3LEG65
3LEG65
3LEG65
Citations:
-- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and
Conditions of the license agreement available at
https://heinonline.org/HOL/License
-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.
-- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your license, please use:
Copyright Information
LetgdTheory 3 (1997), 65-99. Printed in the United States of America
Copyright 0 Cambridge University Press 1352-3252/97 $7.50 + .10
I am grateful to Bruce Ackerman, Jeffrie Murphy, Fernando Teson, and the faculty at the
College of William and Mary for valuable comments.
1. The phrase "liberal legalism" describes a system of law grounded in the principles of
liberal philosophy; as used in feminist and critical-race theory it has become a term of
opprobrium. See, e.g., Richard Delgado, lien a Story Isjust a Story: Does Voice Really Matter?, 76
VA. L REv. 95, 103 (1990) (expressing frustration of critical-race theorists with premises of
liberal legalism); Catharine MacKinnon, TOWARD A FEMINIsT TIEORYOF THE STATE 170 (1989)
("Including, but beyond, the bourgeois in liberal legalism, lies what is male about it"); Robin
West.Jurisprudenceand Gender, 55 U. Clu. L REv. 1 (1988) (arguing that liberal legalism is
essentially and irretrievably masculine").
2. Discussions of "difference" abound in feminist and critical-race theory, as well as in
postmodern literature generally. Set, e.g., Anne Dailey, Feminism's Return to Lileralism, 102 YE
LJ. 1265 (1993) (discussing importance of "difference" question in feminist jurisprudence);
Sheila Foster, Difference andEquality:A iticalAssessmentof the Concept of *Dierity,' 1993 Wis. L
REv. 105 [hereinafter Foster, Difference and Equality];Angela P. Harris, Foreword: Thejurispru-
dence of Reconstruction, 82 Cuir. L REv. 741 (1994); Iris Marion bung, Polity and Group
Difference, 99 Enics 250 (1989); Iris Marion Young. The Ideal of Community and the Politics of
Dirffrnce, in FEMINts1/POrM1ODERnItst 300 (Linda J. Nicholson ed.) (1990) [hereinafter
Young, The Ideal of Community]; Martha Minow, Forruord:Justice Engendered, 101 HARv. L REv.
10 (1987); Martha Minow, Wen Difference Has Its Home- Group Homes for the Mentally Retaned,
EqualProtectionandLegal Treatment ofDifference, 22 HARY. C. R. C. L L REV. 111 (1987); Martha
Minow, MARING AIL THtE DIHmENcE: INCLUSION, ExcLUsION, AND AMERICAN Lw (1990) [herein-
after Minow, Making all the Difference); Iris Marion YoungJUSTIcE AND THE Polmcs OF DiFFER-
ENcE (1990) [hereinafter YoungJustice and the Politics ofDifference).
3. Young, The IdealofCommunity, supranote 2, at 307. See also Minow, MakingAll theDiferene.
supranote 2, at 377 ("Rights analysis.. . fails to supply a basis for remaking . .. institutions to
accommodate difference. Integrated into institutions not designed with them in mind, for-
merly marginalized people may simply become newly marginalized or stigmatized"). As I
discuss below, most critics (including Young) attack a specific type of liberalism, which cele-
brates individual autonomy and agency and advocates their maximization via a legal system
grounded in individual rights. Thus, not all forms of liberalism are subject to all of the
criticisms made here. See infm note 13 and accompanying text.
65
66 CYNTHIA V. WARD
4. See, eg., Christine A. Littleton, Reconstructing Sexual Equality, 75 CAL. L REV. 1279, 1282
(1987) ("As a concept, equality suffers from a 'mathematical fallacy'-that is, the view that only
things that are the same can ever be equal"); Mlinow, Making all the Difference, supra note 2, at
149 ("Both the historical and heuristic versions of [liberal] social contract theory claim to be
inclusive, participatory, and egalitarian, yet both replicate the process of exclusion and subor-
dination that preserves the two tracks of legal treatment"); id. (noting that "lie U.S. Consti-
tution [is based on liberal principles and] is a document produced through an indisputably
exclusionary process"); Young, justice and the Politics of Difference. supra note 2, at 164-66
(claiming that "politics of difference . . . promotes a notion of group solidarity against the
individualism of liberal humanism," which is characterized by an "assimilationist ideal" that sets
facially neutral "norms" that in fact disadvantage oppressed groups).
5. Harris,Jurisprudenceof Reconstruction, supra note 2, at 761 (critical-race theorists advance
an idea of "equality based not on sameness but on difference"; id. at 770 (critical-race theory
attempts to refigure equality in ways beyond sameness and difference); Minow, Whsen Difference
Has Its Home, supra note 2. at 113 (explaining main goal of article is to argue that "categorical
approaches" to law, which attribute "difference" to different people, undermine commitments
to equality); Minow. Making All the Difference, supra note 2, at 50, 74-75 (contesting idea of
equality as sameness); Young, Polity and Group Difference, supra note 2, at 250-51.
6. William Galston, LIBERAL PURPosEs: GooDs, VIRTUES AND DVESTPsVINT iE LIBERAL STATr 4
(1991). See also Bruce Ackerman, SocIALJUSTICE INTE LIBERAL STATE 18 (1980) (advocating "a
liberal conception of equality that is compatible with a social order rich in diversity of talents,
personal ideals, and forms of community"); Ronald Dworkin, TARING Ricirts SERiousLn272-73
(1977) (defining "liberal conception of equality" as mandating that government 'must not
constrain liberty on the ground that one citizen's conception of the good life is nobler or
superior to another's").
7. Minow, MakingAll the Differene, supra note 2, at 227-390 (defending her vision of "rights
in relationship").
On Difference and Equality 67
8
of those differences that have been left out" Scholars have argued that
properly accounting for racial "difference" implies the abolishment of Title
VII and the reimagining of the law of employment discrimination and equal
protection.9 And Iris Marion Young proposes a "politics of difference" that
would incorporate "a principle of representation for oppressed groups in
democratic decisionmaking bodies," as well as other group-based rights.'o
In Part I of this Article I analyze the liberal value of diversity; in Parts II
and III, I compare it with antiliberal conceptions of difference; in Part IV,
I evaluate the connection of "difference," as conceived by critics of liberal
legalism, to the underlying and (I argue) more fundamental value of
equality.
"Difference" advocates advance their legal reform proposals in the name
of true equality-equality grounded not in sameness but in difference."t I
conclude that, although equality can and should accominmodatea wide range
of differences, these efforts to construct equality fromn difference eviscerate
the concept of equality. To argue, as "difference" theorists do, for the
prioritization and celebration of equality based on "difference" is to argue
against any foundational commitment to equality. To the extent it adds
anything new to legal discussion, "difference" theory is necessarily anti-
equality.
1. LIBERAL DIVERSITY
16. See, e.g., John Stuart Mill, ON UERTW ANNOTATED TExr, SOURCES. AND BACKGROUND
CRmcISM 65 (David Spitz ed. 1975) ("Such are the differences among human beings in their
sources of pleasure, their susceptibilities of pain, and the operation on them of different
physical and moral agencies, that unless there is a corresponding diversity in their modes of
life, they neither obtain their fair share of happiness, nor grow up to the mental, moral, and
aesthetic stature of which their nature is capable"); Robert Nozick. ANARCm; STATE. AND
UTOPA 308-09 (1974) (discussing extensive diversity of human beings); Amarta Sen, IN-
EQUALTIy REEXAsNED 19-21 (1992) (discussing impact of "extensive human diversity" on
equality theory).
17. See, e.g., Michel Rosenfeld. Substantive Equality and Equal Opportunity: A jurispnidential
Appraisa 74 CL L REv. 1687, 1702 ('In its broadest terms, then, equalities must be con-
structed so that those who are different are not regarded as inferiors, and conforming
identities are not imposed upon then").
18. See, e.g., Fallon, supra note 13, at 887-88 (defending conception of descriptive autonomy
and noting that "the self, though situated and socially constituted, remains capable of appre-
ciating her situated condition, of assessing and criticizing her assumptions and values, and of
revising her goals and commitments. . . . The self is a creature in and of the world, but one
capable of at least partially transforming herself through thought, criticism, and self-interpre-
tation").
