cheat
and members of the opposing side. In the case of selling a dummy within
the rules of the game, however, no harm should normally result. As for
the case of the assassin, many ideologists would no doubt argue that, in
view of the disastrous consequences likely to ensue upon the telling of the
truth, there is sufficient reason for deceiving the murderer by telling an
untruth. Indeed, they might argue that one should not resort to alterna-
tives (such as maintaining silence) if telling an untruth is likely to be the
most effective means of protecting the intended victim.
Many, perhaps most, Christian ethicists would describe themselves as
neither totally teleologist nor totally deontologist. A present-day scholar
who considers himself to fit into neither camp and yet believes that lying
(by which he presumably means purposely misleading by communicating
an untruth) is always wrong, is Germain Grisez. He sees human goodness
in the fullness of human being. In order to understand what is involved in
being a good person, therefore, we need to find out what are those things
that fulfil humans. These he calls the basic goods, and supplies a list of
them, included in which are: life, health and safety; knowledge and
271
Bernard Hoose
272
Truth and lies
In chapters and articles devoted to the subjects of truth and lies, it seems
customary to analyse cases of conflict such as that of the assassin discussed
above. Another oft-quoted example is the use of lies (or deliberate
untruths) in warfare, a specific example being the ways in which, during
the Second World War, the Allies tried to mislead the Germans about
when and where they would invade mainland Europe. Yet another example
is that of placebos given by doctors to patients who have been led to
believe that they are receiving medicine. As Dietrich Bonhoeffer wrote,
however, restricting the problem of truthful speech to certain cases of
conflict is superficial. Bonhoeffer also believed that 'telling the truth'
means different things in different situations. We need to take into
account the relationships involved in each case. He illustrates this by
taking the example of parents demanding truthfulness of their children.
Bonhoeffer goes on to say that it already emerges from this that telling
the truth means different things in different situations. We need to take
into account in each situation the relevant relationships. We have to ask
whether and in what way a particular person is entitled to demand truthful
speech of other people. 'Speech between parents and children is, in the
nature of the case, different from speech between man and wife, between
273
Bernard Hoose
friends, between teacher and pupil, government and subject, friend and
foe, and in each case the truth which this speech conveys is also different.' 14
In a not entirely different vein, Bernard Haring discusses a case similar
to one mentioned above. During the Nazi period in Germany, employees
of the state went to hospitals and orphanages and asked for lists of children
with certain hereditary diseases. Where such lists were supplied, the
children concerned were sent off to the gas chambers. In many cases, those
who were asked for the lists replied that they had no such children in
their institution. Haring says that, to his mind, they did not lie, although
an analysis of the words alone could reveal a 'false utterance'.
But in the concrete situation, what Hitler's men were really asking
went beyond the words they uttered. Their actual question was, 'How
many children do you have for the gas chambers?' And the only response
to that question could be 'None'. This was truthful communication or
legitimate refusal of communication. Words have their meaning only
within the context, and what, in abstraction, could be called 'lie' or
'false utterance' can be, in the actual situation, the proper response.15
Concluding remarks
It seems clear that there are occasions when it is right to tell a lie, but
most of the time people tell lies when they should not. The temptation
comes suddenly, perhaps to get out of an awkward situation or to
practice some petty fraud or deception, and they succumb. In order to
274
Truth and lies
have the discernment to know when a lie is called for, one needs to be
habitually truthful. 1 6
Notes
1 John Powell, Why Am I Afraid to Tell You Who I Am? (London: Fontana/Collins,
1982), p. 12.
2 See, for instance, Teresa o: Avila, The Interior Castle.
3 See Augustine's De rnendacio (On Lying) and his later work Contra mendaciurn
(Against Lying).
4 Sissela Bok defines a lie ,is 'any intentionally deceptive message which is stated':
Lying: Moral Choice in Public and Private Life (Hassocks: Harvester Press, 1978),
p. 13. Bok sees deception as a larger category, of which lying forms a part. She
does, however, note thai: it is possible to define 'lie' in such a way that it is
identical with deception. Thus, she says, we hear of a person 'living a lie' (p. 14).
5 Deontologists hold that certain acts are always right or always wrong regardless of
consequences. Teleologists, on the other hand, hold that the Tightness or
wrongness of an act depends upon its consequences. Long after Augustine, the
philosopher Immanuel Kant also spoke against lying in all circumstances.
6 John F. Dedek, 'Intrins cally evil acts: an historical study of the mind of St
Thomas', The Thomist 43 (1979), p. 400.
7 Thus Ronald Preston writes: Theologians subsequent to Augustine did not like
to contradict him . . .': Lying' in J. Macquarrie and J. Childress (eds), A Neu:
Dictionary of Christian Ethics (London: SCM Press, 1986), p. 363. John F. Dedek
too is of the opinion that later theologians were generally unwilling to challenge
Augustine's authority regarding this matter: 'Moral absolutes in the predecessors
of St Thomas', Theological Studies 38 (1977), p. 680, and Intrinsically evil acts',
p.412.
8 See note 5.
9 Henry Davis, Moral and Pastoral Theology, vol. II (London: Sheed and Ward,
1946), pp. 413-16.
10 A simply worded presentation of Grisez's basic theory is found in Beyond the Neu'
Morality: The Responsibilities of Freedom (Notre Dame, IN and London: Notre Dame
University Press, 1974), which he co-authored with Russell Shaw. See also his
presentation of it in The Way of The Lord Jesus, vol. 1 (Chicago: Franciscan Herald
Press, 1983).
11 Germain Grisez, The Way of the Lord Jesus, vol. 2 (Quincy, IL: Franciscan Herald
Press, 1993), p. 405.
12 Grisez, The Way of the Lord Jesus, vol. 2, pp. 406-12.
13 Grisez, The Way of the Lord Jesus, vol. 2, p. 407.
14 Dietrich Bonhoeffer, Ethics, ed. Eberhard Bethge (London: Collins, 1966),
pp. 363-72.
15 Bernard Haring, Free and Faithful in Christ, vol. 2 (Slough: St Paul Publications,
1979), p. 48.
