General Relativity - Benjamin Crowell
General Relativity - Benjamin Crowell
General Relativity - Benjamin Crowell
General Relativity
Benjamin Crowell
www.lightandmatter.com
Fullerton, California
www.lightandmatter.com
Copyright c _2009 Benjamin Crowell
rev. February 15, 2010
Permission is granted to copy, distribute and/or modify this docu-
ment under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution Share-
Alike License, which can be found at creativecommons.org. The
license applies to the entire text of this book, plus all the illustra-
tions that are by Benjamin Crowell. All the illustrations are by
Benjamin Crowell except as noted in the photo credits or in paren-
theses in the caption of the gure. This book can be downloaded
free of charge from www.lightandmatter.com in a variety of formats,
including editable formats.
Brief Contents
1 A Geometrical Theory of Spacetime 11
2 Geometry of Flat Spacetime 35
3 Differential Geometry 71
4 Tensors 103
5 Curvature 129
6 Vacuum Solutions 165
7 Sources 193
8 Gravitational Waves 229
5
6
Contents
1 A Geometrical Theory of Spacetime 11
1.1 Time and causality . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12
1.2 Experimental tests of the nature of time . . . . . . . . 14
The Hafele-Keating experiment, 14.Muons, 16.Gravitational
redshifts, 16.
1.3 Non-simultaneity and the maximum speed of cause and
effect . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17
1.4 Ordered geometry. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18
1.5 The equivalence principle. . . . . . . . . . . . . . 20
Proportionality of inertial and gravitational mass, 20.Geometrical
treatment of gravity, 21.Eotvos experiments, 22.Equivalence
of gravitational elds and accelerations, 23.The equivalence principle,
23.Locality of Lorentz frames, 25.Gravitational redshifts, 27.
The Pound-Rebka experiment, 29.
Problems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 33
2 Geometry of Flat Spacetime 35
2.1 Afne properties of Lorentz geometry. . . . . . . . . 35
2.2 Relativistic properties of Lorentz geometry . . . . . . 40
2.3 The light cone . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 49
Velocity addition, 51.Logic, 53.
2.4 Experimental tests of Lorentz geometry. . . . . . . . 53
Dispersion of the vacuum, 54.Observer-independence of c, 54.
Lorentz violation by gravitational forces, 56.
2.5 Three spatial dimensions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 57
Lorentz boosts in three dimensions, 58.Gyroscopes and the equiv-
alence principle, 58.Boosts causing rotations, 60.An experi-
mental test: Thomas precession in hydrogen, 67.
Problems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 68
3 Differential Geometry 71
3.1 The afne parameter revisited, and parallel transport . . 72
The ane parameter in curved spacetime, 72.Parallel transport,
73.
3.2 Models . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 74
3.3 Intrinsic quantities . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 79
Coordinate independence, 80.
3.4 The metric . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 82
The Euclidean metric, 83.The Lorentz metric, 87.Isometry, in-
ner products, and the Erlangen Program, 87.Einsteins carousel,
89.
3.5 The metric in general relativity. . . . . . . . . . . . 95
The hole argument, 95.A Machian paradox, 96.
3.6 Interpretation of coordinate independence. . . . . . . 97
Is coordinate independence obvious?, 97.Is coordinate indepen-
dence trivial?, 97.Coordinate independence as a choice of gauge,
7
99.
Problems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 100
4 Tensors 103
4.1 Lorentz scalars . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 103
4.2 Four-vectors . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 104
The velocity and acceleration four-vectors, 104.The momentum
four-vector, 106.The frequency four-vector and the relativistic
Doppler shift, 111.A non-example: electric and magnetic elds,
112.The electromagnetic potential four-vector, 113.
4.3 The tensor transformation laws . . . . . . . . . . . 114
4.4 Experimental tests . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 117
Universality of tensor behavior, 117.Speed of light diering from
c, 118.Degenerate matter, 118.
4.5 Conservation laws. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 122
No general conservation laws, 122.Conservation of angular mo-
mentum and frame dragging, 123.
Problems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 126
5 Curvature 129
5.1 Tidal curvature versus curvature caused by local sources 130
5.2 The energy-momentum tensor . . . . . . . . . . . 131
5.3 Curvature in two spacelike dimensions . . . . . . . . 132
5.4 Curvature tensors . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 136
5.5 Some order-of-magnitude estimates . . . . . . . . . 138
The geodetic eect, 139.Deection of light rays, 140.
5.6 The covariant derivative . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 141
The covariant derivative in electromagnetism, 142.The covariant
derivative in general relativity, 143.
5.7 The geodesic equation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 146
Characterization of the geodesic, 147.Covariant derivative with
respect to a parameter, 147.The geodesic equation, 148.Uniqueness,
148.
5.8 Torsion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 149
Are scalars path-dependent?, 149.The torsion tensor, 152.Experimental
searches for torsion, 153.
5.9 From metric to curvature . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 156
Finding given g, 156.Numerical solution of the geodesic equation,
157.The Riemann tensor in terms of the Christoel symbols,
159.Some general ideas about gauge, 159.
Problems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 162
6 Vacuum Solutions 165
6.1 Event horizons . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 165
The event horizon of an accelerated observer, 165.Information
paradox, 167.Radiation from event horizons, 168.
6.2 The Schwarzschild metric . . . . . . . . . . . . . 169
The zero-mass case, 170.Geometrized units, 172.A large-r limit,
172.The complete solution, 173.Geodetic eect, 175.Orbits,
178.Deection of light, 182.
8
6.3 Black holes. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 185
Singularities, 185.Event horizon, 186.Expected formation, 186.
Observational evidence, 186.Singularities and cosmic censorship,
187.Black hole radiation, 188.
Problems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 191
7 Sources 193
7.1 Sources in general relativity. . . . . . . . . . . . . 193
Point sources in a background-independent theory, 193.The Ein-
stein eld equation, 194.The uniform gravitational eld revisited,
195.Energy conditions, 199.The cosmological constant, 201.
7.2 Cosmological solutions. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 203
Evidence for expansion of the universe, 206.A singularity at the
Big Bang, 207.Observability of expansion, 207.The vacuum-
dominated solution, 212.The matter-dominated solution, 217.
Observation, 219.
7.3 Machs principle revisited . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 221
The Brans-Dicke theory, 221.Predictions of the Brans-Dicke theory,
224.Hints of empirical support, 225.Machs principle is false.,
225.
Problems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 227
8 Gravitational Waves 229
8.1 The speed of gravity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 229
8.2 Gravitational radiation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 230
Empirical evidence, 230.Expected properties, 231.Some exact
solutions, 233.Energy content, 235.Rate of radiation, 236.
Problems . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 239
Appendix 1: Excerpts from three papers by Einstein . . . . . . . . . 240
On the electrodynamics of moving bodies . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 240
Does the inertia of a body depend upon its energy content? 253
The foundation of the general theory of relativity . . . . . . . . . . . 255
Appendix 2: Hints and solutions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 260
9
10
Chapter 1
A Geometrical Theory of
Spacetime
I always get a slight brain-shiver, now [that] space and time appear
conglomerated together in a gray, miserable chaos. Sommerfeld
This is a book about general relativity, at a level that is meant
to be accessible to advanced undergraduates.
This is mainly a book about general relativity, not special rel-
ativity. Ive heard the sentiment expressed that books on special
relativity generally do a lousy job on special relativity, compared to
books on general relativity. This is undoubtedly true, for someone
who already has already learned special relativity but wants to
unlearn the parts that are completely wrong in the broader context
of general relativity. For someone who has not already learned spe-
cial relativity, I strongly recommend mastering it rst, from a book
such as Taylor and Wheelers Spacetime Physics. Even an advanced
student may be able to learn a great deal from a masterfully writ-
ten, nonmathematical treatment at an even lower level, such as the
ones in Hewitts, Conceptual Physics or the inexpensive paperback
by Gardner, Relativity Simply Explained.
In the back of this book Ive included excerpts from three papers
by Einstein two on special relativity and one on general relativity.
They can be read before, after, or along with this book. There are
footnotes in the papers and in the main text linking their content
with each other.
I should reveal at the outset that I am not a professional rela-
tivist. My eld of research was nonrelativistic nuclear physics until
I became a community college physics instructor. I can only hope
that my pedagogical experience will compensate to some extent for
my shallow background, and that readers who nd mistakes will be
kind enough to let me know about them using the contact informa-
tion provided at http://www.lightandmatter.com/area4author.
html.
11
1.1 Time and causality
Updating Platos allegory of the cave, imagine two super-intelligent
twins, Alice and Betty. Theyre raised entirely by a robotic tutor
on a sealed space station, with no access to the outside world. The
robot, in accord with the latest fad in education, is programmed to
encourage them to build up a picture of all the laws of physics based
on their own experiments, without a textbook to tell them the right
answers. Putting yourself in the twins shoes, imagine giving up
all your preconceived ideas about space and time, which may turn
out according to relativity to be completely wrong, or perhaps only
approximations that are valid under certain circumstances.
Causality is one thing the twins will notice. Certain events re-
sult in other events, forming a network of cause and eect. One
general rule they infer from their observations is that there is an
unambiguously dened notion of betweenness: if Alice observes that
event 1 causes event 2, and then 2 causes 3, Betty always agrees that
2 lies between 1 and 3 in the chain of causality. They nd that this
agreement holds regardless of whether one twin is standing on her
head (i.e., its invariant under rotation), and regardless of whether
one twin is sitting on the couch while the other is zooming around
the living room in circles on her nuclear fusion scooter (i.e., its also
invariant with respect to dierent states of motion).
You may have heard that relativity is a theory that can be inter-
preted using non-Euclidean geometry. The invariance of between-
ness is a basic geometrical property that is shared by both Euclidean
and non-Euclidean geometry. We say that they are both ordered
geometries. With this geometrical interpretation in mind, it will
be useful to think of events not as actual notable occurrences but
merely as an ambient sprinkling of points at which things could hap-
pen. For example, if Alice and Betty are eating dinner, Alice could
choose to throw her mashed potatoes at Betty. Even if she refrains,
there was the potential for a causal linkage between her dinner and
Bettys forehead.
Betweenness is very weak. Alice and Betty may also make a
number of conjectures that would say much more about causality.
For example: (i) that the universes entire network of causality is
connected, rather than being broken up into separate parts; (ii) that
the events are globally ordered, so that for any two events 1 and 2,
either 1 could cause 2 or 2 could cause 1, but not both; (iii) not only
are the events ordered, but the ordering can be modeled by sorting
the events out along a line, the time axis, and assigning a number t,
time, to each event. To see what these conjectures would entail, lets
discuss a few examples that may draw on knowledge from outside
Alice and Bettys experiences.
Example: According to the Big Bang theory, it seems likely that
the network is connected, since all events would presumably connect
12 Chapter 1 A Geometrical Theory of Spacetime
back to the Big Bang. On the other hand, if (i) were false we might
have no way of nding out, because the lack of causal connections
would make it impossible for us to detect the existence of the other
universes represented by the other parts disconnected from our own
universe.
Example: If we had a time machine, we could violate (ii), but
this brings up paradoxes, like the possibility of killing ones own
grandmother when she was a baby, and in any case nobody knows
how to build a time machine.
Example: There are nevertheless strong reasons for believing
that (ii) is false. For example, if we drop Alice into one black hole,
and Betty into another, they will never be able to communicate
again, and therefore there is no way to have any cause and eect
relationship between Alices events and Bettys.
1
Since (iii) implies (ii), we suspect that (iii) is false as well. But
Alice and Betty build clocks, and these clocks are remarkably suc-
cessful at describing cause-and-eect relationships within the con-
nes of the quarters in which theyve lived their lives: events with
higher clock readings never cause events with lower clock readings.
They announce to their robot tutor that theyve discovered a uni-
versal thing called time, which explains all causal relationships, and
which their experiments show ows at the same rate everywhere
within their quarters.
Ah, the tutor sighs, his metallic voice trailing o.
I know that ah, Tutorbot, Betty says. Come on, cant you
just tell us what we did wrong?
You know that my pedagogical programming doesnt allow that.
Oh, sometimes I just want to strangle whoever came up with
those stupid educational theories, Alice says.
The twins go on strike, protesting that the time theory works
perfectly in every experiment theyve been able to imagine. Tutor-
bot gets on the commlink with his masters and has a long, inaudible
argument, which, judging from the hand gestures, the twins imagine
to be quite heated. He announces that hes gotten approval for a
eld trip for one of the twins, on the condition that she remain in a
sealed environment the whole time so as to maintain the conditions
of the educational experiment.
Who gets to go? Alice asks.
Betty, Tutorbot replies, because of the mashed potatoes.
But I refrained! Alice says, stamping her foot.
Only one time out of the last six that I served them.
1
This point is revisited in section 6.1.
Section 1.1 Time and causality 13
The next day, Betty, smiling smugly, climbs aboard the sealed
spaceship carrying a duel bag lled with a large collection of clocks
for the trip. Each clock has a duplicate left behind with Alice. The
clock design that theyre proudest of consists of a tube with two
mirrors at the ends. A ash of light bounces back and forth between
the ends, with each round trip counting as one tick, one unit of
time. The twins are convinced that this one will run at a constant
rate no matter what, since it has no moving parts that could be
aected by the vibrations and accelerations of the journey.
Bettys eld trip is dull. She doesnt get to see any of the outside
world. In fact, the only way she can tell shes not still at home is that
she sometimes feels strong sensations of acceleration. (Shes grown
up in zero gravity, so the pressing sensation is novel to her.) Shes
out of communication with Alice, and all she has to do during the
long voyage is to tend to her clocks. As a crude check, she veries
that the light clock seems to be running at its normal rate, judged
against her own pulse. The pendulum clock gets out of synch with
the light clock during the accelerations, but that doesnt surprise
her, because its a mechanical clock with moving parts. All of the
nonmechanical clocks seem to agree quite well. She gets hungry for
breakfast, lunch, and dinner at the usual times.
When Betty gets home, Alice asks, Well?
Great trip, too bad you couldnt come. I met some cute boys,
went out dancing, . . .
You did not. What about the clocks?
They all checked out ne. See, Tutorbot? The time theory still
holds up.
That was an anticlimax, Alice says. Im going back to bed
now.
Bed? Betty exclaims. Its three in the afternoon.
The twins now discover that although all of Alices clocks agree
among themselves, and similarly for all of Bettys (except for the
ones that were obviously disrupted by mechanical stresses), Alices
and Bettys clocks disagree with one another. A week has passed
for Alice, but only a couple of days for Betty.
1.2 Experimental tests of the nature of time
1.2.1 The Hafele-Keating experiment
In 1971, J.C. Hafele and R.E. Keating
2
of the U.S. Naval Obser-
vatory brought atomic clocks aboard commercial airliners and went
around the world, once from east to west and once from west to east.
(The clocks had their own tickets, and occupied their own seats.) As
2
Hafele and Keating, Science, 177 (1972), 168
14 Chapter 1 A Geometrical Theory of Spacetime
a / The atomic clock has its
own ticket and its own seat.
in the parable of Alice and Betty, Hafele and Keating observed that
there was a discrepancy between the times measured by the trav-
eling clocks and the times measured by similar clocks that stayed
at the lab in Washington. The result was that the east-going clock
lost an amount of time t
E
= 59 10 ns, while the west-going
one gained t
W
= +273 7 ns. This establishes that time is not
universal and absolute.
Nevertheless, causality was preserved. The nanosecond-scale ef-
fects observed were small compared to the three-day lengths of the
plane trips. There was no opportunity for paradoxical situations
such as, for example, a scenario in which the east-going experimenter
arrived back in Washington before he left and then proceeded to
convince himself not to take the trip.
Hafele and Keating were testing specic quantitative predictions
of relativity, and they veried them to within their experiments
error bars. At this point in the book, we arent in possession of
enough relativity to be able to make such calculations, but, like
Alice and Betty, we can inspect the empirical results for clues as to
how time works.
The opposite signs of the two results suggests that the rate at
which time ows depends on the motion of the observer. The east-
going clock was moving in the same direction as the earths rotation,
so its velocity relative to the earths center was greater than that of
the ones that remained in Washington, while the west-going clocks
velocity was correspondingly reduced.
3
The signs of the ts show
that moving clocks were slower.
On the other hand, the asymmetry of the results, with [t
E
[ , =
[t
W
[, implies that there was a second eect involved, simply due
to the planes being up in the air. Relativity predicts that times
rate of ow also changes with height in a gravitational eld. The
deeper reasons for such an eect are given in section 1.5.8 on page
29.
Although Hafele and Keatings measurements were on the ragged
edge of the state of the art in 1971, technology has now progressed
to the point where such eects have everyday consequences. The
satellites of the Global Positioning System (GPS) orbit at a speed
of 1.9 10
3
m/s, an order of magnitude faster than a commercial
jet. Their altitude of 20,000 km is also much greater than that of
an aircraft. For both these reasons, the relativistic eect on time is
stronger than in the Hafele-Keating experiment. The atomic clocks
aboard the satellites are tuned to a frequency of 10.22999999543
MHz, which is perceived on the ground as 10.23 MHz. (This fre-
3
These dierences in velocity are not simply something that can be eliminated
by choosing a dierent frame of reference, because the clocks motion isnt in
a straight line. The clocks back in Washington, for example, have a certain
acceleration toward the earths axis, which is dierent from the accelerations
experienced by the traveling clocks.
Section 1.2 Experimental tests of the nature of time 15
quency shift will be calculated in example 7 on page 46.)
1.2.2 Muons
Although the Hafele-Keating experiment is impressively direct,
it was not the rst verication of relativistic eects on time, it did
not completely separate the kinematic and gravitational eects, and
the eect was small. An early experiment demonstrating a large and
purely kinematic eect was performed in 1941 by Rossi and Hall,
who detected cosmic-ray muons at the summit and base of Mount
Washington in New Hampshire. The muon has a mean lifetime of
2.2 s, and the time of ight between the top and bottom of the
mountain (about 2 km for muons arriving along a vertical path)
at nearly the speed of light was about 7 s, so in the absence of
relativistic eects, the ux at the bottom of the mountain should
have been smaller than the ux at the top by about an order of
magnitude. The observed ratio was much smaller, indicating that
the clock constituted by nuclear decay processes was dramatically
slowed down by the motion of the muons.
1.2.3 Gravitational redshifts
The rst experiment that isolated the gravitational eect on time
was a 1925 measurement by W.S. Adams of the spectrum of light
emitted from the surface of the white dwarf star Sirius B. The grav-
itational eld at the surface of Sirius B is 4 10
5
g, and the gravi-
tational potential is about 3,000 times greater than at the Earths
surface. The emission lines of hydrogen were redshifted, i.e., re-
duced in frequency, and this eect was interpreted as a slowing of
time at the surface of Sirius relative to the surface of the Earth. His-
torically, the mass and radius of Sirius were not known with better
than order of magnitude precision in 1925, so this observation did
not constitute a good quantitative test.
The rst such experiment to be carried out under controlled
conditions, by Pound and Rebka in 1959, is analyzed quantitatively
in example 4 on page 106.
The rst high-precision experiment of this kind was Gravity
Probe A, a 1976 experiment
4
in which a space probe was launched
vertically from Wallops Island, Virginia, at less than escape veloc-
ity, to an altitude of 10,000 km, after which it fell back to earth and
crashed down in the Atlantic Ocean. The probe carried a hydro-
gen maser clock which was used to control the frequency of a radio
signal. The radio signal was received on the ground, the nonrela-
tivistic Doppler shift was subtracted out, and the residual blueshift
was interpreted as the gravitational eect eect on time, matching
the relativistic prediction to an accuracy of 0.01%.
4
Vessot at al., Physical Review Letters 45 (1980) 2081
16 Chapter 1 A Geometrical Theory of Spacetime
b / Gravity Probe A.
1.3 Non-simultaneity and the maximum speed
of cause and effect
Weve seen that time ows at dierent rates for dierent observers.
Suppose that Alice and Betty repeat their Hafele-Keating-style ex-
periment, but this time they are allowed to communicate during
the trip. Once Bettys ship completes its initial acceleration away
from Betty, she cruises at constant speed, and each girl has her own
equally valid inertial frame of reference. Each twin considers herself
to be at rest, and says that the other is the one who is moving.
Each one says that the others clock is the one that is slow. If they
could pull out their phones and communicate instantaneously, with
no time lag for the propagation of the signals, they could resolve
the controversy. Alice could ask Betty, What time does your clock
read right now? and get an immediate answer back.
By the symmetry of their frames of reference, however, it seems
that that Alice and Betty should not be able to resolve the contro-
versy during Bettys trip. If they could, then they could release two
radar beacons that would permanently establish two inertial frames
of reference, A and B, such that time owed, say, more slowly in B
than in A. This would violate the principle that motion is relative,
and that all inertial frames of reference are equally valid. The best
that they can do is to compare clocks once Betty returns, and verify
that the net result of the trip was to make Bettys clock run more
slowly on the average.
Alice and Betty can never satisfy their curiosity about exactly
when during Bettys voyage the discrepancies accumulated or at
Section 1.3 Non-simultaneity and the maximum speed of cause and effect 17
what rate. This is information that they can never obtain, but
they could obtain it if they had a system for communicating in-
stantaneously. We conclude that instantaneous communication is
impossible. There must be some maximum speed at which signals
can propagate or, more generally, a maximum speed at which
cause and eect can propagate and this speed must for example
be greater than or equal to the speed at which radio waves propa-
gate. It is also evident from these considerations that simultaneity
itself cannot be a meaningful concept in relativity.
1.4 Ordered geometry
Lets try to put what weve learned into a general geometrical con-
text.
Euclids familiar geometry of two-dimensional space has the fol-
lowing axioms,
5
which are expressed in terms of operations that can
be carried out with a compass and unmarked straightedge:
E1 Two points determine a line.
E2 Line segments can be extended.
E3 A unique circle can be constructed given any point as its center
and any line segment as its radius.
E4 All right angles are equal to one another.
E5 Parallel postulate: Given a line and a point not on the line,
no more than one line can be drawn through the point and
parallel to the given line.
6
The modern style in mathematics is to consider this type of
axiomatic system as a self-contained sandbox, with the axioms, and
any theorems proved from them, being true or false only in relation
to one another. Euclid and his contemporaries, however, believed
them to be empirical facts about physical reality. For example, they
considered the fth postulate to be less obvious than the rst four,
because in order to verify physically that two lines were parallel,
one would theoretically have to extend them to an innite distance
and make sure that they never crossed. In the rst 28 theorems of
the Elements, Euclid restricts himself entirely to propositions that
can be proved based on the more secure rst four postulates. The
more general geometry dened by omitting the parallel postulate is
known as absolute geometry.
5
These axioms are summarized for quick reference in the back of the book on
page 272.
6
This is a form known as Playfairs axiom, rather than the version of the
postulate originally given by Euclid.
18 Chapter 1 A Geometrical Theory of Spacetime
What kind of geometry is likely to be applicable to general rel-
ativity? We can see immediately that Euclidean geometry, or even
absolute geometry, would be far too specialized. We have in mind
the description of events that are points in both space and time.
Conning ourselves for ease of visualization to one dimension worth
of space, we can certainly construct a plane described by coordi-
nates (t, x), but imposing Euclids postulates on this plane results
in physical nonsense. Space and time are physically distinguishable
from one another. But postulates 3 and 4 describe a geometry in
which distances measured along non-parallel axes are comparable,
and gures may be freely rotated without aecting the truth or
falsehood of statements about them; this is only appropriate for a
physical description of dierent spacelike directions, as in an (x, y)
plane whose two axes are indistinguishable.
We need to throw most of the specialized apparatus of Euclidean
geometry overboard. Once weve stripped our geometry to a bare
minimum, then we can go back and build up a dierent set of equip-
ment that will be better suited to relativity.
The stripped-down geometry we want is called ordered geometry,
and was developed by Moritz Pasch around 1882. As suggested by
the parable of Alice and Betty, ordered geometry does not have
any global, all-encompassing system of measurement. When Betty
goes on her trip, she traces out a particular path through the space
of events, and Alice, staying at home, traces another. Although
events play out in cause-and-eect order along each of these paths,
we do not expect to be able to measure times along paths A and B
and have them come out the same. This is how ordered geometry
works: points can be put in a denite order along any particular
line, but not along dierent lines. Of the four primitive concepts
used in Euclids E1-E5 point, line, circle, and angle only the
non-metrical notions of point (i.e., event) and line are relevant in
ordered geometry. In a geometry without measurement, there is no
concept of measuring distance (hence no compasses or circles), or of
measuring angles. The notation [ABC] indicates that event B lies
on a line segment joining A and C, and is strictly between them.
The axioms of ordered geometry are as follows:
7
7
The axioms are summarized for convenient reference in the back of the book
on page 272. This is meant to be an informal, readable summary of the system,
pitched to the same level of looseness as Euclids E1-E5. Modern mathematicians
have found that systems like these actually need quite a bit more technical
machinery to be perfectly rigorous, so if you look up an axiomatization of ordered
geometry, or a modern axiomatization of Euclidean geometry, youll typically
nd a much more lengthy list of axioms than the ones presented here. The
axioms Im omitting take care of details like making sure that there are more
than two points in the universe, and that curves cant cut through one another
intersecting. The classic, beautifully written book on these topics is H.S.M.
Coxeters Introduction to Geometry, which is introductory in the sense that
its the kind of book a college math major might use in a rst upper-division
Section 1.4 Ordered geometry 19
b / Stephen Hawking (1942-).
a / Axioms O2 (left) and O3
(right).
O1 Two events determine a line.
O2 Line segments can be extended: given A and B, there is at
least one event such that [ABC] is true.
O3 Lines dont wrap around: if [ABC] is true, then [BCA] is false.
O4 Betweenness: For any three distinct events A, B, and C lying
on the same line, we can determine whether or not B is between
A and C (and by statement 3, this ordering is unique except
for a possible over-all reversal to form [CBA]).
O1-O2 express the same ideas as Euclids E1-E2. Not all lines
in the system will correspond physically to chains of causality; we
could have a line segment that describes a snapshot of a steel chain,
and O3-O4 then say that the order of the links is well dened. But
O3 and O4 also have clear physical signicance for lines describing
causality. O3 forbids time travel paradoxes, like going back in time
and killing our own grandmother as a child. O4 says that events
are guaranteed to have a well-dened cause-and-eect order only
if they lie on the same line. This is completely dierent from the
attitude expressed in Newtons famous statement: Absolute, true
and mathematical time, of itself, and from its own nature ows
equably without regard to anything external . . .
If youre dismayed by the austerity of a system of geometry with-
out any notion of measurement, you may be more appalled to learn
that even a system as weak as ordered geometry makes some state-
ments that are too strong to be completely correct as a foundation
for relativity. For example, if an observer falls into a black hole, at
some point he will reach a central point of innite density, called a
singularity. At this point, his chain of cause and eect terminates,
violating statement 2. It is also an open question whether O3s pro-
hibition on time-loops actually holds in general relativity; this is
Stephen Hawkings playfully named chronology protection conjec-
ture. Well also see that in general relativity O1 is almost always
true, but there are exceptions.
1.5 The equivalence principle
1.5.1 Proportionality of inertial and gravitational mass
What physical interpretation should we give to the lines de-
scribed in ordered geometry? Galileo described an experiment (which
he may or may not have actually performed) in which he simultane-
ously dropped a cannonball and a musket ball from a tall tower. The
two objects hit the ground simultaneously, disproving Aristotles as-
sertion that objects fell at a speed proportional to their weights. On
a graph of spacetime with x and t axes, the curves traced by the two
course in geometry.
20 Chapter 1 A Geometrical Theory of Spacetime
a / The cannonball and the mus-
ketball have identical parabolic
world-lines. On this type of
space-time plot, space is conven-
tionally shown on the horizontal
axis, so the tower has to be
depicted on its side.
b / A piece of string held taut
on a globe forms a geodesic
from Mexico City to London.
Although it appears curved, it
is the analog of a straight line
in the non-Euclidean geometry
conned to the surface of the
Earth. Similarly, the world-lines of
gure a appear curved, but they
are the analogs of straight lines
in the non-Euclidean geometry
used to describe gravitational
elds in general relativity.
objects, called their world-lines, are identical parabolas. (The paths
of the balls through x y z space are straight, not curved.) One
way of explaining this observation is that what we call mass is re-
ally two separate things, which happen to be equal. Inertial mass,
which appears in Newtons a = F/m, describes how dicult it is
to accelerate an object. Gravitational mass describes the strength
with which gravity acts. The cannonball has a hundred times more
gravitational mass than the musket ball, so the force of gravity act-
ing on it is a hundred times greater. But its inertial mass is also
precisely a hundred times greater, so the two eects cancel out, and
it falls with the same acceleration. This is a special property of the
gravitational force. Electrical forces, for example, do not behave
this way. The force that an object experiences in an electric eld
is proportional to its charge, which is unrelated to its inertial mass,
so dierent charges placed in the same electric eld will in general
have dierent motions.
1.5.2 Geometrical treatment of gravity
Einstein realized that this special property of the gravitational
force made it possible to describe gravity in purely geometrical
terms. We dene the world-lines of objects acted on by gravity
to be the lines described by the axioms of the geometry. Since we
normally think of the lines described by Euclidean geometry and
its kin as straight lines, this amounts to a redenition of what it
means for a line to be straight. By analogy, imagine stretching a
piece of string taut across a globe, as we might do in order to plan
an airplane ight or aim a directional radio antenna. The string
may not appear straight as viewed from the three-dimensional Eu-
clidean space in which the globe is embedded, but it is as straight
as possible in the sense that it is the path followed by a radio wave,
8
or by an airplane pilot who keeps her wings level and her rudder
straight. The world-line of an object acted on by nongravita-
tional forces is not considered to be a straight line in the sense of
O1-O4. When necessary, one eliminates this ambiguity in the over-
loaded term line by referring to the lines of O1-O4 as geodesics.
The world-line of a low-mass object acted on only by gravity is one
type of geodesic.
9
We can now see the deep physical importance of statement O1,
that two events determine a line. To predict the trajectory of a
golf ball, we need to have some initial data. For example, we could
measure event A when the ball breaks contact with the club, and
event B an innitesimal time after A.
10
This pair of observations can
be thought of as xing the balls initial position and velocity, which
8
Radio waves in the HF band tend to be trapped between the ground and
the ionosphere, causing them to curve over the horizon, allowing long-distance
communication.
9
For more justication of this statement, see ch. 8, problem 1, on page 239.
10
Regarding innitesimals, see p. 77.
Section 1.5 The equivalence principle 21
c / Lor and E otv os (1848-1919).
d / If the geodesics dened
by an airplane and a radio wave
differ from one another, then
it is not possible to treat both
problems exactly using the same
geometrical theory. In general
relativity, this would be analogous
to a violation of the equivalence
principle. General relativitys
validity as a purely geometrical
theory of gravity requires that the
equivalence principle be exactly
satised in all cases.
should be enough to predict a unique world-line for the ball, since
relativity is a deterministic theory. With this interpretation, we can
also see why it is not necessarily a disaster for the theory if O1
fails sometimes. For example, event A could mark the launching of
two satellites into circular orbits from the same place on the Earth,
heading in opposite directions, and B could be their subsequent
collision on the opposite side of the planet. Although this violates
O1, it doesnt violate determinism. Determinism only requires the
validity of O1 for events innitesimally close together. Even for
randomly chosen events far apart, the probability that they will
violate O1 is zero.
1.5.3 E otv os experiments
Einsteins entire system breaks down if there is any violation, no
matter how small, of the proportionality between inertial and grav-
itational mass, and it therefore becomes very interesting to search
experimentally for such a violation. For example, we might won-
der whether neutrons and protons had slightly dierent ratios of
gravitational and inertial mass, which in a Galileo-style experiment
would cause a small dierence between the acceleration of a lead
weight, with a large neutron-to-proton ratio, and a wooden one,
which consists of light elements with nearly equal numbers of neu-
trons and protons. The rst high-precision experiments of this type
were performed by Eotvos around the turn of the twentieth century,
and they veried the equivalence of inertial and gravitational mass
to within about one part in 10
8
. These are generically referred to
as Eotvos experiments.
Figure e shows a strategy for doing Eotvos experiments that al-
lowed a test to about one part in 10
12
. The top panel is a simplied
version. The platform is balanced, so the gravitational masses of
the two objects are observed to be equal. The objects are made
of dierent substances. If the equivalence of inertial and gravita-
tional mass fails to hold for these two substances, then the force
of gravity on each mass will not be exact proportion to its inertia,
and the platform will experience a slight torque as the earth spins.
The bottom panel shows a more realistic drawing of an experiment
by Braginskii and Panov.
11
The whole thing was encased in a tall
vacuum tube, which was placed in a sealed basement whose tem-
perature was controlled to within 0.02
.
the original square, and since bisection is an ane property that
is preserved when we change frames of reference, the parallelogram
must be equilateral.
We can now determine the complete form of the Lorentz transfor-
mation. Let unit square PQRS, as described above, be transformed
to parallelogram P
, t
). Let
the t
coordinate of R
to R
, t
) frame. By
the denition of v, R
and P
, we nd the area of P
to be
2
(1 v
2
),
and setting this equal to 1 gives
=
1
1 v
2
.
Self-check: Interpret the dependence of on the sign of v.
d / The behavior of the factor.
The result for the transformation L, a Lorentz boost along the
x axis with velocity v, is:
t
= t +vx
x
= vt +x
Section 2.2 Relativistic properties of Lorentz geometry 43
The symmetry of P
and Q
.
The observer in this frame of
reference judges them to have
been emitted at different times,
and to have traveled different
distances.
emitting body.
Einsteins P1 is essentially the same as our L3 (equivalence of iner-
tial frames). He implicitly assumes something equivalent to our L1
(homogeneity and isotropy of spacetime). In his system, our L5 (no
simultaneity) is a theorem proved from the axioms P1-P2, whereas
in our system, his P2 is a theorem proved from the axioms L1-L5.
Example: 5
Let the intersection of the parallelograms two diagonals be T in
the original (rest) frame, and T
, where =
_
gdy is the gravitational potential per
unit mass. When is small, this causes a relative effect equal
to . The total effect for a GPS satellite is thus (inserting fac-
tors of c for calculation with SI units, and using positive signs for
blueshifts)
1
c
2
_
+
v
2
2
_
= 5.2 10
10
0.9 10
10
,
where the rst term is gravitational and the second kinematic. A
more detailed analysis includes various time-varying effects, but
46 Chapter 2 Geometry of Flat Spacetime
this is the constant part. For this reason, the atomic clocks aboard
the satellites are set to a frequency of 10.22999999543 MHz be-
fore launching them into orbit; on the average, this is perceived
on the ground as 10.23 MHz. A more complete analysis of the
general relativity involved in the GPS system can be found in the
review article by Ashby.
7
Self-check: Suppose that positioning a clock at a certain dis-
tance from a certain planet produces a fractional change in the
rate at which time ows. In other words, the time dilation factor
is 1 + . Now suppose that a second, identical planet is brought
into the picture, at an equal distance from the clock. The clock is
positioned on the line joining the two planets centers, so that the
gravitational eld it experiences is zero. Is the fractional time dila-
tion now approximately 0, or approximately 2? Why is this only
an approximation?
f / Apparatus used for the test
of relativistic time dilation de-
scribed in example 8. The promi-
nent black and white blocks are
large magnets surrounding a cir-
cular pipe with a vacuum inside.
(c) 1974 by CERN.
Large time dilation Example: 8
The time dilation effect in the Hafele-Keating experiment was very
small. If we want to see a large time dilation effect, we cant do
it with something the size of the atomic clocks they used; the
kinetic energy would be greater than the total megatonnage of
all the worlds nuclear arsenals. We can, however, accelerate
subatomic particles to speeds at which is large. An early, low-
precision experiment of this kind was performed by Rossi and Hall
in 1941, using naturally occurring cosmic rays. Figure f shows a
1974 experiment
8
of a similar type which veried the time dilation
predicted by relativity to a precision of about one part per thou-
sand.
7
N. Ashby, Relativity in the Global Positioning System, http://www.
livingreviews.org/lrr-2003-1
8
Bailey at al., Nucl. Phys. B150(1979) 1
Section 2.2 Relativistic properties of Lorentz geometry 47
h / The change in the frequency
of x-ray photons emitted by
57
Fe
as a function of temperature,
drawn after Pound And Rebka
(1960). Dots are experimental
measurements. The solid curve
is Pound and Rebkas theoretical
calculation using the Debye the-
ory of the lattice vibrations with
a Debye temperature of 420 de-
grees C. The dashed line is one
with the slope calculated in the
text using a simplied treatment
of the thermodynamics. There is
an arbitrary vertical offset in the
experimental data, as well as the
theoretical curves.
g / Muons accelerated to nearly c
undergo radioactive decay much
more slowly than they would
according to an observer at rest
with respect to the muons. The
rst two data-points (unlled
circles) were subject to large
systematic errors.
Muons were produced by an accelerator at CERN, near Geneva.
A muon is essentially a heavier version of the electron. Muons un-
dergo radioactive decay, lasting an average of only 2.197 s be-
fore they evaporate into an electron and two neutrinos. The 1974
experiment was actually built in order to measure the magnetic
properties of muons, but it produced a high-precision test of time
dilation as a byproduct. Because muons have the same electric
charge as electrons, they can be trapped using magnetic elds.
Muons were injected into the ring shown in gure f, circling around
it until they underwent radioactive decay. At the speed at which
these muons were traveling, they had = 29.33, so on the av-
erage they lasted 29.33 times longer than the normal lifetime. In
other words, they were like tiny alarm clocks that self-destructed
at a randomly selected time. Figure g shows the number of ra-
dioactive decays counted, as a function of the time elapsed af-
ter a given stream of muons was injected into the storage ring.
The two dashed lines show the rates of decay predicted with and
without relativity. The relativistic line is the one that agrees with
experiment.
Time dilation in the Pound-Rebka experiment Example: 9
In the description of the Pound-Rebka experiment on page 29, I
postponed the quantitative estimation of the frequency shift due
to temperature. Classically, one expects only a broadening of
the line, since the Doppler shift is proportional to v
/c, where
v
= t +vx
x
= vt +x
y
= y
z
= z
Based on the trivial nature of this generalization, it might seem
as though no qualitatively new considerations would arise in 3+1
dimensions as compared with 1+1. To see that this is not the case,
consider gure a. A boost along the x axis tangles up the x and
t coordinates. A y-boost mingles y and t. Therefore consecutive
boosts along x and y can cause x and y to mix. The result, as
well see in more detail below, is that two consecutive boosts along
non-collinear axes are not equivalent to a single boost; they are
equivalent to a boost plus a spatial rotation. The remainder of this
section discusses this eect, known as Thomas precession, in more
detail; it can be omitted on a rst reading.
Self-check: Apply similar reasoning to a Galilean boost.
2.5.2 Gyroscopes and the equivalence principle
To see how this mathematical fact would play out as a physical
eect, we need to consider how to make a physical manifestation of
the concept of a direction in space.
In two space dimensions, we can construct a ring laser, b/1,
which in its simplest incarnation is a closed loop of optical ber
with a bidirectional laser inserted in one place. Coherent light tra-
verses the loop simultaneously in both directions, interfering in a
beat pattern, which can be observed by sampling the light at some
point along the loops circumference. If the loop is rotated in its
own plane, the interference pattern is altered, because the beam-
sampling device is in a dierent place, and the path lengths traveled
by the two beams has been altered. This phase shift is called the
Sagnac eect, after M. Georges Sagnac, who observed the eect in
1913 and interpreted it, incorrectly, as evidence for the existence of
the aether.
15
The loop senses its own angular acceleration relative
15
Comptes rendus de lAcademie des science 157 (1913) 708
58 Chapter 2 Geometry of Flat Spacetime
to an inertial reference frame. If we transport the loop while always
carefully adjusting its orientation so as to prevent phase shifts, then
its orientation has been preserved. The atomic clocks used in the
Hafele-Keating atomic-clock experiment described on page 14 were
sensitive to Sagnac eects, and it was not practical to maintain their
orientations while they were strapped into seats on a passenger jet,
so this orientational eect had to be subtracted out of the data at
the end of the experiment.
In three spatial dimensions, we could build a spherical cavity
with a reective inner surface, and release a photon inside, b/2.
