Maxine Greene - Aesthetic Literacy in General Education-1
Maxine Greene - Aesthetic Literacy in General Education-1
Maxine Greene - Aesthetic Literacy in General Education-1
MAXINE GREENE
Professor of Philosophy and Education
Teachers College, Col1~mbia Univel'sity
New York, New York
198 I
114
CHAPTER VI
have experienced nor find words for what they have heard or seen.
Then, of course, there are those who attend performances and
visit galleries because they feel it gives them a certain cachet, the
mark of being members of an elite community; and there are
those who remain at the fringes, glancing at the paintings in gal-
lery windows as they pass, listening to classical music on the radio,
watching public television for glimpses of Nureyev, Liv Ullmann,
or Laurence Olivier.
There are numerous qualitative differences in responses to the
arts; but, for all the differences, for all the range of sensitivity and
sophistication, audiences are growing constantly more open and
more curious. Communities are investing in exhibitions and per-
formances. The federal government is paying increasing attention.
The arts, some say, are an important industry; others make the
point that they are the health of our society, a means of counter-
ing materialism. Yet the same arts continue to be treated cavalierly
or suspiciously in educational institutions, at least outside the
studios and music rooms and the few school theaters that exist.
It is rare to find an educator willing to entertain the thought
that the students presently in the classroom will one day compose
the audiences for the exhibitions and performances proliferating
throughout the culture. It seldom occurs to the classroom teacher
that something might be done to empower those students to ap-
proach such art forms with understanding and awareness, to make
informed choices among them, to "cherish" wh:lt they encounter
in an enlightened way.1 Few teachers even consider the possibility
that the capacities needed for grasping and enjoying works of art
may be as basic as those required for verbal and numerical literacy.
If included in the curriculum at all, the arts tend to be relegated
to the "creative" domains. Literature, of course, is an exception;
but literature is not ordinarily categorized as art. Art teachers are
thought of mainly as persons committed to making paint, clay,
papier-mache, and other media available for self-expression. Music
teachers, drama teachers, dance teachers are similarly conceived as
people concerned about playing, performing, improvising; they
are not expected to engage students with the complexities of
group learn to think and talk about it. Individuals are dominated,
in their everyday existence, by what is called the "natural attitude,"
an unquestioning way of addressing a world conceived to be
given, predetermined, resistant to redefinition or to change.
There are, however, interpretations of reality that differ from
commonsense interpretations. They have been called "provinces
of meaning," each one of which is characterized by a detinable
"cognitive style" and mode of directing attention. According to
Alfred Schutz, "all these worlds-the world of dreams, of im-
ageries and phantasms, especially the world of art, the world of
scientific contemplation, the play world of the child . . . -are
finite provinces of meaning." 16 Each province, each "subuniverse,"
includes sets of experiences that are compatible with one another
in attitude taken, degree of distance from the lived world, sym-
bolism used to schematize what is selected out for attention. This
is why people experience "jolts" or "shocks" when they move
from the movie theater to the street, when they are aroused from
dreams, when they go from the church to the scientific laboratory.
It is not that they are moving into disparate worlds; it is simply
that they have to accommodate to different ways of sense making,
of interpreting what they find around them at a particular moment
of time. Much the same thing may be said about the academic
disciplines such as history, sociology, geology, physics, mathemat-
ics. Each may be considered a distinctive province of meaning;
each one offers a distinctive perspective on the world.