16 Ronald Preston, 'Lying' in A Neu1 Dictionary of Christian Ethics, p. 363.
275
Bernard Hoose
Select bibliography
276
Medical ethics
19
Euthanasia
Richard M. Gula
The debate
277
Richard M. Gula
benefits and burdens of being treated, and then to select from alternative
treatments or to refuse treatment altogether. In general, the traditional
Catholic medical-moral principle of the ordinary/extraordinary means
standard supports such practice as the morally proper way to care for the
dying. To refuse treatment which is useless or disproportionately burden-
some (i.e. extraordinary) is the morally appropriate forgoing of treatment.
It is neither euthanasia nor assisted suicide (cf. EV, n. 65).
The debate is about voluntary active euthanasia and physician-assisted
suicide. Voluntary active euthanasia means a deliberate intervention, by
someone other than the person whose life is at stake, directly intended to
end the life of the competent, terminally ill patient who makes a fully
voluntary and persistent request for aid in dying. A common way to think
about euthanasia is to have a physician give a lethal injection to the
patient who wants to die. 'Mercy killing' is commonly used in place of
euthanasia to emphasize that such an act is directly intended as an act of
kindness. But as Pope John Paul II reminds us, 'euthanasia must be called
a false mercy, and indeed a disturbing "perversion" of mercy' (EV, n. 66).
In a physician-assisted suicide, a physician helps to bring on the death
of the patient by providing the means to do it or by giving the necessary
information on how to do it, but the patient performs the lethal act on
himself or herself. The typical procedure of assisted suicide is the patient
taking a lethal dose of poison (by swallowing pills, by taking an injection,
or by inhaling a gas, for example) requested of and then prescribed by the
physician for that purpose. In this case, as in euthanasia, both the
physician and patient play morally responsible roles in bringing about
death. Physician-assisted suicide is not significantly morally different from
euthanasia and so need not be distinguished for purposes of understanding
the moral vision and values at stake in the present debate.
The basic line of argument supporting euthanasia and physician-assisted
suicide can be summarized as follows. On the grounds of respect for
autonomy, human persons should have the right to control their living
and dying, and so they should be able to end their lives when they wish
to terminate needless suffering. Physicians, as agents of the patient's best
interests, should assist either by directly killing the patient or by assisting
the patient in suicide. Euthanasia and assisted suicide are beneficent acts
of relieving human suffering.
The main line of the religious argument against euthanasia and assisted
suicide is as follows. Human persons are stewards of creation and so we
have only limited dominion and thus limited freedom over our lives.
Human life is a 'trust', and not a personal 'possession' over which we can
assume full control. The sanctity of human life is conferred by God and
requires reverence and protection. Taking innocent life is not a human
right, but a grave moral evil. Human suffering, while not a value in itself,
278
Euthanasia
can have meaning when lived in faith and so need not diminish human
dignity.
279
Richard M. Gula
280
Euthanasia
good as more important than the good of any one individual. But as long
as we continue to envision society as 'a mass of individuals placed side by
side, but without any mutual bonds' (EV, n. 20), then we will continue to
miss our responsibility for the common good. A commitment to the
common good forces us to ask whether there are some things which we
want for ourselves but which we ought not to pursue so that the good of
the whole might better be served. To seek the common good, then, is to
seek those actions and policies that would contribute to the total well-
being of persons and the community.
Our responsibility for the common good has implications for the way
we analyse euthanasia. One is that we must move away from the individual
perspective which analyses euthanasia as a private issue and move towards
the societal perspective which analyses it as a social one. Daniel Callahan
has argued along these lines to claim that permitting euthanasia would be
'self-determination run amok'. 7 It cannot properly be classified, he claims,
as a private matter of self-determination or as an autonomous act of
managing one's private affairs. Euthanasia is a social decision. It involves
the one to be killed as well as the one doing the killing, and it requires a
complying society to make it acceptable. Therefore, euthanasia must be
assessed for its social impact on caring for the dying and on our general
attitude toward life. Autonomy must be understood within the limits of
the social responsibilities for the common good. One possible impact of
introducing euthanasia as a policy is that it will only fuel the fires of a
'culture of death' by negatively influencing social standards of acceptable
life. The vulnerable, those with serious dementia or depression who cannot
speak for themselves or defend their values, may be especially at risk of
being killed. Overall, the practice of euthanasia threatens to weaken the
general prohibition against killing in society and so we end up valuing
life less.
Euthanasia perpetuates the illusion that we can control everything, that
we can be masters of nature and of death. By drawing on its religious
beliefs about God's sovereignty and the limited scope of responsible
stewardship for life, as well as its social ethical tradition of advocating for
the common good, the Catholic tradition recognizes limits to autonomy
and so challenges its support for euthanasia.
281
Richard M. Gula
282
Euthanasia
innocent human life as 'always morally evil and can never be licit either as
an end in itself or as a means to a good end' (EV, n. 57).
The divine law prohibiting killing is found in the fifth commandment.
The significance of appealing to this commandment in making a case
against euthanasia is that it protects the bonds of being a covenantal
community by prohibiting the arbitrary taking of life by an individual,
private decision, without community sanction. On the positive side of
this commandment to protect human life is the 'requirement to show
reverence and love for every person and the life of every person' (EV,
nn. 41, 54).
The distinction between killing and allowing to die finds further
support from a different angle in Daniel Callahan's argument against
euthanasia. 12 Callahan defends the distinction by appealing to three
different perspectives on nature and human action: metaphysical, moral,
and medical. The metaphysical perspective is based on a real difference
between us and the external world, which has its own causal dynamism.
As a result, we cannot have unlimited control over everything. To deny
the distinction between killing and allowing to die concedes more power
to human intervention than we actually have. The limitations of the body
are ultimately beyond final human control. The moral perspective draws a
line between physical causality and human responsibility. The line
separates deaths caused by impersonal forces (the disease causes death) for
which no one can be held responsible, and deaths caused by human action
(a lethal injection causes death) for which someone can be held morally
culpable. The medical perspective underscores the social purpose of the
distinction. It protects the role of physicians as the ones who use their
knowledge of the body and diseases to cure or comfort patients rather than
to kill them. Physicians' power over life should be limited to curing and
comforting. To extend their power to killing would violate what it means
to be a physician.
