This Content Downloaded From 52.172.200.163 On Sun, 19 Feb 2023 08:01:41 UTC
This Content Downloaded From 52.172.200.163 On Sun, 19 Feb 2023 08:01:41 UTC
This Content Downloaded From 52.172.200.163 On Sun, 19 Feb 2023 08:01:41 UTC
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
https://www.jstor.org/stable/762391?seq=1&cid=pdf-
reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
The Johns Hopkins University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to Human Rights Quarterly
Gayle Binion*
ABSTRACT
This paper explores the ways in which human rights might be understood if
women's experience were the foundation for the theorizing and enforc
ment. The argument is not that there is but one feminist perspective
indeed the title suggests that there might be many. Rather, it is argued tha
if one works from the life experiences most common to women, t
principles of human rights that would emerge would not necessarily reflect
the universe of such rights as they are commonly understood by libe
nation states. While the prototypic "human rights" case involves t
individual political activist imprisoned for the expression of his views o
political organizing, forms of oppression that do not fit the Bill of Righ
model of liberty are rarely recognized in international understandings
national asylum laws. These forms would include, inter alia, issues relat
to marriage, procreation, labor, property ownership, sexual repression, a
other manifestations of unequal citizenship that are routinely viewed
private, nongovernmental, and reflective of cultural difference.
Human Rights Quarterly 17 (1995) 509-526 ? 1995 by The Johns Hopkins Universi
8. Two caveats are important here. First is that the views of the sources of feminist
theorizing in law were and are very diverse. For example, while Gilligan clearly
addressed perceived differences in how men and women conceptualize moral issues
and dilemmas and Chodorow sought to explain identity and empathy as reflective of
gender-based rearing patterns, Epstein cautioned against making too much of "differ-
ence" and suggested that what men and women have in common far outdistances
perceived gender-distinctive characteristics. The second, and related, caveat is that the
theorizing in law, while influenced by developments in the social sciences and
humanities, is not entirely derivative. A legal scholarship of feminism took root in the
1970s and has flourished as a cross-fertilized but also independent enterprise.
9. UNITED NATIONS, THE WORLD'S WOMEN 1970-1990: TRENDS AND STATISTICS at 30 (1991). It might
also be noted that in the United States women are fewer than 1 percent of the CEOs of
the 500 largest corporations.
10. UNITED NATIONS OFFICE AT VIENNA CENTRE FOR SOCIAL DEVELOPMENT AND HUMANITARIAN AFFAIRS,
WOMEN IN POLITICS AND DECISION-MAKING IN THE LATE TWENTIETH CENTURY at 10, 58 (1992).
11. For analyses of these issues, see, e.g., Melissa Spatz, A "Lesser" Crime: A Comparative
Study of Legal Defenses for Men Who Kill Their Wives, 24 COLUM. J.L. & SOC. PROBS. 597
(1991); Lisa C. Stratton, Note: The Right to Have Rights, 77 MINN. L. REV. 195 (1992);
Grdinne De BOirca, Fundamental Human Rights and the Reach of EC Law, 13 OXFORD J.
LEGAL STUD. 283 (1993).
Feminist studies have more in common than the subject they stu
are a variety of other relatively common features. Feminist analysis
be contextual, experiential, and inductive. Whereas much social t
hierarchical, abstract, and deductive, the feminist starting poin
actual human experience and the implications of that experi
significant sense, it is more anthropological than philosophical,12
marked by what Bartlett calls "practical reasoning."" Because
experience is the source and the focus of the theorizing and inco
the diversity of women's lives is highly valued, grand theory i
eschewed, and absolutes are distinctly suspect.14 This renders f
theorizing necessarily self-consciously limited, tentative, and pro
A final unifying feature of feminist theory is that it is inextricably in
with contemporaneous social, political, and economic movement
law this is an especially prominent feature of the scholarship t
paralleled, influenced, and been influenced by, the movements
equality of women since the late 1960s. The interactive realms o
and political activist, often practiced but rarely openly respecte
quarters of academia, form, in the world of feminism, a natur
While to some such interaction raises questions about the "object
the scholarship, to many feminists the larger question is whether th
16. It must be noted of course that this debate about the appropriateness of involvemen
the practical consequences of one's academic work is limited almost exclusively to on
some of the social sciences. In academic medicine, as in business and law schools, a
well as, for example, in departments of archeology, music, dance, theater, or engineer
ing, to be involved in such activity is mainstream and expected.
17. See, e.g., CATHARINE A. MACKINNON, SEXUAL HARASSMENT OF WORKING WOMEN: A CASE OF SE
DISCRIMINATION (1979); Ann C. Scales, The Emergence of Feminist Jurisprudence: An Essay
95 YALE L.J. 1373 (1986); Smart, supra note 4. I might have added overwhelmingly
"male," but this is not true in all societies. While in the United States and Great Britai
women are fewer than 10 percent of the judiciary, in continental countries a
Scandinavia this is not the case.
18. Leslie J. Calman, Are Women's Rights "Human Rights" in WOMEN IN INT'L DEV.,
(Michigan State Univ. Working Paper No. 146, 1987).
19. I do not read Smart's critique, supra note 4, as necessarily condemnatory of public po
per se.