In reality, the photon-in-a-cavity is not very practical. The pho-
ton would eventually be absorbed or scattered, and it would also be
dicult to accurately initialize the device and read it out later. A
more practical tool is a gyroscope. For example, one of the classic
tests of general relativity is the 2007 Gravity Probe B experiment
(discussed in detail on pages 139 and 175), in which four gyro-
scopes aboard a satellite were observed to precess due to special-
and general-relativistic eects.
The gyroscope, however, is not so obviously a literal implemen-
tation of our basic concept of a direction. How, then, can we be sure
that its behavior is equivalent to that of the photon-in-a-cavity? We
could, for example, carry out a complete mathematical development
of the angular momentum vector in relativity.
16
The equivalence
principle, however, allows us to bypass such technical details. Sup-
pose that we seal the two devices inside black boxes, with identical
external control panels for initializing them and reading them out.
We initialize them identically, and then transport them along side-
by-side world-lines. Classically, both the mechanical gyroscope and
the photon-gyroscope would maintain absolute, xed directions in
space. Relativistically, they will not necessarily maintain their ori-
entations. For example, weve already seen in section 2.5.1 that
there are reasons to expect that their orientations will change if
they are subjected to accelerations that are not all along the same
line. Because relativity is a geometrical theory of spacetime, this
dierence between the classical and relativistic behavior must be
determinable from purely geometrical considerations, such as the
shape of the world-line. If it depended on something else, then we
could conceivably see a disagreement in the outputs of the two in-
struments, but this would violate the equivalence principle.
Suppose there were such a discrepancy. That discrepancy would
be a physically measurable property of the spacetime region through
which the two gyroscopes had been transported. The eect would
have a certain magnitude and direction, so by collecting enough data
we could map it out as vector eld covering that region of spacetime.
16
This is done, for example, in Misner, Thorne, and Wheeler, Gravitation, pp.
157-159.
Section 2.5 Three spatial dimensions 59
c / Classically, the gyroscope
should not rotate as long as the
forces from the hammer are all
transmitted to it at its center of
mass.
This eld evidently causes material particles to accelerate, since it
has an eect on the mechanical gyroscope. Roughly speaking (the
reasoning will be lled in more rigorously on page 117), the fact
that this eld acts dierently on the two gyroscopes is like getting a
non-null result from an Eotvos experiment, and it therefore violates
the equivalence principle. We conclude that gyroscopes b/2 and
b/3 are equivalent. In other words, there can only be one uniquely
dened notion of direction, and the details of how it is implemented
are irrelevant.
2.5.3 Boosts causing rotations
As a quantitative example, consider the following thought ex-
periment. Put a gyroscope in a box, and send the box around the
square path shown in gure c at constant speed. The gyroscope de-
nes a local coordinate system, which according to classical physics
would maintain its orientation. At each corner of the square, the
box has its velocity vector changed abruptly, as represented by the
hammer. We assume that the hits with the hammer are transmitted
to the gyroscope at its center of mass, so that they do not result in
any torque. Classically, if the set of gyroscopes travels once around
the square, it should end up at the same place and in the same ori-
entation, so that the coordinate system it denes is identical with
the original one.
For notation, let L(v x) indicate the boost along the x axis de-
scribed by the transformation on page 58. This is a transformation
that changes to a frame of reference moving in the negative x direc-
tion compared to the original frame. A particle considered to be at
rest in the original frame is described in the new frame as moving
in the positive x direction. Applying such an L to a vector p, we
calculate Lp, which gives the coordinates of the event as measured
in the new frame. An expression like MLp is equivalent by asso-
ciativity to M(Lp), i.e., ML represents applying L rst, and then
M.
In this notation, the hammer strikes can be represented by a
series of four Lorentz boosts,
T = L(v x) L(v y) L(v x) L(v y) ,
where we assume that the square has negligible size, so that all four
Lorentz boosts act in a way that preserves the origin of the coordi-
nate systems. (We have no convenient way in our notation L(. . .) to
describe a transformation that does not preserve the origin.) The
rst transformation, L(v y), changes coordinates measured by the
original gyroscope-dened frame to new coordinates measured by
the new gyroscope-dened frame, after the box has been acceler-
ated in the positive y direction.
The calculation of T is messy, and to be honest, I made a series
of mistakes when I tried to crank it out by hand. Calculations in
60 Chapter 2 Geometry of Flat Spacetime
d / A page from one of Einsteins
notebooks.
relativity have a reputation for being like this. Figure d shows a page
from one of Einsteins notebooks, written in fountain pen around
1913. At the bottom of the page, he wrote zu umstaendlich,
meaning too involved. Luckily we live in an era in which this sort
of thing can be handled by computers. Starting at this point in the
book, I will take appropriate opportunities to demonstrate how to
use the free and open-source computer algebra system Maxima to
keep complicated calculations manageable. The following Maxima
program calculates a particular element of the matrix T.
1 /* For convenience, define gamma in terms of v: */
2 gamma:1/sqrt(1-v*v);
3 /* Define Lx as L(x-hat), Lmx as L(-x-hat), etc.: */
4 Lx:matrix([gamma, gamma*v, 0],
5 [gamma*v, gamma, 0],
6 [0, 0, 1]);
7 Ly:matrix([gamma, 0, gamma*v],
8 [0, 1, 0],
9 [gamma*v, 0, gamma]);
10 Lmx:matrix([gamma, -gamma*v, 0],
11 [-gamma*v, gamma, 0],
12 [0, 0, 1]);
13 Lmy:matrix([gamma, 0, -gamma*v],
Section 2.5 Three spatial dimensions 61
14 [0, 1, 0],
15 [-gamma*v, 0, gamma]);
16 /* Calculate the product of the four matrices: */
17 T:Lx.Ly.Lmx.Lmy;
18 /* Define a column vector along the x axis: */
19 P:matrix([0],[1],[0]);
20 /* Find the result of T acting on this vector,
21 expressed as a Taylor series to second order in v: */
22 taylor(T.P,v,0,2);
Statements are terminated by semicolons, and comments are writ-
ten like /* ... */ On line 2, we see a symbolic denition of the
symbol gamma in terms of the symbol v. The colon means is de-
ned as. Line 2 does not mean, as it would in most programming
languages, to take a stored numerical value of v and use it to cal-
culate a numerical value of . In fact, v does not have a numerical
value dened at this point, nor will it ever have a numerical value
dened for it throughout this program. Line 2 simply means that
whenever Maxima encounters the symbol gamma, it should take it as
an abbreviation for the symbol 1/sqrt(1-v*v). Lines 5-16 dene
some 33 matrices that represent the L transformations. The basis
is
t, x, y. Line 18 calculates the product of the four matrices; the
dots represent matrix multiplication. Line 23 denes a vector along
the x axis, expressed as a column matrix (three rows of one column
each) so that Maxima will know how to operate on it using matrix
multiplication by T.
Finally line 26 outputs
17
the result of T acting on P:
19 [ 0 + . . . ]
20 [ ]
21 (%o9)/T/ [ 1 + . . . ]
22 [ ]
23 [ 2 ]
24 [ - v + . . . ]
In other words,
T
_
_
0
1
0
_
_
=
_
_
0
1
v
2
_
_
+. . . ,
where . . . represents higher-order terms in v. Suppose that we use
the initial frame of reference, before T is applied, to determine that
a particular reference point, such as a distant star, is along the x
axis. Applying T, we get a new vector TP, which we nd has a non-
vanishing y component approximately equal to v
2
. This result is
17
Ive omitted some output generated automatically from the earlier steps in
the computation. The (%o9) indicates that this is Maximas output from the
ninth and nal step.
62 Chapter 2 Geometry of Flat Spacetime
entirely unexpected classically. It tells us that the gyroscope, rather
than maintaining its original orientation as it would have done clas-
sically, has rotated slightly. It has precessed in the counterclockwise
direction in the xy plane, so that the direction to the star, as mea-
sured in the coordinate system dened by the gyroscope, appears
to have rotated clockwise. As the box moved clockwise around the
square, the gyroscope has apparently rotated by a counterclockwise
angle v
2
about the z axis. We can see that this is a purely
relativistic eect, since for v 1 the eect is small. For historical
reasons discussed in section 2.5.4, this phenomenon is referred to as
the Thomas precession.
The particular features of this square geometry are not necessary.
I chose them so that (1) the boosts would be along the Cartesian
axes, so that we would be able to write them down easily; (2) it is
clear that the eect doesnt arise from any asymmetric treatment
of the spatial axes; and (3) the change in the orientation of the
gyroscope can be measured at the same point in space, e.g., by
comparing it with a twin gyroscope that stays at home. In general:
A gyroscope transported around a closed loop in at space-
time changes its orientation compared with one that is not
accelerated.
This is a purely relativistic eect, since a classical gyroscope
does not change its axis of rotation unless subjected to a
torque; if the boosts are accomplished by forces that act at
the gyroscopes center of mass, then there is no classical ex-
planation for the eect.
The eect can occur in the absence of any gravitational elds.
That is, this is a phenomenon of special relativity.
The composition of two or more Lorentz boosts along dierent
axes is not equivalent to a single boost; it is equivalent to a
boost plus a spatial rotation.
Lorentz boosts do not commute, i.e., it makes a dierence what
order we perform them in. Even if there is almost no time lag
between the rst boost and the second, the order of the boosts
matters. If we had applied the boosts in the opposite order,
the handedness of the eect would have been reversed.
Self-check: If Lorentz boosts did commute, what would be the
consequences for the expression L(v x) L(v y) L(v x) L(v y)?
The velocity disk
Figure e shows a useful way of visualizing the combined eects
of boosts and rotations in 2+1 dimensions. The disk depicts all
possible states of motion relative to some arbitrarily chosen frame
Section 2.5 Three spatial dimensions 63
g / A round-trip involving ul-
trarelativistic velocities. All three
legs are at constant acceleration.
e / The velocity disk.
f / Two excursions in a rocket-
ship: one along the y axis and
one along x.
of reference. Lack of motion is represented by the point at the
center. A point at distance v from the center represents motion at
velocity v in a particular direction in the x y plane. By drawing
little axes at a particular point, we can represent a particular frame
of reference: the frame is in motion at some velocity, with its own
x and y axes are oriented in a particular way.
It turns out to be easier to understand the qualitative behavior
of our mysterious rotations if we switch from the low-velocity limit
to the contrary limit of ultrarelativistic velocities. Suppose we have
a rocket-ship with an inertial navigation system consisting of two
gyroscopes at right angles to one another. We rst accelerate the
ship in the y direction, and the acceleration is steady in the sense
that it feels constant to observers aboard the ship. Since it is rapidi-
ties, not velocities, that add linearly, this means that as an observer
aboard the ship reads clock times
1
,
2
, . . . , all separated by equal
intervals , the ships rapidity changes at a constant rate,
1
,
2
,
. . . . This results in a series of frames of reference that appear closer
and closer together on the diagram as the ship approaches the speed
of light, at the edge of the disk. We can start over from the center
again and repeat the whole process along the x axis, resulting in
a similar succession of frames. In both cases, the boosts are being
applied along a single line, so that there is no rotation of the x and
y axes.
Now suppose that the ship were to accelerate along a route like
the one shown in gure g. It rst accelerates along the y axis at a
constant rate (again, as judged by its own sensors), until its velocity
is very close to the speed of light, A. It then accelerates, again at
a self-perceived constant rate and with thrust in a xed direction
as judged by its own gyroscopes, until it is moving at the same
ultrarelativistic speed in the x direction, B. Finally, it decelerates
in the x direction until it is again at rest, O. This motion traces out
a clockwise loop on the velocity disk. The motion in space is also
clockwise.
We might naively think that the middle leg of the trip, from A
to B, would be a straight line on the velocity disk, but this cant be
the case. First, we know that non-collinear boosts cause rotations.
Traveling around a clockwise path causes counterclockwise rotation,
and vice-versa. Therefore an observer in the rest frame O sees the
ship (and its gyroscopes) as rotating as it moves from A to B. The
ships trajectory through space is clockwise, so according to O the
ship rotates counterclockwise as it goes A to B. The ship is always
ring its engines in a xed direction as judged by its gyroscopes, but
according to O the ship is rotating counterclockwise, its thrust is
progressively rotating counterclockwise, and therefore its trajectory
turns counterclockwise. We conclude that leg AB on the velocity
disk is concave, rather than being a straight-line hypotenuse of a
triangle OAB.
64 Chapter 2 Geometry of Flat Spacetime
h / In the limit where A and
B are ultrarelativistic velocities,
leg AB is perpendicular to the
edge of the velocity disk. The
result is that the x y frame
determined by the ships gyro-
scopes has rotated by 90 degrees
by the time it gets home.
We can also determine, by the following argument, that leg AB
is perpendicular to the edge of the disk where it touches the edge of
the disk. In the transformation from frame A to frame O, y coordi-
nates are dilated by a factor of , which approaches innity in the
limit were presently considering. Observers aboard the rocket-ship,
occupying frame A, believe that their task is to re the rockets
engines at an angle of 45 degrees with respect to the y axis, so as
to eliminate their velocity with respect to the origin, and simulta-
neously add an equal amount of velocity in the x direction. This
45-degree angle in frame A, however, is not a 45-degree angle in
frame O. From the stern of the ship to its bow we have displace-
ments x and y, and in the transformation from A to O, y
is magnied almost innitely. As perceived in frame O, the ships
orientation is almost exactly antiparallel to the y axis.
18
As the ship travels from A to B, its orientation (as judged in
frame O) changes from y to x. This establishes, in a much more
direct fashion, the direction of the Thomas precession: its handed-
ness is contrary to the handedness of the direction of motion. We
can now also see something new about the fundamental reason for
the eect. It has to do with the fact that observers in dierent
states of motion disagree on spatial angles. Similarly, imagine that
you are a two-dimensional being who was told about the existence
of a new, third, spatial dimension. You have always believed that
the cosine of the angle between two unit vectors u and v is given by
the vector dot product u
x
v
x
+u
y
v
y
. If you were allowed to explore
a two-dimensional projection of a three-dimensional scene, e.g., on
the at screen of a television, it would seem to you as if all the
angles had been distorted. You would have no way to interpret the
visual conventions of perspective. But once you had learned about
the existence of a z axis, you would realize that these angular dis-
tortions were happening because of rotations out of the xy plane.
Such rotations really conserve the quantity u
x
v
x
+u
y
v
y
+u
z
v
z
; only
because you were ignoring the u
z
v
z
term did it seem that angles
were not being preserved. Similarly, the generalization from three
Euclidean spatial dimensions to 3+1-dimensional spacetime means
that three-dimensional dot products are no longer conserved.
The general low-v limit
Lets nd the low-v limit of the Thomas precession in general,
not just in the highly articial special case of v
2
for the example
involving the four hammer hits. To generalize to the case of smooth
18
Although we will not need any more than this for the purposes of our present
analysis, a longer and more detailed discussion by Rhodes and Semon, www.
bates.edu/
~
msemon/RhodesSemonFinal.pdf, Am. J. Phys. 72(7)2004, shows
that this type of inertially guided, constant-thrust motion is always represented
on the velocity disk by an arc of a circle that is perpendicular to the disk at its
edge. (We consider a diameter of the disk to be the limiting case of a circle with
innite radius.)
Section 2.5 Three spatial dimensions 65
i / If the crack between the
two areas is squashed at, the
two pieces of the path on the
interior coincide, and their contri-
butions to the precession cancel
out (v v, but a +a, so
a v a v). Therefore the
precession obtained by going
around the outside is equal to the
sum
1
+
2
of the precessions
that would have been obtained by
going around the two parts.
acceleration, we rst note that the rate of precession d/dt must
have the following properties.
It is odd under a reversal of the direction of motion, v v.
(This corresponds to sending the gyroscope around the square
in the opposite direction.)
It is odd under a reversal of the acceleration due to the second
boost, a a.
It is a rotation about the spatial axis perpendicular to the
plane of the v and a vectors, in the opposite direction com-
pared to the handedness of the curving trajectory.
It is approximately linear in v and a, for small v and a.
The only rotationally invariant mathematical operation that has
these symmetry properties is the vector cross product, so the rate
of precession must be ka v, where k > 0 is nearly independent of
v and a for small v and a.
To pin down the value of k, we need to nd a connection between
our two results: v
2
for the four hammer hits, and d/dt kav
for smooth acceleration. We can do this by considering the physical
signicance of areas on the velocity disk. As shown in gure i, the
rotation due to carrying the velocity around the boundary of a
region is additive when adjacent regions are joined together. We
can therefore nd for any region by breaking the region down into
elements of area dA and integrating their contributions d. What is
the relationship between dA and d? The velocity disks structure
is nonuniform, in the sense that near the edge of the disk, it takes a
larger boost to move a small distance. But were investigating the
low-velocity limit, and in the low-velocity region near the center of
the disk, the disks structure is approximately uniform. We there-
fore expect that there is an approximately constant proportionality
factor relating dA and d at low velocities. The example of the
hammer corresponds geometrically to a square with area v
2
, so we
nd that this proportionality factor is unity, dA d.
To relate this to smooth acceleration, consider a particle per-
forming circular motion with period T, which has [av[ = 2v
2
/T.
Over one full period of the motion, we have =
_
k[a v[dt =
2kv
2
, and the particles velocity vector traces a circle of area A =
v
2
on the velocity disk. Equating A and , we nd k = 1/2. The
result is that in the limit of low velocities, the rate of rotation is
1
2
a v ,
where is the angular velocity vector of the rotation. In the special
case of circular motion, this can be written as = (1/2)v
2
, where
= 2/T is the angular frequency of the motion.
66 Chapter 2 Geometry of Flat Spacetime
j / States in hydrogen are la-
beled with their and s quantum
numbers, representing their
orbital and spin angular momenta
in units of . The state with
s = +1/2 has its spin angular
momentum aligned with its orbital
angular momentum, while the
s = 1/2 state has the two
angular momenta in opposite
directions. The direction and
order of magnitude of the splitting
between the two = 1 states
is successfully explained by
magnetic interactions with the
proton, but the calculated effect
is too big by a factor of 2. The
relativistic Thomas precession
cancels out half of the effect.
2.5.4 An experimental test: Thomas precession in hydrogen
If we want to see this precession eect in real life, we should look
for a system in which both v and a are large. An atom is such a
system.
The Bohr model, introduced in 1913, marked the rst quantita-
tively successful, if conceptually muddled, description of the atomic
energy levels of hydrogen. Continuing to take c = 1, the over-all
scale of the energies was calculated to be proportional to m
2
, where
m is the mass of the electron, and = ke
2
/ 1/137, known as the
ne structure constant, is essentially just a unitless way of express-
ing the coupling constant for electrical forces. At higher resolution,
each excited energy level is found to be split into several sub-levels.
The transitions among these close-lying states are in the millime-
ter region of the microwave spectrum. The energy scale of this ne
structure is m
4
. This is down by a factor of
2
compared to the
visible-light transitions, hence the name of the constant. Uhlenbeck
and Goudsmit showed in 1926 that a splitting on this order of mag-
nitude was to be expected due to the magnetic interaction between
the proton and the electrons magnetic moment, oriented along its
spin. The eect they calculated, however, was too big by a factor
of two.
The explanation of the mysterious factor of two had in fact been
implicit in a 1916 calculation by Willem de Sitter, one of the rst
applications of general relativity. De Sitter treated the earth-moon
system as a gyroscope, and found the precession of its axis of rota-
tion, which was partly due to the curvature of spacetime and partly
due to the type of rotation described earlier in this section. The
eect on the motion of the moon was noncumulative, and was only
about one meter, which was much too small to be measured at the
time. In 1927, however, Llewellyn Thomas applied similar reason-
ing to the hydrogen atom, with the electrons spin vector playing
the role of gyroscope. Since gravity is negligible here, the eect has
nothing to do with curvature of spacetime, and Thomass eect cor-
responds purely to the special-relativistic part of de Sitters result.
It is simply the rotation described above, with = (1/2)v
2
. Al-
though Thomas was not the rst to calculate it, the eect is known
as Thomas precession. Since the electrons spin is /2, the energy
splitting is (/2), depending on whether the electrons spin is in
the same direction as its orbital motion, or in the opposite direc-
tion. This is less than the atoms gross energy scale by a factor
of v
2
/2, which is
2
. The Thomas precession cancels out half of
the magnetic eect, bringing theory in agreement with experiment.
Uhlenbeck later recalled: ...when I rst heard about [the Thomas
precession], it seemed unbelievable that a relativistic eect could
give a factor of 2 instead of something of order v/c... Even the
cognoscenti of relativity theory (Einstein included!) were quite sur-
prised.
Section 2.5 Three spatial dimensions 67
Problems
1 Suppose that we dont yet know the exact form of the Lorentz
transformation, but we know based on the Michelson-Morley exper-
iment that the speed of light is the same in all inertial frames, and
weve already determined, e.g., by arguments like those on p. 58,
that there can be no length contraction in the direction perpendic-
ular to the motion. We construct a light clock, consisting simply
of two mirrors facing each other, with a light pulse bouncing back
and forth between them.
(a) Suppose this light clock is moving at a constant velocity v in the
direction perpendicular to its own optical arm, which is of length L.
Use the Pythagorean theorem to prove that the clock experiences a
time dilation given by = 1/
1 v
2
, thereby xing the time-time
portion of the Lorentz transformation.
(b) Why is it signicant for the interpretation of special relativity
that the result from part a is independent of L?
(c) Carry out a similar calculation in the case where the clock moves
with constant acceleration a as measured in some inertial frame. Al-
though the result depends on L, prove that in the limit of small L,
we recover the earlier constant-velocity result, with no explicit de-
pendence on a.
Remark: Some authors state a clock postulate for special relativity, which
says that for a clock that is suciently small, the rate at which it runs de-
pends only on v, not a (except in the trivial sense that v and a are related
by calculus). The result of part c shows that the clock postulate is really a
theorem, not a statement that is logically independent of the other postulates
of special relativity. Although this argument only applies to a particular fam-
ily of light clocks of various sizes, one can also make any small clock into an
acceleration-insensitive clock, by attaching an accelerometer to it and apply-
ing an appropriate correction to compensate for the clocks observed sensitiv-
ity to acceleration. (Its still necessary for the clock to be small, since other-
wise the lack of simultaneity in relativity makes it impossible to describe the
whole clock as having a certain acceleration at a certain instant.) Some peo-
ple get confused by this acceleration-independent property of small clocks and
think that it contradicts the equivalence principle. For a good explanation, see
http://math.ucr.edu/home/baez/physics/Relativity/SR/clock.html.
Solution, p. 261
2 (a) On p. 66 (see gure i), we showed that the Thomas pre-
cession is proportional to area on the velocity disk. Use a similar
argument to show that the Sagnac eect (p. 58) is proportional to
the area enclosed by the loop.
(b) Verify this more directly in the special case of a circular loop.
(c) Show that a light clock of the type described in problem 1 is
insensitive to rotation with constant angular velocity.
(d) Connect these results to the commutativity and transitivity as-
sumptions in the Einstein clock synchronization procedure described
on p. 242. Solution, p. 262
68 Chapter 2 Geometry of Flat Spacetime
3 Example 10 on page 50 discusses relativistic bounds on the
properties of matter, using the example of pulling a bucket out of a
black hole. Derive a similar bound by considering the possibility of
sending signals out of the black hole using longitudinal vibrations of
a cable, as in the childs telephone made of two tin cans connected
by a piece of string. (Surprisingly subtle issues can arise in such
calculations. See A.Y. Shiekh, Can. J. Phys. 70, 458 (1992).)
4 The Maxima program on page 61 demonstrates how to mul-
tiply matrices and nd Taylor series. Apply this technique to the
following problem. For successive Lorentz boosts along the same
axis with rapidities
1
and
2
, nd the matrix representing the com-
bined Lorentz transformation, in a Taylor series up to the rst non-
classical terms in each matrix element. A mixed Taylor series in
two variables can be obtained simply by nesting taylor functions.
The taylor function will happily work on matrices, not just scalars.
Solution, p. 262
Problems 69
70 Chapter 2 Geometry of Flat Spacetime
Chapter 3
Differential Geometry
General relativity is described mathematically in the language of
dierential geometry. Lets take those two terms in reverse order.
The geometry of spacetime is non-Euclidean, not just in the
sense that the 3+1-dimensional geometry of Lorentz frames is dif-
ferent than that of 4 interchangeable Euclidean dimensions, but also
in the sense that parallels do not behave in the way described by
E5 or A1-A3. In a Lorentz frame, which describes space without
any gravitational elds, particles whose world-lines are initially par-
allel will continue along their parallel world-lines forever. But in
the presence of gravitational elds, initially parallel world-lines of
free-falling particles will in general diverge, approach, or even cross.
Thus, neither the existence nor the uniqueness of parallels can be
assumed. We cant describe this lack of parallelism as arising from
the curvature of the world-lines, because were using the world-lines
of free-falling particles as our denition of a straight line. Instead,
we describe the eect as coming from the curvature of spacetime it-
self. The Lorentzian geometry is a description of the case in which
this curvature is negligible.
What about the word dierential ? The equivalence principle
states that even in the presence of gravitational elds, local Lorentz
frames exist. How local is local? If we use a microscope to zoom in
on smaller and smaller regions of spacetime, the Lorentzian approx-
imation becomes better and better. Suppose we want to do experi-
ments in a laboratory, and we want to ensure that when we compare
some physically observable quantity against predictions made based
on the Lorentz geometry, the resulting discrepancy will not be too
large. If the acceptable error is , then we should be able to get the
error down that low if were willing to make the size of our labora-
tory no bigger than . This is clearly very similar to the Weierstrass
style of dening limits and derivatives in calculus. In calculus, the
idea expressed by dierentiation is that every smooth curve can be
approximated locally by a line; in general relativity, the equivalence
principle tells us that curved spacetime can be approximated locally
by at spacetime. But consider that no practitioner of calculus ha-
bitually solves problems by lling sheets of scratch paper with ep-
silons and deltas. Instead, she uses the Leibniz notation, in which dy
and dx are interpreted as innitesimally small numbers. You may
be inclined, based on your previous training, to dismiss innitesi-
71
mals as neither rigorous nor necessary. In 1966, Abraham Robinson
demonstrated that concerns about rigor had been unfounded; well
come back to this point in section 3.2. Although it is true that any
calculation written using innitesimals can also be carried out using
limits, the following example shows how much more well suited the
innitesimal language is to dierential geometry.
Areas on a sphere Example: 1
The area of a region S in the Cartesian plane can be calculated
as
_
S
dA, where dA = dxdy is the area of an innitesimal rectan-
gle of width dx and height dy. A curved surface such as a sphere
does not admit a global Cartesian coordinate system in which the
constant coordinate curves are both uniformly spaced and per-
pendicular to one another. For example, lines of longitude on the
earths surface grow closer together as one moves away from the
equator. Letting be the angle with respect to the pole, and the
azimuthal angle, the approximately rectangular patch bounded by
, + d, , and + d has width r sind and height r d, giv-
ing dA = r
2
sindd. If you look at the corresponding derivation
in an elementary calculus textbook that strictly eschews innites-
imals, the technique is to start from scratch with Riemann sums.
This is extremely laborious, and moreover must be carried out
again for every new case. In differential geometry, the curvature
of the space varies from one point to the next, and clearly we
dont want to reinvent the wheel with Riemann sums an innite
number of times, once at each point in space.
3.1 The afne parameter revisited, and parallel
transport
3.1.1 The afne parameter in curved spacetime
An important example of the dierential, i.e., local, nature of our
geometry is the generalization of the ane parameter to a context
broader than ane geometry.
Our construction of the ane parameter with a scaolding of
parallelograms depended on the existence and uniqueness of paral-
lels expressed by A1, so we might imagine that there was no point in
trying to generalize the construction to curved spacetime. But the
equivalence principle tells us that spacetime is locally ane to some
approximation. Concretely, clock-time is one example of an ane
parameter, and the curvature of spacetime clearly cant prevent us
from building a clock and releasing it on a free-fall trajectory. To
generalize the recipe for the construction (gure a), the rst obsta-
cle is the ambiguity of the instruction to construct parallelogram
01q
0
q
1
, which requires us to draw 1q
1
parallel to 0q
0
. Suppose we
construe this as an instruction to make the two segments initially
parallel, i.e., parallel as they depart the line at 0 and 1. By the time
72 Chapter 3 Differential Geometry
a / Construction of an afne
parameter in curved spacetime.
they get to q
0
and q
1
, they may be converging or diverging.
Because parallelism is only approximate here, there will be a
certain amount of error in the construction of the ane parameter.
One way of detecting such an error is that lattices constructed with
dierent initial distances will get out of step with one another. For
example, we can dene
1
2
as before by requiring that the lattice
constructed with initial segment 0
1
2
line up with the original lattice
at 1. We will nd, however, that they do not quite line up at
other points, such as 2. Lets use this discrepancy = 2 2
as
a numerical measure of the error. It will depend on both
1
, the
distance 01, and on
2
, the distance between 0 and q
0
. Since
vanishes for either
1
= 0 or
2
= 0, and since the equivalence
principle guarantees smooth behavior on small scales, the leading
term in the error will in general be proportional to the product
2
. In the language of innitesimals, we can replace
1
and
2
with innitesimally short distances, which for simplicity we assume
to be equal, and which we call d. Then the ane parameter
is dened as =
_
d, where the error of order d
2
is, as usual,
interpreted as the negligible discrepancy between the integral and
its approximation as a Riemann sum.
3.1.2 Parallel transport
If you were alert, you may have realized that I cheated you at
a crucial point in this construction. We were to make 1q
1
and 0q
0
initially parallel as they left 01. How should we even dene this
idea of initially parallel? We could try to do it by making angles
q
0
01 and q
1
12 equal, but this doesnt quite work, because it doesnt
specify whether the angle is to the left or the right on the two-
dimensional plane of the page. In three or more dimensions, the
issue becomes even more serious. The construction workers building
the lattice need to keep it all in one plane, but how do they do that
in curved spacetime?
A mathematicians answer would be that our geometry lacks
some additional structure called a connection, which is a rule that
species how one locally at neighborhood is to be joined seamlessly
onto another locally at neighborhood nearby. If youve ever bought
two maps and tried to tape them together to make a big map, youve
formed a connection. If the maps were on a large enough scale,
you also probably noticed that this was impossible to do perfectly,
because of the curvature of the earth.
Physically, the idea is that in at spacetime, it is possible to
construct inertial guidance systems like the ones discussed on page
59. Since they are possible in at spacetime, they are also possible
in locally at neighborhoods of spacetime, and they can then be
carried from one neighborhood to another.
In three space dimensions, a gyroscopes angular momentum vec-
Section 3.1 The afne parameter revisited, and parallel transport 73
c / Bad things happen if we
try to construct an afne param-
eter along a curve that isnt a
geodesic. This curve is similar
to path ABC in gure b. Par-
allel transport doesnt preserve
the vectors angle relative to
the curve, as it would with a
geodesic. The errors in the
construction blow up in a way
that wouldnt happen if the curve
had been a geodesic. The fourth
dashed parallel ies off wildly
around the back of the sphere,
wrapping around and meeting
the curve at a point, 4, that is
essentially random.
b / Parallel transport is path-
dependent. On the surface of
this sphere, parallel-transporting
a vector along ABC gives a
different answer than transporting
it along AC.
tor maintains its direction, and we can orient other vectors, such as
1q
1
, relative to it. Suppose for concreteness that the construction
of the ane parameter above is being carried out in three space di-
mensions. We place a gyroscope at 0, orient its axis along 0q
0
, slide
it along the line to 1, and then construct 1q
1
along that axis.
In 3+1 dimensions, a gyroscope only does part of the job. We
now have to maintain the direction of a four-dimensional vector.
Four-vectors will not be discussed in detail until section 4.2, but
similar devices can be used to maintain their orientations in space-
time. These physical devices are ways of dening a mathematical
notion known as parallel transport, which allows us to take a vector
from one point to another in space. In general, specifying a notion
of parallel transport is equivalent to specifying a connection.
Parallel transport is path-dependent, as shown in gure b.
Ane parameters dened only along geodesics
In the context of at spacetime, the ane parameter was dened
only along lines, not arbitrary curves, and could not be compared
between lines running in dierent directions. In curved spacetime,
the same limitation is present, but with along lines replaced by
along geodesics. Figure c shows what goes wrong if we try to
apply the construction to a world-line that isnt a geodesic. One
denition of a geodesic is that its the course well end up following
if we navigate by keeping a xed bearing relative to an inertial guid-
ance device such as gyroscope; that is, the tangent to a geodesic,
when parallel-transported farther along the geodesic, is still tangent.
A non-geodesic curve lacks this property, and the eect on the con-
struction of the ane parameter is that the segments nq
n
drift more
and more out of alignment with the curve.
3.2 Models
A typical rst reaction to the phrase curved spacetime or even
curved space, for that matter is that it sounds like nonsense.
How can featureless, empty space itself be curved or distorted? The
concept of a distortion would seem to imply taking all the points
and shoving them around in various directions as in a Picasso paint-
ing, so that distances between points are altered. But if space has
no identiable dents or scratches, it would seem impossible to deter-
mine which old points had been sent to which new points, and the
distortion would have no observable eect at all. Why should we
expect to be able to build dierential geometry on such a logically
dubious foundation? Indeed, historically, various mathematicians
have had strong doubts about the logical self-consistency of both
non-Euclidean geometry and innitesimals. And even if an authori-
tative source assures you that the resulting system is self-consistent,
its mysterious and abstract nature would seem to make it dicult
74 Chapter 3 Differential Geometry
a / Tullio Levi-Civita (1873-
1941) worked on models of
number systems possessing
innitesimals and on differential
geometry. He invented the
tensor notation, which Einstein
learned from his textbook. He
was appointed to prestigious
endowed chairs at Padua and the
University of Rome, but was red
in 1938 because he was a Jew
and an anti-fascist.
for you to develop any working picture of the theory that could
play the role that mental sketches of graphs play in organizing your
knowledge of calculus.
Models provide a way of dealing with both the logical issues and
the conceptual ones. Figure a on page 73 pops o of the page,
presenting a strong psychological impression of a curved surface ren-
dered in perspective. This suggests nding an actual mathematical
object, such as a curved surface, that satises all the axioms of a
certain logical system, such as non-Euclidean geometry. Note that
the model may contain extrinsic elements, such as the existence of
a third dimension, that are not connected to the system being mod-
eled.
Lets focus rst on consistency. In general, what can we say
about the self-consistency of a mathematical system? To start with,
we can never prove anything about the consistency or lack of consis-
tency of something that is not a well-dened formal system, e.g., the
Bible. Even Euclids Elements, which was a model of formal rigor for
thousands of years, is loose enough to allow considerable ambiguity.
If youre inclined to sco at the silly Renaissance mathematicians
who kept trying to prove the parallel postulate E5 from postulates
E1-E4, consider the following argument. Suppose that we replace
E5 with E5
is
a perfectly respectable system called elliptic geometry. So whats
wrong with this supposed proof of its lack of self-consistency? The
issue is the exact statement of E3. E3 does not say that we can
construct a circle given any real number as its radius. Euclid could
not have intended any such interpretation, since he had no notion of
real numbers. To Euclid, geometry was primary, and numbers were
geometrically constructed objects, being represented as lengths, an-
gles, areas, and volumes. A literal translation of Euclids statement
of the axiom is To describe a circle with any center and distance.
1
Distance means a line segment. There is therefore no contradic-
tion in E
, because E
and dx
, although
in our present one-dimensional example = 0 is xed. The reason
for the use of the odd-looking superscripts, rather than subscripts,
will become clear shortly.
The vectors drawn below the curve are called the contravariant
82 Chapter 3 Differential Geometry
vectors, notated dx
dx
, or, equivalently we
say ds
2
= dx
dx
. (Remember, = 0.)
Given a dx
dx
for the
squared arc length, and in dierential geometry we practice the con-
venient notational convention, introduced by Einstein, of assuming
a summation when an index is repeated, so this becomes
ds
2
= dx
dx
.
3.4.1 The Euclidean metric
In a Euclidean plane, where the distinction between covariant
and contravariant vectors is irrelevant, this expression for ds
2
is
simply the Pythagorean theorem, summed over two values of i for
the two coordinates:
ds
2
= dx
i
dx
i
= dx
2
+ dy
2
The symbols dx, dx
0
, and dx
0
are all synonyms, and likewise for
dy, dx
1
, and dx
1
.
In the non-Euclidean case, the Pythagorean theorem is false; dx
and dx
. Substituting
Section 3.4 The metric 83
dx
= g
, we have
ds
2
= g
dx
dx
,
where there are now implied sums over both and . Notice how
implied sums occur only when the repeated index occurs once as
a superscript and once as a subscript; other combinations are un-
grammatical.
Self-check: Why does it make sense to demand that the metric
be symmetric?
In an introductory course in Newtonian mechanics, one makes
a distinction between vectors, which have a direction in space, and
scalars, which do not. These are specic examples of tensors, which
can be expressed as objects with m superscripts and n subscripts.
A scalar has m = n = 0. A covariant vector has (m, n) = (0, 1),
a contravariant vector (1, 0), and the metric (0, 2). We refer to the
number of indices as the rank of the tensor. Tensors are discussed
in more detail, and dened more rigorously, in chapter 4. For our
present purposes, it is important to note that just because we write
a symbol with subscripts or superscripts, that doesnt mean it de-
serves to be called a tensor. This point can be understood in the
more elementary context of Newtonian scalars and vectors. For ex-
ample, we can dene a Newtonian vector u = (m, T, e), where m
is the mass of the moon, T is the temperature in Chicago, and e is
the charge of the electron. This creature u doesnt deserve to be
called a vector, because it doesnt behave as a vector under rota-
tion. Similarly, a tensor is required to behave in a certain way under
rotations and Lorentz boosts.
When discussing the symmetry of rank-2 tensors, it is convenient
to introduce the following notation:
T
(ab)
=
1
2
(T
ab
+T
ba
)
T
[ab]
=
1
2
(T
ab
T
ba
)
Any T
ab
can be split into symmetric and antisymmetric parts. This
is similar to writing an arbitrary function as a sum of and odd
function and an even function. The metric has only a symmetric
part: g
(ab)
= g
ab
, and g
[ab]
= 0. This notation is generalized to
ranks greater than 2 on page 152.
Self-check: Characterize an antisymmetric rank-2 tensor in two
dimensions.
A change of scale Example: 5
How is the effect of a uniform rescaling of coordinates repre-
sented in g?
If we change our units of measurement so that x
, while
demanding that ds
2
come out the same, then we need g
2
g
.
84 Chapter 3 Differential Geometry
Polar coordinates Example: 6
Consider polar coordinates (r , ) in a Euclidean plane. The const-
ant-coordinate curves happen to be orthogonal everywhere, so
the off-diagonal elements of the metric g
r
and g
r
vanish. In-
nitesimal coordinate changes dr and d correspond to innitesi-
mal displacements dr and r d in orthogonal directions, so by the
Pythagorean theorem, ds
2
= dr
2
+ r
2
d
2
, and we read off the
elements of the metric g
r r
= 1 and g
= r
2
.
Notice how in example 6 we started from the generally valid
relation ds
2
= g
dx
dx
= r
2
that were only valid in this particular coordinate system.
To make it clear when this is happening, we adopt a convention in-
troduced by Roger Penrose known as the abstract index notation. In
this convention, Latin superscripts and subscripts indicate that an
equation is of general validity, without regard to any choice of coor-
dinate system, while Greek ones are used for coordinate-dependent
equations. For example, we can write the general expression for
squared dierential arc length with Latin indices,
ds
2
= g
ij
dx
i
dx
j
,
because it holds regardless of the coordinate system, whereas the
vanishing of the o-diagonal elements of the metric in Euclidean
polar coordinates has to be written as g
= 0 for ,= , since it
would in general be false if we used a dierent coordinate system to
describe the same Euclidean plane. The advantages of this notation
became widely apparent to relativists starting around 1980, so for
example it is used in the text by Wald (1984), but not in Misner,
Thorne, and Wheeler (1970). Some of the older literature uses a
notation in which the Greek and Latin indices are instead used to
distinguish between timelike and spacelike components of a vector,
but this usage is dying out, since it inappropriately singles out a
distinction between time and space that is not actually preserved
under a Lorentz boost.
Oblique Cartesian coordinates Example: 7
Oblique Cartesian coordinates are like normal Cartesian coor-
dinates in the plane, but their axes are at at an angle ,= /2 to
one another. Find the metric in these coordinates. The space is
globally Euclidean.