These various perspectives on the distinction between killing and
allowing to die are momentous for the euthanasia debate. If there is no
moral distinction between killing and allowing to die, then every decision
to withhold or withdraw futile or overly burdensome treatment can be
construed as direct killing. If that were so, then we have greased the slide
toward a general policy of euthanasia. Those who hold to the distinction
under all circumstances oppose any policy on euthanasia. Even those who
admit that the distinction does not hold under all circumstances, and so
concede a qualified acceptance of an 'exceptional-case' euthanasia under
certain conditions, do not have to conclude that justifying one act of
euthanasia leads to justiiying a social policy for the general practice of
euthanasia. As James Childress argues, 'Whatever is said about particular
acts of euthanasia, there are strong reasons to oppose a rule or practice of
283
Richard M. Gula
Beneficence
Closely following the argument from autonomy and the moral difference
between killing and allowing to die is the argument from the desire to
relieve the patient of suffering. This brings us within the scope of
beneficence which includes the duty to help others in need and to avoid
harm.
Three dimensions of the scope of beneficence have played a prominent
role in the euthanasia debate: the 'character' of medicine as a profession;
the 'suffering' that is to be relieved; and the 'mercy' that is to be shown
the suffering/dying.
That we cannot reach a moral consensus on euthanasia reflects disagree-
ment on the role of the physician and the very aim of medicine. The
euthanasia debate raises the question whether killing patients is the
physician's business and so fits within the aim of medicine. Dr Timothy
Quill has become a prominent spokesman challenging the wisdom and
tradition that 'Doctors must not kill'. His argument makes clear that
physicians can use their medical skills not only to treat the medical needs
of patients, but also to satisfy their value of life and their desire to live in
a particular way. His justification takes him beyond the physician's
traditional role of using specialized knowledge and skill to treat medical
needs. It reaches into the realm of judging what kind of life is worth
living.14
Opponents to physicians becoming killers argue on the basis of the
traditional aim of medicine and the responsibilities proper to the physi-
cian's social role. Albert Jonsen, for example, has argued that 'killing a
patient' has nothing to do with the social expectations and responsibilities
attached to the physician's role 'to use scientific knowledge and clinical
experience in making decisions and advising patients about the prevention,
diagnosis, and treatment of disease and the maintenance of health'.15
Similarly, Leon Kass argues that the role of the physician is defined by the
goal of medicine - to benefit the wholeness of one who is sick. For him
the physician-euthanizer is self-contradictory. Intentionally killing the
patient does not fit within the physician's aim to promote healing and
wholeness.16
Daniel Callahan also argues that physicians who euthanize or assist in
suicide have moved beyond medicine's proper realm of promoting and
preserving health and into the metaphysical realm of determining the
value of life and what kind of lives are worth living. This broader realm of
what makes for general human happiness is a matter of religion or
284
Euthanasia
285
Richard M. Gula
teaches that suffering, while not a value in itself but an experience of evil,
can be transformed.19 The story of the life—death—resurrection of Jesus
tells us that the tragedy of suffering, dying and death cannot, and will
not, be stronger than God's love. God's love, revealed in the resurrection
of Jesus, gives us the courage to enter into suffering and death knowing
that life ultimately triumphs. If, through suffering, the sufferer is brought
nearer to God in Christ, then that person may bear it courageously because
of the comfort of the spiritual experience it offers. The bonding with
Christ is the means for managing the suffering well (EV, n. 67).
The scope of beneficence is ultimately about mercy, that is, about how
we fulfil the demands of covenantal fidelity that we owe one another.
What kind of mercy towards the dying fits the commitment first to be
faithful and then to be healing whenever possible? While it may be
inappropriate to speak of killing as healing, may it yet be compatible with
mercy towards those who are dying in pain and find life empty, oppressive,
and meaningless? Those who argue in support of euthanasia think so.
But our biblical witness of mercy and compassion points us in a
different direction. In the Bible, mercy and compassion represent the way
that God maintains covenantal fidelity with the chosen people. God's
mercy is the fulfilment of the covenantal commitment to be with and for
the chosen people in all circumstances. Mercy and compassion are the
ways that God, who had covenanted with Israel, continues to love her,
provides for her, and protects her from harm. In the life of Jesus, mercy
and compassion led him to do works which restored the broken to
wholeness. Out of mercy and compassion, he healed the blind, taught the
ignorant, raised the dead, and fed the hungry. 20
The biblical witness, then, shows us that deep personal relationships lie
at the heart of mercy. What from the biblical view is a virtue of fidelity,
love and care becomes for advocates of euthanasia a basis for killing. For
Pope John Paul II, 'True "compassion" leads to sharing another's pain; it
does not kill the person whose suffering we cannot bear' (EV, n. 66).
Resorting to euthanasia is failing to embody the trust that sustains life
and the commitment to be companions to one another, especially those
who are helpless or those who are unable to contribute to the community.
The refusal to participate in euthanasia is a reminder and an encourage-
ment to remain committed to one another as partners who sustain each
other through trust, love and care.
Character, suffering and mercy are three aspects of the scope of
beneficence which are at issue in the euthanasia debate. The Catholic
religious and moral tradition supports the traditional moral centre of
medicine which finds killing incompatible with the commitment to heal.
Faith informed by the biblical stories of covenant and the life-
death—resurrection of Jesus provides a special context of meaning within
286
Euthanasia
A response
287
Richard M. Gula
Notes
1 See, for example, James Rachels, The End of Life: Euthanasia and Morality (New
York: Oxford University Press, 1986).
2 Derek Humphry, 'The case for rational suicide', Euthanasia Review 1 (Fall 1986),
pp. 172-5; Helga Kushe, 'Voluntary euthanasia and the doctor', Free Inquiry 89
(Winter 1988), 17-19.
3 Jack Kevorkian, Free Inquiry 92 (1991), p. 14.
4 For a critical review of this concept, see Leon Kass, 'Is there a right to die?',
Hastings Center Report 23 (January-February 1993), pp. 34-43.
5 Richard J. Clifford and Roland E. Murphy, 'Genesis' in Raymond E. Brown,
Joseph A. Fitzmyer and Roland E. Murphy (eds), The New Jerome Biblical
Commentary (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1990), p. 12.
6 Charles Dougherty, 'The common good, terminal illness, and euthanasia', Issues in
Law and Medicine 9 (1993), pp. 151-66.
288
Euthanasia
Select bibliography
289
20
Ethical problems arising from new
reproductive techniques
Joyce Poole
The science of therapeutics could be said to have begun in 1936 when one
of a group of drugs later to be known as the sulphonamides was used
successfully to treat a patient with septicaemia. The pharmaceutical
company May and Baker had, among others, been working on these
compounds for many years and the first to be used clinically entered
medical history as 'M and B 693', the number indicating how many had
been tried before one was found that would attack the bacteria without
harming the patient.