19. SeeSen, supma note 16, at 12-16 (noting that 'every normative theory of social arrange-
ment that has at all stood the test of time seems to demand equality of somehing-something
that is regarded as particularly important in that theory," and thus that "the battle is not, in an
important sense. about 'why equality?', but about *equality of what?'").
70 CYNTHIA V. WARD
autonomy, agency, or whatever, they have the right to be wrong, or the view
that there are many equally valuable "visions of the good life," and that she
should therefore be encouraging to, and welcoming of, visions that differ
from her own. Both approaches assume a value for diversity that follows
coherently from a liberal understanding of equal respect for individual
personhood.
Third, liberal equality serves as both the value that grounds respect for
diversity and as the boundary to diversity. One's right to pursue one's own
vision of life, which derives from the liberal's equal respect for all people,
is simultaneously limited by the equal right of everyone else to do the same.
'To each his own" is a liberal sentiment that does not apply to persons
whose vision of self-maximization requires the murder or torture of others.
In short, liberal respect for diversity is both derivative of, and subservient
to, the foundational liberal value of (sameness-based) equality. Over time,
however, the exact relationship between these two values has shifted, driv-
ing liberalism toward visions of equality that have continued to embrace
foundational sameness but have also increasingly acknowledged the pro-
fundiLy of human difference.
20. See, e.g., id. at 22 ("ibertarian demands for liberty typically include important features
of 'equal liberty,' e.g., the insistence on equal immunity from interference by others').
21. Ronald Dworkin, Mat Is Equality? PartI. Equality of IWelfarr, and I hat Is Equality?Part 2*
Equality of Resournas. 10 Pilu & Pus. Am. (1981).
22. Rawls, supra note 13.
23. Amy Gutmann may be drawing this distinction between liberalism's equality assumptions,
which she defines as the function of "describing people as equal beings... ,'and egalitarian-
ism, which she defines as the "justif)ing a more equal distribution of goods, services, and
opportunities among those people." Amy Gutmann, LIERAL EQUAlnY2 (1980).
24. Amartya Sen, supra note 16, at 12-30, discusses these two ideas, noting that "[tiwo
central issues for ethical analysis of equality are: (1) 1W1hy equality? (2) Equality of What?"
Discussing the work ofJohn Rawls. Ronald Dworkin notes a similar difference between Rawls's
two conceptions of equality, which consist of claims with respect to the distribution of goods,
and claims to equal concern and respect for all individuals, Dworkin, supm note 6. at 180-82.
On Difference and Equality 71
The connection between these two meanings of equality has changed
significantly within liberal theory. According to its now-standard tale, liber-
alism's earliest vision of egalitarianism found its legal expression in the view
that individuals have "equal rights." This vision of legal equality, also char-
acterized by the phrases "equal treatment" and "formal equality," inter-
preted equal rights to mandate identical treatment, resulting in the
principle that the law may not treat similarly situated persons differently. 2 5
The legal principle of equal treatment begins from a justification of
equality that relies on some shared trait-some "samcness"-among all
humans (for example, autonomy, agency, capacity to have a vision of the
good life and act upon it, or capacity for "moral personality"), and proceeds
mechanically to import this "sameness" justification into the legal and
political spheres via the principle of "equal rights." Equal treatment is based
on the idea that, because people are (in relevant ways) the same, the law
should treat them the same.
Although findamental sameness has remained the core justification of
liberal equality, the sameness-based egalitarian principle has been succeeded
by a myriad of reformulations of the meaning of legal and political egalitari-
anisin, among which are the closely related principles of "equal concern,"2
"
"equal acceptance,"o 7 and "equal opportunity:"2 8 These principles began to
open a divide between the sameness-based justification for legal equality and
the proper means of implementing it. They sought legally to express the view
that liberal law should endorse different treatment for different persons in the
service of the underlying principle that people are, in the relevant liberal
senses, the same. Progressive liberal theorists argued that treating everyone
the same necessarily erased importantand relevantdifferences among them.
Although humans share autonomy, they also have differences that make
treatment "as an equal" inconsistent with identical treatment.29-
Two things are important about this. First, the progression of liberalism
discussed above worked a significant change in the relationship between
equality and diversity within the liberal framework. Equal treatment was
found inadequate as a legal principle precisely because it was in findamen-
tal tension with diversity, and liberal philosophers concluded that treating
people the same took insufficient account of their differences and was
therefore a violation of liberal equality properly conceived.
Second, the liberal progression from equal treatment to a mandate of
"treatment as equals" altered the relationship between equality asjustifica-
25. See, e.g., Ackerman, sufmp note 6, at 18 ("Certain forms of equal treatment-say, formal
equality in the administration ofjustice-have been central to the liberal tradition"). For a
contemporary defense of this idea. ret grnerallvNozick. supra note 16.
26. Dworkin, supranote 6. at 180, 272-78.
27. iuttleton, supra note *1, at 1284-85.
28. Jermna I lill Kay, Equality arit Diffrrere: The Case oflrgnancy. I 1ERKEtEY WOMEoNS Lj. 1,
26-27 (1985).
29. Dworkin, supra note 6, at 180-82.
72 CYNTHIA V. WARD
A. Sameness as Domination
At the heart of most theoretical attacks on "liberal legalism" is the claim
that, contrary to their express commitments, liberal institutions are main-
Unless we do so, she wvill experience employment disadvantages arising from her reproductive
activity that are not encountered by her male co-worker"); id. (episodic analysis will enable
the law to treat women differently than men during a limited period when their needs may be
greater than those of men as a way of ensuring that women will be equal to men with respect
to their overall employment opportunities"); Littleton, supra note 4, at 1283 (arguing that
.equality can be ... reconstructed as a means of challenging, rather than legitimating, social
institutions created from the phallocentric perspective."); id. at 1284 (advancing notion of
equality as acceptance and averring that "[tlo achieve this form of sexual equality, male and
female 'differences' must be costless relative to each other").
32. Suhdefined as rationality, capacity for moral personality, agenc) etc.
33. Nlinow, Making All the Diffrrnmr. supm note 2, at 146-17.
74 CYNTHIA V. WARD
tained by and for a white male elite that hides its domination of society
behind empty claims to respect the equal moral worth of all persons. 34 Of
course, the critics do not need to claim that liberalism suppresses all differ-
ence; they could even acknowledge that, within the constraints of its core
assumptions about human nature-assumptions that justify its view of
equality-liberal theory allows the flourishing of many visions of the good
life. 35 It is those constraints, however, that radical difference theorists target
as parochial and highly restrictive. 36 Indeed, according to this view the
liberal's bounded respect for "diversity" actually suppresses the acknow-
ledgment of fundamental "difference."
Reduced to its core components, the attack on liberal diversity makes two
claims. Critics charge first that liberalism misdescribes human nature by
assuming and celebrating individual autonomy and choice while simultane-
ously excluding from law and politics important parts of the self such as its
interdependence and/or relational capacity 37 ; and second, that those ig-
3-1. Se, e.g.. Derrick Bell, Forteum:The Civil Rights Chanicles, 99 HAR. L Rrv. -1. 6-8 (1985)
(discussing contradiction between America's ideal of equality and its reality of racism, and
arging that tu(luch of what is called the law of civil rights ... has a mythological or fairy-tale
quality"); Harris,juriprudeneof Recontruction, supra note 2, at 754 (critical-race theory "puts
law's supposed objectivity and neutrality on trial, arguing that what looks like race-neutrality
on the surface has a deeper structure that reflects white privilege."); id. at 759 (-History has
shown that racism can coexist happily with formal commitments to objectivity, neutrality, and
colorblindness"); Catharine MacKinnon, TowARD A FratNIMST THEORY OF THtE STATE 220-21
(1989) (liberal conception of equality as employed in sex discrimination law conceals "the
substantive way in which man has become the measure of all things); id. at 224 ("Men's
physiology defines most sports, their health needs largely define insurance coverage, their
socially designed biographies define workplace expectations and successful career patterns,
their perspectives and concerns define quality in scholarship, their experiences and obsessions
define merit, their military service defines citizenship, their presence defines family, their
inability to get along uith each other-their wars and rulerships-defines history: their image
defines god, and their genitals define sex. These are the standards that are presented as gender
neutral"); Young,justice and the PoliticsofDiffere, supra note 2, at 168-69 (arguing that liberal
quality theory has effect of excliding those labeled "different"); id. at 173 ("policies that are
universally formulated and thus blind to differences of race, culture, gender, age, or disability
often perpetuate rather than undermine oppression").