Since the coordinates differ from Cartesian coordinates only in
the angle between the axes, not in their scales, a displacement
dx
i
along either axis, i = 1 or 2, must give ds = dx, so for the diag-
onal elements we have g
11
= g
22
= 1. The metric is always sym-
metric, so g
12
= g
21
. To x these off-diagonal elements, consider
a displacement by ds in the direction perpendicular to axis 1. This
changes the coordinates by dx
1
= ds cot and dx
2
= ds csc .
Section 3.4 The metric 85
c / Example 7.
We then have
ds
2
= g
i j
dx
i
dx
j
= ds
2
(cot
2
+ csc
2
2g
12
cos csc )
g
12
= cos .
Area Example: 8
In one dimension, g is a single number, and lengths are given
by ds =
gdx. The square root can also be understood through
example 5 on page 84, in which we saw that a uniform rescaling
x x is reected in g
2
g
.
In two-dimensional Cartesian coordinates, multiplication of the
width and height of a rectangle gives the element of area dA =
g
11
g
22
dx
1
dx
2
. Because the coordinates are orthogonal, g is di-
agonal, and the factor of
g
11
g
22
is identied as the square root
of its determinant, so dA =
_
[g[dx
1
dx
2
. Note that the scales on
the two axes are not necessarily the same, g
11
,= g
22
.
The same expression for the element of area holds even if the co-
ordinates are not orthogonal. In example 7, for instance, we have
_
[g[ =
_
1 cos
2
= sin, which is the right correction factor
corresponding to the fact that dx
1
and dx
2
form a parallelepiped
rather than a rectangle.
Area of a sphere Example: 9
For coordinates (, ) on the surface of a sphere of radius r , we
have, by an argument similar to that of example 6 on page 85,
g
= r
2
, g
= r
2
sin
2
, g
= +1, g
= a
1
b
1
+ a
2
b
2
+ a
3
b
3
. Like magnitudes,
dot products are invariant under rotations. This is because know-
ing the dot product of vectors a and b entails knowing the value
of a b = [a[[a[ cos
ab
, and Euclids E4 (equality of right angles)
implies that the angle
ab
is invariant. the same axioms also entail
invariance of dot products under translation; Euclid waits only until
the second proposition of the Elements to prove that line segments
can be copied from one location to another. This seeming triviality is
Section 3.4 The metric 87
actually false as a description of physical space, because it amounts
to a statement that space has the same properties everywhere.
The set of all transformations that can be built out of succes-
sive translations, rotations, and reections is called the group of
isometries. It can also be dened as the group
5
that preserves dot
products, or the group that preserves congruence of triangles.
In Lorentzian geometry, we usually avoid the Euclidean term
dot product and refer to the corresponding operation by the more
general term inner product. In a specic coordinate system we have
a
= a
0
b
0
a
1
b
1
a
2
b
2
a
3
b
3
. The inner product is invariant under
Lorentz boosts, and also under the Euclidean isometries. The group
found by making all possible combinations of continuous transfor-
mations
6
from these two sets is called the Poincare group. The
Poincare group is not the symmetry group of all of spacetime, since
curved spacetime has dierent properties in dierent locations. The
equivalence principle tells us, however, that space can be approxi-
mated locally as being at, so the Poincare group is locally valid,
just as the Euclidean isometries are locally valid as a description of
geometry on the Earths curved surface.
The triangle inequality Example: 11
In Euclidean geometry, the triangle inequality [b + c[ < [b[ + [c[
follows from
([b[ + [c[)
2
(b + c) (b + c) = 2([b[[c[ b c) 0 .
The reason this quantity always comes out positive is that for two
vectors of xed magnitude, the greatest dot product is always
achieved in the case where they lie along the same direction.
In Lorentzian geometry, the situation is different. Let b and c be
timelike vectors, so that they represent possible world-lines. Then
the relation a = b+c suggests the existence of two observers who
take two different paths from one event to another. A goes by a
direct route while B takes a detour. The magnitude of each time-
like vector represents the time elapsed on a clock carried by the
observer moving along that vector. The triangle equality is now
reversed, becoming [b + c[ > [b[ + [c[. The difference from the
5
In mathematics, a group is dened as a binary operation that has an identity,
inverses, and associativity. For example, addition of integers is a group. In the
present context, the members of the group are not numbers but the transforma-
tions applied to the Euclidean plane. The group operation on transformations
T1 and T2 consists of nding the transformation that results from doing one and
then the other, i.e., composition of functions.
6
The discontinuous transformations of spatial reection and time reversal are
not included in the denition of the Poincare group, although they do preserve
inner products. General relativity has symmetry under spatial reection (called
P for parity), time reversal (T), and charge inversion (C), but the standard
model of particle physics is only invariant under the composition of all three,
CPT, not under any of these symmetries individually.
88 Chapter 3 Differential Geometry
Euclidean case arises because inner products are no longer nec-
essarily maximized if vectors are in the same direction. E.g., for
two lightlike vectors, b
i
c
j
vanishes entirely if b and c are paral-
lel. For timelike vectors, parallelism actually minimizes the inner
product rather than maximizing it.
7
In his 1872 inaugural address at the University of Erlangen, Felix
Klein used the idea of groups of transformations to lay out a gen-
eral classication scheme, known as the Erlangen program, for all
the dierent types of geometry. Each geometry is described by the
group of transformations, called the principal group, that preserves
the truth of geometrical statements. Euclidean geometrys principal
group consists of the isometries combined with arbitrary changes of
scale, since there is nothing in Euclids axioms that singles out a
particular distance as a unit of measurement. In other words, the
principal group consists of the transformations that preserve simi-
larity, not just those that preserve congruence. Ane geometrys
principal group is the transformations that preserve parallelism; it
includes shear transformations, and there is therefore no invariant
notion of angular measure or congruence. Unlike Euclidean and
ane geometry, elliptic geometry does not have scale invariance.
This is because there is a particular unit of distance that has special
status; as we saw in example 3 on page 79, a being living in an el-
liptic plane can determine, by entirely intrinsic methods, a distance
scale R, which we can interpret in the hemispherical model as the
radius of the sphere. General relativity breaks this symmetry even
more severely. Not only is there a scale associated with curvature,
but the scale is dierent from one point in space to another.
3.4.4 Einsteins carousel
Non-Euclidean geometry observed in the rotating frame
The following example was historically important, because Ein-
stein used it to convince himself that general relativity should be
described by non-Euclidean geometry.
8
Its interpretation is also
fairly subtle, and the early relativists had some trouble with it.
Suppose that observer A is on a spinning carousel while observer
B stands on the ground. B says that A is accelerating, but by the
equivalence principle A can say that she is at rest in a gravitational
7
Proof: Let b and c be parallel and timelike, and directed forward in time.
Adopt a frame of reference in which every spatial component of each vector
vanishes. This entails no loss of generality, since inner products are invariant
under such a transformation. Since the time-ordering is also preserved under
transformations in the Poincare group, but each is still directed forward in time,
not backward. Now let b and c be pulled away from parallelism, like opening
a pair of scissors in the x t plane. This reduces bt ct , while causing bx cx to
become negative. Both eects increase the inner product.
8
The example is described in Einsteins paper The Foundation of the General
Theory of Relativity. An excerpt, which includes the example, is given on
p. 255.
Section 3.4 The metric 89
d / Observer A, rotating with
the carousel, measures an
azimuthal distance with a ruler.
eld, while B is free-falling out from under her. B measures the
radius and circumference of the carousel, and nds that their ratio
is 2. A carries out similar measurements, but when she puts her
meter-stick in the azimuthal direction it becomes Lorentz-contracted
by the factor = (1
2
r
2
)
1/2
, so she nds that the ratio is greater
than 2. In As coordinates, the spatial geometry is non-Euclidean,
and the metric diers from the Euclidean one found in example 6
on page 85.
Observer A feels a force that B considers to be ctitious, but
that, by the equivalence principle, A can say is a perfectly real
gravitational force. According to A, an observer like B is free-falling
away from the center of the disk under the inuence of this gravita-
tional eld. A also observes that the spatial geometry of the carousel
is non-Euclidean. Therefore it seems reasonable to conjecture that
gravity can be described by non-Euclidean geometry, rather than as
a physical force in the Newtonian sense.
At this point, you know as much about this example as Einstein
did in 1912, when he began using it as the seed from which general
relativity sprouted, collaborating with his old schoolmate, mathe-
matician Marcel Grossmann, who knew about dierential geometry.
The remainder of subsection 3.4.4, which you may want to skip on a
rst reading, goes into more detail on the interpretation and math-
ematical description of the rotating frame of reference. Even more
detailed treatments are given by Grn
9
and Dieks.
10
.
Ehrenfests paradox
Ehrenfest
11
described the following paradox. Suppose that ob-
server B, in the lab frame, measures the radius of the disk to be r
when the disk is at rest, and r
. Because
B is in an inertial frame, the spatial geometry does not appear non-
Euclidean according to measurements carried out with his meter
sticks, and therefore the Euclidean relations C = 2r and C
= 2r
both hold. The radial lines are perpendicular to their own motion,
and they therefore have no length contraction, r = r
, implying
C = C
= t.
First we take the Euclidean metric of example 6 on page 85 and
rewrite it as a (globally) Lorentzian metric in spacetime for observer
B,
[1] ds
2
= dt
2
dr
2
r
2
d
2
.
Applying the transformation into As coordinates, we nd
[2] ds
2
= (1
2
r
2
)dt
2
dr
2
r
2
d
2
2r
2
d
dt .
Recognizing r as the velocity of one frame relative to another, and
(1
2
r
2
)
1/2
as , we see that we do have a relativistic time dilation
eect in the dt
2
term. But the dr
2
and d
2
terms look Euclidean.
Why dont we see any Lorentz contraction of the length scale in the
azimuthal direction?
The answer is that coordinates in general relativity are arbi-
trary, and just because we can write down a certain set of coordi-
nates, that doesnt mean they have any special physical interpreta-
tion. The coordinates (t, r,
) coordinates cor-
responded to clock and meter-stick measurements, then we would
expect that when the cars met up again on the far side of the disk,
their dashboards would show equal values of the arc length r
on
Section 3.4 The metric 91
their odometers and equal proper times ds on their clocks. But this
is not the case, because the sign of the d
dt cross-
term by completing the square in the metric [2]. The result is
ds
2
= (1
2
r
2
)
_
dt +
r
2
1
2
r
2
d
_
2
dr
2
r
2
1
2
r
2
d
2
.
The interpretation of the quantity in square brackets is as follows.
Suppose that two observers situate themselves on the edge of the
disk, separated by an innitesimal angle d
. The
quantity in square brackets is the same in both cases, so the amount
by which the clocks must be adjusted is dt = (dt
2
dt
1
)/2, or
dt =
r
2
1
2
r
2
d
.
Substituting this into the metric, we are left with the purely spatial
metric
[3] ds
2
= dr
2
r
2
1
2
r
2
d
2
.
The factor of (1
2
r
2
)
1
=
2
in the d
2
term is simply the
expected Lorentz-contraction factor. In other words, the circumfer-
ence is, as expected, greater than 2r by a factor of .
Does the metric [3] represent the same non-Euclidean spatial
geometry that A, rotating with the disk, would determine by meter-
stick measurements? Yes and no. It can be interpreted as the
one that A would determine by radar measurements. That is, if
A measures a round-trip travel time dt for a light signal between
points separated by coordinate distances dr and d
,
interpreted as a time coordinate that was synchronized in a con-
sistent way for all points on the disk. The trouble with this inter-
pretation becomes evident when we imagine driving a car around
the circumference of the disk, at a speed slow enough so that there
is negligible time dilation of the cars dashboard clock relative to
the clocks tied to the disk. Once the car gets back to its original
position,
, ). If we
tried, it would result in discontinuities (see problem 2, p. 100).
Instead, the GPS system handles clock synchronization in coor-
dinates (t , r ,
, which is
identical to x outside the hole, but diers from it on the inside. If
we reexpress the metric in terms of these new coordinates as g
(x
),
then we are guaranteed that g
(x
, and g
_
dy
dt
_
2
_
dz
dt
_
2
dt ,
which only contains an explicit dependence on the clocks veloc-
ity, not its acceleration. This is an example of the clock postulate
referred to in the remark at the end of homework problem 1 on
page 68. Note that the clock postulate only applies in the limit of
a small clock. This is represented in the above equation by the
use of innitesimal quantities like dx.
4.2 Four-vectors
4.2.1 The velocity and acceleration four-vectors
Our basic Lorentz vector is the spacetime displacement dx
i
. Any
other quantity that has the same behavior as dx
i
under rotations
and boosts is also a valid Lorentz vector. Consider a particle moving
through space, as described in a Lorentz frame. Since the particle
may be subject to nongravitational forces, the Lorentz frame can-
not be made to coincide (except perhaps momentarily) with the
particles rest frame. Dividing the innitesimal displacement by an
innitesimal proper time interval, we have the four-velocity vector
v
i
= dx
i
/d, whose components in a Lorentz coordinate system
are (, v
1
, v
2
, v
3
), where v
t
2
x
2
= 1 .
An observer who is instantaneously at rest with respect to the
ship judges is to have a four-acceleration (0, a, 0, 0) (because the
low-velocity limit applies). The observer in the (t , x) frame agrees
on the magnitude of this vector, so
t
2
x
2
= a
2
.
The solution of these differential equations is t =
1
a
sinha,
x =
1
a
cosha, and eliminating gives
x =
1
a
__
1 + a
2
t
2
1
_
.
As t approaches innity, dx/dt approaches the speed of light.
Section 4.2 Four-vectors 105
4.2.2 The momentum four-vector
In subsection 4.2.1, we obtained the velocity four-vector. Mul-
tiplying by the particles mass, we have the four-momentum p
i
=
mv
i
, which in Lorentz coordinates is (m, mv
1
, mv
2
, mv
3
). The
spacelike components look like the classical momentum vector mul-
tiplied by a factor of , the interpretation being that to an observer
in this frame, the moving particles inertia is increased relative to
its classical value. This is why particle accelerators are so big and
expensive. As the particle approaches the speed of light, diverges,
so greater and greater forces are needed in order to produce the
same acceleration.
The momentum four-vector has locked within it the reason for
Einsteins famous E = mc
2
, which in our relativistic units becomes
simply E = m. To see why, consider the experimentally measured
inertia of a physical object made out of atoms. The subatomic par-
ticles are all moving, and many of the velocities, e.g., the velocities
of the electrons, are quite relativistic. This has the eect of in-
creasing the experimentally determined inertial mass, by a factor
of 1 averaged over all the particles. The same must be true for
the gravitational mass, based on the equivalence principle as veried
by Eotvos experiments. If the object is heated, the velocities will
increase on the average, resulting in a further increase in its mass.
Thus, a certain amount of heat energy is equivalent to a certain
amount of mass. But if heat energy contributes to mass, then the
same must be true for other forms of energy. For example, sup-
pose that heating leads to a chemical reaction, which converts some
heat into electromagnetic binding energy. If one joule of binding
energy did not convert to the same amount of mass as one joule of
heat, then this would allow the object to spontaneously change its
own mass, and then by conservation of momentum it would have
to spontaneously change its own velocity, which would clearly vio-
late the principle of relativity. We conclude that mass and energy
are equivalent, both inertially and gravitationally. In relativity, nei-
ther is separately conserved; the conserved quantity is their sum,
referred to as the mass-energy, E. The timelike component of the
four-momentum, m, is interpreted as the mass-energy of the par-
ticle, consisting of its mass m plus its kinetic energy m( 1). An
alternative derivation, by Einstein, is given in example 11 on page
111.
Gravitational redshifts Example: 4
Since a photons energy E is equivalent to a certain gravitational
mass m, photons that rise or fall in a gravitational eld must
lose or gain energy, and this should be observed as a redshift
or blueshift in the frequency. We expect the change in gravita-
tional potential energy to be E, giving a corresponding op-
posite change in the photons energy, so that E/E = . In
metric units, this becomes E/E = /c
2
, and in the eld near
106 Chapter 4 Tensors
the Earths surface we have E/E = gh/c
2
. This is the same
result that was found in section 1.5.7 based only on the equiva-
lence principle, and veried experimentally by Pound and Rebka
as described in section 1.5.8.
Since the momentum four-vector was obtained from the magni-
tude-1 velocity four-vector through multiplication by m, its squared
magnitude p
i
p
i
is equal to the square of the particles mass. Writing
p for the magnitude of the momentum three-vector, and E for the
mass-energy, we nd the useful relation E
2
p
2
= m
2
.
A common source of confusion for beginners in relativity is the
distinction between quantities that are conserved and quantities that
are the same in all frames. There is nothing relativistic about this
distinction. Before Einstein, physicists already knew that observers
in dierent frames of reference would agree on the mass of a particle.
That is, m was known to be frame-invariant. They also knew that
energy was conserved. But just because energy was conserved, that
didnt mean that it had to be the same for observers in all frames
of reference. The kinetic energy of the chair youre sitting in is
millions of joules in a frame of reference tied to the axis of the
earth. In relativity, m is frame-invariant (i.e., a Lorentz scalar), but
the conserved quantity is the momentum four-vector, which is not
frame-invariant.
Applying E
2
p
2
= m
2
to the special case of a massless particle,
we have [p[ = E, which demonstrates, for example, that a beam of
light exerts pressure when it is absorbed or reected by a surface.
2
A massless particle must also travel at exactly the speed of light,
since [p[ E requires mv m; conversely, a massive particle
always has [v[ < 1.
Constraints on polarization Example: 5
We observe that electromagnetic waves are always polarized
transversely, never longitudinally. Such a constraint can only ap-
ply to a wave that propagates at c. If it applied to a wave that
propagated at less than c, we could move into a frame of refer-
ence in which the wave was at rest. In this frame, all directions in
space would be equivalent, and there would be no way to decide
which directions of polarization should be permitted. For a wave
that propagates at c, there is no frame in which the wave is at rest
(see p. 81).
The Dirac sea Example: 6
A great deal of physics can be derived from the T.H. Whites
principle that whatever is not forbidden in compulsory orig-
inally intended for ants but applied to particles by Gell-Mann.
In quantum mechanics, any process that is not forbidden by a
conservation law is supposed to occur. The relativistic relation
2
cf. p. 28
Section 4.2 Four-vectors 107
E =
_
p
2
+ m
2
has two roots, a positive one and a negative one.
The positive-energy and negative-energy states are separated by
a no-mans land of width 2m, so no continuous classical process
can lead from one side to the other. But quantum-mechanically, if
an electron exists with energy E = +
_
p
2
+ m
2
, it should be able to
make a quantum leap into a state with E =
_
p
2
+ m
2
, emitting
the energy difference of 2E in the form of photons. Why doesnt
this happen? One explanation is that the states with E < 0 are all
already occupied. This is the Dirac sea, which we now interpret
as being full of electrons. A vacancy in the sea manifests itself as
an antielectron.
Massive neutrinos Example: 7
Neutrinos were long thought to be massless, but are now believed
to have masses in the eV range. If they had been massless, they
would always have had to propagate at the speed of light. Al-
though they are now thought to have mass, that mass is six or-
ders of magnitude less than the MeV energy scale of the nuclear
reactions in which they are produced, so all neutrinos observed
in experiments are moving at velocities very close to the speed of
light.
No radioactive decay of massless particles Example: 8
A photon cannot decay into an electron and a positron, e
+
+
e
= (1 +v)f =
_
1 +v
1 v
f ,
where the second form displays more clearly the symmetic form
of the relativistic relationship, such that interchanging the roles of
source and observer is equivalent to ipping the sign of v. That is,
the relativistic version only depends on the relative motion of the
source and the observer, whereas the Newtonian one also depends
on the sources motion relative to the medium (i.e., relative to the
preferred frame in which the waves have the right velocity). In
Newtonian mechanics, we have f
= ax
+ b. The addition
of the constant b is merely a change in the choice of origin, so it
has no eect on the components of the vector, but the dilation by
the factor a gives a change in scale, which results in v
= av
for a
contravariant vector. In the special case where v is an innitesimal
displacement, this is consistent with the result found by implicit dif-
ferentiation of the coordinate transformation. For a contravariant
vector, v
=
1
a
v
= v
[1]
v
= v
. [2]
Note the inversion of the partial derivative in one equation compared
to the other.
Self-check: Recall that the gauge transformations allowed in gen-
eral relativity are not just any coordinate transformations; they
must be (1) smooth and (2) one-to-one. Relate both of these re-
quirements to the features of the vector transformation laws above.
In equation [2], appears as a subscript on the left side of the
equation, but as a superscript on the right. This would appear
to violate our rules of notation, but the interpretation here is that
in expressions of the form /x
i
and /x
i
, the superscripts and
subscripts should be understood as being turned upside-down. Sim-
ilarly, [1] appears to have the implied sum over written ungram-
matically, with both s appearing as superscripts. Normally we
only have implied sums in which the index appears once as a super-
script and once as a subscript. With our new rule for interpreting
indices on the bottom of derivatives, the implied sum is seen to be
written correctly. This rule is similar to the one for analyzing the
units of derivatives written in Leibniz notation, with, e.g., d
2
x/dt
2
having units of meters per second squared.
A quantity v that transforms according to [1] or [2] is referred
to as a rank-1 tensor, which is the same thing as a vector.
The identity transformation Example: 12
In the case of the identity transformation x
= x
, equation [1]
clearly gives v
/x
=
1
x
(wrong!) ,
but this would give innite results for the mixed terms! Only in the
case of functions of a single variable is it possible to ip deriva-
tives in this way; it doesnt work for partial derivatives. To evalu-
ate these partial derivatives, we have to invert the transformation
(which in this example is trivial to accomplish) and then take the
partial derivatives.
The metric is a rank-2 tensor, and transforms analogously:
g
= g
, g
, and g
,
which are entirely determined by the grammatical rules for writing
superscripts and subscripts. Interpret the case of a rank-0 tensor.
An accelerated coordinate system? Example: 13
Lets see the effect on Lorentzian metric g of the transformation
t
= t x
= x +
1
2
at
2
.
The inverse transformation is
t = t
x = x
1
2
at
2
.
The tensor transformation law gives
g
t
= 1 (at
)
2
g
x
= 1
g
t
= at
.
Clearly something bad happens at at
component of the
metric vanishes and then reverses its sign. This would be physi-
cally unreasonable if we viewed this as a transformation from ob-
server As Lorentzian frame into the accelerating reference frame
of observer B aboard a spaceship who feels a constant acceler-
ation. Several things prevent such an interpretation: (1) B cannot
exceed the speed of light. (2) Even before B gets to the speed
of light, the coordinate t
, with a 0 as B
approaches the speed of light. There is nothing invalid about the
coordinate system (t
, x
=
_
x +
1
a
_
sinhat
x
=
_
x +
1
a
_
coshat
Applying the tensor transformation law gives (problem 6, page
126):
g
t
= (1 + ax
)
2
g
x
= 1
6
arxiv.org/abs/physics/0601179
116 Chapter 4 Tensors
Unlike the result of example 13, this one never misbehaves.
The closely related topic of a uniform gravitational eld in general
relativity is considered in problem 5 on page 162.
Accurate timing signals Example: 15
The relation between the potential A and the elds E and B given
on page 114 can be written in manifestly covariant form as F
i j
=
[i
A
j ]
, where F, called the electromagnetic tensor, is an antisym-
metric rank-two tensor whose six independent components corre-
spond in a certain way with the components of the E and B three-
vectors. If F vanishes completely at a certain point in spacetime,
then the linear form of the tensor transformation laws guarantees
that it will vanish in all coordinate systems, not just one. The GPS
system takes advantage of this fact in the transmission of timing
signals from the satellites to the users. The electromagnetic wave
is modulated so that the bits it transmits are represented by phase
reversals of the wave. At these phase reversals, F vanishes, and
this vanishing holds true regardless of the motion of the users
unit or its position in the earths gravitational eld.
4.4 Experimental tests
4.4.1 Universality of tensor behavior
The techniques developed in this chapter allow us to make a vari-
ety of new predictions that can be tested by experiment. In general,
the mathematical treatment of all observables in relativity as ten-
sors means that all observables must obey the same transformation
laws. This is an extremely strict statement, because it requires that
a wide variety of physical systems show identical behavior. For ex-
ample, we already mentioned on page 59 the 2007 Gravity Probe
B experiment (discussed in detail on pages 139 and 175), in which
four gyroscopes aboard a satellite were observed to precess due to
special- and general-relativistic eects. The gyroscopes were compli-
cated electromechanical systems, but the predicted precession was
entirely independent of these complications. We argued that if two
dierent types of gyroscopes displayed dierent behaviors, then the
resulting discrepancy would allow us to map out some mysterious
vector eld. This eld would be a built-in characteristic of space-
time (not produced by any physical objects nearby), and since all
observables in general relativity are supposed to be tensors, the eld
would have to transform as a tensor. Lets say that this tensor was
of rank 1. Since the tensor transformation law is linear, a nonzero
tensor can never be transformed into a vanishing tensor in another
coordinate system. But by the equivalence principle, any special,
local property of spacetime can be made to vanish by transforming
into a free-falling frame of reference, in which the spacetime is has a
generic Lorentzian geometry. The mysterious new eld should there-
Section 4.4 Experimental tests 117
fore vanish in such a frame. This is a contradiction, so we conclude
that dierent types of gyroscopes cannot dier in their behavior.
This is an example of a new way of stating the equivalence prin-
ciple: there is no way to associate a preferred tensor eld with space-
time.
7
4.4.2 Speed of light differing from c
In a Lorentz invariant theory, we interpret c as a property of
the underlying spacetime, not of the particles that inhabit it. One
way in which Lorentz invariance could be violated would be if dif-
ferent types of particles had dierent maximum velocities. In 1997,
Coleman and Glashow suggested a sensitive test for such an eect.
8
Assuming Lorentz invariance, a photon cannot decay into an
electron and a positron, e
+
+ e
.
A less sloppy calculation gives something more like 1.4M
. The self-
consistency of this solution is investigated in homework problem 13
on page 127.
What happens to a star whose mass is above the Chandrasekhar
limit? As nuclear fusion reactions icker out, the core of the star be-
comes a white dwarf, but once fusion ceases completely this cannot
be an equilibrium state. Now consider the nuclear reactions
n p +e
+
p +e
n + ,
which happen due to the weak nuclear force. The rst of these re-
leases 0.8 MeV, and has a half-life of 14 minutes. This explains
why free neutrons are not observed in signicant numbers in our
universe, e.g., in cosmic rays. The second reaction requires an input
of 0.8 MeV of energy, so a free hydrogen atom is stable. The white
dwarf contains fairly heavy nuclei, not individual protons, but sim-
ilar considerations would seem to apply. A nucleus can absorb an
electron and convert a proton into a neutron, and in this context the
process is called electron capture. Ordinarily this process will only
occur if the nucleus is neutron-decient; once it reaches a neutron-
to-proton ratio that optimizes its binding energy, neutron capture
cannot proceed without a source of energy to make the reaction go.
In the environment of a white dwarf, however, there is such a source.
The annihilation of an electron opens up a hole in the Fermi sea.
There is now an state into which another electron is allowed to drop
without violating the exclusion principle, and the eect cascades
upward. In a star with a mass above the Chandrasekhar limit, this
process runs to completion, with every proton being converted into a
neutron. The result is a neutron star, which is essentially an atomic
nucleus (with Z = 0) with the mass of a star!
Observational evidence for the existence of neutron stars came
in 1967 with the detection by Bell and Hewish at Cambridge of a
mysterious radio signal with a period of 1.3373011 seconds. The sig-
nals observability was synchronized with the rotation of the earth
relative to the stars, rather than with legal clock time or the earths
120 Chapter 4 Tensors
rotation relative to the sun. This led to the conclusion that its origin
was in space rather than on earth, and Bell and Hewish originally
dubbed it LGM-1 for little green men. The discovery of a second
signal, from a dierent direction in the sky, convinced them that it
was not actually an articial signal being generated by aliens. Bell
published the observation as an appendix to her PhD thesis, and
it was soon interpreted as a signal from a neutron star. Neutron
stars can be highly magnetized, and because of this magnetization
they may emit a directional beam of electromagnetic radiation that
sweeps across the sky once per rotational period the lighthouse
eect. If the earth lies in the plane of the beam, a periodic signal
can be detected, and the star is referred to as a pulsar. It is fairly
easy to see that the short period of rotation makes it dicult to
explain a pulsar as any kind of less exotic rotating object. In the
approximation of Newtonian mechanics, a spherical body of density
, rotating with a period T =
_
3/G, has zero apparent gravity
at its equator, since gravity is just strong enough to accelerate an
object so that it follows a circular trajectory above a xed point on
the surface (problem 12). In reality, astronomical bodies of plane-
tary size and greater are held together by their own gravity, so we
have T 1/
_
Km
e
m
n
_
2
5M
, x
) =
(t, x), and verify that g
is the same as g.
5 Starting from coordinates (t, x) having a Lorentzian metric g,
transform the metric tensor into Lorentz-boosted coordinates (t
, x
),
and verify that g
is the same as g.
6 Verify the transformation of the metric given in example 14
on page 116.
7 A skeptic claims that the Hafele-Keating experiment can only
be explained correctly by relativity in a frame in which the earths
axis is at rest. Prove mathematically that this is incorrect. Does it
matter whether the frame is inertial? Solution, p. 264
8 Assume the metric g = diag(+1, +1, +1). Which of the fol-
lowing correctly expresses the noncommutative property of ordinary
matrix multiplication?
A
j
i
B
jk
,= B
jk
A
j
i
A
j
i
B
jk
,= B
j
i
A
jk
9 Example 6 on page 107 introduced the Dirac sea, whose
existence is implied by the two roots of the relativistic relation
E =
_
p
2
+m
2
. Prove that a Lorentz boost will never trans-
form a positive-energy state into a negative-energy state.
Solution, p. 264
10 On page 111, we found the relativistic Doppler shift in 1+1
dimensions. Extend this to 3+1 dimensions, and check your result
against the one given by Einstein on page 253.
Solution, p. 264
11 For gamma-rays in the MeV range, the most frequent mode of
126 Chapter 4 Tensors
interaction with matter is Compton scattering, in which the photon
is scattered by an electron without being absorbed. Only part of
the gammas energy is deposited, and the amount is related to the
angle of scattering. Use conservation of four-momentum to show
that in the case of scattering at 180 degrees, the scattered photon
has energy E
, x
t
= (1 +ax
)
2
g
x
x
= 1 ,
where the primes indicate the accelerated observers frame. The fact
that the timelike element is not equal to 1 is not an indication of
129
a / Tidal forces disrupt comet
Shoemaker-Levy.
intrinsic curvature. It arises only from the choice of the coordinates
(t
, x
=
134 Chapter 5 Curvature
h / 1. Gaussian curvature
can be interpreted as the failure
of parallelism represented by
d
2
/dxdy.
i / 2. Gaussian curvature as
L ,= r .
dx, and let d
dxdy
,
where d
2
= d
d.
2. From a point P, emit a fan of rays at angles lling a certain
range of angles in Gaussian polar coordinates (gure i). Let the
arc length of this fan at r be L, which may not be equal to its
Euclidean value L
E
= r. Then
2
K = 3
d
2
dr
2
_
L
L
e
_
.
Lets now generalize beyond elliptic geometry. Consider a space
modeled by a surface embedded in three dimensions, with geodesics
dened as curves of extremal length, i.e., the curves made by a piece
of string stretched taut across the surface. At a particular point
P, we can always pick a coordinate system (x, y, z) such that the
surface z =
1
2
k
1
x
2
+
1
2
k
2
y
2
locally approximates the surface to the
level of precision needed in order to discuss curvature. The surface
is either paraboloidal or hyperboloidal (a saddle), depending on the
signs of k
1
and k
2
. We might naively think that k
1
and k
2
could be
independently determined by intrinsic measurements, but as weve
seen in example 4 on page 79, a cylinder is locally indistinguishable
from a Euclidean plane, so if one k is zero, the other k clearly cannot
be determined. In fact all that can be measured is the Gaussian
curvature, which equals the product k
1
k
2
. To see why this should
be true, rst consider that any measure of curvature has units of
inverse distance squared, and the ks have units of inverse distance.
The only possible intrinsic measures of curvature based on the ks
are therefore k
2
1
+k
2
2
and k
1
k
2
. (We cant have, for example, just k
2
1
,
because that would change under an extrinsic rotation about the z
axis.) Only k
1
k
2
vanishes on a cylinder, so it is the only possible
intrinsic curvature.
Eating pizza Example: 3
When people eat pizza by folding the slice lengthwise, they are
taking advantage of the intrinsic nature of the Gaussian curva-
ture. Once k
1
is xed to a nonzero value, k
2
cant change without
varying K, so the slice cant droop.
1
Proof: Since any two lines cross in elliptic geometry, crosses the x axis. The
corollary then follows by application of the denition of the Gaussian curvature
to the right triangles formed by , the x axis, and the lines at x = 0 and x = dx,
so that K = d/dA = d
2
/dxdy, where third powers of innitesimals have been
discarded.
2
In the spherical model, L = sin u, where u is the angle subtended at the
center of the sphere by an arc of length r. We then have L/LE = sin u/u, whose
second derivative with respect to u is 1/3. Since r = u, the second derivative
of the same quantity with respect to r equals 1/3
2
= K/3.
Section 5.3 Curvature in two spacelike dimensions 135
k / A ea on the football can-
not orient himself by intrinsic,
local measurements.
j / A triangle in a space with
negative curvature has angles
that add to less than .
Elliptic and hyperbolic geometry Example: 4
Weve seen that gures behaving according to the axioms of el-
liptic geometry can be modeled on part of a sphere, which is a
surface of constant K > 0. The model can be made into global
one satisfying all the axioms if the appropriate topological prop-
erties are ensured by identifying antipodal points. A paraboloidal
surface z = k
1
x
2
+ k
2
y
2
can be a good local approximation to
a sphere, but for points far from its apex, K varies signicantly.
Elliptic geometry has no parallels; all lines meet if extended far
enough.
A space of constant negative curvature has a geometry called
hyperbolic, and is of some interest because it appears to be the
one that describes the the spatial dimensions of our universe on
a cosmological scale. A hyperboloidal surface works locally as a
model, but its curvature is only approximately constant; the sur-
face of constant curvature is a horn-shaped one created by re-
volving a mountain-shaped curve called a tractrix about its axis.
The tractrix of revolution is not as satisfactory a model as the
sphere is for elliptic geometry, because lines are cut off at the
cusp of the horn. Hyperbolic geometry is richer in parallels than
Euclidean geometry; given a line and a point P not on , there
are innitely many lines through P that do not pass through .
A ea on a football Example: 5
We might imagine that a ea on the surface of an American foot-
ball could determine by intrinsic, local measurements which di-
rection to go in order to get to the nearest tip. This is impossible,
because the ea would have to determine a vector, and curvature
cannot be a vector, since z =
1
2
k
1
x
2
+
1
2
k
2
y
2
is invariant under the
parity inversion x x, y y. For similar reasons, a measure
of curvature can never have odd rank.
Without violating reection symmetry, it is still conceivable that the
ea could determine the orientation of the tip-to-tip line running
through his position. Surprisingly, even this is impossible. The
ea can only measure the single number K, which carries no
information about directions in space.
5.4 Curvature tensors
The example of the ea suggests that if we want to express curvature
as a tensor, it should have even rank. Also, in a coordinate system
in which the coordinates have units of distance (they are not angles,
for instance, as in spherical coordinates), we expect that the units of
curvature will always be inverse distance squared. More elegantly,
we expect that under a uniform rescaling of coordinates by a factor
of , a curvature tensor should scale down by
2
.
Combining these two facts, we nd that a curvature tensor should
have one of the forms R
ab
, R
a
bcd
, . . . , i.e., the number of lower in-
136 Chapter 5 Curvature
a / The denition of the Riemann
tensor. The vector v
b
changes
by dv
b
when parallel-transported
around the approximate parallel-
ogram. (v
b
is drawn on a scale
that makes its length comparable
to the innitesimals dp
c
, dq
d
, and
dv
b
; in reality, its size would be
greater than theirs by an innite
factor.)
dices should be two greater than the number of upper indices. The
following denition has this property, and is equivalent to the earlier
denitions of the Gaussian curvature that were not written in tensor
notation.
Denition of the Riemann curvature tensor: Let dp
c
and dq
d
be two innitesimal vectors, and use them to form a quadrilateral
that is a good approximation to a parallelogram.
3
Parallel-transport
vector v
b
all the way around the parallelogram. When it comes back
to its starting place, it has a new value v
b
v
b
+ dv
b
. Then the
Riemann curvature tensor is dened as the tensor that computes dv
a
according to dv
a
= R
a
bcd
v
b
dp
c
dq
d
. (There is no standardization in
the literature of the order of the indices.)
A symmetry of the Riemann tensor Example: 6
If vectors dp
c
and dq
d
lie along the same line, then dv
a
must van-
ish, and interchanging dp
c
and dq
d
simply reverses the direction
of the circuit around the quadrilateral, giving dv
a
dv
a
. This
shows that R
a
bcd
must be antisymmetric under interchange of the
indices c and d, R
a
bcd
= R
a
bdc
.
In local normal coordinates, the interpretation of the Riemann
tensor becomes particularly transparent. The constant-coordinate
lines are geodesics, so when the vector v
b
is transported along them,
it maintains a constant angle with respect to them. Any rotation
of the vector after it is brought around the perimeter of the quadri-
lateral can therefore be attributed to something that happens at
the vertices. In other words, it is simply a measure of the angular
defect. We can therefore see that the Riemann tensor is really just
a tensorial way of writing the Gaussian curvature K = d/dA.
In normal coordinates, the local geometry is nearly Cartesian,
and when we take the product of two vectors in an antisymmetric
manner, we are essentially measuring the area of the parallelogram
they span, as in the three-dimensional vector cross product. We can
therefore see that the Riemann tensor tells us something about the
amount of curvature contained within the innitesimal area spanned
by dp
c
and dq
d
. A nite two-dimensional region can be broken
down into innitesimal elements of area, and the Riemann tensor
integrated over them. The result is equal to the nite change v
b
in a vector transported around the whole boundary of the region.
Curvature tensors on a sphere Example: 7
Lets nd the curvature tensors on a sphere of radius .
Construct normal coordinates (x, y) with origin O, and let vec-
tors dp
c
and dq
d
represent innitesimal displacements along x
and y, forming a quadrilateral as described above. Then R
x
yxy
represents the change in the x direction that occurs in a vector
that is initially in the y direction. If the vector has unit magni-
3
Section 5.8 discusses the sense in which this approximation is good enough.
Section 5.4 Curvature tensors 137
b / The change in the vector
due to parallel transport around
the octant equals the integral
of the Riemann tensor over the
interior.
tude, then R
x
yxy
equals the angular decit of the quadrilateral.
Comparing with the denition of the Gaussian curvature, we nd
R
x
yxy
= K = 1/
2
. Interchanging x and y, we nd the same result
for R
y
xyx
. Thus although the Riemann tensor in two dimensions
has sixteen components, only these two are nonzero, and they
are equal to each other.
This result represents the defect in parallel transport around a
closed loop per unit area. Suppose we parallel-transport a vector
around an octant, as shown in gure b. The area of the octant
is (/2)
2
, and multiplying it by the Riemann tensor, we nd that
the defect in parallel transport is /2, i.e., a right angle, as is also
evident from the gure.
The above treatment may be somewhat misleading in that it may
lead you to believe that there is a single coordinate system in
which the Riemann tensor is always constant. This is not the
case, since the calculation of the Riemann tensor was only valid
near the origin O of the normal coordinates. The character of
these coordinates becomes quite complicated far from O; we end
up with all our constant-x lines converging at north and south
poles of the sphere, and all the constant-y lines at east and west
poles.
Angular coordinates (, ) are more suitable as a large-scale de-
scription of the sphere. We can use the tensor transformation law
to nd the Riemann tensor in these coordinates. If O, the origin
of the (x, y) coordinates, is at coordinates (, ), then dx/d =
sin and dy/d = . The result is R
= R
x
yxy
(dy/d)
2
= 1
and R
= R
y
xyx
(dx/d)
2
= sin
2
. The variation in R
= e
i
, where is a constant. The transformation
is also allowed, and it gives (t) = (q/)t, so that
the phase factor e
i(t)
is a function of time t. Now from the point
of view of electromagnetism in the age of Maxwell, with the elec-
tric and magnetic elds imagined as playing their roles against a
background of Euclidean space and absolute time, the form of this
time-dependent phase factor is very special and symmetrical; it de-
pends only on the absolute time variable. But to a relativist, there is
nothing very nice about this function at all, because there is nothing
special about a time coordinate. If were going to allow a function
of this form, then based on the coordinate-invariance of relativity, it
seems that we should probably allow to be any function at all of
the spacetime coordinates. The proper generalization of
is now A
b
A
b
b
, where A
b
is the electromagnetic potential
four-vector (section 4.2.5, page 113).
Self-check: Suppose we said we would allow to be a function
of t, but forbid it to depend on the spatial coordinates. Prove that
142 Chapter 5 Curvature
c / These three rulers represent
three choices of coordinates. As
in gure b on page 142, switching
from one set of coordinates to
another has no effect on any
experimental observables. It is
merely a choice of gauge.
this would violate Lorentz invariance.
The transformation has no eect on the electromagnetic elds,
which are the direct observables. We can also verify that the change
of gauge will have no eect on observable behavior of charged par-
ticles. This is because the phase of a wavefunction can only be
determined relative to the phase of another particles wavefunction,
when they occupy the same point in space and, for example, inter-
fere. Since the phase shift depends only on the location in spacetime,
there is no change in the relative phase.
But bad things will happen if we dont make a corresponding
adjustment to the derivatives appearing in the Schrodinger equation.
These derivatives are essentially the momentum operators, and they
give dierent results when applied to
b
b
_
e
i
_
= e
i
b
+i
b
_
e
i
_
=
_
b
+A
b
A
b
_
b
b
+ ieA
b
, where the correction term compensates for the
change of gauge. We call the operator dened as
b
=
b
+ieA
b
the covariant derivative. It gives the right answer regardless of a
change of gauge.
5.6.2 The covariant derivative in general relativity
Now consider how all of this plays out in the context of gen-
eral relativity. The gauge transformations of general relativity are
arbitrary smooth changes of coordinates. One of the most basic
properties we could require of a derivative operator is that it must
give zero on a constant function. A constant scalar function remains
constant when expressed in a new coordinate system, but the same
is not true for a constant vector function, or for any tensor of higher
rank. This is because the change of coordinates changes the units
in which the vector is measured, and if the change of coordinates is
nonlinear, the units vary from point to point.
Consider the one-dimensional case, in which a vector v
a
has only
one component, and the metric is also a single number, so that we
can omit the indices and simply write v and g. (We just have to
remember that v is really a covariant vector, even though were
leaving out the upper index.) If v is constant, its derivative dv/dx,
computed in the ordinary way without any correction term, is zero.
If we further assume that the coordinate x is a normal coordinate, so
that the metric is simply the constant g = 1, then zero is not just the
answer but the right answer. (The existence of a preferred, global
set of normal coordinates is a special feature of a one-dimensional
Section 5.6 The covariant derivative 143
space, because there is no curvature in one dimension. In more than
one dimension, there will typically be no possible set of coordinates
in which the metric is constant, and normal coordinates only give a
metric that is approximately constant in the neighborhood around
a certain point. See gure g pn page 134 for an example of normal
coordinates on a sphere, which do not have a constant metric.)
Now suppose we transform into a new coordinate system X,
which is not normal. The metric G, expressed in this coordinate
system, is not constant. Applying the tensor transformation law,
we have V = v dX/dx, and dierentiation with respect to X will
not give zero, because the factor dX/dx isnt constant. This is the
wrong answer: V isnt really varying, it just appears to vary because
G does.
We want to add a correction term onto the derivative operator
d/dX, forming a covariant derivative operator
X
that gives the
right answer. This correction term is easy to nd if we consider
what the result ought to be when dierentiating the metric itself.
In general, if a tensor appears to vary, it could vary either because
it really does vary or because the metric varies. If the metric itself
varies, it could be either because the metric really does vary or
. . . because the metric varies. In other words, there is no sensible
way to assign a nonzero covariant derivative to the metric itself, so
we must have
X
G = 0. The required correction therefore consists
of replacing d/dX with
X
=
d
dX
G
1
dG
dX
.
Applying this to G gives zero. G is a second-rank contravariant
tensor. If we apply the same correction to the derivatives of other
second-rank contravariant tensors, we will get nonzero results, and
they will be the right nonzero results. For example, the covariant
derivative of the stress-energy tensor T (assuming such a thing could
have some physical signicance in one dimension!) will be
X
T =
dT/dX G
1
(dG/dX)T.
Physically, the correction term is a derivative of the metric, and
weve already seen that the derivatives of the metric (1) are the clos-
est thing we get in general relativity to the gravitational eld, and
(2) are not tensors. In 1+1 dimensions, suppose we observe that a
free-falling rock has dV/dT = 9.8 m/s
2
. This acceleration cannot be
a tensor, because we could make it vanish by changing from Earth-
xed coordinates X to free-falling (normal, locally Lorentzian) co-
ordinates x, and a tensor cannot be made to vanish by a change of
coordinates. According to a free-falling observer, the vector v isnt
changing at all; it is only the variation in the Earth-xed observers
metric G that makes it appear to change.
Mathematically, the form of the derivative is (1/y)dy/dx, which
is known as a logarithmic derivative, since it equals d(ln y)/dx. It
144 Chapter 5 Curvature
d / Example 8.
measures the multiplicative rate of change of y. For example, if
y scales up by a factor of k when x increases by 1 unit, then the
logarithmic derivative of y is ln k. The logarithmic derivative of
e
cx
is c. The logarithmic nature of the correction term to
X
is a
good thing, because it lets us take changes of scale, which are mul-
tiplicative changes, and convert them to additive corrections to the
derivative operator. The additivity of the corrections is necessary if
the result of a covariant derivative is to be a tensor, since tensors
are additive creatures.
What about quantities that are not second-rank covariant ten-
sors? Under a rescaling of contravariant coordinates by a factor of
k, covariant vectors scale by k
1
, and second-rank covariant tensors
by k
2
. The correction term should therefore be half as much for
covariant vectors,
X
=
d
dX
1
2
G
1
dG
dX
.
and should have an opposite sign for contravariant vectors.
Generalizing the correction term to derivatives of vectors in more
than one dimension, we should have something of this form:
a
v
b
=
a
v
b
+
b
ac
v
c
a
v
b
=
a
v
b
c
ba
v
c
,
where
b
ac
, called the Christoel symbol, does not transform like
a tensor, and involves derivatives of the metric. (Christoel is
pronounced Krist-AWful, with the accent on the middle syllable.)
The explicit computation of the Christoel symbols from the metric
is deferred until section 5.9, but the intervening sections 5.7 and 5.8
can be omitted on a rst reading without loss of continuity.
Christoffel symbols on the globe Example: 8
As a qualitative example, consider the geodesic airplane trajec-
tory shown in gure d, from London to Mexico City. In physics
it is customary to work with the colatitude, , measured down
from the north pole, rather then the latitude, measured from the
equator. At P, over the North Atlantic, the planes colatitude has
a minimum. (We can see, without having to take it on faith from
the gure, that such a minimum must occur. The easiest way to
convince oneself of this is to consider a path that goes directly
over the pole, at = 0.)
At P, the planes velocity vector points directly west. At Q, over
New England, its velocity has a large component to the south.
Since the path is a geodesic and the plane has constant speed,
the velocity vector is simply being parallel-transported; the vec-
tors covariant derivative is zero. Since we have v
= 0 at P, the
only way to explain the nonzero and positive value of
is that
we have a nonzero and negative value of
.
Section 5.6 The covariant derivative 145
a / The geodesic, 1, preserves
tangency under parallel trans-
port. The non-geodesic curve,
2, doesnt have this property;
a vector initially tangent to the
curve is no longer tangent to it
when parallel-transported along
it.
By symmetry, we can infer that
a
U
bc
=
a
U
bc
d
ba
U
dc
d
ca
U
bd
or
a
U
c
b
=
a
U
c
b
d
ba
U
c
d
+
c
ad
U
d
b
.
With the partial derivative
a
, it does not make sense to use the
metric to raise the index and form
a
. It does make sense to do so
with covariant derivatives, so
a
= g
ab
b
is a correct identity.
Comma and semicolon notation
Some authors use superscripts with commas and semicolons to
indicate partial and covariant derivatives. The following equations
give equivalent notations for the same derivatives:
a
X
b
= X
b,a
a
X
b
= X
b;a
a
X
b
= X
;a
b
5.7 The geodesic equation
In this section, which can be skipped at a rst reading, we show how
the Christoel symbols can be used to nd dierential equations that
describe geodesics.
6
On the gravitational eld of a point mass according to Einsteins the-
ory, Sitzungsberichte der K oniglich Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften
1 (1916) 189, translated in arxiv.org/abs/physics/9905030v1.
146 Chapter 5 Curvature
5.7.1 Characterization of the geodesic
A geodesic can be dened as a world-line that preserves tangency
under parallel transport, a. This is essentially a mathematical way
of expressing the notion that we have previously expressed more
informally in terms of staying on course or moving inertially.
A curve can be specied by giving functions x
i
() for its coor-
dinates, where is a real parameter. A vector lying tangent to the
curve can then be calculated using partial derivatives, T
i
= x
i
/.
There are three ways in which a vector function of could change:
(1) it could change for the trivial reason that the metric is changing,
so that its components changed when expressed in the new metric;
(2) it could change its components perpendicular to the curve; or
(3) it could change its component parallel to the curve. Possibility
1 should not really be considered a change at all, and the denition
of the covariant derivative is specically designed to be insensitive
to this kind of thing. 2 cannot apply to T
i
, which is tangent by
construction. It would therefore be convenient if T
i
happened to
be always the same length. If so, then 3 would not happen either,
and we could reexpress the denition of a geodesic by saying that
the covariant derivative of T
i
was zero. For this reason, we will
assume for the remainder of this section that the parametrization
of the curve has this property. In a Newtonian context, we could
imagine the x
i
to be purely spatial coordinates, and to be a uni-
versal time coordinate. We would then interpret T
i
as the velocity,
and the restriction would be to a parametrization describing motion
with constant speed. In relativity, the restriction is that must be
an ane parameter. For example, it could be the proper time of a
particle, if the curve in question is timelike.
5.7.2 Covariant derivative with respect to a parameter
The notation of section 5.6 is not quite adapted to our present
purposes, since it allows us to express a covariant derivative with
respect to one of the coordinates, but not with respect to a param-
eter such as . We would like to notate the covariant derivative of
T
i
with respect to as
T
i
, even though isnt a coordinate. To
connect the two types of derivatives, we can use a total derivative.
To make the idea clear, here is how we calculate a total derivative
for a scalar function f(x, y), without tensor notation:
df
d
=
f
x
x
+
f
y
y
.
This is just the generalization of the chain rule to a function of two
variables. For example, if represents time and f temperature,
then this would tell us the rate of change of the temperature as
a thermometer was carried through space. Applying this to the
Section 5.7 The geodesic equation 147
present problem, we express the total covariant derivative as
T
i
= (
b
T
i
)
dx
b
d
=
_
b
T
i
+
i
bc
T
c
_
dx
b
d
.
5.7.3 The geodesic equation
Recognizing
b
T
i
dx
b
/d as a total non-covariant derivative, we
nd
T
i
=
dT
i
d
+
i
bc
T
c
dx
b
d
.
Substituting x
i
/ for T
i
, and setting the covariant derivative
equal to zero, we obtain
d
2
x
i
d
2
+
i
bc
dx
c
d
dx
b
d
= 0.
This is known as the geodesic equation.
If this dierential equation is satised for one ane parameter
, then it is also satised for any other ane parameter
= a+b,
where a and b are constants (problem 3). Recall that ane param-
eters are only dened along geodesics, not along arbitrary curves.
We cant start by dening an ane parameter and then use it to
nd geodesics using this equation, because we cant dene an ane
parameter without rst specifying a geodesic. Likewise, we cant
do the geodesic rst and then the ane parameter, because if we
already had a geodesic in hand, we wouldnt need the dierential
equation in order to nd a geodesic. The solution to this chicken-
and-egg conundrum is to write down the dierential equations and
try to nd a solution, without trying to specify either the ane pa-
rameter or the geodesic in advance. We will seldom have occasion
to resort to this technique, an exception being example 3 on page
215.
5.7.4 Uniqueness
The geodesic equation is useful in establishing one of the neces-
sary theoretical foundations of relativity, which is the uniqueness of
geodesics for a given set of initial conditions. This is related to ax-
iom O1 of ordered geometry, that two points determine a line, and
is necessary physically for the reasons discussed on page 21; briey,
if the geodesic were not uniquely determined, then particles would
have no way of deciding how to move. The form of the geodesic
equation guarantees uniqueness. To see this, consider the following
algorithm for determining a numerical approximation to a geodesic:
1. Initialize , the x
i
and their derivatives dx
i
/d. Also, set a
small step-size by which to increment at each step below.
148 Chapter 5 Curvature
2. For each i, calculate d
2
x
i
/d
2
using the geodesic equation.
3. Add (d
2
x
i
/d
2
) to the currently stored value of dx
i
/d.
4. Add (dx
i
/d) to x
i
.
5. Add to .
6. Repeat steps 2-5 until the the geodesic has been extended to
the desired ane distance.
Since the result of the calculation depends only on the inputs at
step 1, we nd that the geodesic is uniquely determined.
To see that this is really a valid way of proving uniqueness, it
may be helpful to consider how the proof could have failed. Omitting
some of the details of the tensors and the multidimensionality of the
space, the form of the geodesic equation is essentially x + f x
2
= 0,
where dots indicate derivatives with respect to . Suppose that it
had instead had the form x
2
+ f x = 0. Then at step 2 we would
have had to pick either a positive or a negative square root for x.
Although continuity would usually suce to maintain a consistent
sign from one iteration to the next, that would not work if we ever
came to a point where x vanished momentarily. An equation of this
form therefore would not have a unique solution for a given set of
initial conditions.
The practical use of this algorithm to compute geodesics numer-
ically is demonstrated in section 5.9.2 on page 157.
5.8 Torsion
This section describes the concept of gravitational torsion. It can
be skipped without loss of continuity, provided that you accept the
symmetry property
a
[bc]
= 0 without worrying about what it means
physically or what empirical evidence supports it.
Self-check: Interpret the mathematical meaning of the equation
a
[bc]
= 0, which is expressed in the notation introduced on page 84.
5.8.1 Are scalars path-dependent?
It seems clear that something like the covariant derivative is
needed for vectors, since they have a direction in spacetime, and
thus their measures vary when the measure of spacetime itself varies.
Since scalars dont have a direction in spacetime, the same reasoning
doesnt apply to them, and this is reected in our rules for covariant
derivatives. The covariant derivative has one term for every index
of the tensor being dierentiated, so for a scalar there should be no
terms at all, i.e.,
a
is the same as
a
.
But just because derivatives of scalars dont require special treat-
ment for this particular reason, that doesnt mean they are guaran-
Section 5.8 Torsion 149
a / Measuring
2
T/xy for
a scalar T.
teed to behave as we intuitively expect, in the strange world of
coordinate-invariant relativity.
One possible way for scalars to behave counterintuitively would
be by analogy with parallel transport of vectors. If we stick a vector
in a box (as with, e.g., the gyroscopes aboard Gravity Probe B) and
carry it around a closed loop, it changes. Could the same happen
with a scalar? This is extremely counterintuitive, since there is no
reason to imagine such an eect in any of the models weve con-
structed of curved spaces. In fact, it is not just counterintuitive but
mathematically impossible, according to the following argument.
The only reason we can interpret the vector-in-a-box eect as aris-
ing from the geometry of spacetime is that it applies equally to all
vectors. If, for example, it only applied to the magnetic polariza-
tion vectors of ferromagnetic substances, then we would interpret
it as a magnetic eld living in spacetime, not a property of space-
time itself. If the value of a scalar-in-a-box was path-dependent,
and this path-dependence was a geometric property of spacetime,
then it would have to apply to all scalars, including, say, masses
and charges of particles. Thus if an electrons mass increased by 1%
when transported in a box along a certain path, its charge would
have to increase by 1% as well. But then its charge-to-mass ra-
tio would remain invariant, and this is a contradiction, since the
charge-to-mass ratio is also a scalar, and should have felt the same
1% eect. Since the varying scalar-in-a-box idea leads to a contra-
diction, it wasnt a coincidence that we couldnt nd a model that
produced such an eect; a theory that lacks self-consistency doesnt
have any models.
Self-check: Explain why parallel transporting a vector can only
rotate it, not change its magnitude.
There is, however, a dierent way in which scalars could behave
counterintuitively, and this one is mathematically self-consistent.
Suppose that Helen lives in two spatial dimensions and owns a ther-
mometer. She wants to measure the spatial variation of tempera-
ture, in particular its mixed second derivative
2
T/xy. At home
in the morning at point A, she prepares by calibrating her gyro-
compass to point north and measuring the temperature. Then she
travels = 1 km east along a geodesic to B, consults her gyro-
compass, and turns north. She continues one kilometer north to C,
samples the change in temperature T
1
relative to her home, and
then retraces her steps to come home for lunch. In the afternoon,
she checks her work by carrying out the same process, but this time
she interchanges the roles of north and east, traveling along ADE.
If she were living in a at space, this would form the other two sides
of a square, and her afternoon temperature sample T
2
would be
at the same point in space C as her morning sample. She actually
doesnt recognize the landscape, so the sample points C and E are
dierent, but this just conrms what she already knew: the space
150 Chapter 5 Curvature
b / The gyroscopes both ro-
tate when transported from A
to B, causing Helen to navigate
along BC, which does not form
a right angle with AB. The angle
between the two gyroscopes
axes is always the same, so the
rotation is not locally observable,
but it does produce an observable
gap between C and E.
isnt at.
7
None of this seems surprising yet, but there are now two quali-
tatively dierent ways that her analysis of her data could turn out,
indicating qualitatively dierent things about the laws of physics
in her universe. The denition of the derivative as a limit requires
that she repeat the experiment at smaller scales. As 0, the
result for
2
T/xy should approach a denite limit, and the er-
ror should diminish in proportion to . In particular the dierence
between the results inferred from T
1
and T
2
indicate an error,
and the discrepancy between the second derivatives inferred from
them should shrink appropriately as shrinks. Suppose this doesnt
happen. Since partial derivatives commute, we conclude that her
measuring procedure is not the same as a partial derivative. Lets
call her measuring procedure , so that she is observing a discrep-
ancy between
x
y
and
y
x
. The fact that the commutator
x
doesnt vanish cannot be explained by the Christof-
fel symbols, because what shes dierentiating is a scalar. Since the
discrepancy arises entirely from the failure of T
1
T
2
to scale
down appropriately, the conclusion is that the distance between
the two sampling points is not scaling down as quickly as we ex-
pect. In our familiar models of two-dimensional spaces as surfaces
embedded in three-space, we always have
3
for small , but she
has found that it only shrinks as quickly as
2
.
For a clue as to what is going on, note that the commutator
y
y
x
has a particular handedness to it. For example,
it ips its sign under a reection across the line y = x. When we
parallel-transport vectors, they arent actually staying parallel. In
this hypothetical universe, a vector in a box transported by a small
distance rotates by an angle proportional to . This eect is called
torsion. Although no torsion eect shows up in our familiar models,
that is not because torsion lacks self-consistency. Models of spaces
with torsion do exist. In particular, we can see that torsion doesnt
lead to the same kind of logical contradiction as the varying-scalar-
in-a-box idea. Since all vectors twist by the same amount when
transported, inner products are preserved, so it is not possible to
put two vectors in one box and get the scalar-in-a-box paradox by
watching their inner product change when the box is transported.
Note that the elbows ABC and ADE are not right angles. If
Helen had brought a pair of gyrocompasses with her, one for x and
one for y, she would have found that the right angle between the
gyrocompasses was preserved under parallel transport, but that a
gyrocompass initially tangent to a geodesic did not remain so. There
are in fact two inequivalent denitions of a geodesic in a space with
torsion. The shortest path between two points is not necessarily
the same as the straightest possible path, i.e., the one that parallel-
7
This point was mentioned on page 137, in connection with the denition of
the Riemann tensor.
Section 5.8 Torsion 151
transports its own tangent vector.
5.8.2 The torsion tensor
Since torsion is odd under parity, it must be represented by an
odd-rank tensor, which we call
c
ab
and dene according to
(
a
a
)f =
c
ab
c
f ,
where f is any scalar eld, such as the temperature in the preced-
ing section. There are two dierent ways in which a space can be
non-Euclidean: it can have curvature, or it can have torsion. For
a full discussion of how to handle the mathematics of a spacetime
with both curvature and torsion, see the article by Steuard Jensen at
http://www.slimy.com/
~
steuard/teaching/tutorials/GRtorsion.
pdf. For our present purposes, the main mathematical fact worth
noting is that vanishing torsion is equivalent to the symmetry
a
bc
=
a
cb
of the Christoel symbols. Using the notation introduced on
page 84,
a
[bc]
= 0 if = 0.
Self-check: Use an argument similar to the one in example 5
on page 136 to prove that no model of a two-space embedded in a
three-space can have torsion.
Generalizing to more dimensions, the torsion tensor is odd under
the full spacetime reection x
a
x
a
, i.e., a parity inversion plus
a time-reversal, PT.
In the story above, we had a torsion that didnt preserve tan-
gent vectors. In three or more dimensions, however, it is possible
to have torsion that does preserve tangent vectors. For example,
transporting a vector along the x axis could cause only a rotation in
the y-z plane. This relates to the symmetries of the torsion tensor,
which for convenience well write in an x-y-z coordinate system and
in the fully covariant form
un-
less , , and are all distinct. This is an example of the type
of antisymmetry that is familiar from the vector cross product, in
which the cross products of the basis vectors behave as x y = z,
y z = x, y z = x. Generalizing the notation for symmetrization
and antisymmetrization of tensors from page 84, we have
T
(abc)
=
1
3!
T
abc
T
[abc]
=
1
3!
abc
T
abc
,
where the sums are over all permutations of the indices, and in the
second line the totally antisymmetric Levi-Civita tensor is dened
152 Chapter 5 Curvature
c / Three gyroscopes are ini-
tially aligned with the x, y, and
z axes. After parallel transport
along the geodesic x axis, the
x gyro is still aligned with the x
axis, but the y and z gyros have
rotated.
by
abc
=
bca
=
cab
= +1,
bac
=
acb
=
cba
= 1, and
= 0
for all other combinations of indices. In other words,
is +1 if
represent an even permutation of abc (i.e., they can be obtained
from abc by an even number of pairwise swaps), 1 for odd permu-
tations, and 0 otherwise (i.e., if is not a permutation of abc).
In this notation, a totally antisymmetric torsion tensor is one with
[]
, and torsion of this type preserves tangent vectors under
translation.
In two dimensions, there are no totally antisymmetric rank-3
tensors, because we cant write three indices without repeating one.
In three dimensions, an antisymmetric rank-3 tensor is simply a mul-
tiple of the Levi-Civita tensor, so a totally antisymmetric torsion, if
it exists, is represented by a single number; under translation, vec-
tors rotate like either right-handed or left-handed screws, and this
number tells us the rate of rotation. In four dimensions, we have
four independently variable quantities,
xyz
,
tyz
,
txz
, and
txy
. In
other words, an antisymmetric torsion of 3+1 spacetime can be rep-
resented by a four-vector,
a
=
abcd
bcd
.
5.8.3 Experimental searches for torsion
One way of stating the equivalence principle (see p. 118) is that
it forbids spacetime from coming equipped with a vector eld that
could be measured by free-falling observers, i.e., observers in local
Lorentz frames. A variety of high-precision tests of the equivalence
principle have been carried out. From the point of view of an ex-
perimenter doing this kind of test, it is important to distinguish
between elds that are built in to spacetime and those that live
in spacetime. For example, the existence of the earths magnetic
eld does not violate the equivalence principle, but if an experi-
ment was sensitive to the earths eld, and the experimenter didnt
know about it, there would appear to be a violation. Antisymmet-
ric torsion in four dimensions acts like a vector. If it constitutes
a universal background eect built into spacetime, then it violates
the equivalence principle. If it instead arises from specic material
sources, then it may still show up as a measurable eect in exper-
imental tests designed to detect Lorentz-invariance. Lets consider
the latter possibility.
Since curvature in general relativity comes from mass and en-
ergy, as represented by the stress-energy tensor T
ab
, we could ask
what would be the sources of torsion, if it exists in our universe.
The source cant be the rank-2 stress-energy tensor. It would have
to be an odd-rank tensor, i.e., a quantity that is odd under PT, and
in theories that include torsion it is commonly assumed that the
source is the quantum-mechanical angular momentum of subatomic
particles. If this is the case, then torsion eects are expected to be
proportional to G, the product of Plancks constant and the gravi-
tational constant, and they should therefore be extremely small and
Section 5.8 Torsion 153
d / The University of Wash-
ington torsion pendulum used to
search for torsion. The light gray
wedges are Alnico, the darker
ones SmCo
5
. The arrows with
the lled heads represent the
directions of the electron spins,
with denser arrows indicating
higher polarization. The arrows
with the open heads show the
direction of the B eld. University
of Washington Eot-Wash group,
http://www.npl.washington.
edu/eotwash/publications/
pdf/lowfrontier2.pdf
hard to measure. String theory, for example, includes torsion, but
nobody has found a way to test string theory empirically because it
essentially makes predictions about phenomena at the Planck scale,
_
G/c
3
10
35
m, where both gravity and quantum mechanics
are strong eects.
There are, however, some high-precision experiments that have
a reasonable chance of detecting whether our universe has torsion.
Torsion violates the equivalence principle, and by the turn of the
century tests of the equivalence principle had reached a level of
precision sucient to rule out some models that include torsion.
Figure d shows a torsion pendulum used in an experiment by the
Eot-Wash group at the University of Washington.
8
If torsion exists,
then the intrinsic spin of an electron should have an energy ,
where is the spacelike part of the torsion vector. The torsion
could be generated by the earth, the sun, or some other object at a
greater distance. The interaction will modify the behavior of a
torsion pendulum if the spins of the electrons in the pendulum are
polarized nonrandomly, as in a magnetic material. The pendulum
will tend to precess around the axis dened by .
This type of experiment is extremely dicult, because the pen-
dulum tends to act as an ultra-sensitive magnetic compass, resulting
in a measurement of the ambient magnetic eld rather than the hy-
pothetical torsion eld . To eliminate this source of systematic
error, the UW group rst eliminated the ambient magnetic eld
as well as possible, using mu-metal shielding and Helmholtz coils.
They also constructed the pendulum out of a combination of two
magnetic materials, Alnico 5 and SmCo
5
, in such a way that the
magnetic dipole moment vanished, but the spin dipole moment did
not; Alnico 5s magnetic eld is due almost entirely to electron spin,
whereas the magnetic eld of SmCo
5
contains signicant contribu-
tions from orbital motion. The result was a nonmagnetic object
whose spins were polarized. After four years of data collection, they
found [[ 10
21
eV. Models that include torsion typically predict
such eects to be of the order of m
2
e
/m
P
10
17
eV, where m
e
is
the mass of the electron and m
P
=
_
c/G 10
19
GeV 20 g is
the Planck mass. A wide class of these models is therefore ruled out
by these experiments.
Since there appears to be no experimental evidence for the exis-
tence of gravitational torsion in our universe, we will assume from
now on that it vanishes identically. Einstein made the same as-
sumption when he originally created general relativity, although he
and Cartan later tinkered with non-torsion-free theories in a failed
attempt to unify gravity with electromagnetism. Some models that
include torsion remain viable. For example, it has been argued that
the torsion tensor should fall o quickly with distance from the
8
http://www.npl.washington.edu/eotwash/publications/pdf/lowfrontier2.pdf
154 Chapter 5 Curvature
source.
9
9
Carroll and Field, http://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/9403058
Section 5.8 Torsion 155
5.9 From metric to curvature
5.9.1 Finding given g
Weve already found the Christoel symbol in terms of the metric
in one dimension. Expressing it in tensor notation, we have
d
ba
=
1
2
g
cd
(
?
g
??
) ,
where inversion of the one-component matrix G has been replaced
by matrix inversion, and, more importantly, the question marks indi-
cate that there would be more than one way to place the subscripts
so that the result would be a grammatical tensor equation. The
most general form for the Christoel symbol would be
b
ac
=
1
2
g
db
(L
c
g
ab
+M
a
g
cb
+N
b
g
ca
) ,
where L, M, and N are constants. Consistency with the one-
dimensional expression requires L + M + N = 1, and vanishing
torsion gives L = M. The L and M terms have a dierent physical
signicance than the N term.
Suppose an observer uses coordinates such that all objects are
described as lengthening over time, and the change of scale accu-
mulated over one day is a factor of k > 1. This is described by the
derivative
t
g
xx
< 1, which aects the M term. Since the metric is
used to calculate squared distances, the g
xx
matrix element scales
down by 1/
k. To compensate for
t
v
x
< 0, so we need to add a
positive correction term, M > 0, to the covariant derivative. When
the same observer measures the rate of change of a vector v
t
with
respect to space, the rate of change comes out to be too small, be-
cause the variable she dierentiates with respect to is too big. This
requires N < 0, and the correction is of the same size as the M
correction, so [M[ = [N[. We nd L = M = N = 1.
Self-check: Does the above argument depend on the use of space
for one coordinate and time for the other?
The resulting general expression for the Christoel symbol in
terms of the metric is
c
ab
=
1
2
g
cd
(
a
g
bd
+
b
g
ad
d
g
ab
) .
One can readily go back and check that this gives
c
g
ab
= 0. In fact,
the calculation is a bit tedious. For that matter, tensor calculations
in general can be infamously time-consuming and error-prone. Any
reasonable person living in the 21st century will therefore resort to
a computer algebra system. The most widely used computer alge-
bra system is Mathematica, but its expensive and proprietary, and
it doesnt have extensive built-in facilities for handling tensors. It
156 Chapter 5 Curvature
turns out that there is quite a bit of free and open-source tensor soft-
ware, and it falls into two classes: coordinate-based and coordinate-
independent. The best open-source coordinate-independent facil-
ity available appears to be Cadabra, and in fact the verication of
c
g
ab
= 0 is the rst example given in the Leo Brewins handy guide
to applications of Cadabra to general relativity.
10
Self-check: In the case of 1 dimension, show that this reduces to
the earlier result of (1/2)dG/dX.
Since is not a tensor, it is not obvious that the covariant deriva-
tive, which is constructed from it, is a tensor. But if it isnt obvious,
neither is it surprising the goal of the above derivation was to get
results that would be coordinate-independent.
Christoffel symbols on the globe, quantitatively Example: 9
In example 8 on page 145, we inferred the following properties
for the Christoffel symbol
on a sphere of radius R:
is
independent of and R,
>
0 in the southern hemisphere.
The metric on a sphere is ds
2
= R
2
d
2
+ R
2
sin
2
d
2
. The only
nonvanishing term in the expression for
= 2R
2
sin cos . The result is
= r and
r
= 1/r (problem
1, page 162). Here we compute the geodesic that starts out tangent
to the unit circle at = 0.
1 import math
2
3 l = 0 # affine parameter lambda
4 dl = .001 # change in l with each iteration
5 l_max = 100.
6
7 # initial position:
10
http://arxiv.org/abs/0903.2085
Section 5.9 From metric to curvature 157
8 r=1
9 phi=0
10 # initial derivatives of coordinates w.r.t. lambda
11 vr = 0
12 vphi = 1
13
14 k = 0 # keep track of how often to print out updates
15 while l<l_max:
16 l = l+dl
17 # Christoffel symbols:
18 Grphiphi = -r
19 Gphirphi = 1/r
20 # second derivatives:
21 ar = -Grphiphi*vphi*vphi
22 aphi = -2.*Gphirphi*vr*vphi
23 # ... factor of 2 because G^a_{bc}=G^a_{cb} and b
24 # is not the same as c
25 # update velocity:
26 vr = vr + dl*ar
27 vphi = vphi + dl*aphi
28 # update position:
29 r = r + vr*dl
30 phi = phi + vphi*dl
31 if k%10000==0: # k is divisible by 10000
32 phi_deg = phi*180./math.pi
33 print "lambda=%6.2f r=%6.2f phi=%6.2f deg." % (l,r,phi_deg)
34 k = k+1
It is not necessary to worry about all the technical details of the
language (e.g., line 1, which makes available such conveniences as
math.pi for ). Comments are set o by pound signs. Lines 16-34
are indented because they are all to be executed repeatedly, until it
is no longer true that <
max
(line 15).
Self-check: By inspecting lines 18-22, nd the signs of r and
a
)A
c
= A
d
R
c
dab
A tedious calculation now gives R in terms of the s:
R
a
bcd
=
c
a
db
a
cb
+
a
ce
e
db
a
de
e
cb
This is given as another example later in Brewins manual for apply-
ing Cadabra to general relativity.
11
(Brewin writes the upper index
in the second slot of R.)
5.9.4 Some general ideas about gauge
Lets step back now for a moment and try to gain some physi-
cal insight by looking at the features that the electromagnetic and
relativistic gauge transformations have in common. We have the
following analogies:
11
http://arxiv.org/abs/0903.2085
Section 5.9 From metric to curvature 159
a / The Aharonov-Bohm ef-
fect. An electron enters a beam
splitter at P, and is sent out in
two different directions. The two
parts of the wave are reected so
that they reunite at Q. The arrows
represent the vector potential A.
The observable magnetic eld
B is zero everywhere outside
the solenoid, and yet the inter-
ference observed at Q depends
on whether the eld is turned
on. See page 114 for further
discussion of the A and B elds
of a solenoid.
electromagnetism dierential
geometry
global symmetry A constant phase
shift has no ob-
servable eects.
Adding a con-
stant onto a
coordinate has no
observable eects.
local symmetry A phase shift
that varies from
point to point has
no observable ef-
fects.
An arbitrary co-
ordinate transfor-
mation has no ob-
servable eects.
The gauge is de-
scribed by . . . g
. . . and dierentia-
tion of this gives the
gauge eld. . . A
b
c
ab
A second dieren-
tiation gives the
directly observable
eld(s) . . .
E and B R
c
dab
The interesting thing here is that the directly observable elds
do not carry all of the necessary information, but the gauge elds are
not directly observable. In electromagnetism, we can see this from
the Aharonov-Bohm eect, shown in gure a.
12
The solenoid has
B = 0 externally, and the electron beams only ever move through
the external region, so they never experience any magnetic eld. Ex-
periments show, however, that turning the solenoid on and o does
change the interference between the two beams. This is because the
vector potential does not vanish outside the solenoid, and as weve
seen on page 114, the phase of the beams varies according to the
path integral of the A
b
. We are therefore left with an uncomfort-
able, but unavoidable, situation. The concept of a eld is supposed
to eliminate the need for instantaneous action at a distance, which
is forbidden by relativity; that is, (1) we want our elds to have only
local eects. On the other hand, (2) we would like our elds to be
directly observable quantities. We cannot have both 1 and 2. The
gauge eld satises 1 but not 2, and the electromagnetic elds give
2 but not 1.
12
We describe the eect here in terms of an idealized, impractical experiment.
For the actual empirical status of the Aharonov-Bohm eect, see Batelaan and
Tonomura, Physics Today 62 (2009) 38.
160 Chapter 5 Curvature
b / The cone has zero intrin-
sic curvature everywhere except
at its tip. An observer who never
visits the tip can nevertheless
detect its existence, because
parallel transport around a path
that encloses the tip causes a
vector to change its direction.
Figure b shows an analog of the Aharonov-Bohm experiment in
dierential geometry. Everywhere but at the tip, the cone has zero
curvature, as we can see by cutting it and laying it out at. But even
an observer who never visits the tightly curved region at the tip can
detect its existence, because parallel-transporting a vector around
a closed loop can change the vectors direction, provided that the
loop surrounds the tip.
In the electromagnetic example, integrating A around a closed
loop reveals, via Stokes theorem, the existence of a magnetic ux
through the loop, even though the magnetic eld is zero at every
location where A has to be sampled. In the relativistic example,
integrating around a closed loop shows that there is curvature
inside the loop, even though the curvature is zero at all the places
where has to be sampled.
The fact that is a gauge eld, and therefore not locally ob-
servable, is simply a fancy way of expressing the ideas introduced
on pp. 144 and 146, that due to the equivalence principle, the gravi-
tational eld in general relativity is not locally observable. This non-
observability is local because the equivalence principle is a statement
about local Lorentz frames. The example in gure b is non-local.
Geodetic effect and structure of the source Example: 10
In section 5.5.1 on page 139, we estimated the geodetic effect
on Gravity Probe B and found a result that was only off by a factor
of 3. The mathematically pure form of the 3 suggests that the
geodetic effect is insensitive to the distribution of mass inside the
earth. Why should this be so?
The change in a vector upon parallel transporting it around a
closed loop can be expressed in terms of either (1) the area inte-
gral of the curvature within the loop or (2) the line integral of the
Christoffel symbol (essentially the gravitational eld) on the loop
itself. Although I expressed the estimate as 1, it would have been
equally valid to use 2. By Newtons shell theorem, the gravita-
tional eld is not sensitive to anything about its mass distribution
other than its near spherical symmetry. The earth spins, and this
does affect the stress-energy tensor, but since the velocity with
which it spins is everywhere much smaller than c, the resulting
effect, called frame-dragging, is much smaller.
Section 5.9 From metric to curvature 161
Problems
1 Show, as claimed on page 157, that for polar coordinates in
a Euclidean plane,
r
= r and
r
= 1/r.
2 Partial derivatives commute with partial derivatives. Co-
variant derivatives dont commute with covariant derivatives. Do
covariant derivatives commute with partial derivatives?
3 Show that if the dierential equation for geodesics on page
146 is satised for one ane parameter , then it is also satised for
any other ane parameter
t
= (1 +ax
)
2
g
x
= 1 .
Since this metric was derived by a change of coordinates from a at-
space metric, and the Ricci curvature is an intrinsic property, we
165
a / A spaceship (curved world-
line) moves with an acceleration
perceived as constant by its
passengers. The photon (straight
world-line) come closer and
closer to the ship, but will never
quite catch up.
expect that this one also has zero Ricci curvature. This is straight-
forward to verify. The nonvanishing Christoel symbols are
t
=
a
1 +ax
and
x
t
= a(1 +ax
) .
The only elements of the Riemann tensor that look like they might
be nonzero are R
t
and R
x
, x
vanishes at x
= 1/a. An observer
aboard the ship reasons as follows. If I start out with a head-start
of 1/a relative to some event, then the timelike part of the metric at
that event vanishes. If the event marks the emission of a material
particle, then there is no possible way for that particles world-line
to have ds
2
> 0. If I were to detect a particle emitted at that event,
it would violate the laws of physics, since material particles must
have ds
2
> 0, so I conclude that I will never observe such a particle.
Since all of this applies to any material particle, regardless of its
mass m, it must also apply in the limit m 0, i.e., to photons and
other massless particles. Therefore I can never receive a particle
emitted from this event, and in fact it appears that there is no way
for that event, or any other event behind the event horizon, to have
any eect on me. In my frame of reference, it appears that light
cones near the horizon are tipped over so far that their future light-
cones lie entirely in the direction away from me.
Weve already seen in example 10 on page 50 that a naive New-
tonian argument suggests the existence of black holes; if a body is
166 Chapter 6 Vacuum Solutions
suciently compact, light cannot escape from it. In a relativistic
treatment, this should be described as an event horizon.
6.1.2 Information paradox
The existence of event horizons in general relativity has deep
implications, and in particular it helps to explain why it is so di-
cult to reconcile general relativity with quantum mechanics, despite
nearly a century of valiant attempts. Quantum mechanics has a
property called unitarity. Mathematically, this says that of the state
of a quantum mechanical system is given, at a certain time, in the
form of a vector, then its state at some point in the future can be
predicted by applying a unitary matrix to that vector. A unitary
matrix is the generalization to complex numbers of the ordinary
concept of an orthogonal matrix, and essentially it just represents a
change of basis, in which the basis vectors have unit length and are
perpendicular to one another.
To see what this means physically, consider the following nonex-
amples. The matrix
_
1 0
0 0
_
is not unitary, because its rows and columns are not orthogonal vec-
tors with unit lengths. If this matrix represented the time-evolution
of a quantum mechanical system, then its meaning would be that
any particle in state number 1 would be left alone, but any particle
in state 2 would disappear. Any information carried by particles in
state 2 is lost forever and can never be retrieved. This also violates
the time-reversal symmetry of quantum mechanics.