Until then the treatment of infections had been palliative — nourishing
food and fluid with careful nursing to encourage the body's natural
defences. These were often inadequate, and bacterial infections such as
pneumonia were major killers of young and old. With the advent of a
drug that actually killed the infecting organism came the need for clinical
trials to test its effectiveness against a range of bacteria and, importantly,
for any harmful side-effects. Medicine had entered the era of experiment
in which research became inseparable from its clinical application.
The next few decades brought astonishing therapeutic progress. Penicil-
lin and other antibiotics followed the sulphonamides. Advances in
anaesthesia and technology brought the 'life support system', and with it
the possibility of open heart surgery and organ transplantation. Some of
the new drugs and vaccines proved to have unforeseen side-effects,
however, and the patient's survival time after the first organ transplants
was disappointingly low. It was inevitable that such dramatic advances
would bring new medical dilemmas and some general disquiet among the
public. If something could be done, did it necessarily follow that it should
be done?
The wider ethical issues surrounding experimentation on human
290
New reproductive techniques
There is no doubt that with the appalling experiments carried out in the
Nazi death camps, medical research had sunk to unplumbed depths.
Horror at what went on in these camps still makes many people wary of
any research on human subjects, whether or not any useful knowledge
might be obtained from it
Organ transplantation was viewed at first with some suspicion by the
Christian churches who feared that doctors might be 'playing God' and
interfering too much with nature. Some Catholic commentators such as
Pope Pius XII were uneasy about the 'mutilation' of live kidney donors
but others concluded that donation of a kidney must be seen in its totality
as an act of unselfish generosity. As for 'playing God' it could be said that
the whole aim of medical research and treatment, whether by drugs,
vaccines or surgery, is 'interfering with nature' in that it aims to keep
alive people who might otherwise die.
The rate of advance in medical and surgical therapeutics made it
urgently necessary that research programmes should be regulated and
codified at an international level. A basic rule of medical practice dating
from the time of Hippocrates, Primmn non nocere — above all, do no harm —
could no longer be strictly applied in an age when potentially effective
treatment could ultimately be assessed only by trying it out on human
subjects.
Clinical trials
Trials can be divided into two main categories each with a different ethical
content.
A 'therapeutic trial' involves persons who are already ill. It compares
current therapy (if it exists) with new so that there is a possibility of direct
benefit to the patient concerned. The test may be of a new drug, or of
different treatments for breast cancer which might be treated by surgery,
radiotherapy or by a combination of these. To make valid statistical
conclusions large numbers of patients have to be randomly selected from
those willing to take part in the trials and those who, with hindsight, fall
into the most or least successful groups do so by chance.
In 'non-therapeutic' trials the research aspect is paramount and volun-
291
Joyce Poole
292
New reproductive techniques
293
Joyce Poole
The world was astounded. It was widely reported that the Patriarch of
Venice, later that year to become Pope John Paul I, expressed delight at
the news. The promise of new hope for infertile couples was greeted
enthusiastically by other Churches' leaders and by the public at large.
The Catholic position has hardened, however, since then, and it now
stands alone among other mainstream religious groups in condemning
IVF outright on the grounds that to separate the marital act from the
begetting of a child is an unlawful violation of a divinely established
single act of procreation. This rules out IVF even in the 'simple case' of
fertilizing a single ovum with the father's sperm and implanting it
immediately in the mother's womb. The Catholic objection can be
logically related, of course, to an extreme interpretation of the teaching of
Humanae Vitae ten years earlier, forbidding the separation of conception
from the act of coitus.
In the UK, the Abortion Act of 1967 had already provoked intense
debate among theologians, philosophers and scientists regarding the moral
absolute propounded by the magisterium of the Catholic Church that
from the moment of conception a fertilized ovum has the rights of a
human person. The development of IVF, which had of necessity been
preceded by embryo experiment and disposal, only added fuel to a fire
that was already raging.
Historically, most religious scholars of the mainstream Christian,
Islamic and Judaic schools have subscribed to the philosophic tradition
which relates animation or 'ensoulment' of the embryo—foetus to its
morphological development. The Arab scholars of the ninth and tenth
centuries reinforced what was known of the writings of Aristotle and the
Greeks and the physician-philosopher Avicenna stated the matter simply
— 'a soul comes into existence when a body suitable for it comes into
existence'. Rabbinic teaching varied but the consensus leaned towards
according increasing status to the foetus after the third month, when it
had become recognizably human."
The dualist theories of Plato identified 'soul' as the essential immaterial
part of a human being, independent of, and only temporarily united with
its body. In later Christian understanding of the soul, the body came to
be seen almost as an encumbrance. The concept persists in the teaching
and language of most religions so that it is not surprising that the idea of
a soul 'entering' the foetus at a particular moment or ascending from the
body at death is common to so many cultures.
Aristotle rejected Platonic dualism and it was the moral reasoning
wrought by St Thomas Aquinas out of Aristotle that Catholic teaching
finally endorsed. The latter's theory of hylomorphism — the essential
coexistence of matter and form — led Aquinas to distinguish between the
unanimated and animated foetus.3 In the natural way of generation, he
294
New reproductive techniques
held, the progression is from the imperfect to the perfect; hence in the
generation of man comes first a living thing, then the animal, and finally
man. St Augustine had earlier drawn a distinction between the formed
foetus already endowed with an immortal soul and a 'tissue' or living
entity on the way to becoming a human person, and while the Church
strenuously condemned abortion, the secular and canonical penalties were
graded according to the development of the foetus.
Steptoe and Edwards reported that they were overawed at the sight of
the cleaving embryo they had helped to create in a dish. For the first time
it had been possible to observe from hour to hour the progressive stages of
fertilization, not a 'moment' but a complex process taking 48 hours or
more. They and their colleagues regarded their work as revealing the art
and plan of a grand designer but did not consider that they were
experimenting upon actual children. 4
The rapid and indeed alarming pace of development after 1978 led to
the establishment in the UK of a Departmental Committee of Enquiry
into Human Fertilisation and Embryology chaired by the Oxford philo-
sopher Lady Warnock and published in 1984. Most of the recommenda-
tions of that report were adopted by the British Parliament in the Human
Fertilisation and Embryology Act of 1990.