35. See, e.g., Minow, Mtaking All the Diffi-rrne, supra note 2, at 146-49; 1bung, justice and the
Politics ofDifference, supra note 2. at 157 ("Enlightenment ideals of liberty and political equality
did and do inspire movements against oppression anti domination, whose success has created
social values and institutions we would not want to lose").
3(. See, e.g., Minow, Making All the Dif/erence, supra note 2. at 152 (Ihe [liberal) social
contract approach has been deeply exclusionary"); Ybung,justice and the Politirs of Differrntre,
supra note 2, at 173 ("Policies that are universally formulated and thus blind to differences
of race, culture, gender, age, or disability often perpetuate rather than undermine oppres-
sion").
37. Communitarians have been especially keen on this attack. & generally Miclhael Sandel,
LnIER.RAItSM AN) TIE LtTs oFJUSTICE (1982).
On Difference and Equality 75
nored parts of the self should be both celebrated and incorporated into our
legal institutions. 38
According to some critical scholars, the liberal focus on individual auton-
omy, while validly descriptive of certain groups, obscures or suppresses
other, equally worthy visions of the good that emphasize the primary impor-
tance of relational ability and connectedness. This suppression, they
charge, has the effect in liberal societies of excluding from legal identity
groups that hold more communitarian worldviews. Much relational femi-
nist work takes this approach, arguing, in the well-known words of Carol
Gilligan, for the inclusion of women's "different voice" 39 into moral legiti-
macy and legal institutions. 40
The normative implications of this relational critique of liberalism are
clear* "liberal legalism" should either be supplemented with a legal system
that recognizes relevant characteristics, such as relational capacity, that
liberal law currently ignores, 41 or liberal institutions should be replaced
altogether by a system of communitarian deliberation that celebrates more
important features and ideals of human society.42
38. See generally Suzanna Sherry, Civic Virtue and the Feminine Voice in ConstitutionalAdjudica-
tion, 72 VA. L REV. 543 (1986) (citing Carol Gilligan and arguing for inclusion of women's
"different voice" into law); West, supra note 1 (arguing that law must incorporate women's
focus on connectedness as well as men's concern with individual autonomy).
39. Carol Gilligan, IN A DiFERENr VoIcE (1980).
40. For relational feminist discussions that use Gilligan's ideas to criticize liberal law, see, e.g.,
West, supranote 1, at 2-4. 14-26, 42 (1988) (defending the "connection thesis"-that women
differ essentially from men because they are materially connected to other human lives
through the maternal experience and therefore value connection and nurturing over auton-
omy); Sherry, supra note 38, at 543, 579-84 (hypothesizing that women's concerns about
connection, subjectivity, and responsibility for others accord well with communitarian legal
structures while men's emphasis on autonomy, objectivity, and rights translates into liberal-
ism). For a similar thesis in the context of race relations, see, e.g., Jacinda T. Townsend,
RedaimingSelf-Determination:ACallforintraradalAdoption,2 DUKEJ. GENDER L & PoL'Y 173, 181
(1995) ("The Black community maintains its own set of family values, including collective
responsibility, self-determination, and cooperative economics. These values help define a
communitarian Black society that can be contrasted with an individual rights based dominant
society").
Catharine MacKinnon, a critic of relational feminism, might nevertheless be placed in this
camp as she also appears to assume that although liberal autonomy and the liberal state work
well for men, they oppress women; see, e.g., MacKinnon, supra note 34, at 157-70, 237-49
(1989) (attacking the liberal state and liberal theory as oppressive of women). Unlike the
relational feminists, however, MacKinnon refuses to move beyond the critique of liberalism to
define a positive vision of "woman's point of view"; that is, to paint a picture of what a
postdomination world would look like. See, e.g., Catharine MacKinnon, FEHImSM UNMODIFIED
45 (1987) (ake your foot off our necks, then we will hear in what tongue women speak").
like relational feminists, MacKinnon has been attacked for "gender essentialism'; see generally
Angela Harris, Race and Essentialism in Feminist Legal Theay, 42 STAN. L REv. 581 (1990)
(charging both MacKinnon and West with essentialism).
41. See generally Sherry, supranote 38; West. supra note 1.
42. See, e.g., Sandel, supranote 37 (pointing out flaws in Rawlsian liberalism and arguing for
a communitarian vision of state). Some liberals have recently argued that liberalism and
communitarianism are not essentially opposed; see, e.g., Bruce Ackerman, WE IE PEoPLE 1:
FouNDxttoNs (1991); William Galston, LMrn.u. PURPOSES (1991).
76 CYNTHIA V. WAno
-13. The term "postmodern* can mean many things, and I use it somewhat loosely in this
article. Angela Harris has described the use of this term in jurisprudential literature: "[Post-
modernism] suggest[s] that what has been presented in our social-political and ourintellectual
traditions as knowledge, truth, objectivity, and reason are actually merely the effects of a
particular form of social power, the victory of a particular way of representing the world that
then presents itself as beyond mere interpretation, as truth itself." Harris, stpranote 2, at 748.
.14. &ee, e.g., Hutchinson, supra note 11, at 118-1-85 ("Rather than think of the subject as a
unitary and sovereign subject whose self-directed vocation is to bring the world to heel through
the exacting discipline of rational inquiry, postmodernism interrogates the whole idea of
autonomous subjectivity and abstract reason; it places them in a constantly contingent condi-
tion of provisionality"); id. at 1192 ("postmodernists suggest that te traditional notion of
authenticity-'o thine own self be true*-is an immediate patient for postmodern surgery");
toung, 77eldalofCommunity, supm note 2, at 300,310 ("The idea of the selfasa unified subject
of desire and need and an origin of assertion and action has been powerfully called into
question by contemporary philosophers"); id. at 308-09 (criticizing liberal conception of
moral autonomy).
On Difference and Equality 77
tialist" categories to describe, for example, the differences between men
and wVomcn. 45 They criticize relational theorists for associating the
"male," or white majority, with liberal autonomy and the "female," or
racial minority, with nurturing and community, and then using this
supposedly inherent opposition to argue for the legal recognition of mar-
ginalized groups into law via communitarian reform of liberalism.4 6 An-
tiessentialist scholars charge that such efforts to define, for example, a
"true female self' or a "true male self" deny the full range of human
difference.4 7
In their critique of both liberal diversity and relational views, postmodern
difference theorists promote alternatives to liberal individualism that are
grounded in the celebration of difference itself. 8 To remain internally
consistent, such theories must rely upon some nonessentialist under-
standing of persons for the charge that liberalism "denies difference"4 9 and
the attendant call for fuller recognition of this concept.
A. Antiessentialist Difference
How is the liberal vision of "diversity" distinct from the concept of "dif-
ference" cmployed by liberalism's antiessentialist critics? The latter incor-
45. See, e.g., Judith Butler, Gender Touble, Feminist Theory, and PsychoanalyticDiscourse, in
FrsnNissti/PosmtsonEwNisst 32-1, 338-39 (Unda J. Nicholson ed., 1990) ("Inasmuch as the
construct of women presupposes a specificity and coherence that differentiates it from that of
men, the categories of gender appear as an unproblematic point of departure for feminist
politics. But if . . . 'sex' itself is a category produced in the interests of the heterosexual
contract, or if we consider Foucault's suggestion that 'sex' designates an artificial unity that
works to maintain and amplify the regulation of sexuality within the reproductive domain, then
it seems that gender coherence operates in much the same way, not as a ground of politics but
as its effect").
46. Set, e.g.,Joan Williams, DeconslidingGender, 87 1% icu. L REv. 797 (1989). For criticisms
of feminist essentialism, see generally Harris, supra note 10; Elizabeth Spelman, INEssENr.t.