Identifying the artistic-aesthetic with a province of meaning, as
Schutz does, suggests that certain recognizable kinds of apprehen-
sion are included within it, each one marked by a specifiable
cognitive style-a style that marks them all artistic-aesthetic in
character. These modes of awareness all involve a break with the
"natural attitude," for one thing, with ordinary ways of looking
upon and making sense of the world. Art works select out certain
dimensions of experience, frame them, set them apart; and, by so
doing, they make available new possibilities of perception and cog-
nition. Because so much depends upon the live, attending con-
sciousness of a percipient, this is a domain that depends upon
subjective awareness (and the contribution of such awareness)
more than, for example, mathematics or history. The percipient's
16. Ibid., p. 131.
GREENE 12 7
cially in the face of the fact that new forms are constantly chal-
lenging what we have "known" and taken for granted about
aesthetic phenomena. He proposes, therefore, that "art" be treated
as an "open concept" and that we think about bow the concept
should be used rather than expecting an answer to the question,
"What, finally, is art?" And, indeed, there would seem to be a
value in consideration of aesthetic theories, because they teach us
"what to look for and how to look at it in art." Weitz goes on
to say: "To understand the role of aesthetic theory is not to con-
ceive it as definition, logically doomed to failure, but to read it as
summaries of seriously made recommendations to attend in certain
ways to certain features of art."22 This is how teachers ought to
read it-not for the sake of becoming aestheticians but for the
sake of discovering the modes of attending they can associate with
aesthetic literacy.
Most philosophers of art agree that one perspective is not
enough. They presume that understanding is enriched when vari-
ous, overlapping perspectives are used for examining the artistic-
aesthetic domain. This does not exclude the necessity for locating
specific modes of awareness in the artistic-aesthetic province of
meaning. Nor does it diminish the importance of urging persons
"to attend in certain ways" so as to bring aesthetic objects into
existence as works of art. There is little question but that such
attending enables people to see more, to take more into account.
Art, as Herbert Marcuse has said, "breaks open a dimension in-
accessible to other experience." 28 Doing so, it provides a vantage
point on other experience, a standpoint from which to attend to
patterns and nuances, to see what is ordinarily obscured. Joseph
Conrad was exemplary when he wrote: "My task which I am try-
ing to achieve is by the power of the written word to make you
hear, to make you feel-it is, before all, to make you see. That-
and no more, and it is everything." 24 Writing about Paul cezanne,
Maurice Merleau-Ponty said: "Cezanne, in his own words, 'wrote
Aesthetic Educating
A teacher who attempts to educate with such ends in view
ought to be perceptually and imaginatively involved with several
of the arts and have experience with shaping the raw materials of
at least one into something approximating an expressive form. It
would help to experiment with writing short poems or paragraphs
of imaginative prose, to experiment with the sounds emitted by a
recorder. It would certainly help if teachers were familiar enough
with their own physical beings to experience some degree of body
response when attending to a ballet they wish to make accessible
to students. To say all this, however, is equivalent to saying that
all practicing teachers ought to feel alive and in the world, excited
about their subject matter, even in love with some of it. To say
this is equivalent to saying that teachers need to keep their own
questions open, continually to break with "created structures,"
striving to move beyond. 28
What, then, can such a teacher do to enhance students' oppor-
tunities to achieve aesthetic literacy? It is important, first of all,
to realize that the domain of the aesthetic is more far-reaching than
the world in which works of art exist. Everyone has some memory
of sunsets, moon-flecked woods, snowy streets, children's hands.
An awareness of certain aesthetic concepts (distancing, let us say,
shape, timbre, form) may move an individual teacher to uncouple
certain phenomena from the context of ordinariness and to per-
ceive them aesthetically: a black tree shape on a winter day; the
texture of a flower petal; the wind moving the leaves. In the effort
to enhance perceptual acuity among students, the teacher might
urge them to attend to the appearances of things around in un-
accustomed ways. If teachers can enable the students to detach
what they see and hear from its use value for a time, from its
mundane significance, the students may be brought in touch with
shapes, masses, shadings, tonalities of which they are hardly likely
to have been aware.
The weight of the flagstones making up a wall, the deepening
green on the playing field, the wail of a railway whistle: these are
the kinds of qualities a teacher might bring into the field of atten-
tion. They are the attributes of actual objects and events that may
18. Maurice MerIeau-Ponty. The Structure of Behavior (Boston: Beacon
Press, 1967). pp. 160-66.
134 AESTHETIC LITERACY IN GENERAL EDUCATION