In the presenting letter to the report which bears her name, Mary
Warnock observed that the issues raised by the enquiry reflect fundamental
moral and often religious questions which have taxed philosophers down
the ages and which the report does not attempt to answer. It concentrated
instead on practical recommendations including the establishment of a
statutory body which would regulate and license national infertility
services and experimentation upon human embryos. However, much
public and theological debate since then has centred on the status of the
human embryo during its first fourteen days, as envisaged by Warnock.
The report itself is reserved over status, holding that the answers to
questions of when human life or personhood begins are complex amalgams
of factual and moral judgements. 3
It accepts that once the process of fertilization has begun there is no
particular stage that is more important than another but selects a limit of
fourteen days for experiment because of the appearance at this time of the
first recognizable feature of the embryo proper — the 'primitive streak'. It
may be added that it is around the fourteenth day that, in nature, so many
fertilized but unimplanted embryos are lost in the ensuing menstrual
period, or, conversely, that a woman will begin to suspect that she has
conceived.
There was naturally some disagreement among members of the War-
nock committee on its recommendations. Three members registered
dissent based on their conclusion first, that special status must be accorded
295
Joyce Poole
Until 1827 when the developing ovum was first seen and recognized it
was believed that the whole genetic inheritance of the offspring was
contained in the male seed. Early microscopists had imagined that they
saw a tiny 'homunculus' in the head of the spermatozoon. The maternal
contribution was thought to be only that of providing the raw materials
and environment necessary for the development of her husband's offspring.
Thus Sarai, Abraham's wife, who had borne him no children, could say to
her husband 'go in to my maid Hagar; it may be that / shall have children
by her'(Gen 16:1-3).
There can be little doubt that ignorance of the human ovum and its
genetic importance has contributed to the inferior status of women
throughout history. Certainly it was not until after the discovery of the
ovum that the equal and complementary roles of the male and female
gametes were understood for the first time and the idea of a 'moment of
fertilization' arose. The philosophic notion of gradual animation held since
the time of the early Greeks had, however, provided a much-needed
working hypothesis that aided moral judgement in the face of conflicting
human claims and is still, in many ways, closely in accord with modern
scientific insight.
Throughout recorded history women have sought means to end
unwanted pregnancies, with or without the help of semi-skilled prac-
titioners. Ancient pharmacological texts are full of recipes for abortifacient
potions, some of them as lethal to the mother as to the foetus. With
advancing medical knowledge in the nineteenth century safer and more
certain methods became available. The consequent rise in the practice
alarmed Pope Pius IX who in his bull Apostolicae Sedis in 1869 removed
from the code of Canon Law the distinction between the 'ensouled' and
'unensouled' foetus. Excommunication was now pronounced on all who
procured abortion without regard to the gestational age of the foetus,
formed, unformed, animate or inanimate. Human status was to be
accorded from the moment of fertilization.6
Without actually claiming that there is a human person from the
moment of conception Catholic teaching holds that in the absence of proof
one way or the other the fertilized ovum must be treated as though it were
a person. In its Declaration on Abortion in 1974 (para. 1471) the Sacred
296
New reproductive techniques
Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith went further: 'it is not for the
biological sciences to pass a definitive judgment on questions which are
properly moral or philosophical, such as that of the moment when the
human person first exists. . . . He who will be a human being is already a
human being . . . neither divine law nor human reason admit the right of
directly killing a human person.' In 1987 Donum Vitae (SCDF, 1987; para.
13) claimed 'the conclusions of science provide a valuable indication for
discerning by the use of reason a personal presence from the moment of
conception'.7
These teachings have been reinforced by Pope John Paul II in his
sermons, speeches, and, of course, in encyclicals such as Veritatis Splendor
in 1993 and in his 'Letter to the World' Evangelium Vitae in 1995. Both
of these claim that the moral truth on this matter is clear and that the
hierarchical magisterium has the authority to proclaim it, this truth being
based solidly on the authority of revelation and tradition. It might
reasonably be asked, however, if a specific Christian ethic that can be
substantiated only by appealing to such authority is consistent with the
basic rationalism that traditionally informs Catholic moral theology.8
Many thoughtful and well-informed people of undoubted integrity are
unable to accept the early embryo as a human person. Nor is the Catholic
insistence on instant human status shared by other Christian denomina-
tions or by other religions who in the main do not oppose either
responsible research on embryos or IVF.
Newman considered that it was not reasonable to try to discern scientific
truths from moral and scriptural communications designed for religious
purposes. Nor, of course, can the philosophical question of person or personal
presence be gleaned from scientific evidence alone. Modern scientific insights
may, however, require additional moral arguments over and above appeals
to historical tradition.
297
Joyce Poole
298
New reproductive techniques
stage in the IVF process that a sample cell may be removed to examine its
genetic pattern and identify a single-gene defect such as Huntington's
disease. This is at the cutting edge of advance in IVF technology but it
seems that removal of a single cell for diagnostic purposes does not affect
further development and that an embryo 'screened' in this way can be
safely implanted in the uterus.
Twinning, if it arises from a single ovum, is observed most frequently
between five and eight days after fertilization, while the cells are dividing
rapidly but not yet differentiated. This phenomenon raises immediate
questions about a 'personal presence' from the time of fertilization. Some
submissions to the Warnock enquiry suggested that the potential to form
monovular twins might be determined at fertilization and that two or
more ensouled 'persons' might have been present, so to speak, in the mind
of God. No genetic determinant has been demonstrated, however; twin-
ning can be induced artificially, and it appears almost certainly to be
caused by factors external to the conceptus itself.
Division continues rapidly with the cells becoming progressively
smaller. By fourteen days the cells are visibly differentiating into those
that will form the embryo - the 'primitive streak' — and those that will
form the membranes and placenta. 9
Twinning occasionally takes place as late as the fourteenth day, when
two primitive streaks may appear. Incomplete separation at this stage is
the cause of conjoined ('Siamese') twins in which case the number of
individual 'persons' would be reckoned on the number of heads. This
would accord with the views of many twentieth-century theologians —
Karl Rahner and Bernard Haring among them — who have suggested that
the presence of a primitive cerebral cortex should have at least some
bearing on the requirements for personhood.