WoMA.tN (1988). Criticism of relational feminist essentialism comes not only from postmodern
scholars but also from liberal and radical feminists. See, e.g.Jean Hampton, Feminist Contractari-
anism, in A MIND OF ONes OWN: FEmNiST EssAxs ON RLSON AND OBJECnTTY 227, 231 (1993)
(In the results of Gilligan's research showing that boys are more autonomous while girls are
more caring. "I hear the voice of a child who is preparing to be a member of a dominating
group and the voice of another who is preparing to be a member of the group that is
dominated"); MacKinnon, supra note 40, at 38-39 (criticizing relational feminists for valuing
as essentially feminine characteristics, such as nurturing and care, that are the result of male
domination).
47. See, e.g., Harris, supranote 40, at 585 (arguing that result of "gender essentialism" is "not
only that some voices are silenced in order to privilege others ... but that the voices that are
silenced turn out to be the same voices silenced by the mainstream legal voice of We the
People-among them, the voices of black women").
48. See, e.g., Minow, AtakingAll the Diffrence, supra note 2, at 3-4 (raising worries about the
process of categorization that results in the conclusion of difference).
49. Young, The Ideal ofaommunity, supranote 2,at 307.
78 CYNTHIA V. WARD
50. See, e.g., Foster, Difference and Equality, supranote 2, at I II (To be useful in achieving the
goal of equality, a diversity rationale should recognize those differences that have been
constructed into a basis for, and have resulted in, systemic exclusion and disadvantage for
individuals possessing those differences");Janet E Hlalley, Sexual Orientation and the Politics of
Biology: A Critique of the Argument From Immutability, 46 STN. L Riv. 503, 505 (1994) ('The
postuodern critique of liberal explanations of the self posits that culture, not human nature,
gives humans their sexual orientations"); Harris, supranote 2, at 762 (discussing the postmod-
ern "problem of the subject" and claiming that 1[t]he language of race creates, maintains, and
destroys subjects, both inside and outside the law"); id. at 784 ("Racial communities, like other
human communities, are the products of invention, not discovery"); Hutchinson, supra note
11, at 1192 ('The subject is a cultural creation, not a biological given"): Hutchinson, Inessen-
tially Speaking (Is There Politics After Postmodernism?), 89 Micit. L REv. 1549, 1552 (1991) (book
review of Martha Minow, Making All the Diference) (The postmodern temper has no eternal
truth to offer and no immutable knowledge to dispense; it accepts the historically situated and
socially constructed character of truths and knowledges"); id. at 1564 ("Differences are cultur.
ally imposed and socially policed"); Minow, Making All the Difference, supra note 2, at 19-23
(discussing social construction of difference in context of the "difference dilemmas" it pro-
duces).
51. Se,e.g., Butler, supra note 45, at 326 (construction of the autonomous subject requires
domination and oppression); Hutchinson, supra note 50, at 1563 ("Domination has been
perpetuated and rationalized both by embracing difference (superiority of men over women
and white-skinned people over black-skinned people) and by eschewing difference (treatment
of women as men and African Americans as white Europeans). These are the advantages that
have made the establishment of power overwhelmingly white and male"); Minow, Making All
the Deference, supra note 2, at 50 (criticizing linkage in law between "difference" and "devi-
ance"); id. at 53 ("Assertions of a difference as 'the truth' may indeed obscure the power of the
person attributing the difference while excluding important competing perspectives. Differ-
ence is a clue to the social arrangements that make some people less accepted and less
integrated while expressing the needs and interests of others who constitute the presumed
model").
52. Harris, supra note 2, at 762 ('The language of race creates, maintains, and destroys
subjects, both inside and outside die law"): Hutchinson, supranote 50, at 1554 (The process
of labeling and naming is particularly fraught with dangers when it concerns people. To
categorize is to choose, and, in so doing, there is no escaping the responsibility of judgment
or its context of power); Minow, MakingAll the Differnce, supranote 2, at 174-77 (identifying
labeling theory as antecedent to her social relations approach, and explaining that 'labeling
theory studies the process by which an audience or community identifies some people as
deviants. That very pattern of identification has consequences for the labeled person which
are difficult to escape. Those consequences include recurring patterns of exclusion and
deviant behavior. Labeling theory thus treats difference as an idea developed by some people
to describe others and to attribute meaning to others' behavior").
On Difference and Equality 79
53
or her own individual reality. Fourth, the fact that difference is socially
constructed rather than "natural" or intrinsic opens up the possibility of
changing it and reforming societ 5 4 Finally, and perhaps most importantly,
we should worry about the hierarchical deployment of difference labels
because only in doing so will we transcend liberal sameness-based equal-
ity55 and achieve real equality S6
53. See, e.g., Hutchinson, supra note 50, at 1565 ("Although people are never not in a local
context, they are never in a context that is not open to contingent revision"); id. at 1570
("While persons are not reducible to their autobiographies, they never fully escape them; they
forge their identities through the existential tension between confronting or confounding
their autobiographies"); Hutchinson, supra note II, at 1187 ('Embedded in a constitute
discourse of power, readers are also disciplined by the extant protocols of power - they are
subjects in transition"); Minow, MakingalliMeDiffnm r, supra note 2, at 53 ('There is no single,
superior perspective for judging questions of difference. No perspective asserted to produce
'tihe truth' is without a situated perspective, because any statement is made by a person who
has a perspective").
54. See, e.g., Hutchinson, supra note 11, at 1209 ("In the face of the problematized subject,
postmodernism does not capitulate to or retreat from the task of struggling towards an
enhanced social solidarity and experience of justice. The hope is to empower subjects by
making them individually aware of their capacity for self (re)creation and collectively respon-
sible for establishing a mode of social life that multiplies the opportunities for transformative
action"); Alinow. MakingAll tht DiffornCe, supra note 2, at 53 ("Difference is a clue to the social
arrangements that make some people less accepted and less integrated while expressing the
needs and interests of others who constitute the presumed model. And social arrangements
can be changed. Arrangements that assign the burden of "differences" to some people while
making others comfortable are historical artifacts. Maintaining these historical patterns em-
bedded in the status quo is not neutral and cannot be justified by the claim that everyone has
freely chosen to do so').
55. Se, e.g.. notes 4-5 and accompanying text.
56. 'Ze, e.g., note 11 and accompanying text.
57. MerlHutchinson, supma note 50,at 1550-51 (reviewing Professor Minow's book Aaking All
the Diffrne and noting that "In the jurisprudential corner of postmodern scholarship, the
work of Martha Minow deserves especial attention. Infused with a postmodern perspective,
[Minow's] writing stands at the frontiers of modern legal thinking in its efforts to reject and
move beyond the modernist project ofjurisprudence").
58. Suprm note 2. Minow has also explained her viewof difference, and her proposals to cure
the "difference dilennma," in Ier otlier work. See grnerally Minow, Wen Diference Has Its Hone,
supmr note 2; Minow, Formernt:JusticeEngrnderd, supra note 2.
59. Minow. MakingAll the Differnce, supra note 2, at 50-74.
80 CYNTHIA V. WARD
60. Id. at 81-83 (discussing case of Rowley v. Board of Educ., 483 F. Supp. 528 (S.D.N.Y
1980). affd F.2d 945 (2d Cir. 1980); rev'd 158 U.S. 176 (1982). involving dispute between
Rowleys and Board of Education over whether federal law entitled the Rowleys' hearing-im-
paired child, Amy: to a sign-language interpreter in all her classes, or whether the school's
educational plan, which supplemented Amy's experience in 'mainstream" classroom with
special tutoring, satisfied the law). Minow notes. id. at 82, that "[bloth sides [in the case]
assumed that the problem was Amy's: because she was different from other students, the
solution must focus on her. Both sides deployed the unstated norm of the hearing student who
receives educational input from a teacher, rather than imagining a different norm around
which the entire classroom might be constructed."
61. Id.at5l.
62. Id. See also, Young,Justice and the Politics ofDfference. su/a note 2. at 169 (lThe attempt
to reduce all persons to the unity of a common measure constructs as deviant those whose
attributes differ from the group-specific attributes implicitly presumed in the norm. The drive
to unify the particularity and multiplicity of practices ... turns difference into exclusion").
63. Mi now, Aaking AU the Difference, supm note 2. at 31-17.
&M. Id. at 51-52 (describing how U.S. constitutional equality norms "[make] the recognition
of differences a basis for den)ing equal treatment').
65. Id.
On Difference and Equality 81
represented plaintiffs in discrimination cases, would identify with those who
suffer race or sex discrimination. The defendant assumed that Judge Mot-
ley's personal identity and her past political work had made her different,
lacking the [normal judicial] ability to perceive without a perspcctive." 6
Declining to recuse herselfJudge Motley pointed out that "[ilf background
or sex or race of each judge were, by definition, sufficient grounds for
removal, no judge on this court could hear this case [since] ... all of them
were attorneys, of a sex, often with distinguished law firm or public service
backgrounds."67
Fourth, the perspective of those being labeled "different" is either ig-
nored outright or assumed to have been accounted for by those who create
and maintain the particular norm in question.CA Thus,
Fifth, these legal and social practices reinforce the false assumption that
our existing institutional arrangements are natural, neutral, and therefore
inevitable.- 0
Minow argues that the root problem with this way of handling difference
is that it creates and perpetuates inequality- "Buried in the questions about
difference are assumptions that difference is linked to stigma or deviance
and that sameness is a prerequisite for equality." 71 On her view "[dliffer-
ence is relational, not intrinsic," 72 because "[w]ho or what should be taken
as the point of reference for defining differences is debatable." From the
viewpoint of the majority a person in a wheelchair is "handicapped"; from
that person's perspective the majority may be termed "Temporarily Able
Persons." Whose point of view should serve as the anchor of law is a
question that must be discussed rather than buried.73 A related assumption
66. A. at 60-61.
67. li. at 61.
68. Id.
69. Id. at 71.
70. Id.
71. Id. at 50. See also mlinow, Group Hlomes for the Mentally Retarlde, supra note 2. at 113
("Categorical approaches"-attributing difference to different people-ndennine conunit-
ments to equality).
72. I.
73. Id. at 51.
82 CarNix V. WARD
Minow argues that liberal "sameness" assumptions endanger the few spe-
cial benefits accorded to the historically "different": 'Thus, efforts to elimi-
nate gender bias in divorce law have removed alimony and child-custody
provisions that preferred women, and some observers attribute to these
reforms the increased impoverishment and worsened bargaining position
of women following divorce."83 In short, rights-based approaches to law
end tip reinforcing inequality not only by embracing the legal processes
of difference-creation embodied in the five core assumptions outlined
81. See, e.g., Minow, id., supm note 2, at 147 ("Rights analysis offers release from hierarchy
and subordination to those who can match the picture of the abstract, autonomous individual
presupposed by the theory of rights. For those who do not match that picture, application of
rights analysis can be not only unresponsive but also punitive").
82. Id. at 116.
83. Id. at 146-47.
84. See supra, text accompanying notes 59-70.
84 CYNTHIA V. WARD
above, 84 but also by hiding the continuation of social, political, and legal
hierarchy behind the (false) appearance of equal opportunity. 85
At its core, this critique attacks the liberal assumption that autonomy is a
species-wide trait among humans, 86 charging that this assumption illegiti-
mately excludes some persons.8 7 Thus, Minow's fundamental complaint is
against liberal equality as justification: She argues that grounding legal rights
in the descriptive samenesses of agency, rationality, or autonomy is wrong
because it is exclusionary.8 8
85. &e, e.g., 11inow, Aaking All the Diffiirnce, supra note 2, at 152 ("Pretense of universal,
inclusive norms in the public sphere obscures the power of assigned differences in the private
sphere"); id. at 223 ("The relational challenge suggests that [the limits set on responsibilities
by rights analysis] reflect a particular perspective not because it is correct but because it
expresses the worldview of those who have had sufficient power to shape prevailing social
institutions"); id. at 217 (feminist work has contributed to the relational project by "recasting
issues of'difference' as problems of domination or subordination in order to disclose the social
relationships of power within which difference is named and enforced"); id. at 224 (social
relations approach sees "[d]ifferences that yield social distance and exclusion . . . as the self-
serving expressions of the more powerful"); id. at 239 ('Those who win a given struggle for
control may have better access to the means of producing knowledge, such as mass media and
schools. Such control may even shape the terms of access so that exclusions of other points of
view appear neutral, based on merit or on other standards endorsed even by those who remain
excluded").
86. Erg., id. at 155 (criticizing as inevitably situated the liberal reliance on notion of "autono-
mous, able-bodied" person); id. at 150 (tthe heuristic device of the social contract presumes to
address only autonomous, independent individuals"); id. at 216 (charging that rights analysis
applies only to those who are, or can analogize themselves to, independent persons); id. at 147
("Rights analysis offers release from hierarchy and subordination to those who can match the
picture of the abstract, autonomous individual presupposed by the theory of rights. For those
who do not match that picture, application of rights analysis can be not only unresponsive but
also punitive").
87. & e.g., id. at 152 ("Despite the implied aspiration to universal inclusion, the social
contract approach has been deeply exclusionary"); id. at 153 (The presentation of a type of
human being as though it described all human beings risks excluding any who do not fit or
treating such misfits as deviant"); id. at 154 ("Rawls's difference principle preserves too much
of the concept of the abstract individual-a concept that claims but fails to secure universal-
ity-to respond fully to issues of difference"); id. at 155-56 (The natural rights tradition also
partakes of the assumptions of the autonomous and abstract individual and excludes or
subordinates any who fail to meet these assumptions"); id. at 156 ('The premise of a basic
human nature, found in the abstract indhidual capable of reason, undergirds [natural law]
theory and risks excluding any who do not meet it. Theories of natural law locate the
justification for universal rights in human reason or cognition. This focus on reason makes
problematic any persons who do not manifest to the satisfaction of those in charge the requisite
capacities for rational thought," and offering children and the mentally disabled as examples
of such excluded persons).
88. Eg., id. at 146 ('The 'sameness' between people emphasized by rights analysis chal-
lenges special accommodations made for disabled people, women, and others historically
treated as different"); id. at 152 ("All persons are equal because of this finamental same-
ness-yet this sameness seems to be the emptiness left when we are each sheared of all that
makes us different"); id. at 223 ("Equating sameness with equality, rights analysis offers a kind
of certainty and a set of limits: equal treatment, yes, but limited to a comparison with the other
group'); seealsoYoung,Justireand the llitics of Diffrenc, supranote 2, at 171 ("In general, then,
a relational understanding of group difference rejects exclusion").
On Difference and Equality 85
This "argument from exclusion" cannot survive analysis, for at least two
reasons. First, the argument rests upon a dramatically impoverished con-
ception of liberalism. Professor Minow writes that, despite its "admirable
commitment to universality and inclusion,"
the (liberall social contract approach has been deeply exclusionary. It is not
only that any sign of difference, any shred of situated perspective, threatens
the claim to similarity, equality, and identity as an abstract individual-al-
though these problems are serious enough; it is that this conception amounts
to a preference for some points of view over others; it takes some types of
people as the norm and assigns a position of difference to others (thus
adopting the assumptions behind the difference dilemma). 89
what justifies legal equality? Alinow advocates "real equality" through the
proper recognition of difference; but such hopes arc empty rhetoric in the
absence of some underlying justification for the declared equality principle.
As I argue below, 8 equality cannot he fully justified without affirming
sameness of some kind-the rejection of sameness, therefore, necessarily
implies the rejection of any rich theory of legal equality.
b. Ainow's "socialrelations"approach: back to essentialism. The discussion
thus far has revealed core weaknesses in Minow's attack on liberal sameness-
based equality. As a little reflection makes clear, her proposed replacement for
liberal legal structures is even more flawed. In place of conventional civil-
rights methodology, which focuses on crasing miscategorizations of persons
as inferior in behalf of an underlying belief in the rational, autonomous self-
hood of all human beings, 9 Professor Minow advances a suspicion of catego-
rization perse. Minow attempts to move the inquiry from one involving "true"
and "false" categories to one involving the dangers of categorization itself:
[Tihe social relations approach assumes that there is a basic connectedness
between people, instead of assuming that autonomy is the prior and essential
dimension of personhood. ... The social relations approach is dubious of
the method of social organization that constructs human relationships in
terms of immutable categories, fixed statuses and inherited or ascribed
traits. 100
This focus on the primary importance of relationships as the basis for legal
equality immediately raises two questions. First, if it is "ongoing relation-
ships" that ought to trigger the enforcement of constitutional protections,
what happens to individuals-such as those in a "persistent vegetative state"
and those with severe mental disabilities-who are incapable of forming
relationships with others? Isn't Minow simply advocating a new form of
essentialist sameness-the capacity to have relationships-and arguing, in
direct contradiction to her simultaneous rejection of sameness-based rights
per se, that this new sameness should replace autonomy and rationality as
the proper justification of equality? If so, Minow's social relations approach
raises the very same problem of exclusion that prompted her attacks on
liberalism.
Second, the social relations approach relies heavily on the faculty of
empathy as a way of producing discussions about difference between the
powerful and the dominated. Professor Minow wites that the social rela-
tions theory is rooted in "learning to take the perspective of another," and
she presents it as "an opening wedge for an alternative to traditional legal
treatments of difference." 03 By talking and listening to others who are
different, those in power will come to realize that "difference" is relational
and debatable-that the hearing children in a classroom are as different
from their deaf classmate as she is from them-and that issues of difference
thus necessarily place both the "normal" and the "different" person in
relationship to each other. Thus, Minow makes empathy, particularly judi-
cial empathy, into the chief means of moving society from the status quo,
which she depicts as illegitimately individualist and elitist, toward a greater
focus upon the importance of connectedness and relationships.10 4 She
hopes that such empathic perspective-taking will help reconceive rights,
102. Minow. Mien Difference Has Its Home, supra note 2, at 130.
103. 'Minow, AlakingAll theDfference, supm note 2, at 379.
104. See, e.g., id. at 38-1-87. 389 (discussing importance of such perspective taking); Minow:
Ml7int Dqferenre Has Its Home, supm note 2, at 129 (discussing need for judges to adopt the
perspective of those labeled "different"). At one point in her book Nlinow denies that her
approach embraces empathy; see id. at 219. But she seems only to intend by that statement to
separate herself from relational feminist claims that empathy is a natural, organic, and/or
unreflectively easy process, at least for women. Id. at 219-20 (making this point in context of
a short story: "AJury of Her Peers"). In fact, Minow's advocacy of perspective taking constitutes
the definition of empathy* ser: e.g., Robert N. Goldenson, I THE ENClLOPEntA OF I IUmLN
BEItI~lOR: PSILHtOOGY, PSITIlATRL AND MENTAt. HFOLTi 395 (1970) (defining empathy as "the
capacity to understand and in some measure share another person's state of tind"). Whether
empathy comes naturally or is an acquired characteristic, andi whether or not women possess
it more than men, are questions external to the definition of the concept.
90 CvNTHIA V. WARD
105. Minow, Making All the Difference, supra note 2, at 382-83 (defending her concept or
"rights in relationship" as an important tool for challenging hierarchical effects of socially
created difference).
106. For examples of empathy's promotion as a tool of political and legal reform, see, e.g.,
Nancy L Rosenblum, ANOTHER UIBERALISM: RoMxATcIsM A.ND THE RECONSTRUCrION OF LBERAL
THoourr 184 (1987) (linking communitarianism with a "politics of . .. empathy"); Cass Sun-
stein, Beyond the Republiran Reviva 97 YALE .J. 1539. 1555 (1988) (explaining the concept of
political empathy and its connection to communitarian visions of law); Robin West, Laur Rights,
and Other Totemic Illusions:Legal Liberalism and Freud's Theory oftheRuleof Law, 134 U. PA. L REV.
817, 859 (1986) (associating promotion of empathic law with relational feminists and commu-
nitarians); see generally Dailey, supra note 2. 1 have been skeptical about empathy's potential as
a tool for promoting legal communitarianism. See Cynthia V1Ward, A Kinder Gentler Liberalisn
Visions of Enpathy in Feminist and CommunitarianLiterature, 61 U. Citi. L REv. 929 (1994). The
discussion in this section applies the conceptions of empathy introduced in that article.
107. Ward, supra note 106, at 936.
108. Id. at 934-15 (developing a concept of projective empathy as an inherent premise of
liberalism).
109. 347 U.S. 483 (1954).
110. For discussions of empathy's possible role in the Bmwn decision, see, e.g., Lynne N.
Henderson, Legality and Empathy, 85 Micii. L RLv. 1574 (1987); Ward, supra note 106, at
941-12.
111. See, e.g.,bMinow, Making All the Diffemire, supra note 2, at 50, 74-75 (citing defects of
equality principle based on sameness).
On Difference and Equality 91
vision of enipathy, which I have called "imaginative empathy."1"2 This un-
derstanding of empathy acknowledges radical diversity-that empathizer
and other are ineradicably different and separate-but nevertheless as-
sumes that it is possible at least partially to understand the other despite his
or her difference. Imaginative empathy therefore recognizes diversity and
may escape reliance on sameness-but, I have argued, loses any innate
connection with equality1 3 While projective empathy sees through differ-
ence to find equality, imaginative empathy stops at the point of acknow-
ledging and appreciating difference, thereby losing any innate connection
to equality.it 4 The point should be clear: Liberalism incorporates an equal-
ity-friendly understanding of empathy that is rooted in sameness, whereas
nonliberal empathy stands in direct tension with equality. Professor Mi-
now's social relations approach must fail because its core premise, that
empathic "perspective taking" can simultaneously transcend sameness and
embrace equality, is false.
a The emptiness of the postmodern vision of dafference. In sum, neither AMi-
now's critical attacks on liberalism nor her affirmative proposals to replace
it can survive careful analysis. Her critique of liberal rights theories reduces
to one claim: That such theories improperly rely on the concept of auton-
omy to justify equal and individual rights. Minow argues that this reliance
is wrong because it excludes some persons from being treated as equals,
resulting in the labeling of such individuals as "different" and inferior. But
her narrow depiction of the foundations of liberal thought, coupled with
her failure to offer an equality-basedjustification for her universal inclusion
principle, leaves this critique completely undefended.
Minow's affirmative argument for the "social relations approach" not
only raises the spectre of essentialism-which she elsewhere firmly and
repeatedly repudiatesti 5-but also relies heavily on a difference-based con-
cept of empathy that is actually antiequality. Two premises form the core of
the social relations approach: First, sameness-based theories of equality are
wrong because they label some persons as different and inferior; second,
our shared human capacity for empathic dialogue can lead us to real
equality. But to the extent it is rooted in the rejection of sameness, Minow's
theory fights with equality; and insofar as she introduces a new sameness,
the sameness of empathic ability, as the proper basis for rights and legal
categories, Minow-like communitarians and relational feminists-simply
deploys the notion of difference as a stalking horse for her own particular
brand of sameness-based equality.Ir
("Whether intended or not, Minow's reconstruction of "rights language* through the recogni-
tion of their "inevitable relational dimensions" leads her down a familiar path of embracing
communitarianisin") (citation omitted); id. at 187 (Thus, like advocates of the communi-
tarian movement, Minow envisions a community, universal in nature, where the 'language of
rights" draws each claimant into the community and "grants each a basis opportunity to
participate in the process of communal debate").
117. See, e.g., sources cited in note 51; see also, from the critical legal studies camp, Duncan
Kennedy, A Cultural Pluralist Case for Affirmative Action in Legal Academia 1990 DuKE L]. 705,
724 ("Though communities are different in ways that are best understood through the non-hi-
crarchical, neutral idea of culture ... some differences are not like that. Americans pursue
their collective and individual projects in a situation of group domination and group subordi-
nation. With respect to ... common measures of equality and inequality, we all recognize that
some groups are enormously better off than others").
118. This idea of difference as hierarchy is of course shared by many feminists and applied
by them to the analysis of gender issues. See, e.g.,. MacKinnon, supranote 34, at 219 ("Difference
is the velvet glove on the iron fist of [male] domination").