Another nonunitary matrix is:
_
1 0
0
2
_
Here, any particle in state 2 is increased in amplitude by a factor of
=
_
(1 +ax
)
2
. Say the pair is created
right near the horizon, at x
= at
r
=
1
r
r
=
1
r
= r
= r sin
2
= sin cos
= cot
Self-check: If wed been using the ( + ++) metric instead of
(+), what would have been the eect on the Christoel sym-
bols? What if wed expressed the metric in dierent units, rescaling
all the coordinates by a factor k?
170 Chapter 6 Vacuum Solutions
Use of ctensor
In fact, when I calculated the Christoel symbols above by hand,
I got one of them wrong, and missed calculating one other because I
thought it was zero. I only found my mistake by comparing against
a result in a textbook. The computation of the Riemann tensor is
an even bigger mess. Its clearly a good idea to resort to a com-
puter algebra system here. Cadabra, which was discussed earlier, is
specically designed for coordinate-independent calculations, so it
wont help us here. A good free and open-source choice is ctensor,
which is one of the standard packages distributed along with the
computer algebra system Maxima, introduced on page 61.
The following Maxima program calculates the Christoel sym-
bols found in section 6.2.1.
1 load(ctensor);
2 ct_coords:[t,r,theta,phi];
3 lg:matrix([1,0,0,0],
4 [0,-1,0,0],
5 [0,0,-r^2,0],
6 [0,0,0,-r^2*sin(theta)^2]);
7 cmetric();
8 christof(mcs);
Line 1 loads the ctensor package. Line 2 sets up the names of the
coordinates. Line 3 denes the g
ab
, with lg meaning the version of
g with lower indices. Line 7 tells Maxima to do some setup work
with g
ab
, including the calculation of the inverse matrix g
ab
, which
is stored in ug. Line 8 says to calculate the Christoel symbols.
The notation mcs refers to the tensor
a
bc
with the indices swapped
around a little compared to the convention
a
bc
followed in this
book. On a Linux system, we put the program in a le flat.mac
and run it using the command maxima -b flat.mac. The relevant
part of the output is:
1 1
2 (%t6) mcs = -
3 2, 3, 3 r
4
5 1
6 (%t7) mcs = -
7 2, 4, 4 r
8
9 (%t8) mcs = - r
10 3, 3, 2
11
12 cos(theta)
13 (%t9) mcs = ----------
Section 6.2 The Schwarzschild metric 171
14 3, 4, 4 sin(theta)
15
16 2
17 (%t10) mcs = - r sin (theta)
18 4, 4, 2
19
20 (%t11) mcs = - cos(theta) sin(theta)
21 4, 4, 3
Adding the command ricci(true); at the end of the program re-
sults in the output THIS SPACETIME IS EMPTY AND/OR FLAT, which
saves us hours of tedious computation. The tensor ric (which here
happens to be zero) is computed, and all its nonzero elements are
printed out. There is a similar command riemann(true); to com-
pute the Riemann rensor riem. This is stored so that riem[i,j,k,l]
is what we would call R
l
ikj
. Note that l is moved to the end, and j
and k are also swapped.
6.2.2 Geometrized units
If the mass creating the gravitational eld isnt zero, then we
need to decide what units to measure it in. It has already proved
very convenient to adopt units with c = 1, and we will now also set
the gravitational constant G = 1. Previously, with only c set to 1,
the units of time and length were the same, [T] = [L], and so were
the units of mass and energy, [M] = [E]. With G = 1, all of these
become the same units, [T] = [L] = [M] = [E].
Self-check: Verify this statement by combining Newtons law of
gravity with Newtons second law of motion.
The resulting system is referred to as geometrized, because units
like mass that had formerly belonged to the province of mechanics
are now measured using the same units we would use to do geometry.
6.2.3 A large-r limit
Now lets think about how to tackle the real problem of nding
the non-at metric. Although general relativity lets us pick any co-
ordinates we like, the spherical symmetry of the problem suggests
using coordinates that exploit that symmetry. The at-space coor-
dinates and can stil be dened in the same way, and they have
the same interpretation. For example, if we drop a test particle
toward the mass from some point in space, its world-line will have
constant and . The r coordinate is a little dierent. In curved
spacetime, the circumference of a circle is not equal to 2 times the
distance from the center to the circle; in fact, the discrepancy be-
tween these two is essentially the denition of the Ricci curvature.
This gives us a choice of two logical ways to dene r. Well de-
ne it as the circumference divided by 2, which has the advantage
172 Chapter 6 Vacuum Solutions
that the last two terms of the metric are the same as in at space:
r
2
d
2
r
2
sin
2
d
2
. Since were looking for static solutions, none
of the elements of the metric can depend on t. Also, the solution
is going to be symmetric under t t, , and , so
we cant have any o-diagonal elements. The result is that we have
narrowed the metric down to something of the form
ds
2
= h(r)dt
2
k(r)dr
2
r
2
d
2
r
2
sin
2
d
2
,
where both h and k approach 1 for r , where spacetime is at.
For guidance in how to construct h and k, lets consider the
acceleration of a test particle at r m, which we know to be
m/r
2
, since nonrelativistic physics applies there. We have
t
v
r
=
t
v
r
+
r
tc
v
c
.
An observer free-falling along with the particle observes its acceler-
ation to be zero, and a tensor that is zero in one coordinate system
is zero in all others. Since the covariant derivative is a tensor, we
conclude that
t
v
r
= 0 in all coordinate systems, including the
(t, r, . . .) system were using. If the particle is released from rest,
then initially its velocity four-vector is (1, 0, 0, 0), so we nd that its
acceleration in (t, r) coordinates is
r
tt
=
1
2
g
rr
r
g
tt
=
1
2
h
/k.
Setting this equal to m/r
2
, we nd h
/k = 2m/r
2
for r m.
Since k 1 for large r, we have
h
2m
r
2
for r m .
The interpretation of this calculation is as follows. We assert the
equivalence principle, by which the acceleration of a free-falling par-
ticle can be said to be zero. After some calculations, we nd that
the rate at which time ows (encoded in h) is not constant. It is
dierent for observers at dierent heights in a gravitational poten-
tial well. But this is something we had already deduced, without
the tensor gymnastics, in example 4 on page 106.
Integrating, we nd that for large r, h = 1 2m/r.
6.2.4 The complete solution
A series solution
Weve learned some interesting things, but we still have an ex-
tremely nasty nonlinear dierential equation to solve. One way to
attack a dierential equation, when you have no idea how to pro-
ceed, is to try a series solution. We have a small parameter m/r to
expand around, so lets try to write h and k as series of the form
h =
n=0
a
k
_
m
r
_
n
k =
n=0
b
k
_
m
r
_
n
Section 6.2 The Schwarzschild metric 173
We already know a
0
, a
1
, and b
0
. Lets try to nd b
1
. In the
following Maxima code I omit the factor of m in h
1
for convenience.
In other words, were looking for the solution for m = 1.
1 load(ctensor);
2 ct_coords:[t,r,theta,phi];
3 lg:matrix([(1-2/r),0,0,0],
4 [0,-(1+b1/r),0,0],
5 [0,0,-r^2,0],
6 [0,0,0,-r^2*sin(theta)^2]);
7 cmetric();
8 ricci(true);
I wont reproduce the entire output of the Ricci tensor, which
is voluminous. We want all four of its nonvanishing components to
vanish as quickly as possible for large values of r, so I decided to
ddle with R
t
t, which looked as simple as any of them. It appears
to vary as r
4
for large r, so lets evaluate lim
r
_
r
4
R
tt
_
:
9 limit(r^4*ric[1,1],r,inf);
The result is (b
1
2)/2, so lets set b
1
= 2. The approximate solution
weve found so far (reinserting the ms),
ds
2
_
1
2m
r
_
dt
2
_
1 +
2m
r
_
dr
2
r
2
d
2
r
2
sin
2
d
2
,
was rst derived by Einstein in 1915, and he used it to solve the
problem of the non-Keplerian relativistic correction to the orbit of
Mercury, which was one of the rst empirical tests of general rela-
tivity.
Continuing in this fashion, the results are as follows:
a
0
= 1 b
0
= 1
a
1
= 2 b
1
= 2
a
2
= 0 b
2
= 4
a
3
= 0 b
2
= 8
The closed-form solution
The solution is unexpectedly simple, and can be put into closed
form. The approximate result we found for h was in fact exact.
For k we have a geometric series 1/(1 2/r), and when we reinsert
the factor of m in the only way that makes the units work, we get
1/(1 2m/r). The result for the metric is
ds
2
=
_
1
2m
r
_
dt
2
_
1
1 2m/r
_
dr
2
r
2
d
2
r
2
sin
2
d
2
.
A quick calculation in Maxima demonstrates that this is an exact
solution for all r, i.e., the Ricci tensor vanishes everywhere, even at
r < 2m, which is outside the radius of convergence of the geometric
series.
174 Chapter 6 Vacuum Solutions
6.2.5 Geodetic effect
As promised in section 5.5.1, we now calculate the geodetic eect
on Gravity Probe B, including all the niggling factors of 3 and . To
make the physics clear, we approach the actual calculation through
a series of warmups.
Flat space
As a rst warmup, consider two spatial dimensions, represented
by Euclidean polar coordinates (r, ). Parallel-transport of a gyro-
scopes angular momentum around a circle of constant r gives
= 0
L
r
= 0 .
Computing the covariant derivatives, and we have
0 =
r
L
r
0 =
L
r
+
r
.
The Christoel symbols are
r
= 1/r and
r
= r. This is
all made to look needlessly complicated because L
and L
r
are ex-
pressed in dierent units. Essentially the vector is staying the same,
but were expressing it in terms of basis vectors in the r and di-
rections that are rotating. To see this more transparently, let r = 1,
and write P for L
and Q for L
r
, so that
P
= Q
Q
= P ,
which have solutions such as P = sin , Q = cos . For each orbit
(2 change in ), the basis vectors rotate by 2, so the angular
momentum vector once again has the same components. In other
words, it hasnt really changed at all.
Spatial curvature only
The at-space calculation above diers in two ways from the
actual result for an orbiting gyroscope: (1) it uses a at spatial
geometry, and (2) it is purely spatial. The purely spatial nature of
the calculation is manifested in the fact that there is nothing in the
result relating to how quickly weve moved the vector around the
circle. We know that if we whip a gyroscope around in a circle on
the end of a rope, there will be a Thomas precession (section 2.5.4),
which depends on the speed.
As our next warmup, lets curve the spatial geometry, but con-
tinue to omit the time dimension. Using the Schwarzschild metric,
we replace the at-space Christoel symbol
r
= r with r+2m.
The dierential equations for the components of the L vector, again
Section 6.2 The Schwarzschild metric 175
evaluated at r = 1 for convenience, are now
P
= Q
Q
= (1 )P ,
where = 2m. The solutions rotate with frequency
=
1 .
The result is that when the basis vectors rotate by 2, the compo-
nents no longer return to their original values; they lag by a factor
of
, L
r
, L
t
). The physical interpretation of the L
t
com-
ponent is obscure at this point; well return to this question later.
Writing down the total derivatives of the three components, and
notating dt/d as
1
, we have
dL
d
=
+
1
t
L
dL
r
d
=
L
r
+
1
t
L
r
dL
t
d
=
L
t
+
1
t
L
t
Setting the covariant derivatives equal to zero gives
0 =
r
L
r
0 =
L
r
+
r
0 =
t
L
r
+
r
tt
L
t
0 =
t
L
t
+
t
tr
L
r
.
176 Chapter 6 Vacuum Solutions
Self-check: There are not just four but six covariant derivatives
that could in principle have occurred, and in these six covariant
derivatives we could have had a total of 18 Christoel symbols. Of
these 18, only four are nonvanishing. Explain based on symmetry
arguments why the following Christoel symbols must vanish:
t
,
t
tt
.
Putting all this together in matrix form, we have L
= ML,
where
M =
_
_
0 1 0
1 0 (1 )/2
0 /2(1 ) 0
_
_
.
The solutions of this dierential equation oscillate like e
it
, where
i is an eigenvalue of the matrix.
Self-check: The frequency in the purely spatial calculation was
found by inspection. Verify the result by applying the eigenvalue
technique to the relevant 2 2 submatrix.
To lowest order, we can use the Newtonian relation
2
r = Gm/r
and neglect terms of order
2
, so that the two new o-diagonal ma-
trix elements are both approximated as
_
/2. The three resulting
eigenfrequencies are zero and = [1 (3/2)m/r].
The presence of the mysterious zero-frequency solution can now
be understood by recalling the earlier mystery of the physical inter-
pretation of the angular momentums L
t
component. Our results
come from calculating parallel transport, and parallel transport is
a purely geometric process, so it gives the same result regardless
of the physical nature of the four-vector. Suppose that we had
instead chosen the velocity four-vector as our guinea pig. The def-
inition of a geodesic is that it parallel-transports its own tangent
vector, so the velocity vector has to stay constant. If we inspect
the eigenvector corresponding to the zero-frequency eigenfrequency,
we nd a timelike vector that is parallel to the velocity four-vector.
In our 2+1-dimensional space, the other two eigenvectors, which
are spacelike, span the subspace of spacelike vectors, which are the
ones that can physically be realized as the angular momentum of
a gyroscope. These two eigenvectors, which vary as e
i
, can be
superposed to make real-valued spacelike solutions that match the
initial conditions, and these lag the rotation of the basis vectors
by = (3/2)mr. This is greater than the purely spatial result
by a factor of 3/2. The resulting precession angle, over n orbits of
Gravity Probe B, is 3nGm/c
2
r = 3 10
5
radians, in excellent
agreement with experiment.
One will see apparently contradictory statements in the litera-
ture about whether Thomas precession occurs for a satellite: The
Thomas precession comes into play for a gyroscope on the surface
of the Earth . . . , but not for a gyroscope in a freely moving satel-
Section 6.2 The Schwarzschild metric 177
lite.
3
But: The total eect, geometrical and Thomas, gives the
well-known Fokker-de Sitter precession of 3m/r, in the same sense
as the orbit.
4
The second statement arises from subtracting the
purely spatial result from the 2+1-dimensional result, and noting
that the absolute value of this dierence is the same as the Thomas
precession that would have been obtained if the gyroscope had been
whirled at the end of a rope. In my opinion this is an unnatural
way of looking at the physics, for two reasons. (1) The signs dont
match, so one is forced to say that the Thomas precession has a dif-
ferent sign depending on whether the rotation is the result of grav-
itational or nongravitational forces. (2) Referring to observation, it
is clearly articial to treat the spatial curvature and Thomas eects
separately, since neither one can be disentangled from the other by
varying the quantities n, m, and r.
6.2.6 Orbits
The main event of Newtons Principia Mathematica is his proof
of Keplers laws. Similarly, Einsteins rst important application in
general relativity, which he began before he even had the exact form
of the Schwarzschild metric in hand, was to nd the non-Newtonian
behavior of the planet Mercury. The planets deviate from Keplerian
behavior for a variety of Newtonian reasons, and in particular there
is a long list of reasons why the major axis of a planets elliptical
orbit is expected to gradually rotate. When all of these were taken
into account, however, there was a remaining discrepancy of about
40 seconds of arc per century, or 6.6 10
7
radians per orbit. The
direction of the eect was in the forward direction, in the sense
that if we view Mercurys orbit from above the ecliptic, so that it
orbits in the counterclockwise direction, then the gradual rotation
of the major axis is also counterclockwise. In other words, Mercury
spends more time near perihelion than it should classically. During
this time, it sweeps out a greater angle than classically expected,
so that when it ies back out and away from the sun, its orbit has
rotated counterclockwise.
We can easily understand why there should be such an eect
according to general relativity, by passing to the limit in which the
relativistic eect is very large. Consider the orbits of material ob-
jects in the vicinity of a black hole. An object that passes through
the event horizon spends innite time at its perihelion and never
emerges again. Applying this reasoning to the case of Mercurys
orbit, we nd that an eect in the observed direction is expected.
Based on the examples in section 5.5, we also expect that the
eect will be of order m/r, where m is the mass of the sun and r
is the radius of Mercurys orbit. This works out to be 2.5 10
8
,
which is smaller than the observed precession by a factor of about
3
Misner, Thorne, and Wheeler, Gravitation, p. 1118
4
Rindler, Essential Relativity, 1969, p. 141
178 Chapter 6 Vacuum Solutions
b / Proof that if the metrics
components are independent of
t , the geodesic of a test particle
conserves p
t
.
26.
Conserved quantities
If Einstein had had a computer on his desk, he probably would
simply have integrated the motion numerically using the geodesic
equation. But it is possible to simplify the problem enough to at-
tack it with pencil and paper, if we can nd the relevant conserved
quantities of the motion. Classically, these are energy and angular
momentum.
Consider a rock falling directly toward the sun. The Schwarzschild
metric is of the special form
ds
2
= h(r)dt
2
k(r)dr
2
. . . .
The rocks trajectory is a geodesic, so it extremizes the proper time
s between any two events xed in spacetime, just as a piece of string
stretched across a curved surface extremizes its length. Let the rock
pass through distance r
1
in coordinate time t
1
, and then through r
2
in t
2
. (These should really be notated as r
1
, . . . or dr
1
, . . . , but we
avoid the s or ds for convenience.) Approximating the geodesic
using two line segments, the proper time is
s = s
1
+s
2
=
_
h
1
t
2
1
k
1
r
2
1
+
_
h
2
t
2
2
k
2
r
2
2
=
_
h
1
t
2
1
k
1
r
2
1
+
_
h
2
(T t
1
)
2
k
2
r
2
2
,
where T = t
1
+ t
2
is xed. If this is to be extremized with respect
to t
1
, then ds/dt
1
= 0, which leads to
0 =
h
1
t
1
s
1
h
2
t
2
s
2
,
which means that
h
dt
ds
= g
tt
dx
t
ds
=
dx
t
ds
is a constant of the motion. Except for an irrelevant factor of m,
this is the same as p
t
, the timelike component of the covariant mo-
mentum vector. Weve already seen that in special relativity, the
timelike component of the momentum four-vector is interpreted as
the mass-energy E, and the quantity p
t
has a similar interpretation
here. Note that no special assumption was made about the form of
the functions h and k. In addition, it turns out that the assumption
of purely radial motion was unnecessary. All that really mattered
was that h and k were independent of t. Therefore we will have
a similar conserved quantity p
.
In particular, the Schwarzschild metrics components are indepen-
dent of as well as t, so we have a second conserved quantity p
,
which is interpreted as angular momentum.
Section 6.2 The Schwarzschild metric 179
Writing these two quantities out explicitly in terms of the con-
travariant coordinates, in the case of the Schwarzschild spacetime,
we have
E =
_
1
2m
r
_
dt
ds
and
L = r
2
d
ds
for the conserved energy per unit mass and angular momentum per
unit mass. In interpreting the energy E, it is important to under-
stand that in the general-relativistic context, there is no useful way
of separating the rest mass, kinetic energy, and potential energy into
separate terms; E includes all of these, and turns out to be less than
the rest mass (i.e., less than 1) for a planet orbiting the sun.
Perihelion advance
For convenience, let the mass of the orbiting rock be 1, while m
stands for the mass of the gravitating body.
The unit mass of the rock is a third conserved quantity, and
since the magnitude of the momentum vector equals the square of
the mass, we have for an orbit in the plane = /2,
1 = g
tt
p
2
t
g
rr
p
2
r
g
p
2
= g
tt
p
2
t
g
rr
(p
r
)
2
g
p
2
=
1
1 2m/r
E
2
1
1 2m/r
_
dr
ds
_
2
1
r
2
L
2
.
Rearranging terms and writing r for dr/ds, this becomes
r
2
= E
2
(1 2m/r)(1 +L
2
/r
2
)
or
r
2
= E
2
U
2
where
U
2
= (1 2m/r)(1 +L
2
/r
2
) .
There is a varied and strange family of orbits in the Schwarzschild
eld, including bizarre knife-edge trajectories that take several nearly
circular turns before suddenly ying o. We turn our attention in-
stead to the case of an orbit such as Mercurys which is nearly
classical and nearly circular.
180 Chapter 6 Vacuum Solutions
Classically, a circular orbit has radius r = L
2
/m and period
T = 2L
3
/m
2
.
Relativistically, a circular orbit occurs when there is only one
turning point at which r = 0. This requires that E
2
equal the
minimum value of U
2
, which occurs at
r =
L
2
2m
_
1 +
_
1 12m
2
/L
2
_
L
2
m
(1 ) ,
where = 3(m/L)
2
. A planet in a nearly circular orbit oscillates
between perihelion and aphelion with a period that depends on the
curvature of U
2
at its minimum. We have
k =
d
2
(U
2
)
dr
2
=
d
2
dr
2
_
1
2m
r
+
L
2
r
2
2mL
2
r
3
_
=
4m
r
3
+
6L
2
r
4
24mL
2
r
5
= 2L
6
m
4
(1 + 2)
The period of the oscillations is
s
osc
= 2
_
2/k
= 2L
3
m
2
(1 ) .
The period of the azimuthal motion is
s
az
= 2r
2
/L
= 2L
3
m
2
(1 2) .
The periods are slightly mismatched because of the relativistic cor-
rection terms. The period of the radial oscillations is longer, so
that, as expected, the perihelion shift is in the forward direction.
The mismatch is s, and because of it each orbit rotates the ma-
jor axis by an angle 2 = 6(m/L)
2
= 6m/r. Plugging in the
data for Mercury, we obtain 5.8 10
7
radians per orbit, which
agrees with the observed value to within about 10%. Eliminating
some of the approximations weve made brings the results in agree-
ment to within the experimental error bars, and Einstein recalled
that when the calculation came out right, for a few days, I was
beside myself with joyous excitement.
Further attempts were made to improve on the precision of this
historically crucial test of general relativity. Radar now gives the
most precise orbital data for Mercury. At the level of about one part
per thousand, however, an eect creeps in due to the oblateness of
the sun, which is dicult to measure precisely.
Section 6.2 The Schwarzschild metric 181
In 1974, astronomers J.H. Taylor and R.A. Hulse of Princeton,
working at the Arecibo radio telescope, discovered a binary star
system whose members are both neutron stars. The detection of
the system was made possible because one of the neutron stars is
a pulsar: a neutron star that emits a strong radio pulse in the
direction of the earth once per rotational period. The orbit is highly
elliptical, and the minimum separation between the two stars is very
small, about the same as the radius of our sun. Both because the
r is small and because the period is short (about 8 hours), the rate
of perihelion advance per unit time is very large, about 4.2 degrees
per year. The system has been compared in great detail with the
predictions of general relativity,
5
giving extremely good agreement,
and as a result astronomers have been condent enough to reason in
the opposite direction and infer properties of the system, such as its
total mass, from the general-relativistic analysis. The systems orbit
is decaying due to the radiation of energy in the form of gravitational
waves, which are predicted to exist by relativity.
6.2.7 Deection of light
As discussed on page 140, one of the rst tests of general rel-
ativity was Eddingtons measurement of the deection of rays of
light by the suns gravitational eld. The deection measured by
Eddington was 1.6 seconds of arc. For a light ray that grazes the
suns surface, the only physically relevant parameters are the suns
mass m and radius r. Since the deection is unitless, it can only
depend on m/r, the unitless ratio of the suns mass to its radius.
Expressed in SI units, this is Gm/c
2
r, which comes out to be about
10
6
. Roughly speaking, then, we expect the order of magnitude of
the eect to be about this big, and indeed 10
6
radians comes out
to be in the same ball-park as a second of arc. We get a similar
estimate in Newtonian physics by treating a photon as a (massive)
particle moving at speed c.
It is possible to calculate a precise value for the deection us-
ing methods very much like those used to determine the perihelion
advance in section 6.2.6. However, some of the details would have
to be changed. For example, it is no longer possible to parametrize
the trajectory using the proper time s, since a light ray has ds = 0;
we must use an ane parameter. Let us instead use this an an
example of the numerical technique for solving the geodesic equa-
tion, rst demonstrated in section 5.9.2 on page 157. Modifying our
earlier program, we have the following:
1 import math
2
3 # constants, in SI units:
4 G = 6.67e-11 # gravitational constant
5
http://arxiv.org/abs/astro-ph/0407149
182 Chapter 6 Vacuum Solutions
5 c = 3.00e8 # speed of light
6 m_kg = 1.99e30 # mass of sun
7 r_m = 6.96e8 # radius of sun
8
9 # From now on, all calculations are in units of the
10 # radius of the sun.
11
12 # mass of sun, in units of the radius of the sun:
13 m_sun = (G/c**2)*(m_kg/r_m)
14 m = 1000.*m_sun
15 print "m/r=",m
16
17 # Start at point of closest approach.
18 # initial position:
19 t=0
20 r=1 # closest approach, grazing the suns surface
21 phi=-math.pi/2
22 # initial derivatives of coordinates w.r.t. lambda
23 vr = 0
24 vt = 1
25 vphi = math.sqrt((1.-2.*m/r)/r**2)*vt # gives ds=0, lightlike
26
27 l = 0 # affine parameter lambda
28 l_max = 20000.
29 epsilon = 1e-6 # controls how fast lambda varies
30 while l<l_max:
31 dl = epsilon*(1.+r**2) # giant steps when farther out
32 l = l+dl
33 # Christoffel symbols:
34 Gttr = m/(r**2-2*m*r)
35 Grtt = m/r**2-2*m**2/r**3
36 Grrr = -m/(r**2-2*m*r)
37 Grphiphi = -r+2*m
38 Gphirphi = 1/r
39 # second derivatives:
40 # The factors of 2 are because we have, e.g., G^a_{bc}=G^a_{cb}
41 at = -2.*Gttr*vt*vr
42 ar = -(Grtt*vt*vt + Grrr*vr*vr + Grphiphi*vphi*vphi)
43 aphi = -2.*Gphirphi*vr*vphi
44 # update velocity:
45 vt = vt + dl*at
46 vr = vr + dl*ar
47 vphi = vphi + dl*aphi
48 # update position:
49 r = r + vr*dl
50 t = t + vt*dl
51 phi = phi + vphi*dl
52
Section 6.2 The Schwarzschild metric 183
53 # Direction of propagation, approximated in asymptotically flat coords.
54 # First, differentiate (x,y)=(r cos phi,r sin phi) to get vx and vy:
55 vx = vr*math.cos(phi)-r*math.sin(phi)*vphi
56 vy = vr*math.sin(phi)+r*math.cos(phi)*vphi
57 prop = math.atan2(vy,vx) # inverse tan of vy/vx, in the proper quadrant
58 prop_sec = prop*180.*3600/math.pi
59 print "final direction of propagation = %6.2f arc-seconds" % prop_sec
At line 14, we take the mass to be 1000 times greater than the
mass of the sun. This helps to make the deection easier to calcu-
late accurately without running into problems with rounding errors.
Lines 17-25 set up the initial conditions to be at the point of closest
approach, as the photon is grazing the sun. This is easier to set
up than initial conditions in which the photon approaches from far
away. Because of this, the deection angle calculated by the pro-
gram is cut in half. Combining the factors of 1000 and one half, the
nal result from the program is to be interpreted as 500 times the
actual deection angle.
The result is that the deection angle is predicted to be 870
seconds of arc. As a check, we can run the program again with
m = 0; the result is a deection of 8 seconds, which is a measure
of the accumulated error due to rounding and the nite increment
used for .
Dividing by 500, we nd that the predicted deection angle is
1.74 seconds, which, expressed in radians, is exactly 4Gm/c
2
r. The
unitless factor of 4 is in fact the correct result in the case of small
deections, i.e., for m/r 1.
Although the numerical technique has the disadvantage that it
doesnt let us directly prove a nice formula, it has some advantages
as well. For one thing, we can use it to investigate cases for which
the approximation m/r 1 fails. For m/r = 0.3, the numerical
techique gives a deection of 222 degrees, whereas the weak-eld
approximation 4Gm/c
2
r gives only 69 degrees. What is happening
here is that were getting closer and closer to the event horizon of a
black hole. Black holes are the topic of section 6.3, but it should be
intuitively reasonable that something wildly nonlinear has to happen
as we get close to the point where the light wouldnt even be able
to escape.
The precision of Eddingtons original test was only about 30%,
and has never been improved on signicantly with visible-light as-
tronomy. A better technique is radio astronomy, which allows mea-
surements to be carried out without waiting for an eclipse. One
merely has to wait for the sun to pass in front of a strong, compact
radio source such as a quasar. These techniques have now veried
the deection of light predicted by general relativity to a relative
184 Chapter 6 Vacuum Solutions
precision of about 10
5
.
6
6.3 Black holes
6.3.1 Singularities
A provocative feature of the Schwarzschild metric is that it has
elements that blow up at r = 0 and at r = 2m. If this is a description
of the sun, for example, then these singularities are of no physical
signicance, since we only solved the Einstein eld equation for the
vacuum region outside the sun, whereas r = 2m would lie about 3
km from the suns center. Furthermore, it is possible that one or
both of these singularities is nothing more than a spot where our
coordinate system misbehaves. This would be known as a coordinate
singularity. For example, the metric of ordinary polar coordinates
in a Euclidean plane has g
as r 0.
One way to test whether a singularity is a coordinate singularity
is to calculate a scalar measure of curvature, whose value is inde-
pendent of the coordinate system. We can take the trace of the
Ricci tensor, R
a
a
, but since the Ricci tensor is zero, its not sur-
prising that that is zero. A dierent scalar we can construct is the
product R
abcd
R
abcd
of the Riemann tensor with itself. The Maxima
command lriemann(true) displays the nonvanishing components
of R
abcd
. The component that misbehaves the most severely at
r = 0 is R
trrt
= 2m/r
3
. Because of this, R
abcd
R
abcd
blows up like
r
6
as r 0. This shows that the singularity at r = 0 is a real,
physical singularity.
The singularity at r = 2m, on the other hand, turns out to
be only a coordinate singularity. To prove this, we have to use
some technique other than constructing scalar measures of curva-
ture. Even if every such scalar we construct is nite at r = 2m, that
doesnt prove that every such scalar we could construct is also well
behaved. We can instead search for some other coordinate system
in which to express the solution to the eld equations, one in which
no such singularity appears. A partially successful change of coordi-
nates for the Schwarzschild metric, found by Eddington in 1924, is
t t
dt .
Identify the two values of r at which singularities occur, and classify
them as coordinate or non-coordinate singularities.
(b) The corresponding spatial metric was found to be
ds
2
= dr
2
r
2
1
2
r
2
d
2
.
Identify the two values of r at which singularities occur, and classify
them as coordinate or non-coordinate singularities.
(c) Consider the following argument, which is intended to provide
an answer to part b without any computation. In two dimensions,
there is only one measure of curvature, which is equivalent (up to a
constant of proportionality) to the Gaussian curvature. The Gaus-
sian curvature is proportional to the angular decit of a triangle.
Since the angular decit of a triangle in a space with negative cur-
vature satises the inequality < < 0, we conclude that the
Gaussian curvature can never be innite. Since there is only one
measure of curvature in a two-dimensional space, this means that
there is no non-coordinate singularity. Is this argument correct,
and is the claimed result consistent with your answers to part b?
Solution, p. 265
4 The rst experimental verication of gravitational redshifts
was a measurement in 1925 by W.S. Adams of the spectrum of light
emitted from the surface of the white dwarf star Sirius B. Sirius B
has a mass of 0.98M
t
never blow up, but that g
t
does
blow up.
Problems 191
192 Chapter 6 Vacuum Solutions
Chapter 7
Sources
7.1 Sources in general relativity
7.1.1 Point sources in a background-independent theory
Schrodinger equation and Maxwells equations treat spacetime
as a stage on which particles and elds act out their roles. General
relativity, however, is essentially a theory of spacetime itself. The
role played by atoms or rays of light is so peripheral that by the time
Einstein had derived an approximate version of the Schwarzschild
metric, and used it to nd the precession of Mercurys perihelion, he
still had only vague ideas of how light and matter would t into the
picture. In his calculation, Mercury played the role of a test particle:
a lump of mass so tiny that it can be tossed into spacetime in order
to measure spacetimes curvature, without worrying about its eect
on the spacetime, which is assumed to be negligible. Likewise the
sun was treated as in one of those orchestral pieces in which some
of the brass play from o-stage, so as to produce the eect of a
second band heard from a distance. Its mass appears simply as an
adjustable parameter m in the metric, and if we had never heard of
the Newtonian theory we would have had no way of knowing how
to interpret m.
When Schwarzschild published his exact solution to the vacuum
eld equations, Einstein suered from philosophical indigestion. His
strong belief in Machs principle led him to believe that there was a
paradox implicit in an exact spacetime with only one mass in it. If
Einsteins eld equations were to mean anything, he believed that
they had to be interpreted in terms of the motion of one body rela-
tive to another. In a universe with only one massive particle, there
would be no relative motion, and so, it seemed to him, no motion
of any kind, and no meaningful interpretation for the surrounding
spacetime.
Not only that, but Schwarzschilds solution had a singularity
at its center. When a classical eld theory contains singularities,
Einstein believed, it contains the seeds of its own destruction. As
weve seen on page 188, this issue is still far from being resolved, a
century later.
However much he might have liked to disown it, Einstein was
now in possession of a solution to his eld equations for a point
source. In a linear, background-dependent theory like electromag-
193
netism, knowledge of such a solution leads directly to the ability to
write down the eld equations with sources included. If Coulombs
law tells us the 1/r
2
variation of the electric eld of a point charge,
then we can infer Gausss law. The situation in general relativity
is not this simple. The eld equations of general relativity, unlike
the Gausss law, are nonlinear, so we cant simply say that a planet
or a star is a solution to be found by adding up a large number of
point-source solutions. Its also not clear how one could represent a
moving source, since the singularity is a point that isnt even part
of the continuous structure of spacetime (and its location is also
hidden behind an event horizon, so it cant be observed from the
outside).
7.1.2 The Einstein eld equation
The Einstein tensor
Given these diculties, its not surprising that Einsteins rst
attempt at incorporating sources into his eld equation was a dead
end. He postulated that the eld equation would have the Ricci
tensor on one side, and the energy-momentum tensor T
ab
(page
131) on the other,
R
ab
= 8T
ab
,
where a factor of G/c
4
on the right is suppressed by our choice
of units, and the 8 is determined on the basis of consistency with
Newtonian gravity in the limit of weak elds and low velocities. The
problem with this version of the eld equations can be demonstrated
by counting variables. R and T are symmetric tensors, so the eld
equation contains 10 constraints on the metric: 4 from the diagonal
elements and 6 from the o-diagonal ones. In addition, conservation
of mass-energy requires the divergence-free property
b
T
ab
= 0,
because otherwise, for example, we could have a mass-energy tensor
that varied as T
00
= kt, describing a region of space in which mass
was uniformly appearing or disappearing at a constant rate. But
this adds 4 more constraints on the metric, for a total of 14. The
metric, however, is a symmetric rank-2 tensor itself, so it only has
10 independent components. This overdetermination of the metric
suggests that the proposed eld equation will not in general allow a
solution to be evolved forward in time from a set of initial conditions
given on a spacelike surface, and this turns out to be true. It can in
fact be shown that the only possible solutions are those in which the
traces R = R
a
a
and T = T
a
a
are constant throughout spacetime.
The solution is to replace R
ab
in the eld equations with the a
dierent tensor G
ab
, called the Einstein tensor, dened by G
ab
=
R
ab
(1/2)Rg
ab
,
G
ab
= 8T
ab
.
The Einstein tensor is constructed exactly so that it is divergence-
free,
b
G
ab
= 0. (This is not obvious, but can be proved by direct
194 Chapter 7 Sources
computation.) Therefore any energy-momentum tensor that satis-
es the eld equation is automatically divergenceless, and thus no
additional constraints need to be applied in order to guarantee con-
servation of mass-energy.
Self-check: Does replacing R
ab
with G
ab
invalidate the Schwarzschild
metric?
Further interpretation of the energy-momentum tensor
The energy-momentum tensor was briey introduced in section
5.2 on page 131. By applying the Newtonian limit of the eld equa-
tion to the Schwarzschild metric, we nd that T
tt
is to be identied
as the mass density. The Schwarzschild metric describes a spacetime
using coordinates in which the mass is at rest. In the cosmological
applications well be considering shortly, it also makes sense to adopt
a frame of reference in which the local mass-energy is, on average, at
rest, so we can continue to think of T
tt
as the (average) mass density.
By symmetry, T must be diagonal in such a frame. For example, if
we had T
tx
,= 0, then the positive x direction would be distinguished
from the negative x direction, but there is nothing that would allow
such a distinction. The spacelike components are associated with
the pressure, P. The form of the tensor with mixed upper and lower
indices has the simple form T
= diag(, P, P, P).
7.1.3 The uniform gravitational eld revisited
This subsection gives a somewhat exotic example that provides
a little practice in interpreting the energy-momentum tensor. It is
not necessary to read it in order to understand the later material.
In problem 5 on page 162, we made a wish list of desired proper-
ties for a uniform gravitational eld, and found that they could not
all be satised at once. That is, there is no global solution to the
Einstein eld equations that uniquely and satisfactorily embodies
all of our Newtonian ideas about a uniform eld. We now revisit
this question in the light of our new knowledge about sources and
the stress-energy tensor.
The 1+1-dimensional metric
ds
2
= e
2gz
dt
2
dz
2
is the one that uniquely satises our expectations based on the
equivalence principle (example 7, p. 46), and it is a vacuum so-
lution. We might logically try to generalize this to 3+1 dimensions
as follows:
ds
2
= e
2gz
dt
2
dx
2
dy
2
dz
2
.
But a funny thing happens now simply by slapping on the two
new Cartesian axes x and y, it turns out that we have made our
vacuum solution into a non-vacuum solution, and not only that,
but the resulting energy-momentum tensor is unphysical (problem
1, p. 227).
Section 7.1 Sources in general relativity 195
One way to proceed would be to relax our insistence on making
the spacetime one that exactly embodies the equivalence principles
requirements for a uniform eld.
1
This can be done by taking g
tt
=
e
2
, where is not necessarily equal to 2gz. By requiring that the
metric be a 3+1 vacuum solution, we arrive at a dierential equation
whose solution is = ln(z +k
1
) +k
2
, which recovers the at-space
metric that we found in example 14 on page 116 by applying a
change of coordinates to the Lorentz metric.
What if we want to carry out the generalization from 1+1 to
3+1 without violating the equivalence principle? For physical mo-
tivation in how to get past this obstacle, consider the following ar-
gument made by Born in 1920.
2
Take a frame of reference tied to a
rotating disk, as in the example from which Einstein originally took
much of the motivation for creating a geometrical theory of gravity
(subsection 3.4.4, p. 89). Clocks near the edge of the disk run slowly,
and by the equivalence principle, an observer on the disk interprets
this as a gravitational time dilation. But this is not the only rela-
tivistic eect seen by such an observer. Her rulers are also Lorentz
contracted as seen by a non-rotating observer, and she interprets
this as evidence of a non-Euclidean spatial geometry. There are
some physical dierences between the rotating disk and our default
conception of a uniform eld, specically in the question of whether
the metric should be static (i.e., lacking in cross-terms between the
space and time variables). But even so, these considerations make
it natural to hypothesize that the correct 3+1-dimensional metric
should have transverse spatial coecients that decrease with height.
With this motivation, lets consider a metric of the form
ds
2
= e
2z
dt
2
e
2jz
dx
2
e
2kz
dy
2
dz
2
,
where j and k are constants, and Ive taken g = 1 for convenience.
3
The following Maxima code calculates the scalar curvature and the
Einstein tensor:
1 load(ctensor);
2 ct_coords:[t,x,y,z];
3 lg:matrix([exp(2*z),0,0,0],
4 [0,-exp(-2*j*z),0,0],
5 [0,0,-exp(-2*k*z),0],
6 [0,0,0,-1]
7 );
1
Thanks to physicsforums.com user Mentz114 for suggesting this approach
and demonstrating the following calculation.
2
Max Born, Einsteins Theory of Relativity, 1920. In the 1962 Dover edition,
the relevant passage is on p. 320
3
A metric of this general form is referred to as a Kasner metric. One usually
sees it written with a logarithmic change of variables, so that z appears in the
base rather than in the exponent.