In the early eighteenth century, St Alphonsus Liguori, patron saint of
moral theology, regarded it as certain that the foetus is not ensouled before
it is formed, and, in 1713 the Holy Office of the Catholic Church actually
issued a decree - which still applies — forbidding the baptism of a foetus
before human form can be discerned. If, as the Catholic Church now
maintains, science provides a valuable indication for discerning by the use
of reason a personal presence from the moment of conception, questions
arise not only with regard to twins but about why so many embryos
should simply fail to develop or implant, or why another should develop
into a tumour or a foetus so abnormally formed that no personal activity
will be possible.
If the ascription of an individual soul to the early embryo leads to
insoluble difficulties, then perhaps the ascription needs to be recon-
sidered.10 Much of the discussion of the time of 'ensoulment' of the
embryo has, in fact, a disconcertingly medieval ring, often sitting oddly
299
Joyce Poole
with the detailed science that is called in aid. A sounder basis for
scientifically informed debate would perhaps be a concept of ensoulment
that regarded the soul not as a separate entity 'infused' at a moment in
time, but rather, in more hylomorphic and Aristotelian terms, as the set
of capabilities of a living organism; understood thus, the soul is not a
separate entity but the measure of the development of the living body
through which we become present to the world.
Potential
Those members of the Warnock committee who based their dissent on the
potential of the embryo to develop into a human person were on much
firmer ground than those who look to the evidence of science to support
their argument for actual personhood. Although in nature relatively few
fertilized ova develop into persons it is beyond dispute that all persons
started life as fertilized ova. The only real question is whether the
argument from potential will bear the weight that is put upon it.
Any answer to such a question has important implications for ethical
practice. Can it support, for example a right to life for an early embryo or
even a right to respect? Before there can be a person there must be an
individual and there can be no individual before the conceptus has passed
the stage when it might still divide into two or more embryos. It is at
this point that the law dictates that experimentation must stop. If only
persons have rights then it follows that the embryo in vitro has no rights.
This does not, however, absolve us from our human duty to accord it
respect. This duty derives not from rights possessed by the embryo by
virtue of what it is, but something we owe to it through our own primary
relationship with other members of the species; there is a danger that an
exaggerated language of rights could eclipse this sense of duty.
Respect demands the observance of high ethical standards in laboratories
and infertility clinics; it would clearly exclude, for example, the production
of embryos for commercial purposes.
A duty to preserve life on the other hand would outlaw all forms of IVF
on account of the experimental work that underpins it. This objection on
the grounds of potential is logical even if it is not universally shared.
Against such an objection it could, for instance, be argued that there are
few other areas of life where potential is equated with actuality. The acorn
cannot be said to be the oak-tree it may eventually become and in nature
few acorns become trees just as few early embryos develop into human
persons. This is more than a philosophical argument; an early miscarriage
does not present a woman with the same degree of loss as a still-birth or a
neo-natal death.
An absolute duty to preserve life is not, furthermore, one which is
300
New reproductive techniques
301
Joyce Poole
female infertility caused by blocked uterine tubes. The ovum is that of the
natural mother and the sperm is that of the natural father so that the child
is truly that of the parents in both the genetic and social sense. It thus
presents a paradigm case against which ethical questions can be weighed.
The complex questions surrounding freezing, storing, selecting are
secondary and beyond the scope of this single chapter. So also are the
moral, social and biological problems raised by the possibility of donated
gametes - male or female - and by surrogate motherhood.
Reproductive technology is an emotive subject. Ignorance and fear can
lead to imagined 'designer babies' growing in bottles or monstrous hybrids
produced from human and animal gametes. At the same time it cannot be
denied that the possibilities and ramifications are serious matters and laws
and professional codes must keep pace with new developments. All
practitioners engaged in this work must demonstrate that they are worthy
of the trust the profession has traditionally enjoyed.
In IVF we are not 'making babies' but, having ourselves been made in
the image of an inventive, imaginative and compassionate God, we are
allowed the dignity of co-operating with Him in the creation of a new
human being. It is essential, therefore, that all those engaged in reproduc-
tive technology, doctors, lawyers, policy-makers or parents must place at
the centre of the debate the interests and identity of the child that is to be
born.
Notes
302
New reproductive techniques
Select bibliography
Michael J. Coughlan, The Vatican, the Law and the Human Embryo (London: Macmillan,
1990).
G. R. Dunstan and Mary J. Seller (eels), The Status of the Human Embryo (London: King
Edward's Hospital Fund, 1988).
Anthony Dyson and John Harris (eds), Experiments on Embryos (London: Routledge,
1990).
R. A. McCormick, Corrective Vision: Explorations in Moral Theology (Kansas City, MO:
Sheed and Ward, 1994).
John Mahoney, Bioethics and Belief (London: Sheed and Ward, 1984).
Joyce Poole, The Harm We Do: A Catholic Doctor Confronts Church, Moral and Medical
Teaching (Mystic, CT: Twenty-Third Publications, 1993).
303
21
Organ transplantation
David F. Kelly
304
Organ transplantation
Theological context
305
David F. Kelly
306
Organ transplantation
Reactions to Cunningham
Cunningham's thesis was hotly debated by Catholic moralists during the
1940s and 1950s. Many European moralists continued to oppose all
organic transplantation. Most American moralists, and some Europeans,
accepted Cunningham's conclusion that organ transplantation was licit,
though many of them expressed hesitation at the lack of caution or
proportion found in some of Cunningham's judgements. They had a moral
sense, I believe, which tended toward allowing operations which seemed
to do little if any harm to the donor and to be of great benefit to the
recipient. Since the magisterium (the Catholic pope and bishops) had not
made any pronouncements directly to the contrary, these Catholic moral-
ists were willing to permit: the procedure. They disagreed, however, about
whether or not the principle of totality could be applied. Some argued
that that principle must continue to apply only to the individual body;
these justified organ transplantations on the basis of Christian charity.
Others argued that, with proper safeguards, the principle of totality might
be extended in a way similar to Cunningham's proposal. And some
opposition to transplantation continued.
But by I960 or so most Catholic moralists accepted the moral Tightness
of at least some organ transplants, and Catholics have now joined others
in seeing in this procedure not only a morally correct act but indeed a
laudable one to be supported by public policy. The 1994 'Ethical and
religious directives for Catholic health care services'7 permits living donor
transplantation.
307
David F. Kelly
308
Organ transplantation
309
David F. Kelly
310
Organ transplantation
It is quite likely that the costs would decrease if more hearts were made.