119. See, e.g., Roy L Brooks and Mary Jo Newborn, Critical Race Theory and Classical-Libeml
Civil Rights Scholarship: A Distinction Without a Difference?, 82 CA.1. L REv. 787, 804-44 (arguing
that critical-race critiques of liberal discrimination law imply abolishment of Tile VII); Sheila
Foster, Difference and Equality, supra note 2, at 154 ("At the core of a substantive concept of
diversity, under an equality paradigm, should be a commitment to include individuals with
differences that have been constructed into a basis for systematic disadvantage and exclu-
sion"); id. at 156 ("We must establish institutional participatory patterns that accept and value
the contributions of those differences that have been left out); Harris, The Jurisprudence of
Reconstruction, supm note 2, at 761 ("Rather than supporting assimilation to the dominant
culture, the new social movements have demanded a recognition of their members' 'differ-
ence'").
On Difference and Equality 93
At the root of their proposed "politics of difference"o 20
is the idea that
disadvantaged groups-most prominently racial minorities-have devel-
oped distinct methods of viewing the world and functioning within it that,
as a matter of justice to those groups, must be preserved via the explicit
importation into law of group rights and special treatment.12 1 The goal is
to promote equality'2"-an equality based not on sameness, as in the liberal
rubric, but on racial differences. As critical-race theorist Angela Harris puts
it, This claim to equality based not on sameness but rather on difference
is at the heart of the politics of difference."1 2 3
On a critical-race-theory view, Martha Minow's concern for the dangers
of categorization actually overlooks the positive aspects of difference for
those groups that have been marginalized. According to Sheila Foster, for
example, the danger of Mlinow's approach is that "Minow leaves the power
of transformation, this time with respect to creating identities, in the hands
of those already in power." 24 Foster argues that Minow's social relations
theory constitutes an appeal to the already powerful to listen to the perspec-
tives of the marginalized, while Foster urges more action by the latter
themselves to control the meaning and consequences of differencel25:
120. The term is used by Harris, ThtJurisprudenceof Reconstruction, supra note 2, at 159-66.
and Young,Justire and the Politics of Difference, supranote 2.
121. Ybung,justice and the Politics of Diference, supra note 2, at 156-91 (outlining tenets of
"politics of difference"and describing specific group rights such a politics would favor).
122. Foster, Differencr and Equality, sulna note 2, at 109, 110.
123. Harris,jurispnulenceof Reconstrucion, supranote 2, at 761.
12-1. Foster, suprn note 116, at 191.
125. Foster acknowledges that Minow creates discutrsive space for "adifferent analysiswhen
self-assigned differences" are at stake, id. at 191, but feels that Minow pays too little attention
to this aspect of difference and fails to build it into her social relations approach. Id. at 191-93.
126. Foster, Differenceand Equality, supranote 2, at 192.
127. Id. at 192.
128. Id.
94 CYNTHIA V. WARD
B. Sameness Revisited
These ideas may have much political utility 42 ; the effort here is to isolate
and analyze the concept of difference they employ. Two fundamental asser-
tions lie at its base. First, critical-race theorists urge groups that have been
assigned the label "different" as a badge of inferiority to embracethat differ-
ence in order to "reclaim" it.II3 Second, their goal appears to be to craft
racial equalityfrom such difference, to build a "politics of difference" that,
grounded in the group's internalsameness of shared oppression, takes racial
equality to be its foundational goal.
1. Sameness from Difference?
To rrlnm difference in the name nf enualitv when difference has meant
96 CYNTHIA V. WARD
145. See, e.g., Sunstein, supranote 106 (describing liberal pluralism in these terms); Cynthia
V. Ward, The Limits of LiberalRepublicanism: lWy Gmup-BasedRemedies and Republican Citizenship
Don't Alix, 91 CoLuM. L REv. 581 (1991) (contrasting liberal pluralism with communitarian
republicanism).
146. See, e.g., Foster, Difference and Equality, supranote 2, at 158-59 (1The dominant culture
has exercised its power to develop social and cultural definitions for those deemed outside of
that culture. Consequently, the story of Blacks and other minorities has been created and told
primarily by Whites, with little contribution from the subjects themselves. Blacks and other
minorities have been effectively rendered 'inisible' not because Whites cannot see them, but
because 'whites see primarily what a white dominant culture has trained them to see' and
because the Black stories 'simply do not register'"); Kennedy, supra note 117, at 722 ("An
important human reality is the experience of defining oneself as'a member of a group' in this
strong sense of sharing goals and a discursive practice"); id. at 723 ("Communities have
cultures. This means that individuals have traits that are neither genetically determined nor
voluntarily chosen, but rather consciously and unconsciously taught through community life.
Community life forms customs and habits, capacities to produce linguistic and other perform-
ances, and indiidual understandings of good and bad, true and false, worthy and unworthy");
Young,Justice and the Politics of Diffrence, supranote 2, at 163 ('Today and for the foreseeable
fiutre societies are certainly structured by groups, and some are privileged while others are
oppressed").
147. But see Derrick Bell, Radal Realism, 24 CoNN. L REv. 363, 373-74 (1992) (arguing that
African Americans should abandon quest for racial equality and focus on bettering their
situation in society); Derrick Bell, FACES AT TiHE BoTrosf OF THtE WEll: THIE PERMANENCE OF
RAcism 12 (1992) ("Black people will never gain equality in this country-) (emphasis omitted).
On Difference and Equality 97
different from, but nevertheless equal to, each other. But "equal" in what
sense? The creation of group-defining "sameness" from shared oppres-
sion-or from cultural traditions that originatedin shared oppression-ac-
tually relies upon the continuing existence of difference between groups.
Difference from the other becomes the basis for sameness within the group,
for the very definition of the group as a group.
On what basis, then, can group A argue that its members should be
treated equally to group B? Group definitions that rely upon the shared
"difference" of oppression might create community and a sense of equality
within a group, but cannot justify the establishment of equality between
groups. If the goal is to win equality for one's group vis-fi-vis all other groups
in society, some otherjustification of the intergroup equality principle must
be advanced.148 I submit that this justification can only be grounded in
sameness-not only the sameness of group members to each other, but the
sameness of all groups to all other groups, or in other words, the sameness
of all human beings.
148. Relational feminist theory also faces this problem. Some of Robin West's work, for
example, suggests that women are profoundly different from men at every level. See, e.g., West,
supra note 1, at 17 ("According to the vast literature on difference now being developed by
cultural feminists, women's cognitive development, literary sensibility, aesthetic taste, and
psychological development, no less than our anatomy, are all fundamentally different from
men's. . . . The most significant aspect of our difference, though, is surely the moral differ-
ence"). If this is true, women's equality to men (rather than preferential or inferior treatment)
requires an independent argument showing why women, although so very different, never the-
less possess equal worth.
149. Seen e.g., Harris. supm note 2, at 761.
98 CYNTHIA V. WARD
150. Segenerally Bell, Racial Realism, suprm note 147; Bell, FcFSATTHE lOTflt oFrTHE WELL,
supranote 147; see also Brooks and Newborn, supra note I19, at 798 (racism is "normal science"
in the United States); Harris, supra note 2, at 749 ("Derrick Bell argues that racism is a
permanent feature of the American landscape, not something we can throw off in a magic
moment of emancipation. And in a moment of deep pessimism. Richard Delgado's fictional
friend 'Rodrigo Crenshaw' has suggested that racism is an intrinsic feature of the 'The
Enlightenment' itself') (citations onitted).
On Difference and Equality 99
can legitimately form the basis of citizenship, one is left without a rich
defense of egalitarianism.
The assault on "equality as sameness" must take one of two routes. Either
its consists of a charge that the wmng sameness has grounded politics and
law, or it implies the rejection of equality altogether. In the first instance,
difference theorists are left to find and defend some new commonality (a
task they have so far rejected as "essentialist") 151, in which case the current
focus on the "difference" question ought to be transcended in favor of an
open debate over which vision of equality is the best. In the second instance,
difference advocates are left to discover an entirely new, nonequality-based
structure for law and politics. If political and legal equality are not proper
goals given the "difference" critique, what should be our goals? In the name
of what principle should we worry about differences in power between the
races and genders? In an environment of irreconcilable "difference," how
should we make justice-based arguments for change, or even think about
justice itself Scholars who deploy radical views of difference in order to
argue for social justice must bear the burden of answering these questions.
151. e&gnzenlly I arris, supra not 40 EflZmbeth Spelrnan, supra note 46.
G~A
THEOS
Voum
Nube 2
June
7,>199 7 777 7 77
.. .. .. ... >
CAMBIDG
UNIVERSITYPRS
LEGAL THEORY
ISSN 1352.3252
EDITORS
Jules L Coleman, Yale Law School
Larry Alexander, University of San Diego School of Law
Frederick Schauer, Harvard University,JohnE Kennedy School of Government
EDITORIAL BOARD
BruceAckerman, lthUniversity Saul Levrmore, University of Virginia
Robert Alexy, University of Kid David Lyons, Boston University
AnitaAllen, Georgetown University Neil MacCormick, Edinburgh University
Lea Brilmayer, Nero York University And rei Marmoor, Universityof TelAviv
Ruth Chang, Rutgers University Frank Micheltnan, HarvardUniversity
RobertCooter, UniversityofCalifornia,Berkrhy Michael Moore, UniversityofPennsylvania
Richard Craswell, University of Chicago Stephen Munzer, University of California,Los
feir Dan-Cohen, UniversityofCalifornia,Berkeley Angeles
Antony Duff, StirlingUniversity Jeffrie Mturphy, Arizona State University
Gerald Dworkin, Universityof California, Davis Denn is Patterson, Rutgers University
Ronald Dworkin,New YorkUniversity; Oxford Stephen Perry, University ofPennsylvania
University Gerald Postema, University offNorth Carolina
Robert Ellickson, Yale University MargaretJane Radin,StanfordUniversity
Joel Feinberg, University ofArizona Joseph Raz, Oxford University
John Finnis, Oxford University Donald Regan, University oflich igan
Ruth Gavison, Hebrew University Janet Radcliffe Richards, The Open University, UK
Kent Greenawalt, Columbia University Carol Rose, Yale University
Thomas Grey, Stanford University Roger Shiner, University ofAlberta
Michael Hiechter, UniversityofArizona Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Dartmouth College
Douglas Hleckathorn, University of Connecticut Patricia Smith, UniversityofKentucky
Risto H ilpinen, University ofAliami Cass Sunstein, University ofChicago
Heidi H urd, University of~lennsylvania Csaba larga, Budapest University
Frances Kamm, New York University Jeremy Waldron, Columbia University
Louis Kaplow, HarvardUniversity Steven Walt, University of Virginia
Mark Kelman, Stanford University Wil Waltnchow, AlcAlaster University
Lewis Kornhauser, New York University Richard Wasserstrom, University of Cafornia,
Jody Kraus, University of Virginia SantaCri
Kenneth Kress, University of Iowa Alan Wertheimer, University of Vermont
Brian Leiter, University of Texas, Austin Robin West, Georgetorn University
Editorial Office: Legal Theory, Yale Law School, 127 Wall Street, New Haven, Connecticut 06511. USA; e-mail:
coleman@mail.1aw.yale.edu; fax: 203-432-1040.
Publishing, Subscription, and Advertising Ofices: Cambridge University Press. 40 West 20th Street, New York NY
10011; or Cambridge University Press, The Edinburgh Building, Shaftesbury Road, Cambridge CB2 2RU, England.
Igal Theory is published quarterly. Annual subscription rates for Volume 3, 1997: Institutions: $100.00 in the USA,
Canadaand Mexico; UK066.00 in all other countries. Individuals: $50.00 in the USA, Canada, andMexico; UKS33.00 in
all other countries. Prices include postage and insurance; airmail outside the USA, Canada,and Mexicois £20.00 extra.
Copyright 01997 Cambridge University Press. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, in
any form or by any means, electronic, photocopying or otherwise, without permission from Cambridge University
Press. Photocopying information for users in the USA. The Item-Fee Code for this publication (1352-3252/97 $7.50
+.10) indicates that copying for internal orpersonal use beyond that permitted bySec. 107 or 108 of the US Copyright
Law is authorized for users duly registered with the Copyright Clearance Center (CCC) Transaction Reporting Service,
provided that the appropriate remittance of $7.50 per article is paid directly to: CCC, 222 Rosewood Drive, Danvers,
IA 01923. Specific written permission must be obtained from Cambridge University Press for all other copying.
Contact the ISI Tearsheet Service, 3501 Market Street, Philadelphia, PA 19104, for single copies of separate articles.
Periodicals postage paid at NewYork, NY, and additional mailing offices. Forwarding and Return Postage Guaranteed,
Address Correction Requested. Postmaster Send address changes in the USA and Canada to: Legal Theory, Cambridge
University PressJournals Fulfillment Dept., 110 Midland Ave., Port Chester, NY 10573-4930.
Printed in the United States of America.
CAMBRIDGE: the best in legal studies
-
and to provide an opportunity for them to keep abreast of new Ideas and the progress of
legal reform. Each issue also contains an extensive section of book reviews.
Triannual (ISSN 0008-1973) * Subscription to Volume 56 (1997):
Subscriptions $93.00
International Affairs
Editor: J. E. SPENCE, Managing Editor CAROLINE BLACKER
Published for The Royal Institute of International Affalrs
international Affairs founded In 1922, is the leading policy journal of contemporary world
affairs. It combines broad-based coverage of global policy questions with up-to-date and pen-
etrating analysis of the key processes shaping world developments. Articles by practising poll-
cy-makers and academic specialists keep both general and specialist readers In touch with the
leading edge of European debates, as well as authoritative thinking worldwide on current
International issues.
'in the depth of its analysis, as much as In the range of its policy discussion,
there Is no journal to match International Affairs.'
Professor Fred Halliday, London School of Economics
Quarterly (ISSN 0020-5850) * Subscription to Volume 73 (1997):
Institutions $94.00 * Individuals $64.00
Submitted articles and editorial correspondence should be sent tojules L Coleman, Editor,
Legal Theory, Yale LawSchool, 127 Wall Street, New Haven, CT 06511, USA.
Legal Theory is a quarterly, peer-reviewed journal that will be edited to the highest standards
with the assistance of a prestigious international editorial board. Legal Theory encompasses a
broad range of topics, including but not limited to analytical jurisprudence, normative
jurisprudence, policy analyses of legal institutions and doctrines, theories of law as a social or
cultural phenomenon, and critical perspectives on law and legal institutions.
Preparationofmanuscript. A separate title page should be prepared including the article title,
short title for use as a running head (not to exceed 45 characters), author's full name and
affiliation, and complete contact information (including phone number and e-mail ad-
dress).
Manuscripts should be submitted in triplicate and should conform to ChicagVstyle (however,
see below concerning preparation of reference and note material). Please include a diskette
version of the manuscript; the disk and the hard copy versions should match perfectly.
Manuscripts should be shorter than 10,000 words exclusive of notes. An abstract of no more
than 150 words should be included. Submissions directly commenting on other works in the
existing literature are welcome.
The entire manuscript (including notes and references) should be typed double-spaced on
8-1/2 by 11 inch orA4 paper, with wide margins for copyediting. Manuscript pages should be
numbered consecutively. Authors of accepted articles will be asked to prepare a final version
in thejournal's style and to submit it on disk together with a hard copy version.
Figures. If the manuscriptis accepted for publication, the author must provide figures that are
ready for photographic reproduction; they cannot be redrawn by the publisher, unless the
author pays for the cost of such work. Charts, graphs, or other artwork must be drawn by a
professional artist or computergenerated on a laser printer, in black ink on white paper, and
should remain legible after a 50% reduction. All labels and details on figures should be
clearly printed.
References and notes. References should conform to the legal style of The Bluebook: A Uniform
System ofCitation, 15th edition, published by the Harvard Law Review Association.
Copyediting andproofreading.The publisher reserves the right to copyedit and proofread all
articles accepted for publication, but authors will be consulted in the case of any substantial
changes. Page proofs of each article will be sent to the lead author for correction of
typographical errors only.
General. Submitting an article to Legal Theory implies that it has not been published elsewhere
and is not being considered for publication elsewhere. Authors must obtain written permis-
sion to publish any material for which they do not own copyright. They will be asked to assign
the copyright of their article, under certain conditions, to Cambridge University Press.
Authors of articles will receive 25 offprints of their article free of charge; additional copies
may be purchased if ordered at proof stage on the form provided. (In the case of joint
contributions, offprints will be sent to the first named author unless otherwise requested.)