196 Chapter 7 Sources
8 cmetric();
9 scurvature();
10 leinstein(true);
The output from line 9 shows that the scalar curvature is constant,
which is a necessary condition for any spacetime that we want to
think of as representing a uniform eld. Inspecting the Einstein
tensor output by line 10, we nd that in order to get G
xx
and G
yy
to vanish, we need j and k to be (1
3z and
g
yy
= e
z
sin
3, where n is an
integer.
It turns out, however, that there is a very similar solution, found
by Petrov in 1962,
4
that is real-valued. The Petrov metric, which
describes a spacetime with cylindrical symmetry, is:
ds
2
= dr
2
e
2r
dz
2
+e
r
[2 sin
3rddt cos
3r(d
2
dt
2
)]
Note that it has many features in common with the complex oscilla-
tory solution we found above. There are transverse length contrac-
tions that decay and oscillate in exactly the same way. The presence
of the ddt term tells us that this is a non-static, rotating solution
exactly like the one that Einstein and Born had in mind in their
prototypical example! We typically obtain this type of eect due
to frame dragging by some rotating massive body (see p. 123), and
the Petrov solution can indeed be interpreted as the spacetime that
exists in the vacuum on the exterior of an innite, rigidly rotating
cylinder of dust dust in the sense of material particles with
an energy-momentum tensor of the form T
= diag(, 0, 0, 0).
The complicated Petrov metric might seem like the furthest pos-
sible thing from a uniform gravitational eld, but in fact it is about
the closest thing general relativity provides to such a eld. We rst
note that the metric displays symmetry under z z +c, +c,
and t t + c, so it has at least three out of the four translation
symmetries we expect from a uniform eld. By analogy with elec-
tromagnetism, we would expect this symmetry to be absent in the
radial direction, since by Gausss law the electric eld of a line of
4
Petrov, in Recent Developments in General Relativity, 1962, Pergamon, p.
383. For a presentation that is freely accessible online, see Gibbons and Gielen,
The Petrov and Kaigorodov-Ozsv ath Solutions: Spacetime as a Group Mani-
fold, arxiv.org/abs/0802.4082.
Section 7.1 Sources in general relativity 197
charge falls o like 1/r. Adding in a centrifugal force, we dont get
anything like a constant. But surprisingly, the Petrov metric has
a constant scalar curvature (problem 2, p. 227). This is what we
want in a uniform eld, and it also suggests that this spacetime has
an even higher degree of symmetry than the threefold translational
symmetry one would guess by looking at the metric.
For insight into this surprising result, recall that in our attempt
at constructing the Cartesian version of this metric, we ran into the
problem that the metric became degenerate at z = n/2
3. The
presence of the ddt term prevents this from happening in Petrovs
cylindrical version; two of the metrics diagonal components can
vanish at certain values of r, but the presence of the o-diagonal
component prevents the determinant from going to zero. (The de-
terminant is in fact equal to 1 everywhere.) What is happening
physically is that although the labeling of the and t coordinates
suggests a time and an azimuthal angle, these two coordinates are
in fact treated completely symmetrically. At values of r where the
cosine factor equals 1, the metric is diagonal, and has signature
(t, , r, z) = (+, , , ), but when the cosine equals 1, this be-
comes (, +, , ), so that is now the timelike coordinate. This
perfect symmetry between and t is an extreme example of frame-
dragging, and is produced because of the specially chosen rate of
rotation of the dust cylinder, such that the velocity of the dust at
the outer surface is exactly c (or approaches it).
Classically, we would expect that a test particle released close
enough to the cylinder would be pulled in by the gravitational at-
traction and destroyed on impact, while a particle released farther
away would y o due to the centrifugal force, escaping and even-
tually approaching a constant velocity. Neither of these would be
anything like the experience of a test particle released in a uniform
eld. But consider a particle released at rest in the rotating frame
at a radius r
1
for which cos
3r
1
= 1, so that t is the timelike co-
ordinate. The particle accelerates (lets say outward), but at some
point it arrives at an r
2
where the cosine equals zero, and the t
part of the metric is purely of the form ddt. At this location, we
can dene local coordinates u = t and v = + t, so that the
metric depends only on du
2
dv
2
. One of the coordinates, say u, is
now the timelike one. Since our particle is material, its world-line
must be timelike, so it is swept along in the direction. Gibbons
and Gielen show that the particle will now come back inward, and
continue forever by oscillating back and forth between two radii at
which the cosine vanishes.
This oscillation still doesnt sound like the motion of a particle
in a uniform eld, but another strange thing happens, as we can
see by taking another look at the values of r at which the cosine
vanishes. At such a value of r, construct a curve of the form (t =
constant, r = constant, , z = constant). This is a closed curve, and
198 Chapter 7 Sources
its proper length is zero, i.e., it is lightlike. This violates causality.
A photon could travel around this path and arrive at its starting
point at the same time when it was emitted. Something similarly
weird hapens to the test particle described above: whereas it seems
to fall sometimes up and sometimes down, in fact it is always falling
down but sometimes it achieves this by falling up while moving
backward in time!
Although the Petov metric violates causality, Gibbons and Gie-
len have shown that it satises the chronology protection conjecture:
In the context of causality violation we have shown that one cannot
create CTCs [closed timelike curves] by spinning up a cylinder be-
yond its critical angular velocity by shooting in particles on timelike
or null curves.
7.1.4 Energy conditions
The eld equations are agnostic on the question of what kinds
of matter elds contribute to the energy-momentum tensor. In fact,
any spacetime at all is a solution to the Einstein eld equations, pro-
vided were willing to admit the corresponding energy-momentum
tensor. Suppose that we want to prove all-encompassing theorems
about general relativity. For instance, we may want to reassure our-
selves that general relativity will never lead to violations of causality
such as the closed timelike curves exhibited by the Petrov metric
(p. 197). We can never make this type of general proof without
assuming something about the energy-momentum tensor.
In example 10 on page 110, we saw that radiation has P = /3
and dust has P = 0. Both have 0. If the universe is made out
of nothing but dust and radiation, then we can obtain the following
four constraints on the energy-momentum tensor:
trace energy condition 3P 0
strong energy condition + 3P 0 and +P 0
dominant energy condition 0 and [P[
weak energy condition 0 and +P 0
null energy condition +P 0
These are arranged roughly in order from strongest to weakest. They
all have to do with the idea that negative mass-energy doesnt seem
to exist in our universe, i.e., that gravity is always attractive rather
than repulsive. With this motivation, it would seem that there
should only be one way to state an energy condition: > 0. But
the symbols and P refer to the form of the energy-momentum
tensor in a special frame of reference, interpreted as the one that
is at rest relative to the average motion of the ambient matter. In
this frame, the tensor is diagonal. Switching to some other frame of
reference, the and P parts of the tensor would mix, and it might
be possible to end up with a negative energy density. The weak
energy condition is the constraint we need in order to make sure
Section 7.1 Sources in general relativity 199
that the energy density is never negative in any frame.
The dominant energy condition is like the weak energy condition,
but it also guarantees that no observer will see a ux of energy
owing at speeds greater than c.
As an example of the use of the energy conditions, Hawking and
Ellis have proved that under the assumption of the strong energy
condition, any body that becomes suciently compact will end up
forming a singularity. We might imagine that the formation of a
black hole would be a delicate thing, requiring perfectly symmetric
initial conditions in order to end up with the perfectly symmetric
Schwarzschild metric. Many early relativists thought so, for good
reasons. If we look around the universe at various scales, we nd
that collisions between astronomical bodies are extremely rare. This
is partly because the distances are vast compared to the sizes of the
objects, but also because conservation of angular momentum has
a tendency to make objects swing past one another rather than
colliding head-on. Starting with a cloud of objects, e.g., a globular
cluster, Newtons laws make it extremely dicult, regardless of the
attractive nature of gravity, to pick initial conditions that will make
them all collide the future. For one thing, they would have to have
exactly zero total angular momentum.
Most relativists now believe that this is not the case. General
relativity describes gravity in terms of the tipping of light cones.
When the eld is strong enough, there is a tendency for the light
cones to tip over so far that the entire future light-cone points at the
source of the eld. If this occurs on an entire surface surrounding
the source, it is referred to as a trapped surface. Any lumpiness or
rotation in the initial conditions becomes irrelevant, because every
particles entire future world-line lies inward rather than outward.
A possible loophole in this argument is the question of whether the
light cones will really tip over far enough. We could imagine that
under extreme conditions of high density and temperature, matter
might demonstrate unusual behavior, perhaps including a negative
energy density, which would then give rise to a gravitational repul-
sion. Gravitational repulsion would tend to make the light cones tip
outward rather than inward, possibly preventing the collapse to a
singularity. We can close this loophole by assuming an appropriate
energy condition. Penrose and Hawking have formalized the above
argument in the form of a series of theorems, known as the singular-
ity theorems. One of these applies to the formation of black holes,
and another one to cosmological singularities such as the Big Bang.
The current status of the energy conditions is shaky. Although
it is clear that all of them hold in a variety of situations, there are
strong reasons to believe that they are violated at both microscopic
and cosmological scales, for reasons both classical and quantum-
200 Chapter 7 Sources
mechanical.
5
We will see such a violation in the following section.
7.1.5 The cosmological constant
Having included the source term in the Einstein eld equations,
our most important application will be to cosmology. Some of the
relevant ideas originate long before Einstein. Once Newton had
formulated a theory of gravity as a universal attractive force, he
realized that there would be a tendency for the universe to collapse.
He resolved this diculty by assuming that the universe was innite
in spatial extent, so that it would have no center of symmetry, and
therefore no preferred point to collapse toward. The trouble with
this argument is that the equilibrium it describes is unstable. Any
perturbation of the uniform density of matter breaks the symmetry,
leading to the collapse of some pocket of the universe. If the radius
of such a collapsing region is r, then its gravitational is proportional
to r
3
, and its gravitational eld is proportional to r
3
/r
2
= r. Since
its acceleration is proportional to its own size, the time it takes to
collapse is independent of its size. The prediction is that the uni-
verse will have a self-similar structure, in which the clumping on
small scales behaves in the same way as clumping on large scales;
zooming in or out in such a picture gives a landscape that appears
the same. With modern hindsight, this is actually not in bad agree-
ment with reality. We observe that the universe has a hierarchical
structure consisting of solar systems, galaxies, clusters of galaxies,
superclusters, and so on. Once such a structure starts to condense,
the collapse tends to stop at some point because of conservation of
angular momentum. This is what happened, for example, when our
own solar system formed out of a cloud of gas and dust.
Einstein confronted similar issues, but in a more acute form.
Newtons symmetry argument, which failed only because of its in-
stability, fails even more badly in relativity: the entire spacetime
can simply contract uniformly over time, without singling out any
particular point as a center. Furthermore, it is not obvious that
angular momentum prevents total collapse in relativity in the same
way that it does classically, and even if it did, how would that apply
to the universe as a whole? Einsteins Machian orientation would
have led him to reject the idea that the universe as a whole could
be in a state of rotation, and in any case it was sensible to start the
study of relativistic cosmology with the simplest and most symmet-
ric possible models, which would have no preferred axis of rotations.
Because of these issues, Einstein decided to try to patch up his
eld equation so that it would allow a static universe. Looking back
over the considerations that led us to this form of the equation,
we see that it is very nearly uniquely determined by the following
criteria:
5
Barcelo and Visser, Twilight for the energy conditions?, http://arxiv.
org/abs/gr-qc/0205066v1.
Section 7.1 Sources in general relativity 201
The equivalence principle is satised.
It should be coordinate-independent.
It should be equivalent to Newtonian gravity in the appropri-
ate limit.
It should not be overdetermined.
This is not meant to be a rigorous proof, just a general observation
that its not easy to tinker with the theory without breaking it.
A failed attempt at tinkering Example: 1
As an example of the lack of wiggle room in the structure of the
eld equations, suppose we construct the scalar T
a
a
, the trace of
the energy-momentum tensor, and try to insert it into the eld
equations as a further source term. The rst problem is that
the eld equation involves rank-2 tensors, so we cant just add
a scalar. To get around this, suppose we multiply by the metric.
We then have something like G
ab
= c
1
T
ab
+ c
2
g
ab
T
c
c
, where the
two constants c
1
and c
2
would be constrained by the requirement
that the theory agree with Newtonian gravity in the classical limit.
This particular attempt fails, because it violates the equivalence
principle. Consider a beam of light directed along the x axis.
Its momentum is equal to its energy (see page 106), so its con-
tributions to the local energy density and pressure are equal.
Thus its contribution to the energy-momentum tensor is of the
form T
= G
= 2
a
a
+
_
a
a
_
2
+ka
2
,
where dots indicate dierentiation with respect to time.
Since we have G
a
b
with mixed upper and lower indices, we either
have to convert it into G
ab
, or write out the eld equations in this
mixed form. The latter turns out to be simpler. In terms of mixed
indices, g
a
b
is always simply diag(1, 1, 1, 1). Arbitrarily singling out
r = 0 for simplicity, we have g = diag(1, a
2
, 0, 0). The energy-
momentum tensor is T
_
a
a
_
2
=
1
3
.
This is referred to as a vacuum-dominated universe. The solution is
a = exp
_
_
3
t
_
.
The implications for the fate of the universe are depressing. All parts
of the universe will accelerate away from one another faster and
Section 7.2 Cosmological solutions 213
faster as time goes on. The relative separation between two objects,
say galaxy A and galaxy B, will eventually be increasing faster than
the speed of light. (The Lorentzian character of spacetime is local,
so relative motion faster than c is only forbidden between objects
that are passing right by one another.) At this point, an observer
in either galaxy will say that the other one has passed behind an
event horizon. If intelligent observers do actually exist in the far
future, they may have no way to tell that the cosmos even exists.
They will perceive themselves as living in island universes, such as
we believed our own galaxy to be a hundred years ago.
When I introduced the standard cosmological coordinates on
page 204, I described them as coordinates in which events that
are simultaneous according to this t are events at which the local
properties of the universe are the same. In the case of a perfectly
vacuum-dominated universe, however, this notion loses its meaning.
The only observable local property of such a universe is the vacuum
energy described by the cosmological constant, and its density is al-
ways the same, because it is built into the structure of the vacuum.
Thus the vacuum-dominated cosmology is a special one that maxi-
mally symmetric, in the sense that it has not only the symmetries of
homogeneity and isotropy that weve been assuming all along, but
also a symmetry with respect to time: it is a cosmology without
history, in which all times appear identical to a local observer. In
the special case of this cosmology, the time variation of the scaling
factor a(t) is unobservable, and may be thought of as the unfortu-
nate result of choosing an inappropriate set of coordinates, which
obscure the underlying symmetry. When I argued in section 7.2.3
for the observability of the universes expansion, note that all my
arguments assumed the presence of matter or radiation. These are
completely absent in a perfectly vacuum-dominated cosmology.
For these reasons de Sitter originally proposed this solution as a
static universe in 1927. But by 1920 it was realized that this was an
oversimplication. The argument above only shows that the time
variation of a(t) does not allow us to distinguish one epoch of the
universe from another. That is, we cant look out the window and
infer the date (e.g., from the temperature of the cosmic microwave
background radiation). It does not, however, imply that the uni-
verse is static in the sense that had been assumed until Hubbles
observations. The r-t part of the metric is
ds
2
= dt
2
a
2
dr
2
,
where a blows up exponentially with time, and the k-dependence
has been neglected, as it was in the approximation to the Friedmann
equations used to derive a(t).
12
Let a test particle travel in the radial
direction, starting at event A = (0, 0) and ending at B = (t
, r
). In
12
A computation of the Einstein tensor with ds
2
= dt
2
a
2
(1 kr
2
)
1
dr
2
shows that k enters only via a factor the form (. . .)e
(...)t
+(. . .)k. For large t, the
214 Chapter 7 Sources
at space, a world-line of the linear form r = vt would be a geodesic
connecting A and B; it would maximize the particles proper time.
But in the this metric, it cannot be a geodesic. The curvature of
geodesics relative to a line on an r-t plot is most easily understood
in the limit where t
dr
2
1
2m
r
1
3
r
2
r
2
d
2
r
2
sin
2
d
2
is an exact solution to the Einstein eld equations with cosmo-
logical constant , and can be interpreted as a universe in which
the only mass is a black hole of mass m located at r = 0. Near
the black hole, the terms become negligible, and this is simply
the Schwarzschild metric. As argued in section 7.2.3, page 207,
this is a simple example of how cosmological expansion does not
cause all structures in the universe to grow at the same rate.
216 Chapter 7 Sources
The Big Bang singularity in a universe with a cosmological
constant
On page 207 we discussed the possibility that the Big Bang
singularity was an artifact of the unrealistically perfect symmetry
assumed by our cosmological models, and we found that this was
not the case: the Penrose-Hawking singularity theorems demon-
strate that the singularity is real, provided that the cosmological
constant is zero. The cosmological constant is not zero, however.
Models with a very large positive cosmological constant can also
display a Big Bounce rather than a Big Bang. If we imagine us-
ing the Friedmann equations to evolve the universe backward in
time from its present state, the scaling arguments of example 10 on
page 110 suggest that at early enough times, radiation and mat-
ter should dominate over the cosmological constant. For a large
enough value of the cosmological constant, however, it can happen
that this switch-over never happens. In such a model, the universe
is and always has been dominated by the cosmological constant,
and we get a Big Bounce in the past because of the cosmological
constants repulsion. In this book I will only develop simple cos-
mological models in which the universe is dominated by a single
component; for a discussion of bouncing models with both matter
and a cosmological constant, see Carroll, The Cosmological Con-
stant, http://www.livingreviews.org/lrr-2001-1. By 2008, a
variety of observational data had pinned down the cosmological con-
stant well enough to rule out the possibility of a bounce caused by
a very strong cosmological constant.
7.2.5 The matter-dominated solution
Our universe is not perfectly vacuum-dominated, and in the past
it was even less so. Let us consider the matter-dominated epoch,
in which the cosmological constant was negligible compared to the
material sources. The equations of state for nonrelativistic matter
(p. 110) are
P = 0
a
3
so the Friedmann equations become
a
a
=
4
3
_
a
a
_
2
=
8
3
ka
2
,
where for compactness s dependence on a, with some constant
of proportionality, is not shown explicitly. A static solution, with
constant a, is impossible, and a is negative, which we can inter-
pret semiclassically in terms of the deceleration of the matter in the
universe due to gravitational attraction. There are three cases to
consider, according to the value of k.
Section 7.2 Cosmological solutions 217
The closed universe
Weve seen that k = +1 describes a universe in which the spatial
curvature is positive, i.e., the circumference of a circle is less than
its Euclidean value. By analogy with a sphere, which is the two-
dimensional surface of constant positive curvature, we expect that
the total volume of this universe is nite.
The second Friedmann equation also shows us that at some value
of a, we will have a = 0. The universe will expand, stop, and then
recollapse, eventually coming back together in a Big Crunch which
is the time-reversed version of the Big Bang.
Suppose we were to describe an initial-value problem in this
cosmology, in which the initial conditions are given for all points in
the universe on some spacelike surface, say t = constant. Since the
universe is assumed to be homogeneous at all times, there are really
only three numbers to specify, a, a, and : how big is the universe,
how fast is it expanding, and how much matter is in it? But these
three pieces of data may or may not be consistent with the second
Friedmann equation. That is, the problem is overdetermined. In
particular, we can see that for small enough values of , we do
not have a valid solution, since the square of a/a would have to be
negative. Thus a closed universe requires a certain amount of matter
in it. The present observational evidence (from supernovae and the
cosmic microwave background, as described above) is sucient to
show that our universe does not contain this much matter.
The at universe
The case of k = 0 describes a universe that is spatially at.
It represents a knife-edge case lying between the closed and open
universes. In a semiclassical analogy, it represents the case in which
the universe is moving exactly at escape velocity; as t approaches
innity, we have a , 0, and a 0. This case, unlike the
others, allows an easy closed-form solution to the motion. Let the
constant of proportionality in the equation of state a
3
be xed
by setting 4/3 = ca
3
. The Friedmann equations are
a = ca
2
a =
2ca
1/2
.
Looking for a solution of the form a t
p
, we nd that by choosing
p = 2/3 we can simultaneously satisfy both equations. The constant
c is also xed, and we can investigate this most transparently by
recognizing that a/a is interpreted as the Hubble constant, H, which
is the constant of proportionality relating a far-o galaxys velocity
to its distance. Note that H is a constant in the sense that it is
the same for all galaxies, in this particular model with a vanishing
cosmological constant; it does not stay constant with the passage
of cosmological time. Plugging back into the original form of the
218 Chapter 7 Sources
a / The angular scale of uc-
tuations in the cosmic microwave
background can be used to infer
the curvature of the universe.
Friedmann equations, we nd that the at universe can only exist if
the density of matter satises =
crit
= 2H
2
/8 = 2H
2
/8G. The
observed value of the Hubble constant is about 1/(14 10
9
years),
which is roughly interpreted as the age of the universe, i.e., the
proper time experienced by a test particle since the Big Bang. This
gives
crit
10
26
kg/m
3
.
The open universe
The k = 1 case represents a universe that has negative spatial
curvature, is spatially innite, and is also innite in time, i.e., even
if the cosmological constant had been zero, the expansion of the uni-
verse would have had too little matter in it to cause it to recontract
and end in a Big Crunch.
7.2.6 Observation
Historically, it was very dicult to determine the universes av-
erage density, even to within an order of magnitude. Most of the
matter in the universe probably doesnt emit light, making it dif-
cult to detect. Astronomical distance scales are also very poorly
calibrated against absolute units such as the SI.
A strong constraint on the models comes from accurate mea-
surements of the cosmic microwave background, especially by the
1989-1993 COBE probe, and its 2001-2009 successor, the Wilkin-
son Microwave Anisotropy Probe, positioned at the L2 Lagrange
point of the earth-sun system, beyond the Earth on the line con-
necting sun and earth. The temperature of the cosmic microwave
background radiation is not the same in all directions, and its can
be measured at dierent angles. In a universe with negative spatial
curvature, the sum of the interior angles of a triangle is less than
the Euclidean value of 180 degrees. Therefore if we observe a varia-
tion in the CMB over some angle, the distance between two points
on the surface of last scattering is actually greater than would have
been inferred from Euclidean geometry. The distance scale of such
variations is limited by the speed of sound in the early universe, so
one can work backward and infer the universes spatial curvature
based on the angular scale of the anisotropies. The measurements
of spatial curvature are usually stated in terms of the parameter ,
dened as the total average density of all source terms in the Ein-
stein eld equations, divided by the critical density that results in
a at universe. includes contributions from matter,
M
, the cos-
mological constant,
M
,
rather than their sum =
+
M
. This is because these data
Section 7.2 Cosmological solutions 219
c / The cosmological param-
eters of our universe, after
Perlmutter et al., arxiv.org/
abs/astro-ph/9812133.
b / A Hubble plot for distant
supernovae. Each data point
represents an average over
several different supernovae with
nearly the same z.
measure the acceleration or deceleration of the universes expansion.
Matter produces deceleration, while the cosmological constant gives
acceleration. Figure b shows some recent supernova data.
13
The
horizontal axis gives the redshift factor z = (
)/, where
is
the wavelength observed on earth and the wavelength originally
emitted. It measures how fast the supernovas galaxy is receding
from us. The vertical axis is (mM) = (mM) (mM)
empty
,
where m is the apparent magnitude, M is the absolute magnitude,
and (m M)
empty
is the value expected in a model of an empty
universe, with = 0. The dierence mM is a measure of distance,
so essentially this is a graph of distance versus recessional velocity, of
the same general type used by Hubble in his original discovery of the
expansion of the universe. Subtracting (mM)
empty
on the vertical
axis makes it easier to see small dierences. Since the WMAP data
require = 1, we need to t the supernova data with values of
M
and
nonzero.
14
We can tell that it originated in a Big Bang singularity, that it
will go on expanding forever, and that it is very nearly at. Note
that in a cosmology with nonzero values for both
M
and
, there
is no strict linkage between the spatial curvature and the question
of recollapse, as there is in a model with only matter and no cosmo-
logical constant; therefore even though we know that the universe
will not recollapse, we do not know whether its spatial curvature is
slightly positive (closed) or negative (open).
Astrophysical considerations provide further constraints and con-
sistency checks. In the era before the advent of high-precision cos-
mology, estimates of the age of the universe ranged from 10 billion
to 20 billion years, and the low end was inconsistent with the age
of the oldest globular clusters. This was believed to be a problem
either for observational cosmology or for the astrophysical models
used to estimate the age of the clusters: You cant be older than
your ma. Current data have shown that the low estimates of the
age were incorrect, so consistency is restored.
Another constraint comes from models of nucleosynthesis dur-
ing the era shortly after the Big Bang (before the formation of the
rst stars). The observed relative abundances of hydrogen, helium,
and deuterium cannot be reconciled with the density of dust (i.e.,
nonrelativistic matter) inferred from the observational data. If the
inferred mass density were entirely due to normal baryonic matter
(i.e., matter whose mass consisted mostly of protons and neutrons),
13
Riess et al., 2007, arxiv.org/abs/astro-ph/0611572
14
See Carroll, The Cosmological Constant, http://www.livingreviews.
org/lrr-2001-1 for a full mathematical treatment of such models.
220 Chapter 7 Sources
then nuclear reactions in the dense early universe should have pro-
ceeded relatively eciently, leading to a much higher ratio of helium
to hydrogen, and a much lower abundance of deuterium. The con-
clusion is that most of the matter in the universe must be made of
an unknown type of exotic non-baryonic matter, known generically
as dark matter.
7.3 Machs principle revisited
7.3.1 The Brans-Dicke theory
Mach himself never succeeded in stating his ideas in the form of
a precisely testable physical theory, and weve seen that to the ex-
tent that Einsteins hopes and intuition had been formed by Machs
ideas, he often felt that his own theory of gravity came up short.
The reader has so far encountered Machs principle in the context of
certain thought experiments that are obviously impossible to realize,
involving a hypothetical universe that is empty except for certain
apparatus (e.g., section 3.5.2, p. 96). It would be easy, then, to get
an impression of Machs principle as one of those theories that is
not even wrong, i.e., so ill-dened that it cannot even be falsied
by experiment, any more than Christianity can be.
But in 1961, Robert Dicke and his student Carl Brans came up
with a theory of gravity that made testable predictions, and that
was specically designed to be more Machian than general relativity.
Their paper
15
is extremely readable, even for the non-specialist. On
the rst page, they propose one of those seemingly foolish thought
experiments about a nearly empty universe:
The imperfect expression of [Machs ideas] in general
relativity can be seen by considering the case of a space
empty except for a lone experimenter in his laboratory.
[...] The observer would, according to general relativity,
observe normal behavior of his apparatus in accordance
with the usual laws of physics. However, also accord-
ing to general relativity, the experimenter could set his
laboratory rotating by leaning out a window and ring
his 22-caliber rie tangentially. Thereafter the delicate
gyroscope in the laboratory would continue to point in a
direction nearly xed relative to the direction of motion
of the rapidly receding bullet. The gyroscope would ro-
tate relative to the walls of the laboratory. Thus, from
the point of view of Mach, the tiny, almost massless,
very distant bullet seems to be more important than the
massive, nearby walls of the laboratory in determining
15
C. Brans and R. H. Dicke, Machs Principle and a Relativistic Theory of
Gravitation, Physical Review 124 (1961) 925
Section 7.3 Machs principle revisited 221
inertial coordinate frames and the orientation of the gy-
roscope.
They then proceed to construct a mathematical and more Machian
theory of gravity. From the Machian point of view, the correct lo-
cal denition of an inertial frame must be determined relative to the
bulk of the matter in the universe. We want to retain the Lorentzian
local character of spacetime, so this inuence cant be transmitted
via instantaneous action at a distance. It must propagate via some
physical eld, at a speed less than or equal to c. It is implausible that
this eld would be the gravitational eld as described by general rel-
ativity. Suppose we divide the cosmos up into a series of concentric
spherical shells centered on our galaxy. In Newtonian mechanics,
the gravitational eld obeys Gausss law, so the eld of such a shell
vanishes identically on the interior. In relativity, the corresponding
statement is Birkhos theorem, which states that the Schwarzschild
metric is the unique spherically symmetric solution to the vacuum
eld equations. Given this solution in the exterior universe, we can
set a boundary condition at the outside surface of the shell, use the
Einstein eld equations to extend the solution through it, and nd
a unique solution on the interior, which is simply a at space.
Since the Machian eect cant be carried by the gravitational
eld, Brans and Dicke took up an idea earlier proposed by Pascual
Jordan
16
of hypothesizing an auxiliary eld . The fact that such a
eld has never been detected directly suggests that it has no mass or
charge. If it is massless, it must propagate at exactly c, and this also
makes sense because if it were to propagate at speeds less than c,
there would be no obvious physical parameter that would determine
that speed. How many tensor indices should it have? Since Machs
principle tries to give an account of inertia, and inertial mass is a
scalar, should presumably be a scalar (quantized by a spin-zero
particle). Theories of this type are called tensor-scalar theories,
because they use a scalar eld in addition to the metric tensor.
The wave equation for a massless scalar eld, in the absence of
sources, is simply
i
i
= 0. The solutions of this wave equa-
tion fall o as 1/r. This is gentler than the 1/r
2
variation of
the gravitational eld, so results like Newtons shell theorem and
Birkhos theorem no longer apply. If a spherical shell of mass acts
as a source of , then can be nonzero and varying inside the shell.
The that you experience right now as you read this book should be
a sum of wavelets originating from all the masses whose world-lines
intersected the surface of your past light-cone. In a static universe,
this sum would diverge linearly, so a self-consistency requirement for
Brans-Dicke gravity is that it should produce cosmological solutions
16
Jordan was a member of the Nazi Sturmabteilung or brown shirts who
nevertheless ran afoul of the Nazis for his close professional relationships with
Jews.
222 Chapter 7 Sources
that avoid such a divergence, e.g., ones that begin with Big Bangs.
Masses are the sources of the eld . How should they cou-
ple to it? Since is a scalar, we need to construct a scalar as its
source, and the only reasonable scalar that can play this role is the
trace of the stress-energy tensor, T
i
i
. As discussed in example 1
on page 202, this vanishes for light, so only material particles are
sources of . Even so, the Brans-Dicke theory retains a form of the
equivalence principle. As discussed on pp. 34 and 29, the equiva-
lence principle is a statement about the results of local experiments,
and at any given location in the universe is dominated by con-
tributions from matter lying at cosmological distances. Objects of
dierent composition will have diering fractions of their mass that
arise from internal electromagnetic elds. Two such objects will still
follow identical geodesics, since their own eect on the local value
of is negligible. This is unlike the behavior of electrically charged
objects, which experience signicant back-reaction eects in curved
space (p. 34). However, the strongest form of the equivalence princi-
ple requires that all experiments in free-falling laboratories produce
identical results, no matter where and when they are carried out.
Brans-Dicke gravity violates this, because such experiments could
detect dierences between the value of at dierent locations
but of course this is part and parcel of the purpose of the theory.
We now need to see how to connect to the local notion of
inertia so as to produce an eect of the kind that would tend to
fulll Machs principle. In Machs original formulation, this would
entail some kind of local rescaling of all inertial masses, but Brans
and Dicke point out that in a theory of gravity, this is equivalent to
scaling the Newtonian gravitational constant G down by the same
factor. The latter turns out to be a better approach. For one thing,
it has a natural interpretation in terms of units. Since s amplitude
falls o as 1/r, we can write m
i
/r, where the sum is over the
past light cone. If we then make the identication of with 1/G
(or c
2
/G in a system wher c ,= 1), the units work out properly, and
the coupling constant between matter and can be unitless. If this
coupling constant, notated 1/, were not unitless, then the theorys
predictive value would be weakened, because there would be no way
to know what value to pick for it. For a unitless constant, however,
there is a reasonable way to guess what it should be: in any sensible
theory, Brans and Dicke write, must be of the general order of
magnitude of unity. This is, of course, assuming that the Brans-
Dicke theory was correct. In general, there are other reasonable
values to pick for a unitless number, including zero and innity. The
limit of recovers the special case of general relativity. Thus
Machs principle, which once seemed too vague to be empirically
falsiable, comes down to measuring a specic number, , which
quanties how non-Machian our universe is.
17
17
There are also good technical reasons for thinking of as relating to the
Section 7.3 Machs principle revisited 223
7.3.2 Predictions of the Brans-Dicke theory
Returning to the example of the spherical shell of mass, we can
see based on considerations of units that the value of inside should
be m/r, where m is the total mass of the shell and r is its radius.
There may be a unitless factor out in front, which will depend on ,
but for 1 we expect this constant to be of order 1. Solving the
nasty set of eld equations that result from their Lagrangian, Brans
and Dicke indeed found [2/(3 + 2)](m/r), where the constant
in square brackets is of order unity if is of order unity. In the
limit of , = 0, and the shell has no physical eect on its
interior, as predicted by general relativity.
Brans and Dicke were also able to calculate cosmological models,
and in a typical model with a nearly spatially at universe, they
found would vary according to
= 8
4 + 3
6 + 4
o
t
2
o
_
t
t
o
_
2/(4+3)
,
where
o
is the density of matter in the universe at time t = t
o
.
When the density of matter is small, G is large, which has the same
observational consequences as the disappearance of inertia; this is
exactly what one expects according to Machs principle. For ,
the gravitational constant G = 1/ really is constant.
Returning to the thought experiment involving the 22-caliber ri-
e red out the window, we nd that in this imaginary universe, with
a very small density of matter, G should be very large. This causes
a frame-dragging eect from the laboratory on the gyroscope, one
much stronger than we would see in our universe. Brans and Dicke
calculated this eect for a laboratory consisting of a spherical shell,
and although technical diculties prevented the reliable extrapo-
lation of their result to
o
0, the trend was that as
o
became
small, the frame-dragging eect would get stronger and stronger,
gravitational constant is that general relativity has a standard prescription for
describing elds on a background of curved spacetime. The vacuum eld equa-
tions of general relativity can be derived from the principle of least action, and
although the details are beyond the scope of this book (see, e.g., Wald, General
Relativity, appendix E), the general idea is that we dene a Lagrangian density
LG that depends on the Ricci scalar curvature, and then extremize its integral
over all possible histories of the evolution of the gravitational eld. If we want to
describe some other eld, such as matter, light, or , we simply take the special-
relativistic Lagrangian LM for that eld, change all the derivatives to covariant
derivatives, and form the sum (1/G)LG + LM. In the Brans-Dicke theory, we
have three pieces, (1/G)LG + LM + L
for .
If we were to interpret as a rescaling of inertia, then we would have to have
appearing as a fudge factor modifying all the inner workings of LM. If, on the
other hand, we think of as changing the value of the gravitational constant G,
then the necessary modication is extremely simple. Brans and Dicke introduce
one further modication to L
of a quasar,
so that the quasars radio waves came within about 3 light-seconds
of the planet on their way to the earth. Since Jupiter moves with
v = 410
5
, one expects naively that the radio waves passing by it
should be deected by the eld produced by Jupiter at the position it
had 3 seconds earlier. This position diers from its present position
by about 10
4
light-seconds, and the result should be a dierence
in propagation time, which should be dierent when observed from
dierent locations on earth. Fomalont and Kopeikin measured these
phase dierences with picosecond precision, and found them to be
in good agreement with the predictions of general relativity. The
real excitement started when they published their result with the
interpretation that they had measured, for the rst time, the speed
1
http://arxiv.org/abs/astro-ph/0302294
229
of gravity, and found it to be within 20% error bars of c. Samuel
2
and Will
3
published refutations, arguing that Kopeikins calcula-
tions contained mistakes, and that what had really been measured
was the speed of light, not the speed of gravity.
The reason that the interpretation of this type of experiment
is likely to be controversial is that although we do have theories of
gravity that are viable alternatives to general relativity (e.g., the
Brans-Dicke theory, in which the gravitational constant is a dynam-
ically changing variable), such theories have generally been carefully
designed to agree with general relativity in the weak-eld limit, and
in particular every such theory (or at least every theory that remains
viable given current experimental data) predicts that gravitational
eects propagate at c in the weak-eld limit. Without an alternative
theory to act as a framework one that disagrees with relativity
about the speed of gravity it is dicult to know whether an ob-
servation that agrees with relativity is a test of this specic aspect
of relativity.
8.2 Gravitational radiation
8.2.1 Empirical evidence
So we still dont know, a century after Einstein found the eld
equations, whether gravitational ripples travel at c. Nevertheless,
we do have strong empirical evidence that such ripples exist. The
Hulse-Taylor system (page 182) contains two neutron stars orbiting
around their common center of mass, and the period of the orbit
is observed to be lengthening gradually over time, a. This is inter-
preted as evidence that the stars are losing energy to radiation of
gravitational waves.
4
More dramatic, if less clearcut, evidence is provided by Komossa,
Zhou, and Lus observationhttp://arxiv.org/abs/0804.4585 of a
supermassive black hole that appears to be recoiling from its parent
galaxy at a velocity of 2650 km/s (projected along the line of sight).
They interpret this as evidence for the following scenario. In the
early universe, galaxies form with supermassive black holes at their
centers. When two such galaxies collide, the black holes can merge.
The merger is a violent process in which intense gravitational waves
are emitted, and these waves carry a large amount of momentum,
causing the black holes to recoil at a velocity greater than the escape
velocity of the merged galaxy.
2
http://arxiv.org/abs/astro-ph/0304006
3
http://arxiv.org/abs/astro-ph/0301145
4
Stairs, Testing General Relativity with Pulsar Timing, http://
relativity.livingreviews.org/Articles/lrr-2003-5/
230 Chapter 8 Gravitational Waves
a / The Hulse-Taylor pulsars or-
bital motion is gradually losing
energy due to the emission of
gravitational waves. The linear
decrease of the period is inte-
grated on this plot, resulting in
a parabola. From Weisberg and
Taylor, http://arxiv.org/abs/
astro-ph/0211217.
8.2.2 Expected properties
To see what properties we should expect for such radiation, rst
consider the reasoning that led to the construction of the Ricci and
Einstein tensors. If a certain volume of space is lled with test
particles, then the Ricci and Einstein tensors measure the tendency
for this volume to accelerate; i.e., d
2
V/dt
2
is a measure of the
attraction of any mass lying inside the volume. A distant mass,
however, will exert only tidal forces, which distort a region without
changing its volume. This suggests that as a gravitational wave
passes through a certain region of space, it should distort the shape
of a given region, without changing its volume.
When the idea of gravitational waves was rst discussed, there
was some skepticism about whether they represented an eect that
was observable, even in principle. The most naive such doubt is of
the same avor as the one discussed in section 7.2.3 about the ob-
servability of the universes expansion: if everything distorts, then
Section 8.2 Gravitational radiation 231
b / As the gravitational wave
propagates in the z direction, the
metric oscillates in the x and y
directions, preserving volume.
dont our meter-sticks distort as well, making it impossible to mea-
sure the eect? The answer is the same as before in section 7.2.3;
systems that are gravitationally or electromagnetically bound do
not have their scales distorted by an amount equal to the change in
the elements of the metric.
A less naive reason to be skeptical about gravitational waves is
that just because a metric looks oscillatory, that doesnt mean its
oscillatory behavior is observable. Consider the following example.
ds
2
= dt
2
_
1 +
1
10
sin x
_
dx
2
dy
2
dz
2
The Christoel symbols depend on derivatives of the form
a
g
bc
, so
here the only nonvanishing Christoel symbol is
x
xx
. It is then
straightforward to check that the Riemann tensor R
a
bcd
=
c
a
db
a
cb
+
a
ce
e
db
a
de
e
cb
vanishes by symmetry. Therefore this
metric must really just be a at-spacetime metric that has been
subjected to a silly change of coordinates.
Self-check: Do the Christoel symbols vanish for this metric?
Is there a reason for paying more attention to one or the other, R
or ?
To keep the curvature from vanishing, it looks like we need a
metric in which the oscillation is not restricted to a single variable.
For example, the metric
ds
2
= dt
2
_
1 +
1
10
sin y
_
dx
2
dy
2
dz
2
does have nonvanishing curvature. In other words, it seems like
we should be looking for transverse waves rather than longitudinal
ones.
5
On the other hand, this metric cannot be a solution to the
vacuum eld equations, since it doesnt preserve volume. It also
stands still, whereas we expect that solutions to the eld equations
should propagate at the velocity of light, at least for small ampli-
tudes. These conclusions are self-consistent, because a waves po-
larization can only be constrained if it propagates at c (see p. 107).
Based on what weve found out, the following seems like a metric
that might have a ghting chance of representing a real gravitational
wave:
ds
2
= dt
2
(1 +Asin(z t)) dx
2
dy
2
1 +Asin(z t)
dz
2
It is transverse, it propagates at c(= 1), and the fact that g
xx
is the
reciprocal of g
yy
makes it volume-conserving. The following Maxima
program calculates its Einstein tensor:
5
A more careful treatment shows that longitudinal waves can always be inter-
preted as physically unobservable coordinate waves, in the limit of large distances
from the source. Longitudinal waves near the source are referred to as Type III
solutions in a classication scheme due to Petrov. Transverse waves, which are
what we could actually observe in practical experiments, are type N.
232 Chapter 8 Gravitational Waves
1 load(ctensor);
2 ct_coords:[t,x,y,z];
3 lg:matrix([1,0,0,0],
4 [0,-(1+A*sin(z-t)),0,0],
5 [0,0,-1/(1+A*sin(z-t)),0],
6 [0,0,0,-1]);
7 cmetric();
8 einstein(true);
For a representative component of the Einstein tensor, we nd
G
tt
=
A
2
cos
2
(z t)
2 + 4Asin(z t) + 2A
2
sin
2
(z t)
For small values of A, we have [G
tt
[ A
2
/2. The vacuum eld
equations require G
tt
= 0, so this isnt an exact solution. But all
the components of G, not just G
tt
, are of order A
2
, so this is an
approximate solution to the equations.
It is also straightforward to check that propagation at approx-
imately c was a necessary feature. For example, if we replace the
factors of sin(z t) in the metric with sin(z 2t), we get a G
xx
that
is of order unity, not of order A
2
.
To prove that gravitational waves are an observable eect, we
would like to be able to display a metric that (1) is an exact solution
of the vacuum eld equations; (2) is not merely a coordinate wave;
and (3) carries momentum and energy. As late as 1936, Einstein and
Rosen published a paper claiming that gravitational waves were a
mathematical artifact, and did not actually exist.
6
8.2.3 Some exact solutions
In this section we study several examples of exact solutions to
the eld equations. Each of these can readily be shown not to be
a mere coordinate wave, since in each case the Riemann tensor has
nonzero elements.
An exact solution Example: 1
Weve already seen, e.g., in the derivation of the Schwarzschild
metric in section 6.2.4, that once we have an approximate solu-
tion to the equations of general relativity, we may be able to nd a
series solution. Historically this approach was only used as a last
resort, because the lack of computers made the calculations too
complex to handle, and the tendency was to look for tricks that
would make a closed-form solution possible. But today the series
method has the advantage that any mere mortal can have some
reasonable hope of success with it and there is nothing more
boring (or demoralizing) than laboriously learning someone elses
6
Some of the history is related at http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Sticky_
bead_argument.
Section 8.2 Gravitational radiation 233
special trick that only works for a specic problem. In this exam-
ple, well see that such an approach comes tantalizingly close
to providing an exact, oscillatory plane wave solution to the eld
equations.
Our best solution so far was of the form
ds
2
= dt
2
(1 + f ) dx
2
dy
2
1 + f
dz
2
,
where f = Asin(z t ). This doesnt seem likely to be an exact
solution for large amplitudes, since the x and y coordinates are
treated asymmetrically. In the extreme case of [A[ 1, there
would be singularities in g
yy
, but not in g
xx
. Clearly the metric will
have to have some kind of nonlinear dependence on f , but we just
havent found quite the right nonlinear dependence. Suppose we
try something of this form:
ds
2
= dt
2
_
1 + f + cf
2
_
dx
2
_
1 f + df
2
_
dy
2
dz
2
This approximately conserves volume, since (1+f +. . .)(1f +. . .)
equals unity, up to terms of order f
2
. The following program tests
this form.
1 load(ctensor);
2 ct_coords:[t,x,y,z];
3 f : A*exp(%i*k*(z-t));
4 lg:matrix([1,0,0,0],
5 [0,-(1+f+c*f^2),0,0],
6 [0,0,-(1-f+d*f^2),0],
7 [0,0,0,-1]);
8 cmetric();
9 einstein(true);
In line 3, the motivation for using the complex exponential rather
than a sine wave in f is the usual one of obtaining simpler ex-
pressions; as well see, this ends up causing problems. In lines 5
and 6, the symbols c and d have not been dened, and have not
been declared as depending on other variables, so Maxima treats
them as unknown constants. The result is G
t t
(4d + 4c 3)A
2
for small A, so we can make the A
2
term disappear by an appro-
priate choice of d and c. For symmetry, we choose c = d = 3/8.
With these values of the constants, the result for G
t t
is of order
A
4
. This technique can be extended to higher and higher orders
of approximation, resulting in an exact series solution to the eld
equations.
Unfortunately, the whole story ends up being too good to be true.
The resulting metric has complex-valued elements. If general rel-
ativity were a linear eld theory, then we could apply the usual
234 Chapter 8 Gravitational Waves
c / The sticky bead argument
for the reality of gravitational
waves. As a gravitational wave
with the appropriate polarization
passes by, the bead vibrates back
and forth on the rod. Friction cre-
ates heat. This demonstrates that
gravitational waves carry energy,
and are thus real, observable
phenomena.
technique of forming linear combinations of expressions of the
form e
+i ...
and e
i ...
, so as to give a real result. Unfortunately the
eld equations of general relativity are nonlinear, so the resulting
linear combination is no longer a solution. The best we can do is
to make a non-oscillatory real exponential solution (problem 2).
An exact, oscillatory, non-monochromatic solution Example: 2
Assume a metric of the form
ds
2
= dt
2
p(z t )
2
dx
2
q(z t )
2
dy
2
dz
2
,
where p and q are arbitrary functions. Such a metric would clearly
represent some kind of transverse-polarized plane wave traveling
at velocity c(= 1) in the z direction. The following Maxima code
calculates its Einstein tensor.
1 load(ctensor);
2 ct_coords:[t,x,y,z];
3 depends(p,[z,t]);
4 depends(q,[z,t]);
5 lg:matrix([1,0,0,0],
6 [0,-p^2,0,0],
7 [0,0,-q^2,0],
8 [0,0,0,-1]);
9 cmetric();
10 einstein(true);
The result is proportional to q/q + p/p, so any functions p and
q that satisfy the differential equation q/q + p/p = 0 will result
in a solution to the eld equations. Setting p(u) = 1 + Acos u, for
example, we nd that q is oscillatory, but with a period longer than
2 (problem 3).
An exact, plane, monochromatic wave Example: 3
Any metric of the form
ds
2
= (1 h)dt
2
dx
2
dy
2
(1 + h)dz
2
+ 2hdzdt ,
where h = f (z t )xy, and f is any function, is an exact solution of
the eld equations (problem 4).
Because h is proportional to xy, this does not appear at rst
glance to be a uniform plane wave. One can verify, however, that
all the components of the Riemann tensor depend only on z t ,
not on x or y. Therefore there is no measurable property of this
metric that varies with x and y.
8.2.4 Energy content
To show that these waves carry momentum and energy, we can
use the nonmathematical sticky bead argument (gure c), which
was originated by Feynman in 1957 and later popularized by Bondi.
Section 8.2 Gravitational radiation 235
d / The power emitted by a
multipole source of order m is
proportional to
2(m+1)
, when
the size of the source is small
compared to the wavelength. The
main reason for the depen-
dence is that at low frequencies,
the wavelength is long, so the
number of wavelengths traveled
to a particular point in space is
nearly the same from any point
in the source; we therefore get
strong cancellation.
We would next like to nd an expression for the energy of the
wave in terms of its amplitude. Alas, this was not meant to be.
It seems like it ought to be straightforward. We have such ex-
pressions in other classical eld theories. In electromagnetism, we
have energy densities +(1/8k)[E[
2
and +(1/2
o
)[B[
2
associated
with the electric and magnetic elds. In Newtonian gravity, we can
assign an energy density (1/8G)[g[
2
to the gravitational eld g;
the minus sign indicates that when masses glom onto each other,
they produce a greater eld, and energy is released.
In general relativity, however, the equivalence principle tells us
that for any gravitational eld measured by one observer, we can
nd another observer, one who is free-falling, who says that the local
eld is zero. It follows that we cannot associate an energy with the
curvature of a particular region of spacetime in any exact way. The
best we can do is to nd expressions that give the energy density (1)
in the limit of weak elds, and (2) when averaged over a region of
space that is large compared to the wavelength. These expressions
are not unique. There are a number of ways to write them in terms
of the metric and its derivatives, and they all give the same result
in the appropriate limit. The reader who is interested in seeing the
subject developed in detail is referred to Carrolls Lecture Notes on
General Relativity, http://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/?9712019.
8.2.5 Rate of radiation
How can we nd the rate of gravitational radiation from a system
such as the Hulse-Taylor pulsar?
Lets proceed by analogy. The simplest source of sound waves
is something like the cone of a stereo speaker. Since typical sound
waves have wavelengths measured in meters, the entire speaker is
generally small compared to the wavelength. The speaker cone is
a surface of oscillating displacement x = x
o
sin t. Idealizing such
a source to a radially pulsating spherical surface, we have an oscil-
lating monopole that radiates sound waves uniformly in all direc-
tions. To nd the power radiated, we note that the velocity of the
source-surface is proportional to x
o
, so the kinetic energy of the air
immediately in contact with it is proportional to
2
x
2
o
. The power
radiated is therefore proportional to
2
x
2
o
.
In electromagnetism, conservation of charge forbids the existence
of an oscillating electric monopole. The simplest radiating source is
therefore an oscillating electric dipole q = q
o
sin t. If the dipoles
physical size is small compared to a wavelength of the radiation,
then the radiation is an inecient process; at any point in space,
there is only a small dierence in path length between the positive
and negative portions of the dipole, so there tends to be strong
cancellation of their contributions, which were emitted with opposite
phases. The result is that the waves electromagnetic potential four-
236 Chapter 8 Gravitational Waves
vector (section 4.2.5) is proportional to q
o
, the elds to q
o
2
, and
the radiated power to q
2
o
4
. The factor of
4
can be broken down
into (
2
)(
2
), where the rst factor of
2
occurs for reasons similar
to the ones that explain the
2
factor for the monopole radiation
of sound, while the second
2
arises because the smaller is, the
longer the wavelength, and the greater the ineciency in radiation
caused by the small size of the source compared to the wavelength.
Since our universe doesnt seem to have particles with negative
mass, we cant form a gravitational dipole by putting positive and
negative masses on opposite ends of a stick and furthermore,
such a stick will not spin freely about its center, because its center
of mass does not lie at its center! In a more realistic system, such as
the Hulse-Taylor pulsar, we have two unequal masses orbiting about
their common center of mass. By conservation of momentum, the
mass dipole moment of such a system is constant, so we cannot have
an oscillating mass dipole. The simplest source of gravitational ra-
diation is therefore an oscillating mass quadrupole, Q = Q
o
sin t.
As in the case of the oscillating electric dipole, the radiation is sup-
pressed if, as is usually the case, the source is small compared to
the wavelength. The suppression is even stronger in the case of a
quadrupole, and the result is that the radiated power is proportional
to Q
2
o
6
.
The general pattern we have observed is that for multipole radi-
ation of order m (0=monopole, 1=dipole, 2=quadrupole), the radi-
ated power depends on
2(m+1)
. Since gravitational radiation must
always have m = 2 or higher, we have the very steep
6
depen-
dence of power on frequency. This demonstrates that if we want
to see strong gravitational radiation, we need to look at systems
that are oscillating extremely rapidly. For a binary system with un-
equal masses of order m, with orbits having radii of order r, we have
Q
o
mr
2
. Newtons laws give m
1/2
r
3/2
, which is essentially
Keplers law of periods. The result is that the radiated power should
depend on (m/r)
5
. In units with G = 1 and c = 1, power is unit-
less, so the units of this expression check out. Reinserting the proper
constants to give an equation that allows practical calculation in SI
units, we have
P = k
G
4
c
5
_
m
r
_
5
,
where k is a unitless constant of order unity.
For the Hulse-Taylor pulsar,
7
we have m 3 10
30
kg (about
one and a half solar masses) and r 10
9
m. The binary pulsar is
made to order our purposes, since m/r is extremely large compared
to what one sees in almost any other astronomical system. The
resulting estimate for the power is about 10
24
watts.
The pulsars period is observed to be steadily lengthening at a
7
http://arxiv.org/abs/astro-ph/0407149
Section 8.2 Gravitational radiation 237
rate of = 2.418 10
12
seconds per second. To compare this with
our crude theoretical estimate, we take the Newtonian energy of the
system Gm
2
/r and multiply by , giving 10
25
W, which checks to
within an order of magnitude. A full general-relativistic calculation
reproduces the observed value of to within the 0.1% error bars of
the data.
238 Chapter 8 Gravitational Waves
Problems
1 (a) Starting on page 21, we have associated geodesics with
the world-lines of low-mass objects (test particles). Use the Hulse-
Taylor pulsar as an example to show that the assumption of low
mass was a necessary one. How is this similar to the issues encoun-
tered on pp. 34 involving charged particles?
(b) Show that if low-mass, uncharged particles did not follow geodesics
(in a spacetime with no ambient electromagnetic elds), it would vi-
olate Lorentz invariance. Make sure that your argument explicitly
invokes the low mass and the lack of charge, because otherwise your
argument is wrong. Solution, p. 266
2 Show that the metric ds
2
= dt
2
Adx
2
Bdy
2
dz
2
with
A = 1 f +
3
8
f
2
25
416
f
3
+
15211
10729472
f
5
B = 1 +f +
3
8
f
2
+
25
416
f
3
15211
10729472
f
5
f = Ae
k(tz)
is an approximate solution to the vacuum eld equations, provided
that k is real which prevents this from being a physically realistic,
oscillating wave. Find the next nonvanishing term in each series.
3 Verify the claims made in example 2. Characterize the (some-
what complex) behavior of the function q obtained when p(u) =
1 +Acos u.
4 Verify the claims made in example 3 using Maxima. Although
the result holds for any function f, you may nd it more convenient
to use some specic form of f, such as a sine wave, so that Maxima
will be able to simplify the result to zero at the end. Note that when
the metric is expressed in terms of the line element, there is a factor
of 2 in the 2hdzdt term, but when expressing it as a matrix, the 2 is
not present in the matrix elements, because there are two elements
in the matrix that each contribute an equal amount.
Problems 239
Appendix 1: Excerpts from three papers by
Einstein
The following English translations of excerpts from three papers by Einstein were originally
published in The Principle of Relativity, Methuen and Co., 1923. The translation was by
W. Perrett and G.B. Jeery, and notes were provided by A. Sommerfeld. John Walker (www.
fourmilab.ch) has provided machine-readable versions of the rst two and placed them in the
public domain. Some notation has been modernized, British spelling has been Americanized,
etc. Footnotes by Sommerfeld, Walker, and B. Crowell are marked with initials. B. Crowells
modications to the present version are also in the public domain.
The paper On the electrodynamics of moving bodies contains two parts, the rst dealing
with kinematics and the second with electrodynamics. Ive given only the rst part here, since
the second one is lengthy, and painful to read because of the cumbersome old-fashioned notation.
The second section can be obtained from John Walkers web site.
The paper Does the inertia of a body depend upon its energy content?, which begins on
page 253, is very short and readable. A shorter and less general version of its main argument is
given on p. 111.
The foundation of the general theory of relativity is a long review article in which Einstein
systematically laid out the general theory, which he had previously published in a series of
shorter papers. The rst three sections of the paper give the general physical reasoning behind
coordinate independence, referred to as general covariance. It begins on page 255.
The reader who is interested in seeing these papers in their entirety can obtain them inex-
pensively in a Dover reprint of the original Methuen anthology.
On the electrodynamics of moving bodies
A. Einstein, Annalen der Physik 17 (1905) 891.
It is known that Maxwells electrodynamicsas usually understood at the present time
when applied to moving bodies, leads to asymmetries which do not appear to be inherent in
the phenomena.
8
Take, for example, the reciprocal electrodynamic action of a magnet and
a conductor. The observable phenomenon here depends only on the relative motion of the
conductor and the magnet, whereas the customary view draws a sharp distinction between the
two cases in which either the one or the other of these bodies is in motion. For if the magnet
is in motion and the conductor at rest, there arises in the neighbourhood of the magnet an
electric eld with a certain denite energy, producing a current at the places where parts of
the conductor are situated. But if the magnet is stationary and the conductor in motion, no
electric eld arises in the neighbourhood of the magnet. In the conductor, however, we nd an
electromotive force, to which in itself there is no corresponding energy, but which gives rise
assuming equality of relative motion in the two cases discussedto electric currents of the same
path and intensity as those produced by the electric forces in the former case.
Examples of this sort, together with the unsuccessful attempts to discover any motion of the
earth relative to the light medium, suggest that the phenomena of electrodynamics as well as
8
Einstein begins by giving an example involving electromagnetic induction, considered in two dierent frames
of reference. With modern hindsight, we would describe this by saying that a Lorentz boost mixes the electric
and magnetic elds, as described in section 4.2.4, p. 112. BC
240 Chapter 8 Gravitational Waves
of mechanics possess no properties corresponding to the idea of absolute rest.
9
They suggest
rather that, as has already been shown to the rst order of small quantities,
10
the same laws
of electrodynamics and optics will be valid for all frames of reference for which the equations
of mechanics hold good.
11
We will raise this conjecture (the purport of which will hereafter be
called the Principle of Relativity) to the status of a postulate, and also introduce another
postulate, which is only apparently irreconcilable with the former, namely, that light is always
propagated in empty space with a denite velocity c which is independent of the state of motion
of the emitting body.
12
These two postulates suce for the attainment of a simple and consistent
theory of the electrodynamics of moving bodies based on Maxwells theory for stationary bodies.
The introduction of a luminiferous ether will prove to be superuous inasmuch as the view
here to be developed will not require an absolutely stationary space provided with special
properties, nor assign a velocity-vector to a point of the empty space in which electromagnetic
processes take place.
The theory to be developed is basedlike all electrodynamicson the kinematics of the
rigid body, since the assertions of any such theory have to do with the relationships between
rigid bodies (systems of coordinates), clocks, and electromagnetic processes.
13
Insucient con-
sideration of this circumstance lies at the root of the diculties which the electrodynamics of
moving bodies at present encounters.
I. KINEMATICAL PART
1. Denition of Simultaneity
Let us take a system of coordinates in which the equations of Newtonian mechanics hold
good.
14
In order to render our presentation more precise and to distinguish this system of
coordinates verbally from others which will be introduced hereafter, we call it the stationary
9
Einstein knew about the Michelson-Morley experiment by 1905 (J. van Dongen, arxiv.org/abs/0908.1545),
but it isnt cited specically here. The 1881 and 1887 Michelson-Morley papers are available online at en.
wikisource.org. BC
10
I.e., to rst order in v/c. Experimenters as early as Fresnel (1788-1827) had shown that there were no eects
of order v/c due to the earths motion through the aether, but they were able to interpret this without jettisoning
the aether, my contriving models in which solid substances dragged the aether along with them. The negative
result of the Michelson-Morley experiment showed a lack of an eect of order (v/c)
2
. BC
11
The preceding memoir by Lorentz was not at this time known to the author. AS
12
The second postulate is redundant if we take the laws of electrodynamics and optics to refer to Maxwells
equations. Maxwells equations require that light move at c in any frame of reference in which they are valid, and
the rst postulate has already claimed that they are valid in all inertial frames of reference. Einstein probably
states constancy of c as a separate postulate because his audience is accustomed to thinking of Maxwells equations
as a partial mathematical representation of certain aspects of an underlying aether theory. Throughout part I of
the paper, Einstein is able to derive all his results without assuming anything from Maxwells equations other than
the constancy of c. The use of the term postulate suggests the construction of a formal axiomatic system like
Euclidean geometry, but Einsteins real intention here is to lay out a set of philosophical criteria for evaluating
candidate theories; he freely brings in other, less central, assumptions later in the paper, as when he invokes
homogeneity of spacetime on page 245. BC
13
Essentially what Einstein means here is that you cant have Maxwells equations without establishing position
and time coordinates, and you cant have position and time coordinates without clocks and rulers. Therefore even
the description of a purely electromagnetic phenomenon such as a light wave depends on the existence of material
objects. He doesnt spell out exactly what he means by rigid, and we now know that relativity doesnt actually
allow the existence of perfectly rigid solids (see p. 90). Essentially he wants to be able to talk about rulers that
behave like solids rather than liquids, in the sense that if they are accelerated suciently gently from rest and
later brought gently back to rest, their properties will be unchanged. When he derives the length contraction
later, he wants it to be clear that this isnt a dynamical phenomenon caused by an eect such as the drag of the
aether.
14
i.e., to the rst approximation.AS
Problems 241
system.
If a material point is at rest relative to this system of coordinates, its position can be dened
relative thereto by the employment of rigid standards of measurement and the methods of
Euclidean geometry, and can be expressed in Cartesian coordinates.
If we wish to describe the motion of a material point, we give the values of its coordinates
as functions of the time. Now we must bear carefully in mind that a mathematical description
of this kind has no physical meaning unless we are quite clear as to what we understand by
time. We have to take into account that all our judgments in which time plays a part are
always judgments of simultaneous events. If, for instance, I say, That train arrives here at 7
oclock, I mean something like this: The pointing of the small hand of my watch to 7 and the
arrival of the train are simultaneous events.
15
It might appear possible to overcome all the diculties attending the denition of time
by substituting the position of the small hand of my watch for time. And in fact such a
denition is satisfactory when we are concerned with dening a time exclusively for the place
where the watch is located; but it is no longer satisfactory when we have to connect in time
series of events occurring at dierent places, orwhat comes to the same thingto evaluate
the times of events occurring at places remote from the watch.
We might, of course, content ourselves with time values determined by an observer stationed
together with the watch at the origin of the coordinates, and coordinating the corresponding
positions of the hands with light signals, given out by every event to be timed, and reaching him
through empty space. But this coordination has the disadvantage that it is not independent of
the standpoint of the observer with the watch or clock, as we know from experience. We arrive
at a much more practical determination along the following line of thought.
If at the point A of space there is a clock, an observer at A can determine the time values
of events in the immediate proximity of A by nding the positions of the hands which are
simultaneous with these events. If there is at the point B of space another clock in all respects
resembling the one at A, it is possible for an observer at B to determine the time values of
events in the immediate neighbourhood of B. But it is not possible without further assumption
to compare, in respect of time, an event at A with an event at B. We have so far dened only
an A time and a B time. We have not dened a common time for A and B, for the latter
cannot be dened at all unless we establish by denition that the time required by light to
travel from A to B equals the time it requires to travel from B to A. Let a ray of light start
at the A time t
A
from A towards B, let it at the B time t
B
be reected at B in the direction
of A, and arrive again at A at the A time t
A
.
In accordance with denition the two clocks synchronize if
t
B
t
A
= t
A
t
B
.
We assume that this denition of synchronism is free from contradictions, and possible for
any number of points; and that the following relations are universally valid:
1. If the clock at B synchronizes with the clock at A, the clock at A synchronizes with the
clock at B.
15
We shall not here discuss the inexactitude which lurks in the concept of simultaneity of two events at approx-
imately the same place, which can only be removed by an abstraction.AS
242 Chapter 8 Gravitational Waves
2. If the clock at A synchronizes with the clock at B and also with the clock at C, the clocks
at B and C also synchronize with each other.
16
Thus with the help of certain imaginary physical experiments we have settled what is to
be understood by synchronous stationary clocks located at dierent places, and have evidently
obtained a denition of simultaneous, or synchronous, and of time. The time of an event
is that which is given simultaneously with the event by a stationary clock located at the place
of the event, this clock being synchronous, and indeed synchronous for all time determinations,
with a specied stationary clock.
In agreement with experience we further assume the quantity
2AB
t
A
t
A
= c,
to be a universal constantthe velocity of light in empty space.
It is essential to have time dened by means of stationary clocks in the stationary system,
and the time now dened being appropriate to the stationary system we call it the time of the
stationary system.
2. On the Relativity of Lengths and Times
The following reections are based on the principle of relativity and on the principle of the
constancy of the velocity of light. These two principles we dene as follows:
1. The laws by which the states of physical systems undergo change are not aected, whether
these changes of state be referred to the one or the other of two systems of coordinates in uniform
translatory motion.
2. Any ray of light moves in the stationary system of coordinates with the determined
velocity c, whether the ray be emitted by a stationary or by a moving body. Hence
velocity =
light path
time interval
where time interval is to be taken in the sense of the denition in 1.
Let there be given a stationary rigid rod; and let its length be l as measured by a measuring-
rod which is also stationary. We now imagine the axis of the rod lying along the axis of x of
the stationary system of coordinates, and that a uniform motion of parallel translation with
velocity v along the axis of x in the direction of increasing x is then imparted to the rod. We
now inquire as to the length of the moving rod, and imagine its length to be ascertained by the
following two operations:
(a) The observer moves together with the given measuring-rod and the rod to be measured,
and measures the length of the rod directly by superposing the measuring-rod, in just the same
way as if all three were at rest.
(b) By means of stationary clocks set up in the stationary system and synchronizing in
accordance with 1, the observer ascertains at what points of the stationary system the two
16
This assumption fails in a rotating frame (see p. 92), but Einstein has restricted himself here to an approxi-
mately inertial frame of reference.BC
Problems 243
ends of the rod to be measured are located at a denite time. The distance between these two
points, measured by the measuring-rod already employed, which in this case is at rest, is also a
length which may be designated the length of the rod.
In accordance with the principle of relativity the length to be discovered by the operation
(a)we will call it the length of the rod in the moving systemmust be equal to the length
l of the stationary rod.
The length to be discovered by the operation (b) we will call the length of the (moving)
rod in the stationary system. This we shall determine on the basis of our two principles, and
we shall nd that it diers from l.
Current kinematics tacitly assumes that the lengths determined by these two operations are
precisely equal, or in other words, that a moving rigid body at the epoch t may in geometrical
respects be perfectly represented by the same body at rest in a denite position.
We imagine further that at the two ends A and B of the rod, clocks are placed which syn-
chronize with the clocks of the stationary system, that is to say that their indications correspond
at any instant to the time of the stationary system at the places where they happen to be.
These clocks are therefore synchronous in the stationary system.
We imagine further that with each clock there is a moving observer, and that these observers
apply to both clocks the criterion established in 1 for the synchronization of two clocks. Let
a ray of light depart from A at the time
17
t
A
, let it be reected at B at the time t
B
, and reach
A again at the time t
A
. Taking into consideration the principle of the constancy of the velocity
of light we nd that
t
B
t
A
=
r
AB
c v
and t
A
t
B
=
r
AB
c +v
where r
AB
denotes the length of the moving rodmeasured in the stationary system. Observers
moving with the moving rod would thus nd that the two clocks were not synchronous, while
observers in the stationary system would declare the clocks to be synchronous.
So we see that we cannot attach any absolute signication to the concept of simultaneity, but
that two events which, viewed from a system of coordinates, are simultaneous, can no longer be
looked upon as simultaneous events when envisaged from a system which is in motion relative
to that system.
3. Theory of the Transformation of coordinates and Times from a Stationary System to
another System in Uniform Motion of Translation Relative to the Former
Let us in stationary space take two systems of coordinates, i.e., two systems, each of three
rigid material lines, perpendicular to one another, and issuing from a point. Let the axes of X
of the two systems coincide, and their axes of Y and Z respectively be parallel. Let each system
be provided with a rigid measuring-rod and a number of clocks, and let the two measuring-rods,
and likewise all the clocks of the two systems, be in all respects alike.
Now to the origin of one of the two systems (k) let a constant velocity v be imparted in
the direction of the increasing x of the other stationary system (K), and let this velocity be
communicated to the axes of the coordinates, the relevant measuring-rod, and the clocks. To
17
Time here denotes time of the stationary system and also position of hands of the moving clock situated
at the place under discussion.AS
244 Chapter 8 Gravitational Waves
any time of the stationary system K there then will correspond a denite position of the axes
of the moving system, and from reasons of symmetry we are entitled to assume that the motion
of k may be such that the axes of the moving system are at the time t (this t always denotes
a time of the stationary system) parallel to the axes of the stationary system.
We now imagine space to be measured from the stationary system K by means of the
stationary measuring-rod, and also from the moving system k by means of the measuring-rod
moving with it; and that we thus obtain the coordinates x, y, z, and , , respectively. Further,
let the time t of the stationary system be determined for all points thereof at which there are
clocks by means of light signals in the manner indicated in 1; similarly let the time of the
moving system be determined for all points of the moving system at which there are clocks at
rest relative to that system by applying the method, given in 1, of light signals between the
points at which the latter clocks are located.
To any system of values x, y, z, t, which completely denes the place and time of an event
in the stationary system, there belongs a system of values , , , , determining that event
relative to the system k, and our task is now to nd the system of equations connecting these
quantities.
In the rst place it is clear that the equations must be linear on account of the properties of
homogeneity which we attribute to space and time.
If we place x
= x vt, it is clear that a point at rest in the system k must have a system of
values x
, y, z, and t. To do this
we have to express in equations that is nothing else than the summary of the data of clocks
at rest in system k, which have been synchronized according to the rule given in 1.
From the origin of system k let a ray be emitted at the time
0
along the X-axis to x
, and at
the time
1
be reected thence to the origin of the coordinates, arriving there at the time
2
; we
then must have
1
2
(
0
+
2
) =
1
, or, by inserting the arguments of the function and applying
the principle of the constancy of the velocity of light in the stationary system:
1
2
_
(0, 0, 0, t) +
_
0, 0, 0, t +
x
c v
+
x
c +v
__
=
_
x
, 0, 0, t +
x
c v
_
.
Hence, if x
t
=
x
+
1
c v
t
,
or
+
v
c
2
v
2
t
= 0.
It is to be noted that instead of the origin of the coordinates we might have chosen any other
point for the point of origin of the ray, and the equation just obtained is therefore valid for all
values of x
, y, z.
An analogous considerationapplied to the axes of Y and Zit being borne in mind that
light is always propagated along these axes, when viewed from the stationary system, with the
velocity
c
2
v
2
gives us
Problems 245
y
= 0,
z
= 0.
Since is a linear function, it follows from these equations that
= a
_
t
v
c
2
v
2
x
_
where a is a function (v) at present unknown, and where for brevity it is assumed that at the
origin of k, = 0, when t = 0.
With the help of this result we easily determine the quantities , , by expressing in
equations that light (as required by the principle of the constancy of the velocity of light, in
combination with the principle of relativity) is also propagated with velocity c when measured
in the moving system. For a ray of light emitted at the time = 0 in the direction of the
increasing
= c or = ac
_
t
v
c
2
v
2
x
_
.
But the ray moves relative to the initial point of k, when measured in the stationary system,
with the velocity c v, so that
x
c v
= t.
If we insert this value of t in the equation for , we obtain
= a
c
2
c
2
v
2
x
.
In an analogous manner we nd, by considering rays moving along the two other axes, that
= c = ac
_
t
v
c
2
v
2
x
_
when
y
c
2
v
2
= t, x
= 0.
Thus
= a
c
c
2
v
2
y and = a
c
c
2
v
2
z.
Substituting for x
2
+
2
+
2
= c
2
2
.
The wave under consideration is therefore no less a spherical wave with velocity of propaga-
tion c when viewed in the moving system. This shows that our two fundamental principles are
compatible.
18
In the equations of transformation which have been developed there enters an unknown
function of v, which we will now determine.
For this purpose we introduce a third system of coordinates K
2
+
2
+
2
= c
2
2
.AS
19
In Einsteins original paper, the symbols (, H, Z) for the coordinates of the moving system k were introduced
without explicitly dening them. In the 1923 English translation, (X, Y, Z) were used, creating an ambiguity
between X coordinates in the xed system K and the parallel axis in moving system k. Here and in subsequent
references we use when referring to the axis of system k along which the system is translating with respect to
K. In addition, the reference to system K
of the system K
be zero. We
call the coordinates, measured in the system K
, x
, y
, z
= (v)(v)( +v/c
2
) = (v)(v)t,
x
= (v) = (v)(v)y,
z
= (v) = (v)(v)z.
Since the relations between x
, y
, z
are at rest with respect to one another, and it is clear that the transformation from K
to K
2
+
2
+
2
= R
2
.
The equation of this surface expressed in x, y, z at the time t = 0 is
x
2
(
_
1 v
2
/c
2
)
2
+y
2
+z
2
= R
2
.
A rigid body which, measured in a state of rest, has the form of a sphere, therefore has in a
state of motionviewed from the stationary systemthe form of an ellipsoid of revolution with
the axes
R
_
1 v
2
/c
2
, R, R.
Thus, whereas the Y and Z dimensions of the sphere (and therefore of every rigid body of no
matter what form) do not appear modied by the motion, the X dimension appears shortened
in the ratio 1 :
_
1 v
2
/c
2
, i.e., the greater the value of v, the greater the shortening. For v = c
all moving objectsviewed from the stationary systemshrivel up into plane gures.
21
For
velocities greater than that of light our deliberations become meaningless; we shall, however,
nd in what follows, that the velocity of light in our theory plays the part, physically, of an
innitely great velocity.
It is clear that the same results hold good of bodies at rest in the stationary system,
viewed from a system in uniform motion.
Further, we imagine one of the clocks which are qualied to mark the time t when at rest
relative to the stationary system, and the time when at rest relative to the moving system,
to be located at the origin of the coordinates of k, and so adjusted that it marks the time .
What is the rate of this clock, when viewed from the stationary system?
Between the quantities x, t, and , which refer to the position of the clock, we have, evidently,
x = vt and
=
1
_
1 v
2
/c
2
(t vx/c
2
).
Therefore,
20
That is, a body possessing spherical form when examined at rest.AS
21
In the 1923 English translation, this phrase was erroneously translated as plain gures. I have used the
correct plane gures in this edition.JW
Problems 249
= t
_
1 v
2
/c
2
= t (1
_
1 v
2
/c
2
)t
whence it follows that the time marked by the clock (viewed in the stationary system) is slow by
1
_
1 v
2
/c
2
seconds per second, orneglecting magnitudes of fourth and higher orderby
1
2
v
2
/c
2
.
From this there ensues the following peculiar consequence. If at the points A and B of K
there are stationary clocks which, viewed in the stationary system, are synchronous; and if the
clock at A is moved with the velocity v along the line AB to B, then on its arrival at B the
two clocks no longer synchronize, but the clock moved from A to B lags behind the other which
has remained at B by
1
2
tv
2
/c
2
(up to magnitudes of fourth and higher order), t being the time
occupied in the journey from A to B.
It is at once apparent that this result still holds good if the clock moves from A to B in any
polygonal line, and also when the points A and B coincide.
If we assume that the result proved for a polygonal line is also valid for a continuously curved
line, we arrive at this result: If one of two synchronous clocks at A is moved in a closed curve
with constant velocity until it returns to A, the journey lasting t seconds, then by the clock
which has remained at rest the travelled clock on its arrival at A will be
1
2
tv
2
/c
2
second slow.
Thence we conclude that a spring-clock at the equator must go more slowly, by a very small
amount, than a precisely similar clock situated at one of the poles under otherwise identical
conditions.
22
5. The Composition of Velocities
In the system k moving along the axis of X of the system K with velocity v, let a point move
in accordance with the equations
= w
, = w
, = 0,
where w
and w
denote constants.
Required: the motion of the point relative to the system K. If with the help of the equations
of transformation developed in 3 we introduce the quantities x, y, z, t into the equations of
motion of the point, we obtain
22
Einstein species a spring-clock (unruhuhr) because the eective gravitational eld is weaker at the equator
than at the poles, so a pendulum clock at the equator would run more slowly by about two parts per thousand
than one at the north pole, for nonrelativistic reasons. This would completely mask any relativistic eect, which
he expected to be on the order of v
2
/c
2
, or about 10
13
. In any case, Einstein later realized that he was mistaken
about this example. There is also a gravitational time dilation, which produces an eect in the opposite direction.
The two eects cancel out, as we can see by going into the frame that rotates with the earth. In this frame,
both clocks are at rest, so the kinematic time dilation vanishes. The earths surface is a surface of constant
gravitational potential , and the gtt component of the metric depends only on , so the gravitational time
dilation also vanishes. The two clocks in this example would actually agree.
250 Chapter 8 Gravitational Waves
x =
w
+v
1 +vw
/c
2
t,
y =
_
1 v
2
/c
2
1 +vw
/c
2
w
t,
z = 0.
Thus the law of the parallelogram of velocities is valid according to our theory only to a rst
approximation. We set
23
V
2
=
_
dx
dt
_
2
+
_
dy
dt
_
2
,
w
2
= w
2
+w
2
,
a = tan
1
w
/w
,
a is then to be looked upon as the angle between the velocities v and w. After a simple calculation
we obtain
V =
_
(v
2
+w
2
+ 2vwcos a) (vwsin a/c)
2
1 +vwcos a/c
2
.
It is worthy of remark that v and w enter into the expression for the resultant velocity in a
symmetrical manner. If w also has the direction of the axis of X, we get
V =
v +w
1 +vw/c
2
.
It follows from this equation that from a composition of two velocities which are less than c,
there always results a velocity less than c. For if we set v = c , w = c , and being
positive and less than c, then
V = c
2c
2c +/c
< c.
It follows, further, that the velocity of light c cannot be altered by composition with a
velocity less than that of light. For this case we obtain
V =
c +w
1 +w/c
= c.
We might also have obtained the formula for V, for the case when v and w have the same
direction, by compounding two transformations in accordance with 3. If in addition to the
systems K and k guring in 3 we introduce still another system of coordinates k
moving
parallel to k, its initial point moving on the axis of
24
with the velocity w, we obtain equations
23
This equation was incorrectly given in Einsteins original paper and the 1923 English translation as a =
tan
1
wy/wx.JW
24
X in the 1923 English translation.JW
Problems 251
between the quantities x, y, z, t and the corresponding quantities of k
= l
1
v
c
cos
_
1 v
2
/c
2
where c denotes the velocity of light. We shall make use of this result in what follows.
Let there be a stationary body in the system (x, y, z), and let its energyreferred to the
system (x, y, z) be E
0
. Let the energy of the body relative to the system (, , ) moving as
above with the velocity v, be H
0
.
Let this body send out, in a direction making an angle with the axis of x, plane waves
of light, of energy
1
2
L measured relative to (x, y, z), and simultaneously an equal quantity of
light in the opposite direction. Meanwhile the body remains at rest with respect to the system
(x, y, z). The principle of energy must apply to this process, and in fact (by the principle of
relativity) with respect to both systems of coordinates. If we call the energy of the body after
the emission of light E
1
or H
1
respectively, measured relative to the system (x, y, z) or (, , )
respectively, then by employing the relation given above we obtain
E
0
= E
1
+
1
2
L +
1
2
L,
H
0
= H
1
+
1
2
L
1
v
c
cos
_
1 v
2
/c
2
+
1
2
L
1 +
v
c
cos
_
1 v
2
/c
2
= H
1
+
L
_
1 v
2
/c
2
.
By subtraction we obtain from these equations
26
The principle of the constancy of the velocity of light is of course contained in Maxwells equations.AS
27
See homework problem 10, p. 126.
Problems 253
H
0
E
0
(H
1
E
1
) = L
_
1
_
1 v
2
/c
2
1
_
.
The two dierences of the form HE occurring in this expression have simple physical signica-
tions. H and E are energy values of the same body referred to two systems of coordinates which
are in motion relative to each other, the body being at rest in one of the two systems (system
(x, y, z)). Thus it is clear that the dierence H E can dier from the kinetic energy K of the
body, with respect to the other system (, , ), only by an additive constant C, which depends
on the choice of the arbitrary additive constants of the energies H and E. Thus we may place
H
0
E
0
= K
0
+ C,
H
1
E
1
= K
1
+ C,
since C does not change during the emission of light. So we have
K
0
K
1
= L
_
1
_
1 v
2
/c
2
1
_
.
The kinetic energy of the body with respect to (, , ) diminishes as a result of the emission
of light, and the amount of diminution is independent of the properties of the body. Moreover,
the dierence K
0
K
1
, like the kinetic energy of the electron ( 10), depends on the velocity.
Neglecting magnitudes of fourth and higher orders we may place
K
0
K
1
=
1
2
L
c
2
v
2
.
From this equation it directly follows that:
If a body gives o the energy L in the form of radiation, its mass diminishes by L/c
2
. The
fact that the energy withdrawn from the body becomes energy of radiation evidently makes no
dierence, so that we are led to the more general conclusion that
The mass of a body is a measure of its energy-content; if the energy changes by L, the mass
changes in the same sense by L/9 10
20
, the energy being measured in ergs, and the mass in
grammes.
It is not impossible that with bodies whose energy-content is variable to a high degree (e.g.
with radium salts) the theory may be successfully put to the test.
If the theory corresponds to the facts, radiation conveys inertia between the emitting and
absorbing bodies.
254 Chapter 8 Gravitational Waves
The foundation of the general theory of relativity
A. Einstein, Annalen der Physik 49 (1916) 769.
[A one-page introduction relating to history and personalities is omitted.BC]
A. FUNDAMENTAL CONSIDERATIONS ON THE POSTULATE OF RELATIVITY
1. Observations on the Special Theory of Relativity
The special theory of relativity is based on the following postulate, which is also satised by
the mechanics of Galileo and Newton. If a system of coordinates K is chosen so that, in relation
to it, physical laws hold good in their simplest form, the same laws also hold good in relation to
any other system of coordinates K
relative to K.
Thus the special theory of relativity does not depart from classical mechanics through the
postulate of relativity, but through the postulate of the constancy of the velocity of light in
vacuo, from which, in combination with the special principle of relativity, there follow, in the
well-known way, the relativity of simultaneity, the Lorentzian transformation and the related
laws for the behaviour of moving bodies and clocks.
The modication to which the special theory of relativity has subjected the theory of space
and time is indeed far-reaching, but one important point has remained unaected. For the laws of
geometry, even according to the special theory of relativity, are to be interpreted directly as laws
relating to the possible relative positions of solid bodies at rest; and, in a more general way, the
laws of kinematics are to be interpreted as laws which describe the relations of measuring bodies
and clocks. To two selected material points of a stationary rigid body there always corresponds
a distance of quite denite length, which is independent of the locality and orientation of the
body, and is also independent of the time. To two selected positions of the hands of a clock at
rest relative to the privileged system of reference there always corresponds an interval of time
of a denite length, which is independent of place and time. We shall soon see that the general
theory of relativity cannot adhere to this simple physical interpretation of space and time.
29
2. The Need for an Extension of the Postulate of Relativity
In classical mechanics, and no less in the special theory of relativity, there is an inherent
epistemological defect which was, perhaps for the rst time, clearly pointed out by Ernst Mach.
We will elucidate it by the following example:
30
Two uid bodies of the same size and nature
28
Here Einstein denes the distinction between special and general relativity according to whether accelerated
frames of reference are allowed. The modern tendency is to pose this distinction in terms of at versus curved
spacetime, so that accelerated frames of reference in at spacetime are considered to be part of special relativity.
None of this has anything to do with the ability to describe accelerated objects. For example, special relativity is
perfectly capable of describing the twin paradox.
29
Einstein is just starting to lay out his argument, and has not yet made clear in what sense these statements
about location-independence of clocks and rulers could be empirically tested. It becomes more clear later that
he means something like this. We could try to ll spacetime with a lattice of clocks and rulers, to synchronize
the clocks, and to construct the lattice so that it consisted of right angles and equal-length line segments. This
succeeds in special relativity, so that the geometry of spacetime is compatible with frames of reference that split
up spacetime into 3+1 dimensions, where the three dimensions are Euclidean. The same prescription fails in
general relativity.
30
This example was described on p. 96.
Problems 255
hover freely in space at so great a distance from each other and from all other masses that only
those gravitational forces need be taken into account which arise from the interaction of dierent
parts of the same body. Let the distance between the two bodies be invariable, and in neither
of the bodies let there be any relative movements of the parts with respect to one another.
But let either mass, as judged by an observer at rest relative to the other mass, rotate
with constant angular velocity about the line joining the masses. This is a veriable relative
motion of the two bodies. Now let us imagine that each of the bodies has been surveyed by
means of measuring instruments at rest relative to itself, and let the surface of S
1
prove to be a
sphere, and that of S
2
an ellipsoid of revolution. Thereupon we put the question What is the
reason for this dierence in the two bodies? No answer can be admitted as epistemologically
satisfactory,
31
unless the reason given is an observable fact of experience. The law of causality
has not the signicance of a statement as to the world of experience, except when observable
facts ultimately appear as causes and eects.
Newtonian mechanics does not give a satisfactory answer to this question. It pronounces as
follows: The laws of mechanics apply to the space R
1
, in respect to which the body S
1
is at
rest, but not to the space R
2
, in respect to which the body S
2
is at rest. But the privileged
space R
1
of Galileo, thus introduced, is a merely factitious
32
cause, and not a thing that can be
observed. It is therefore clear that Newtons mechanics does not really satisfy the requirement
of causality in the case under consideration but only apparently does so, since it makes the
factitious cause R
1
responsible for the observable dierence in the bodies S
1
and S
2
.
The only satisfactory answer must be that the physical system consisting of S
1
and S
2
reveals within itself no imaginable cause to which the diering behaviour of S
1
and S
2
can be
referred. The cause must therefore lie outside this system. We have to take it that the general
laws of motion, which in particular determine the shapes of S
1
and S
2
, must be such that the
mechanical behaviour of S
1
and S
2
is partly conditioned in quite essential respects, by distant
masses which we have not included in the system under consideration. These distant masses
and their motions relative to S
1
and S
2
must then be regarded as the seat of the causes (which
must be susceptible to observation) of the dierent behaviour of our two bodies S
1
and S
2
. They
take over the role of the factitious cause R
1
. Of all imaginable spaces R
1
, R
2
, etc., in any kind
of motion relative to one another there is none which we may look upon as privileged a priori
without reviving the above-mentioned epistemological objection. The laws of physics must be
of such a nature that they apply to systems reference in any kind of motion.
33
Along this road
we arrive at an extension at the postulate of relativity.
In addition to this weighty argument from the theory of knowledge, there is a well-known
physical fact which favours an extension of the theory of relativity. Let K be a Galilean system
of reference, i.e., a system relative to which (at least in the four-dimensional region under
consideration) a mass, suciently distant from other masses, is moving with uniform motion
in a straight line. Let K
.
This view is made possible for us by the teaching of experience as to the existence of a eld
of force, namely, the gravitational eld, which possesses the remarkable property of imparting
the same acceleration to all bodies.
34
The mechanical behaviour of bodies relative to K
is
the same as presents itself to experience in the case of systems which we are wont to regard
as stationary or as privileged. Therefore, from the physical standpoint, the assumption
readily suggests itself that the systems K and K
(x
, y
, z
, t
) in uniform rotation
36
relative to
K. Let the origins of both systems, as well as their axes of Z, permanently coincide. We shall
show that for a space-time measurement in the system K
, Y
plane of K
.
The notion of coordinates dened above, which presupposes the validity of Euclidean geometry,
therefore breaks down in relation to the system K
.
To convince ourselves of this impossibility, let us imagine two clocks of identical constitution
placed, one at the origin of coordinates, and the other at the circumference of the circle, and
both envisaged from the stationary system K. By a familiar result of the special theory of
relativity, the clock at the circumference judged from K goes more slowly than the other,
because the former is in motion and the latter at rest. An observer at the common origin
of coordinates, capable of observing the clock at the circumference by means of light, would
therefore see it lagging behind the clock beside him. As he will not make up his mind to let the
velocity of light along the path in question depend explicitly on the time, he will interpret his
observations as showing that the clock at the circumference really goes more slowly than the
clock at the origin. So he will be obliged to dene time in such a way that the rate of a clock
depends upon where the clock may be.
We therefore reach this result: In the general theory of relativity, space and time cannot
be dened in such a way that dierences of the spatial coordinates can be directly measured by
the unit measuring-rod, or dierences in the time coordinate by a standard clock.
The method hitherto employed for laying coordinates into the space-time continuum in a
denite manner thus breaks down, and there seems to be no other way which would allow us
to adapt systems of coordinates to the four-dimensional universe so that we might expect from
their application a particularly simple formulation of the laws of nature. So there is nothing for
it but to regard all imaginable systems of coordinates, on principle, as equally suitable for the
description of nature.
39
This comes to requiring that:
36
This example of a rotating frame of reference was discussed on p. 89.BC
37
Einstein implicitly assumes that the measuring rods are perfectly rigid, but it is not obvious that this is
possible. This issue is discussed on p. 94.
38
As described on p. 90, Ehrenfest originally imagined that the circumference of the disk would be reduced
by its rotation. His argument was incorrect, because it assumed the ability to start the disk rotating when it
had originally been at rest. The present paper marks the rst time that Einstein asserted the opposite, that the
circumference is increased.
39
This is a conceptual leap, not a direct inference from the argument about the rotating frame. Einstein started
thinking about this argument in 1912, and concluded from it that he should base a theory of gravity on non-
Euclidean geometry. Inuenced by Levi-Civita, he tried to carry out this project in a coordinate-independent way,
but he failed at rst, and for a while explored a theory that was not coordinate-independent. Only later did he
return to coordinate-independence. It should be clear, then, that the link between the rotating-frame argument
and coordinate-independence was not as clearcut as Einstein makes out here, since he himself lost faith in it for
258 Chapter 8 Gravitational Waves
The general laws of nature are to be expressed by equations which hold good for all the
systems of coordinates, that is, are covariant with respect to any substitutions whatever (generally
covariant).
40
It is clear that a physical theory which satises this postulate will also be suitable for the
general postulate of relativity.
41
For the sum of all substitutions in any case includes those
which correspond to all relative motions of three-dimensional systems of coordinates. That
this requirement of general covariance, which takes away from space and time the last remnant
of physical objectivity,
42
is a natural one, will be seen from the following reection. All our
space-time verications invariably amount to a determination of space-time coincidences.
43
If,
for example, events consisted merely in the motion of material points, then ultimately nothing
would be observable but the meetings of two or more of these points. Moreover, the results
of our measurings are nothing but verications of such meetings of the material points of our
measuring instruments with other material points, coincidences between the hands of a clock
and points on the clock-dial, and observed point-events happening at the same place at the same
time.
The introduction of a system of reference serves no other purpose than to facilitate the
description of the totality of such coincidences. We allot to the universe four space-time variables
x
1
, x
2
, x
3
, x
4
in such a way that for every point-event there is a corresponding system of values
of the variables x
1
. . . x
4
. To two coincident point-events there corresponds one system of values
of the variables x
1
. . . x
4
, i.e., coincidence is characterized by the identity of the coordinates.
If, in place of the variables x
1
. . . x
4
, we introduce functions of them, x
1
, x
2
, x
3
, x
4
, as a new
system of coordinates, so that the systems of values are made to correspond to one another
without ambiguity, the equality of all four coordinates in the new system will also serve as an
expression for the space-time coincidence of the two point-events. As all our physical experience
can be ultimately reduced to such coincidences, there is no immediate reason for preferring
certain systems of coordinates to others, that is to say, we arrive at the requirement of general
covariance.
a while.BC
40
In this book Ive used the more transparent terminology coordinate independence rather than general
covariance.BC
41
For more on this point, see p. 97.
42
This is an extreme interpretation of general covariance, and one that Einstein himself didnt hew closely to
later on. He presented an almost diametrically opposed interpretation in a philosophical paper, On the aether,
Schweizerische naturforschende Gesellschaft 105 (1924) 85.BC
43
i.e., what this book refers to as incidence measurements (p. 80)BC
Problems 259
Appendix 2: Hints and solutions
Hints
Hints for Chapter 1
Page 33, problem 5: Apply the equivalence principle.
Solutions to Selected Homework Problems
Solutions for Chapter 1
Page 33, problem 3:
Pick two points P1 and P2. By O2, there is another point P3 that is distinct from P1 and
P2. (Recall that the notation [ABC] was dened so that all three points must be distinct.)
Applying O2 again, there must be a further point P4 out beyond P3, and by O3 this cant be
the same as P1. Continuing in this way, we can produce as many points as there are integers.
Page 33, problem 4:
(a) If the violation of (1) is tiny, then of course Kip wont really have any practical way to
violate (2), but the idea here is just to illustrate the idea, so to make things easy, lets imagine an
unrealistically large violation of (1). Suppose that neutrons have about the same inertial mass as
protons, but zero gravitational mass, in extreme violation of (1). This implies that neutron-rich
elements like uranium would have a much lower gravitational acceleration on earth than ones
like oxygen that are roughly 50-50 mixtures of neutrons and protons. Lets also simplify by
making a second unrealistically extreme assumption: lets say that Kip has a keychain in his
pocket made of neutronium, a substance composed of pure neutrons. On earth, the keychain
hovers in mid-air. Now he can release his keychain in the prison cell. If hes on a planet, it
will hover. If hes in an accelerating spaceship, then the keychain will follow Newtons rst law
(its tendency to do so being measured by its nonzero inertial mass), while the deck of the ship
accelerates up to hit it.
(b) It violates O1. O1 says that objects prepared in identical inertial states (as dened by
two successive events in their motion) are predicted to have identical motion in the future. This
fails in the case where Kip releases the neutronium keychain side by side with a penny.
Page 33, problem 5: By the equivalence principle, we can adopt a frame tied to the tossed
clock, B, and in this frame there is no gravitational eld. We see a desk and clock A go by.
The desk applies a force to clock A, decelerating it and then reaccelerating it so that it comes
back. Weve already established that the eect of motion is to slow down time, so clock A reads
a smaller time interval.
Page 33, problem 6: (a) In case 1 there is no source of energy, so the particle cannot radiate.
In case 2-4, the particle radiates, because there are sources of energy (loss of gravitational energy
in 2 and 3, the rocket fuel in 4).
(b) In 1, Newton says the object is subject to zero net force, so its motion is inertial. In
2-4, he says the object is subject to a nonvanishing net force, so its motion is noninertial. This
matches up with the results of the energy analysis.
260 Chapter 8 Gravitational Waves
(c) The equivalence principle, as discussed on page 34, is vague, and is particularly dicult
to apply successful and unambiguously to situations involving electrically charged objects, due
to the diculty of dening locality. Applying the equivalence principle in the most naive way,
we predict that there can be no radiation in cases 2 and 3 (because the object is following a
geodesic, minding its own business). In case 4, everyone agrees that there will be radiation
observable back on earth (although its possible that it would not be observable to an observer
momentarily matching velocities with the rocket). The naive equivalence principle says that 1
and 4 must give the same result, so we should have radiation in 1 as well. These predictions are
wrong in two out of the four equations, which tells us that we had better either not apply the
equivalence principle to charged objects, or not apply it in such a naive way.
Page 34, problem 7:
(a) The dominant form of radiation from the orbiting charge will be the lowest-order non-
vanishing multipole, which in this case is a dipole. The power radiated from a dipole scales like
d
2
4
, where d is the dipole moment. For an orbit of radius r, this becomes q
2
r
2
4
. To nd
the reaction force on the charged particle, we can use the relation p = E/c for electromagnetic
waves (section 1.5.7), which tells us that the force is equal to the power, up to a proportionality
constant c. Therefore a
r
q
2
r
2
4
/m. The gravitational acceleration is a
g
=
2
r, so we have
a
r
/a
g
(q
2
/m)
2
r, or a
r
/a
g
(q
2
/m)a
g
, where the a
g
on the right can be taken as an orbital
parameter, and for a low-earth orbit is very nearly equal to the usual acceleration of gravity at
the earths surface.
(b) In SI units, a
r
/a
g
(k/c
4
)(q
2
/m)a
g
, where k is the Coulomb constant.
(c) The result is 10
34
. If one tried to do this experiment in reality, the eect would be
impossible to detect, because the proton would be aected much more strongly by ambient
electric and magnetic elds than by the eect weve calculated.
Remark: It is odd that the result depends on q
2
/m, rather than on the charge-to-mass ratio
q/m, as is usually the case for a test particles trajectory. This means that we get a dierent
answer if we take two identical objects, place them side by side, and consider them as one big
object! This is not as unphysical as it sounds. The two side-by-side objects radiate coherently,
so the eld they radiate is doubled, and the radiated power is quadrupled. Each objects rate
of orbital decay is doubled, with the extra eect coming from electromagnetic interactions with
the other objects elds.
Solutions for Chapter 2
Page 68, problem 1:
(a) Let t be the time taken in the lab frame for the light to go from one mirror to the other,
and t
= L, and (vt)
2
+L
2
= t
2
, where the
use of the same L in both equations makes use of our prior knowledge that there is no transverse
length contraction. Eliminating L, we nd the expected expression for , which is independent
of L (b) If the result of a were independent of L, then the relativistic time dilation would depend
on the details of the construction of the clock measuring the time dilation. We would be forced
to abandon the geometrical interpretation of special relativity. (c) The eect is to replace vt with
vt+at
2
/2 as the quantity inside the parentheses in the expression (. . .)
2
+L
2
= t
2
. The resulting
correction terms are of higher order in t than the ones appearing in the original expression, and
can therefore be made as small in relative size as desired by shortening the time t. But this is
Problems 261
exactly what happens when we make the clock suciently small.
Page 68, problem 2:
(a) Reinterpret gure i on p. 66 as a picture of a Sagnac ring interferometer. Let light waves
1 and 2 move around the loop in opposite senses. Wave 1 takes time t
1i
to move inward along
the crack, and time t
1o
to come back out. Wave 2 takes times t
2i
and t
2o
. But t
1i
= t
2i
(since
the two world-lines are identical), and similarly t
1o
= t
2o
. Therefore creating the crack has no
eect on the interference between 1 and 2, and splitting the big loop into two smaller loops
merely splits the total phase shift between them. (b) For a circular loop of radius r, the time
of ight of each wave is proportional to r, and in this time, each point on the circumference
of the rotating interferometer travels a distance v(time) = (r)(time) r
2
. (c) The eect is
proportional to area, and the area is zero. (d) The light clock in c has its two ends synchronized
according to the Einstein prescription, and the success of this synchronization veries Einsteins
assumption of commutativity in this particular case. If we make a Sagnac interferometer in the
shape of a triangle, then the Sagnac eect measures the failure of Einsteins assumption that all
three corners can be synchronized with one another.
Page 69, problem 4:
Here is the program:
1 L1:matrix([cosh(h1),sinh(h1)],[sinh(h1),cosh(h1)]);
2 L2:matrix([cosh(h2),sinh(h2)],[sinh(h2),cosh(h2)]);
3 T:L1.L2;
4 taylor(taylor(T,h1,0,2),h2,0,2);
The diagonal components of the result are both 1 +
2
1
/2 +
2
2
/2 +
1
2
+ . . . Everything after
the 1 is nonclassical. The o-diagonal components are
1
+
2
+
1
2
2
/2 +
2
2
1
/2 +. . ., with the
third-order terms being nonclassical.
Solutions for Chapter 3
Page 100, problem 1:
(a) As discussed in example 4 on page 79, a cylinder has local, intrinsic properties identical
to those of at space. The cylindrical model therefore has the same properties L1-L5 as our
standard model of Lorentzian space, provided that L1-L5 are taken as purely local statements.
(b) The cylindrical model does violate L3. In this model, the doubly-intersecting world-lines
described by property G will not occur if the world-lines are oriented exactly parallel to the
cylinder. This picks out a preferred direction in space, violating L3 if L3 is interpreted globally.
Frames moving parallel to the axis have dierent properties from frames moving perpendicular
to the axis.
But just because this particular model violates the global interpretation of L3, that doesnt
mean that all models of G violate it. We could instead construct a model in which space wraps
around in every direction. In the 2+1-dimensional case, we can visualize the spatial part of such
a model as the surface of a doughnut embedded in three-space, with the caveat that we dont
want to think of the doughnut holes circumference as being shorter than the doughnuts outer
radius. Giving up the idea of a visualizable model embedded in a higher-dimensional space,
we can simply take a three-dimensional cube and identify its opposite faces. Does this model
262 Chapter 8 Gravitational Waves
violate L3? Its not quite as obvious, but actually it does. The spacelike great-circle geodesics of
this model come in dierent circumferences, with the shortest being those parallel to the cubes
axes.
We cant prove by constructing a nite number of models that every possible model of G
violates L3. The two models weve found, however, can make us suspect that this is true, and
can give us insight into how to prove it. For any pair of world-lines that provide an example of
G, we can x a coordinate system K in which the two particles started out at A by ying o
back-to-back. In this coordinate system, we can measure the sum of the distances traversed by
the two particles from A to B. (If homegeneity, L1, holds, then they make equal contributions
to this sum.) The fact that the world-lines were traversed by material particles means that we
can, at least in principle, visit every point on them and measure the total distance using rigid
rulers. We call this the circumference of the great circle AB, as measured in a particular frame.
The set of all such circumferences has some greatest lower bound. If this bound is zero, then
such geodesics can exist locally, and this would violate even the local interpretation of L1-L5.
If the bound is nonzero, then lets x a circle that has this minimum circumference. Mark the
spatial points this circle passes through, in the frame of reference dened above. This set of
points is a spacelike circle of minimum radius. Near a given point on the circle, the circle looks
like a perfectly straight axis, whose orientation is presumably random. Now let some observer
K
travel around this circle at a velocity v relative to K, measuring the circumference with a
Lorentz-contracted ruler. The circumference is greater than the minimal one measured by K.
Therefore for any axis with a randomly chosen orientation, we have a preferred rest frame in
which the corresponding great circle has minimum circumference. This violates L3. Thanks to
physicsforums user atyy for suggesting this argument.
More detailed discussions of these issues are given in Bansal et al., arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/
0503070v1, and Barrow and Levin, arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/0101014v1.
Page 100, problem 4:
(a) No. The track is straight in the lab frame, but curved in the rotating frame. Since the
spatial metric in the rotating frame is symmetric with respect to clockwise and counterclockwise,
the metric can never result in geodesics with a specic handedness. (b) The d
2
term of the
metric blows up here. A geodesic connecting point A, at r = 1/, with point B, at r < 1/,
must have minimum length. This requires that the geodesic be directly radial at A, so that
d
, p
), with E
= f(1+v cos ), which agrees with Einsteins equation on page 253, except for the arbitrary
convention involved in dening the sign of v.
Solutions for Chapter 5
Page 162, problem 5:
(a) Expanding in a Taylor series, they both have g
tt
= 1 + 2gz +. . .
(b) This property holds for [2] automatically because of the way it was constructed. In [1],
the nonvanishing Christoel symbols (ignoring permutations of the lower indices) are
t
zt
= g
and
z
tt
= ge
2gz
. We can apply the geodesic equation with the ane parameter taken to be the
264 Chapter 8 Gravitational Waves
proper time, and this gives z = ge
2gz
t
2
, where dots represent dierentiation with respect to
proper time. For a particle instantaneously at rest,
t = 1/
g
tt
= e
2gz
, so z = g.
(c) [2] was constructed by performing a change of coordinates on a at-space metric, so it
is at. The Riemann tensor of [1] has R
t
ztz
= g
2
, so [1] isnt at. Therefore the two cant be
the same under a change of coordinates.
(d) [2] is at, so its curvature is constant. [1] has the property that under the transformation
z z + c, where c is a constant, the only change is a rescaling of the time coordinate; by
coordinate invariance, such a rescaling is unobservable.
Solutions for Chapter 6
Page 191, problem 3: (a) There are singularities at r = 0, where g
= 0, and r = 1/,
where g
tt
= 0. These are considered singularities because the inverse of the metric blows up.
Theyre coordinate singularities, because they can be removed by a change of coordinates back
to the original non-rotating frame.
(b) This one has singularities in the same places. The one at r = 0 is a coordinate singularity,
because at small r the dependence is negligible, and the metric is simply that of ordinary
plane polar coordinates in at space. The one at r = 1/ is not a coordinate singularity. The
following Maxima code calculates its scalar curvature R = R
a
a
, which is esentially just the
Gaussian curvature, since this is a two-dimensional space.
1 load(ctensor);
2 dim:2;
3 ct_coords:[r,theta];
4 lg:matrix([-1,0],
5 [0,-r^2/(1-w^2*r^2)]);
6 cmetric();
7 ricci(true);
8 scurvature();
The result is R = 6
2
/(1 2
2
r
2
+
4
r
4
). This blows up at r = 1/, which shows that this is
not a coordinate singularity. The fact that R does not blow up at r = 0 is consistent with our
earlier conclusion that r = 0 is a coordinate singularity, but would not have been sucient to
prove that conclusion.
(c) The argument is incorrect. The Gaussian curvature is not just proportional to the angular
decit , it is proportional to the limit of /A, where A is the area of the triangle. The area of
the triangle can be small, so there is no upper bound on the ratio /A. Debunking the argument
restores consistency with the answer to part b.
Solutions for Chapter 7
Page 227, problem 1:
(a) The Ricci tensor is R
tt
= g
2
e
2gz
, R
zz
= g
2
. The scalar curvature is 2g
2
, which is
constant, as expected.
(b) Both G
tt
and G
zz
vanish by a straightforward computation.
(c) The Einstein tensor is G
tt
= 0, G
xx
= G
yy
= g
2
, G
zz
= 0. It is unphysical because it has
Problems 265
a zero mass-energy density, but a nonvanishing pressure.
Page 227, problem 2:
The following Maxima code does the calculation:
1 load(ctensor);
2 ct_coords:[t,r,phi,z];
3 c: cos(sqrt(3)*r);
4 s: sin(sqrt(3)*r);
5 tt : exp(r)*c;
6 phit : exp(r)*s;
7 lg:matrix([tt,0,phit,0],
8 [0,-1,0,0],
9 [phit,0,-tt,0],
10 [0,0,0,-exp(-2*r)]
11 );
12 cmetric();
13 scurvature(); /* scalar curvature */
14 leinstein(true); /* Einstein tensor with lower indices, display=true */
Note that our denition of phit omits the factor of 2 from the line element, because were using
it to set two dierent o-diagonal elements of the metric, and we dont want to double-count.
The output of leinstein is silent, despite our setting the display ag to true; this is because
G
ab
s elements are all zero, and the function only outputs any nonzero elements. We can verify
this by explicitly asking for output of the components lein[1,1], etc.
Maxima computes the scalar curvature R and outputs it, but isnt smart enough to simplify
it completely. It is smart enough, however, to show us that it does not depend on t, , or z. A
good way to get around this problem is to expand R in a Taylor series as a function of r. For
example, a call to taylor(scurvature(),r,0,12) shows that the rst 12 terms of the Taylor
series all vanish.
Solutions for Chapter 8
Page 239, problem 1: (a) The members of the Hulse-Taylor system are spiraling toward one
another as they lose energy to gravitational radiation. If one of them were replaced with a
low-mass test particle, there would be negligible radiation, and the motion would no longer be
a spiral. This is similar to the issues encountered on pp. 34 because the neutron stars in the
Hulse-Taylor system suer a back-reaction from their own gravitational radiation.
(b) If this occurred, then the particles world-line would be displaced in space relative to a
geodesic of the spacetime that would have existed without the presence of the particle. What
would determine the direction of that displacement? It cant be determined by properties of
this preexisting, ambient spacetime, because the Riemann tensor is that spacetimes only local,
intrinsic, observable property. At a xed point in spacetime, the Riemann tensor is even under
spatial reection, so theres no way it can distinguish a certain direction in space from the
opposite direction.
What else could determine this mysterious displacement? By assumption, its not deter-
mined by a preexisting, ambient electromagnetic eld. If the particle had charge, the direction
266 Chapter 8 Gravitational Waves
could be one imposed by the back-reaction from the electromagnetic radiation it had emitted
in the past. If the particle had a lot of mass, then we could have something similar with gravi-
tational radiation, or some other nonlinear interaction of the particles gravitational eld with
the ambient eld. But these nonlinear or back-reaction eects are proportional to q
2
and m
2
,
so they vanish when q = 0 and m 0.
The only remaining possibility is that the result violates the symmetry of space expressed by
L1 on p. 40; the Lorentzian geometry is the result of L1-L5, so violating L1 should be considered
a violation of Lorentz invariance.
Problems 267
Photo Credits
Cover Galactic center: NASA, ESA, SSC, CXC, and STScI 15 Atomic clock: USNO
ocial photograph, public domain. 17 Gravity Probe A: I believe this diagram to be pub-
lic domain, due to its age and the improbability of its copyright having been renewed. 20
Stephen Hawking: unknown NASA photographer, 1999, public-domain product of NASA. 22
Eotvos: Unknown source. Since Eotvos died in 1919, the painting itself would be public do-
main if done from life. Under U.S. law, this makes photographic reproductions of the painting
public domain. 24 Earth: NASA, Apollo 17. Public domain. 24 Orion: Wikipedia user
Mouser, GFDL. 24 M100: European Southern Observatory, CC-BY-SA. 24 Supercluster:
Wikipedia user Azcolvin429, CC-BY-SA. 32 Pound and Rebka photo: Harvard University. I
presume this photo to be in the public domain, since it is unlikely to have had its copyright re-
newed. 35 Lorentz: Jan Veth (1864-1925), public domain. 47 Muon storage ring at CERN:
(c) 1974 by CERN; used here under the U.S. fair use doctrine. 50 Galaxies: Hubble Space
Telescope. Hubble material is copyright-free and may be freely used as in the public domain
without fee, on the condition that NASA and ESA is credited as the source of the material. The
material was created for NASA by STScI under Contract NAS5-26555 and for ESA by the Hub-
ble European Space Agency Information Centre. 54 Gamma-Ray burst: NASA/Swift/Mary
Pat Hrybyk-Keith and John Jones. 75 Levi-Civita: Believed to be public domain. Source:
http://www-history.mcs.st-and.ac.uk/PictDisplay/Levi-Civita.html. 78 Einsteins
ring: I have lost the information about the source of this image. I would be grateful to anyone
who could put me in touch with the copyright owners. 99 SU Aurigaes eld lines: P. Petit,
GFDL 1.2. 95 Galaxies: Hubble Space Telescope. Hubble material is copyright-free and may
be freely used as in the public domain without fee, on the condition that NASA and ESA is cred-
ited as the source of the material. The material was created for NASA by STScI under Contract
NAS5-26555 and for ESA by the Hubble European Space Agency Information Centre. 120
Chandrasekhar: University of Chicago. I believe the use of this photo in this book falls under the
fair use exception to copyright in the U.S. 123 Relativistic jet: Biretta et al., NASA/ESA, pub-
lic domain. 129 Rocks: Siim Sepp, CC-BY-SA 3.0. 130 Jupiter and comet: Hubble Space
Telescope, NASA, public domain. 131 Earth: NASA, Apollo 17. Public domain. 131
Moon: Luc Viatour, CC-BY-SA 3.0. 132 Heliotrope: ca. 1878, public domain. 132 Tri-
angulation survey: Otto Lueger, 1904, public domain. 136 Triangle in a space with negative
curvature: Wikipedia user Kie, public domain. 141 Eclipse: Eddingtons original 1919 photo,
public domain. 154 Torsion pendulum: University of Washington Eot-Wash group, http:
//www.npl.washington.edu/eotwash/publications/pdf/lowfrontier2.pdf. 165 Coin:
Kurt Wirth, public-domain product of the Swiss government. 168 Bill Unruh: Wikipedia user
Childrenofthedragon, public domain. 187 Accretion disk: Public-domain product of NASA
and ESA. 219 Cosmic microwave background image: NASA/WMAP Science Team, public
domain. 225 Dickes apparatus: Dicke, 1967. Used under the US fair-use doctrine.. ??
Graph of pulsars period: Weisberg and Taylor, http://arxiv.org/abs/astro-ph/0211217.
268 Chapter 8 Gravitational Waves
Index
absolute geometry, 18
abstract index notation, 85
Adams, W.S., 16
ane geometry, 37
ane parameter, 38
Aharonov-Bohm eect, 160
angular defect, 133
antisymmetrization, 84
Aristotelian logic, 53
atomic clocks, 14, 59
background independence, 98
Bell, John, 51
spaceship paradox, 51, 163
Big Bang, 206
Big Crunch, 78
Birkhos theorem, 222
black body spectrum, 168
Bohr model, 67
boost, 41
Brans-Dicke theory, 28, 221, 230
cadabra, 157, 159
Cartan, 154
curved-spacetime theory of Newtonian grav-
ity, 35, 97, 131
Casimir eect, 203
Cerenkov radiation, 118
Chandrasekhar limit, 120
Chiaos paradox, 26, 29
Christoel symbol, 145
chronology protection conjecture, 20, 199
clock postulate, 68, 104
cloning of particles, 167
closed timelike curve, 199
comoving cosmological coordinates, 204
Compton scattering, 127
conformal cosmological coordinates, 204
connection, 73
coordinate independence, 81
coordinate singularity, 185
correspondence principle, 28, 30, 44, 170
cosmic censorship, 187
cosmic microwave background, 213
cosmic rays, 16
cosmological constant, 50, 202
cosmological coordinates
comoving, 204
conformal, 204
standard, 204
covariant derivative, 142, 143
in electromagnetism, 142, 143
in relativity, 143
ctensor, 171
Cygnus X-1, 187
dark energy, 25
dark matter, 221
de Sitter, 204
Willem, 67
deection of light, 140, 182
derivative
covariant, 142, 143
in electromagnetism, 142
in relativity, 143
Dirac sea, 107, 126
dual, 82
dust, 110, 197
Eotvos experiments, 22
Eddington, 140
Ehrenfests paradox, 90
Einstein eld equation, 202
Einstein tensor, 194
Einstein-Cartan theory, 154
electromagnetic potential four-vector, 113, 117
electromagnetic tensor, 117
electron capture, 120
elliptic geometry, 75
energy conditions, 199
violated by cosmological constant, 203
energy-momentum tensor, 132, 195
equiconsistency, 76
equivalence principle
accelerations and elds equivalent, 23
application to charged particles, 26, 29
no preferred eld, 118
spacetime locally Lorentzian, 25
Erlangen program, 89
ether, 55
event horizon, 165
extrinsic quantity, 79
Fermats principle, 113
ne structure constant, 67
frame dragging, 125, 197
frame of reference
inertial, 23
frame-dragging, 161
frequency four-vector, 111
Friedmann equations, 206
Friedmann-Robertson-Walker cosmology, 206
Godels theorem, 76
Godel, Kurt, 76
gauge transformation, 99, 142
Gaussian curvature, 134
Gell-Mann, Murray, 107
general covariance, 81
geodesic, 21
as world-line of a test particle, 21, 239
dierential equation for, 146
geodesic equation, 146
geodetic eect, 139, 175
geometrized units, 172
geometry
elliptic, 75
hyperbolic, 136
spherical, 76
Goudsmit, 67
GPS
frames of reference used in, 93
timing signals, 117
gravitational constant, 172
gravitational eld
uniform, 162, 195, 227
gravitational mass, 21
gravitational redshift, 29
gravitational waves
transverse nature, 232
Gravity Probe A, 16
Gravity Probe B, 59, 117
frame dragging, 125
geodetic eect calculated, 175
geodetic eect estimated, 139
group, 88
Hafele-Keating experiment, 14, 59
Hawking
Stephen, 20
hole argument, 95
Hubble constant, 218
Hubble, Edwin, 206
Hulse, R.A., 182
Hulse-Taylor pulsar, 182, 237
hyperbolic geometry, 136
inertial frame, 23
inertial mass, 21
information paradox, 167, 188
inner product, 88
intrinsic quantity, 79
isometry, 88
Kasner metric, 196
Lense-Thirring eect, 125, 197
Levi-Civita
Tullio, 97
Levi-Civita tensor, 152
light
deection by sun, 140, 182
light clock, 68
light cone, 49
lightlike, 49
logic
Aristotelian, 53
loop quantum gravity, 54
Lorentz boost, 41
lune, 78
Mossbauer eect, 31
Machs principle, 97, 193, 221
mass
gravitational, 21
inertial, 21
mass-energy, 106
Maxima, 61, 171
Mercury
orbit of, 174
metric, 83
Michelson-Morley experiment, 55
Minkowski, 35
model
mathematical, 76
muon, 16
270 Index
naked singularity, 188
neutrino, 108
neutron star, 120, 182
no-cloning theorem, 167
normal coordinates, 134
parallel transport, 73, 74
Pasch
Moritz, 19
Penrose, Roger, 85, 188
Penrose-Hawking singularity theorems, 200, 207
Penzias, Arno, 206
Petrov classication, 232
Petrov metric, 197, 227
photon
mass, 108
Pioneer anomaly, 211
Planck mass, 154
Planck scale, 154
Poincare group, 88
polarization
of gravitational waves, 232
of light, 107
Pound-Rebka experiment, 16, 29
principal group, 89
prior geometry, 98
projective geometry, 80
proper time, 103
pulsar, 121, 182
rank of a tensor, 84
rapidity, 51
redshift
gravitational, 16, 29
Ricci curvature, 131
dened, 138
Riemann tensor
dened, 137
Rindler coordinates, 162
ring laser, 58
Robinson
Abraham, 72, 77
rotating frame of reference, 89, 196
Sagnac eect, 92
dened, 58
in GPS, 46
proportional to area, 68
Schwarzschild
Karl, 169
singularity, 20, 187
naked, 188
singularity theorems, 200
Sirius B, 16
spacelike, 49
spaceship paradox, 51, 163
spherical geometry, 76
standard cosmological coordinates, 204
stress-energy tensor, 132
string theory, 154
surface of last scattering, 207
Susskind, Leonard, 189
symmetrization, 84
Tarski, Alfred, 76
Taylor, J.H., 182
tensor, 84, 115
antisymmetric, 84
rank, 84
symmetric, 84
transformation law, 115
Thomas
Llewellyn, 67
Thomas precession, 139, 175
timelike, 49
Tolman-Oppenheimer-Volko limit, 121
torsion, 149
tensor, 152
transverse polarization
of gravitational waves, 232
of light, 107
trapped surface, 200
triangle inequality, 88
Type III solution, 232
Type N solution, 232
Uhlenbeck, 67
uniform gravitational eld, 162, 195, 227
unitarity, 167, 188
units
geometrized, 172
velocity vector, 104
wavenumber, 111
white dwarf, 119
Wilson, Robert, 206
world-line, 21
Index 271
Euclidean geometry (page 18):
E1 Two points determine a line.
E2 Line segments can be extended.
E3 A unique circle can be constructed given any point as its center and any line segment as
its radius.
E4 All right angles are equal to one another.
E5 Parallel postulate: Given a line and a point not on the line, exactly one line can be drawn
through the point and parallel to the given line.
44
Ordered geometry (page 19):
O1 Two events determine a line.
O2 Line segments can be extended: given A and B, there is at least one event such that [ABC]
is true.
O3 Lines dont wrap around: if [ABC] is true, then [BCA] is false.
O4 Betweenness: For any three distinct events A, B, and C lying on the same line, we can
determine whether or not B is between A and C (and by statement 3, this ordering is
unique except for a possible over-all reversal to form [CBA]).
Ane geometry (page 37):
In addition to O1-O4, postulate the following axioms:
A1 Constructibility of parallelograms: Given any P, Q, and R, there exists S such that [PQRS],
and if P, Q, and R are distinct then S is unique.
A2 Symmetric treatment of the sides of a parallelogram: If [PQRS], then [QRSP], [QPSR],
and [PRQS].
A3 Lines parallel to the same line are parallel to one another: If [ABCD] and [ABEF], then
[CDEF].
Experimentally motivated statements about Lorentzian geometry (page 272):
L1 Spacetime is homogeneous and isotropic. No point has special properties that make it
distinguishable from other points, nor is one direction distinguishable from another.
L2 Inertial frames of reference exist. These are frames in which particles move at constant
velocity if not subject to any forces. We can construct such a frame by using a particular
particle, which is not subject to any forces, as a reference point.
44
This is a form known as Playfairs axiom, rather than the version of the postulate originally given by Euclid.
272 Index
L3 Equivalence of inertial frames: If a frame is in constant-velocity translational motion
relative to an inertial frame, then it is also an inertial frame. No experiment can distinguish
one inertial frame from another.
L4 Causality: Observers in dierent inertial frames agree on the time-ordering of events.
L5 No simultaneity: The experimental evidence in section 1.2 shows that observers in dierent
inertial frames do not agree on the simultaneity of events.
Statements of the equivalence principle:
Accelerations and gravitational elds are equivalent. There is no experiment that can
distinguish one from the other (page 23).
It is always possible to dene a local Lorentz frame in a particular neighborhood of space-
time (page 25).
There is no way to associate a preferred tensor eld with spacetime (page 118).
Index 273