The problem of rejection, and thus the cost of immunosuppressant drugs,
would seem to be less than with human or animal hearts. It might be
easier to 'fix' and to 'do maintenance on' a human-made heart than an
organic one.
But there has thus far been little success with the permanent artificial
heart. Recipients are tied to machines which inhibit mobility. They suffer
from consistent periods of significant incapacity. And the devices fail in a
relatively short time.
In the absence of any real hope of success, experimentation with
permanent artificial hearts should be strictly limited. If and when it is
determined that they are not advancing vital knowledge, no more should
be attempted even if patients (experimental subjects) consent to them.
But what about the temporary artificial heart? Unfortunately, major
ethical problems arise even with the temporary artificial heart. Since this
is not a substitute for, but an addition to organic heart transplantation,
costs are increased. And the scarcity of organs is not alleviated; it is rather
increased. Thus, as long as there are too few cadaver hearts for those who
need them, the temporary artificial hearts only add to the list of the
needing without adding to the list of the donors. This would change
if enough human hearts became available, but for now the procedure
seems to be of no benefit to heart patients as a whole. Potential recip-
ients without artificial hearts are passed over in favour of those with
them, who would otherwise already have died. Since this is done at great
cost, and since it merely shifts the outcome of who will live and who
will die from one group to another within patients with end-stage heart
disease, it does seem to be unethical. As in the case of permanent im-
plants, temporary implants are ethically right when performed on a
restricted experimental basis in order to gain knowledge which might
lead to a successful permanent device. Some recent advances support this
claim.
311
David F. Kelly
Organ procurement
Organ procurement involves a number of policy questions apart from the
determination of death. Principal among these is the question of who
controls the body of a deceased person and thus decides whether or not
organs can be taken. There are a number of different policy options, and
governments have adopted one or another of them. Some argue that
cadaver organs ought to be considered the property of the state, or at least
that the common good should require by law that they be available for
transplantation regardless of the wishes of the person before death or of
the relatives after death. Opposing this is the position that organs be
taken only if relatives spontaneously volunteer them or if the now-dead
person has made his or her wishes to donate clear during life. In between
these two positions is the policy generally known as required request, a
policy now adopted by a number of states in the United States. This
policy requires by law that the relatives of a dying or newly dead person
be asked about possible organ donation if it is medically possible. If the
deceased carried an organ donor card or otherwise made his or her wish to
donate known this wish is seen as valid consent.
There is not any clear Christian position on this issue. On the one hand
is the importance of giving as a free gift and the freedom of choice that
this entails. On the other hand, Catholic social ethics recognizes that there
are times when individual choice must cede to the common good. Perhaps
it is best here to support a moderate policy such as required request,
which includes both the freedom necessary for giving and the valid needs
of the common good.
Determination of death
Determining death has been a problem for much of human history. Today
it arises in the context of medical technology which can maintain even in
corpses the outward appearance of biological life. Thus it became necessary
in some cases to develop criteria for determining that death had occurred,
and these became known as 'brain-death' criteria. Two proposals were
made. Some argued that since all real human activity requires the abilities
of the 'higher brain' or cortex, the death of the cortex should be sufficient
to declare that a person has died.
But the majority have thus far rejected this argument. To accept it
would not only have changed the way death was diagnosed but would
have changed the meaning of death as well. Cortically dead patients, such
as those in persistent vegetative states, can breathe spontaneously. To
declare such persons dead would mean we must be willing to bury
breathing bodies, or to act directly to stop the breathing prior to burial.
312
Organ transplantation
Thus the generally accepted consensus is that only 'whole brain death',
including the death of the brain stem, is sufficient to know that a person
has died. In this way no one is declared dead, by these new diagnostic
criteria, who would otherwise have been thought living. This approach
has been generally adopted in the United States.
It is essential to note that none of this has any direct connection with
organ transplantation. The issue of determination of death ought be
studied and resolved on its own. Yet there is a connection which comes
when cadaver organs are needed. Since 'fresh' organs are better than 'stale'
ones, a quick means of diagnosing death is desirable. And the criteria of
brain death may be involved since the best organs are often those of young
persons who have died with head injuries resulting in trauma to the brain
and little direct injury to the rest of the body. As we have seen, in the
United States the criteria used are those which determine 'total brain'
death. No organs can be taken from a patient in a persistent vegetative
state or from an anencephalic infant since these are considered to be alive.
There is considerable discussion about this. Some argue that we should
turn to a higher brain-death standard that would permit the taking of
organs from the permanently comatose. Christian theology might be used
to support either position. On the one hand, it is clear that the human
person is more than mere biological life, and Catholic ethics has for a long
time recognized that there is no obligation to sustain life when the
benefits of doing so are outweighed by the burdens of the treatment.
Catholic tradition does not require that persons in persistent vegetative
states be kept alive by medical means. They may, and ought, be allowed
to die. Thus Catholic and general Christian opinion might change toward
permitting neo-cortical determination of death. On the other hand,
Christian and Catholic theology would reject the notion that the entire
human person is contained in brain functioning. So far most Catholic
moralists are hesitant to say that the permanently unconscious are already
dead.
There is one final aspect of this problem to be addressed. It must be
repeated that the issue of determining death is not as such an issue of
organ transplantation, even though that has often been its context. We
ought not change laws merely in order to facilitate organ procurement. In
fact, it is possible that if we do so the availability of organs will be
harmed, not helped. Far too many of us already fear that physicians might
not care properly for us if they need our organs. To add anencephalics or
other cortically-dead bodies to the list of the legally dead would change
what it means to be dead. There could be a backlash that would work to
the detriment of organ transplantation. This could change in the future,
of course, as people become more open to the notion of cortical death. But
at least for now caution should rule.
313
David F. Kelly
Foetal transplantation
The question of foetal organ and tissue transplants, such as the transplan-
tation of foetal dopamine-producing cells for treatment of Parkinson's
disease, raises issues additional to those we have already developed, and
leads to much controversy, especially in Roman Catholic ethics. The
reason, of course, is the connection to abortion. Official Catholic teaching
argues that from the moment of conception the foetus must be treated as
a human person and rejects all direct abortions, even those of very early
embryos. Even for some who would permit early abortion for serious
reasons, it seems clearly right to oppose any attempt at 'growing' human
foetuses simply in order to use their organs after abortion.
Less clear, however, is transplantation from a foetus which has been
aborted. On one side of this question are those who argue that this will
increase the likelihood of abortion and that it means a moral identification
of the physician and the recipient with the abortion. These also question
the authority of the woman to consent for the foetus. On the other side
are those suggesting that once the abortion has taken place and the foetus
is dead, the organs and tissue may be taken as with any other cadaver.
There is a general agreement rejecting any techniques used to keep the
organs viable if these techniques would further endanger the life of the
woman or of the foetus, as well as an insistence that any child born alive
be treated like any other person.
Conclusion
Over the years Catholic medical ethics has changed its judgement about
organ transplantation. It now recognizes the contribution this remarkable
procedure can make to human healing. Yet risks remain. Christian medical
ethics will continue to find in organ transplantation a procedure that
requires ongoing vigilance.
Acknowledgements
314
Organ transplantation
Notes
1 For a complete history cf this development, see David F. Kelly, The Emergence of
Roman Catholic Medical Ethics in North America (New York: Edwin Mellen Press,
1979).
2 I have developed these themes at greater length in a special publication of the
National Association of Catholic Chaplains entitled A Theological Basis for Health
Care and Health Care Ethics (New York: National Association of Catholic
Chaplains, 1985).
3 Bert Cunningham, 'The morality of organ transplantation', dissertation, Catholic
University of America: Studies in Sacred Theology, no. 86 (Washington: Catholic
University of America Press, 1944).
4 Cunningham cites the late 1930s manuals of Noldin-Schmitt and lorio, popular
and influential textbooks ol that time (pp. 64—70).
5 Cunningham, pp. 87—99.
6 Cunningham, p. 106.
7 'Ethical and religious directives for Catholic health care services', Origins 24.27
(15 December 1994), pp. 449-58.
8 Richard A. McCormick, 'Transplantation of organs: a comment on Paul Ramsey',
Theological Studies 36 (1975), pp. 503-9.
9 Louis Janssens, 'Transplantation d'organes', Foi et Temps 4 (1983), pp. 308—24.
10 Janssens, p. 318, translation mine.
11 Janssens, p. 320, translation mine.
12 Benedict M. Ashley and Kevin D. O'Rourke, Health Care Ethics: A Theological
Analysis (2nd edn; St Louis, MO: Catholic Health Association of the United
States, 1982), pp. 308-11.
13 Ashley and O'Rourke, p. 310.
14 James B. Nelson and Joanne Smith Rohricht, Human Medicine: Ethical Perspectives
on Today's Medical Issues (rev. edn; Minneapolis, MN: Augsburg, 1984),
pp. 176-99.
Select bibliography
Benedict M. Ashley and Kevin D. O'Rourke, Health Care Ethics: A Theological Analysis
(2nd edn; St Louis, MO: Catholic Health Association of the United States, 1982).
Louis Janssens, 'Transplantation d'organes', Foi et Temps 4 (1983), pp. 308—24.
David F. Kelly, The Emergence of Roman Catholic Medical Ethics in North America (New
York: Edwin Mellen Press, 1979).
315
David F. Kelly
David F. Kelly, A Theological Basis for Health Care and Health Care Ethics (New York:
National Association of Catholic Chaplains, 1985).
Richard A. McCormick, 'Transplantation of organs: a comment on Paul Ramsey',
Theological Studies 36 (1975), pp. 503-9.
James B. Nelson and Joanne Smith Rohricht, Human Medicine: Ethical Perspectives on
Today's Medical Issues (rev. edn; Minneapolis, MN: Augsburg, 1984).
Richard C. Sparks, 'Ethical issues of fetal tissue transplantation: research, procurement,
and complicity with abortion', The Annual of the Society of Christian Ethics
(Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 1990).
United States Catholic Conference. 'Ethical and religious directives for Catholic health
care services', Origins 24.27 (15 December 1994), pp. 449-58.
316
22
Hypnosis and general anaesthesia
Aureliano Pacciolla
Translated by Bernard Hoose
Hypnosis
317
Aureliano Pacciolla
318
Hypnosis and general anaesthesia
319
Aureliano Pacciolla
320
Hypnosis and general anaesthesia
Another problem
Another problem connected with hypnosis, although this time in the
religious rather than the forensic sphere, concerns reincarnation. Some
subjects regress, not only to a remote past, and then recall in detail
experiences from their childhood. It even seems that they can regress to a
preceding life, but, at this point, it would be more exact to say, to a
'presumed' preceding life. Even if some testimonies are really very
surprising, so much so that, for many, there are doubts and perplexity
concerning the different explanations about reincarnation, it is, neverthe-
less, important to point out that, up to this point in time, there has been
insufficient research to prove the reliability of what is said under hypnosis.
So far, the scientific literature on hypnosis and regression to presumed
preceding lives has not produced evidence in favour of reincarnation.
Furthermore, the methodology used in hypnotic regressions to presumed
preceding lives cannot be said to be scientifically adapted, and, therefore,
the results cannot be regarded as reliable. Nevertheless, research continues,
even if there are now many who regard it as useless or inappropriate, given
that no amount of scientific research can produce a conviction of faith.
321
Aureliano Pacciolla
322
Hypnosis and general anaesthesia
I have used this example from a Catholic manual of moral theology which
predates the Second Vatican Council precisely to show that the attitude of
openness and prudence on the part of the Catholic Church (and, indeed, other
churches) in regard to hypnosis is not only a characteristic of the present
theological position, but has always been there. Of course, I do not mean
to say that this has been a universal attitude shared by all theologians of
all times. If there have been exceptions, these have certainly been rare and
lacking any doctrinal relevance. The prudential attitude also comes from
the fact that many — above all in the past - confused hypnosis with
spiritualism and magic.
The main concern of theologians springs from the consequences of an
improper use of hypnosis, especially if the practitioners are not pro-
fessionals. This means that no theologian has ever had any objections to
hypnosis if it is used for therapeutic ends and if the practitioners are
professionals. It can be said that this is, in substance, the position of the
manuals of Christian moral theology.
General anaesthesia
323
Aureliano Pacciolla
324
Hypnosis and general anaesthesia
325
Aureliano Pacciolla
326
Hypnosis and general anaesthesia
Notes
327
Aureliano Pacciolla
328
Hypnosis and general anaesthesia
329
This page intentionally left blank
Index
331
Index
332
Index
333
Index
334
Index
335
Index
336
Index
337