20. While the European Court of Justice and the European Court of Human Rights, as we
other similar regional international bodies, have developed some significant hum
rights law, albeit far more readily for men than for women (see, Marie Provine
Human Rights of Women: A Feminist Analysis (on file with the author); Rebecca J. C
International Human Rights Law Concerning Women: Case Notes and Comments
VAND. J. TRANSNAT'L L. 779 (1990)), the minimal volume of output, as well as the cl
27. See Hilary Charlesworth & Christine Chinkin, The Gender ofJus Cogen
63, 72-73 (1993) (suggesting that, despite the right to life and freedom
are incorporated within jus cogens in international human rights law,
the spheres in which these rights of women are most often jeopardize
28. PATEMAN, supra note 12; OKIN, supra note 12, at 110-33.
29. As a related matter, some states and, no doubt, many nonstate interests oppose the
International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights because of its material
quality, guaranteeing, inter alia, an adequate standard of living, free compulsory primary
education, and paid childbearing leave for women. The last provision is one of the
reasons why the United States, the only industrial democracy not to provide paid
maternity leave, has not yet ratified the treaty, which has been in effect since 1976.
30. Philip Alston, Conjuring up New Human Rights: A Proposal for Quality Control, 78 AM.
J. INT'L L. 607 (1984).
31. See AMNESTY INTERNATIONAL PUBLICATIONS, WOMEN IN THE FRONT LINE (1991), which clearly states
throughout the introductory section that Amnesty International's mandate is to free
prisoners of conscience and that its only focus is on state action. It was only in 1989 that
Human Rights Watch, an organization with a self-consciously broader mandate than
Amnesty International, first set up a Women's Rights Project. See Dorothy Q. Thomas,
Holding Governments Accountable by Public Pressure, in OURS B RIGHT, supra note 21,
at 83.
32. For example, Dorothy Q. Thomas & Michele E. Beasley, Domestic Violence as a Human
Rights Issue, 15 HUM. RTS. Q. 36, 43 (1993), while arguing for the inclusion of such
violence within the purview of human rights concerns, would do so only where it could
be demonstrated that the state's nonenforcement of its laws against violence was gender-
based and, therefore, an official act of sex discrimination.
33. Riane Eisler, Human Rights: Toward an Integrated Theory for Action, 9 HUM. RTs. Q
293 (1987).
34. It should be noted, of course, that while imprisonment and intimidation of a voter are
recognized human rights problems because of their close connection to the liberal
model of the free citizen, rape and battery, common dehumanizing experiences of
women, are not so defined by the international community, unless directly linked to
political acts of the state, such as war. See Anna H. Phelan, The Latest Political Weapon
in Haiti: Military Rapes of Women and Girls, L.A. TIMES, 5 June 1994, at M4; see also
Rape was Weapon of Serbs, U.N. Says, N.Y. TIMES, 20 Oct. 1993, at Al.
35. This approach to human rights, holding the private perpetrator directly responsible, is
one of the most difficult reforms to initiate within a system bent on the nation state as
defendant. There are, however, models of human rights that emerge from the Treaty of
Rome and European court decisions, which do include "private," albeit nonfamilial,
defendants.
40. See in this regard, Annie Bunting, Theorizing Women's Cultural Div
International Human Rights Strategies, 20 J.L. & Soc'Y 6 (1993); Kim
Alison D. Renteln, The Concept of Human Rights, 83 ANTHROPOS 34
Cultural Approach to Validating International Human Rights: The C
Tied to Proportionality, in HUMAN RIGHTS: THEORY AND MEASUREMENT 7 (Da
ed., 1988).
41. Marie-Aimed Helie-Lucas, Women Living Under Muslim Laws, in OUR
note 21, at 61. One might add to Helie-Lucas' examples of internatio
human rights within the context of alleged cultural difference the
Singapore of an American teenager convicted of vandalism.
42. Marsha A. Freeman, Women, Development and Justice: Using the Int
tion on Women's Rights, in OURS BY RIGHT, supra note 21, at 100.
43. Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination again
18 Dec. 1979, art. 5, G.A. Res. 34/180, U.N. GAOR, 34th Sess., Su
Doc. A/34/46 (1979).
44. Freeman, supra note 42.
A RESPONSIBILITY MODEL
One of the most interesting aspects of the debates within feminist juris
dence is the question of whether rights analysis, domestically or interna
50. Bunch, supra note 21, at 147. In the longer view, it may turn out that this event, th
successful worldwide organizing effort, will constitute a watershed in the interna
women's rights movement, and that the multiple strategies used successfully an
liaisons formed will have unexpected consequences.
51. Thomas, supra note 31, at 84.
52. See, e.g., Kim, supra note 22, at 82.
53. See, e.g., Charlotte Bunch, Women's Rights as Human Rights: Toward a Re-V
Human Rights, 12 HUM. RTS. Q. 486 (1990); Rebecca J. Cook, Women's Internat
Human Rights Law: The Way Forward, 15 HUM. RTS. Q. 230 (1993); M.
Governmental Interferences With Human Rights, 56 BRIT. Y.B. INT'L L. 25
54. GILLIGAN, supra note 5, at 54.
55. See, e.g., Sherry, supra note 3, at 582, 604; Schneider, supra note 3, a
56. One is regularly reminded that the UN Charter itself speaks to a c
"peoples," not states.
57. The vast majority of human rights principles are in fact already oriented t
(politically, socially, and economically) disempowered. Capitalist princip
rights of property holders, while extremely well protected by the existing wo
distinctly second-order within twentieth-century human rights discourse.
58. For example, CEDAW, the International Covenant on Civil and Political
International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights.