Solution Manual For Criminology Theories Patterns and Typologies 11th Edition by Siegel ISBN 1133049648 9781133049647
Solution Manual For Criminology Theories Patterns and Typologies 11th Edition by Siegel ISBN 1133049648 9781133049647
Solution Manual For Criminology Theories Patterns and Typologies 11th Edition by Siegel ISBN 1133049648 9781133049647
CHAPTER TWO
The Nature and Extent of Crime
CHAPTER OBJECTIVES
After reading this chapter, the student should be able to:
SUMMARY
Criminologists measure crime trends and rates using the Uniform Crime Report
(UCR), the National Crime Victimization Survey (NCVS), and self report surveys. These
are primary sources of crime data. Secondary sources, such as cohort research,
observational research, and meta-analysis, supplement primary data sources and are used
by criminologists to identify specific crime problems and trends, to examine the lives of
criminal offenders, and to assess the effectiveness of crime control efforts.
The Federal Bureau of Investigation publishes the UCR that contains data provided
by law enforcement agencies across the country. Once compiled, data are reported as Part
I and Part II crimes. Part I crimes include murder and nonnegligent manslaughter,
forcible rape, robbery, aggravated assault, burglary, larceny, motor vehicle theft and
arson. Part II crimes are all other offenses not included in Part I. Crime data in the UCR
are expressed three ways: as raw figures and arrests made, rates per 100,000 people, and
changes in the number and rate of crime over time. The main weaknesses impacting the
validity of the UCR are that not all crimes are reported, law enforcement practices that
distort reporting, and methodology issues. The FBI is looking to eventually replace the
UCR with the National Incident-Based Reporting System (NIBRS) that was started in
1982 and collects information on 22 categories and 46 specific offenses and includes
more comprehensive information than the UCR.
Instructor’s
Chapter 2: The
Manual
Nature and Extent of Crime
26
Instructor’s
Chapter 2: The
Manual
Nature and Extent of Crime
urban areas and in the southern and western United States. Although crime rates are highest
in inner city high poverty areas, there is little support for the idea that crime is
27
Instructor’s
Chapter 2: The
Manual
Nature and Extent of Crime
primarily a lower-class phenomenon. One reason may be that the methods used to
measure social class vary widely. A second reason may be that the association between
social class and crime may be more complex than a simple linear relationship.
Age is inversely related to crime – younger people commit more crime than their older
peers. Aging out refers to the process by which offenders reduce the frequency of their
offending behavior as they age. Aging out may be a function of the natural history of the
life cycle. Some criminologists contend that the population may contain different sets of
criminals: one group whose criminal behavior declines with age, another whose criminal
behavior remains constant through maturity.
Firearms play a dominant role in criminal activity and impact crime trends and
justice policy. The banning of firearms, even if only handguns, is controversial. Some
experts propose strict gun control, and there is research to suggest defensive gun use
deters crime. However, some criminologists question the benefits of carrying a handgun,
and research also shows that defensive gun use may be more limited than believed.
Primary and secondary sources of crime data confirm that male crime rates are
higher than those of females. Over the years, a variety of reasons have been given for this
phenomenon such as the masculinity hypothesis, the chivalry hypothesis, socialization
and development, and liberal feminist theory. Self-report studies indicate that the pattern
of female criminality is similar to that of male criminality. Recent data also indicate that
female crime rates are rising faster than male crime rates and that females are joining gangs
in record numbers.
Minorities are involved in a disproportionate share of criminal activity, and racial
differences in the crime rate remain an extremely sensitive issue. However, research
indicates no relationship between race and self-reported delinquency. Some of the
reasons for high minority levels of criminal activity may be true racial differences in the
crime rate, racial bias in justice processing including increases in social control that
police direct at minority group members (racial threat hypothesis), racism and
discrimination, institutional racism, economic disparity, social disparity, and family
dissolution. If social and economic obstacles are removed, convergence of majority and
minority crime rates is possible.
Most offenders commit a single crime and discontinue after arrest. Nevertheless, as
Wolfgang, Figlio, and Sellin found, there is a small group responsible for the majority of
all crimes. The offenders in this group are called chronic offenders or career criminals. The
chronic offender has been the central focus of crime control policy resulting in “get tough”
measures like “three strikes” and “truth in sentencing” legislation.
CHAPTER OUTLINE
I. Introduction
28
Another document from Scribd.com that is
random and unrelated content:
20,000 years ago as the end of glacial and the commencement of recent
or postglacial time. He bases his estimates on the sediments of the Yoldia
Sea in Sweden. His method consists in the actual counting of certain
seasonally-laminated clay layers, presumably left behind by the receding
ice sheet of the continental glacier. The melting is registered by annual
deposition, in which the thinner layers of finer sand from the winter
flows alternate with thicker layers of coarser material from the summer
flows. In warm years, the layers are thicker, in colder years they are
thinner, so that these laminated Pleistocene clays constitute a
thermographic as well as a chronological record. De Geer began his
study of Pleistocene clays in 1878, and in 1920 he led an expedition to
the United States, for the purpose of extending his researches. (Cf.
Science, Sept. 24, 1920, pp. 284-286.) At that time, he claimed to have
worked out the chronology of the past 12,000 years. His figure of 20,000
years for postglacial time, while very displeasing to that reckless foe of
scientific caution and conservatism, Henry Fairfield Osborn, tallies very
well with the estimates of Sollas and Wright. H. Obermaier, basing his
computation on Croll’s theory that glaciation is caused by variations in
the eccentricity of the earth’s orbit about the sun, which would bring
about protracted winters in the hemisphere having winter, when the earth
was farthest from the sun (with consequent accumulation of ice), gives
30,000 years ago as the date of the first appearance of man on earth.
Father Hugues Obermaier, it may be noted, like Abbé Henri Breuil, is
one of the foremost authorities on the subject of prehistoric Man. Both
are Catholic priests.
All such computations of the age of man are, of course, uncertain and
theoretical. Evolutionists calculate it in hundreds of thousands, and even
millions, of years. After giving such a table of recklessly tremendous
figures, Osborn has the hypocritical meticulosity to add that, for the sake
of precision (save the mark!) the nineteen hundred and some odd years
of the Christian era should be added to his figures. But, even according
to the most conservative scientific estimates, as we have seen, man is
said to have been in existence for 30,000 years, and the prevalence of
right-handedness among men is as old as the human race. One would
expect, then, to find modern man equipped with a gigantic right arm and
a dwarfed left arm. In other words, man should exhibit a condition
comparable to that of a lobster, which has one large and one small chela.
Yet, in spite of the fact that the comparative inaction of the human left
hand is supposed to have endured throughout a period of, at least, 30,000
years, this state of affairs has not resulted in the faintest trace of atrophy
or retrogression. Bones, muscles, tendons, ligaments, nerves, blood
vessels, and all parts are of equal size in both arms and both hands.
Excessive exercise may overdevelop the musculature of the right arm,
but this is an individual and acquired adaptation, which is never
transmitted to the offspring, e.g. the child of a blacksmith does not
inherit the muscular hypertrophy of his father. Disuse, therefore, has not
the efficacy which Lamarck and Darwin ascribed to it.
In fine, it must be recognized, once for all, that organisms are not-
molded on a Lamarckian basis of use, nor yet on a Darwinian basis of
selected utility. Expediency, in other words, is not the sole governing
principle of the organic world. Neither instinctive habitude nor the
struggle for existence succeeds in forcing structural adaptation of a
predictable nature. Animals with different organic structure have the
same instincts, e.g. monkeys with, and without, prehensile tails alike
dwell in trees; while animals having the same organic structure may have
different instincts, e.g. the rabbit, which burrows, and the hare, which
does not, are practically identical in anatomical structure. Again, some
animals are highly specialized for a function, which other animals
perform without specialized organs, as is instanced in the case of moles,
which possess a special burrowing apparatus, and prairie-dogs, which
burrow without a specialized apparatus. Any system of evolution, which
ignores the internal or hereditary factors of organic life and strives to
explain all in terms of the environmental factors, encounters an
insuperable obstacle in this remorseless resistance of conflicting facts.
Another flaw in the Darwinian argument from rudimentary organs is
that it confounds, in many cases, apparent, with real inutility (or absence
of function). Darwin and his followers frequently argued out of their
ignorance, and falsely concluded that an organ was destitute of a
function, merely because they had failed to discover its utility. Large
numbers, accordingly, of highly serviceable organs were catalogued as
vestigial or rudimentary, simply because nineteenth century science did
not comprehend their indubitable utility. With the advance of present-day
physiology, this list of “useless organs” is being rapidly depleted, so that
the scientific days of the rudimentary organ appear to be numbered. At
any rate, in arbitrarily pronouncing many important and functioning
organs to be useless vestiges of a former stage in the history of the race,
the Darwinians were not the friends of Science, but rather its reactionary
enemies, inasmuch as they sought to discourage further investigation by
their dogmatic decision that there was no function to be found. In so
doing, however, they were merely exploiting the ignorance of their times
in the interest of a preconceived theory, which whetted their appetite for
discovering, at all costs, the presence in man of functionless organs.
Their anxiety in this direction led them to consider the whole group of
organs constituting a most important regulatory and coördinative system
in man and other vertebrates as so many useless vestigial organs. This
system is called the cryptorhetic system and is made of internally-
secreting, ductless glands, now called endocrine glands. These glands
generate and instill into the blood stream certain chemical substances
called hormones, which, diffusing in the blood, produce immediate
stimulatory, and remote metabolic effects on special organs distant from
the endocrine gland, in which the particular hormone is elaborated. As
examples of such endocrine glands, we may mention the pineal gland
(epiphysis), the pituitary body (hypophysis), the thyroid glands, the
parathyroids, the islelets of Langerhans, the adrenal bodies (suprarenal
capsules), and the interstitial cells of the gonads. The importance of these
alleged useless organs is now known to be paramount. Death, for
instance, will immediately ensue in man and other animals, upon
extirpation of the adrenal bodies.
The late Robert Wiedersheim, it will be remembered, declared the
pineal gland or epiphysis to be the surviving vestige of a “third eye”
inherited from a former ancestor, in whom it opened between the parietal
bones of the skull, like the median or pineal eye of certain lizards, the
socket of which is the parietal foramen formed in the interparietal suture.
If the argument is based on homology alone, then the coincidence in
position between the human epiphysis and the median optic nerve of the
lizards in question has the ordinary force of the evolutionary argument
from homology. But when one attempts to reduce the epiphysis to the
status of a useless vestigial rudiment, he is in open conflict with facts; for
the pineal body is, in reality, an endocrine gland generating and
dispersing a hormone, which is very important for the regulation of
growth in general and of sexual development in particular. Hence this
tiny organ in the diencephalic roof, no larger than a grain of wheat, is not
a functionless rudiment, but an important functioning organ of the
cryptorhetic system. We have no ground, therefore, on this score for
inferring that our pineal gland functioned in former ancestors as a
median eye comparable to that of the cyclops Polyphemus of Homeric
fame.
In like manner, the pituitary body or hypophysis, which in man is a
small organ about the size of a cherry, situated at the base of the brain,
buried in the floor of the skull, and lying just behind the optic chiasma,
was formerly rated as a rudimentary organ. It was, in fact, regarded as
the vestigial remnant of a former connection between the neural and
alimentary canals, reminiscent of the invertebrate stage. “The
phylogenetic explanation of this organ generally accepted,” says Albert
P. Mathews, “is that formerly the neural canal connected at this point
with the alimentary canal. A probable and almost the only explanation of
this, though an explanation almost universally rejected by zoölogists, is
that of Gaskell, who has maintained that the vertebrate alimentary canal
is a new structure, and that the old invertebrate canal is the present neural
canal. The infundibulum, on this view, would correspond to the old
invertebrate œsophagus, the ventricle of the thalamus to the invertebrate
stomach, and the canal originally connected posteriorly with the anus.
The anterior lobe of the pituitary body could then correspond to some
glandular adjunct of the invertebrate canal, and the nervous part to a
portion of the original circumœsophageal nervous ring of the
invertebrates.” (“Physiological Chemistry,” 2nd ed., 1916, pp. 641, 642.)
This elaborate piece of evolutionary contortion calls for no comment
here. We are only interested in the fact that this wild and weird
speculation was originally inspired by the false assumption that the
hypophysis was a functionless organ. As a matter of fact, it is the source
of two important hormones. The one generated in its anterior lobe is
tethelin, a metabolic hormone, which promotes the growth of the body in
general and of the bony tissue in particular. Hypertrophy and
overfunction of this gland produces giantism, or acromegaly
(enlargement of hands, feet, and skull), while atrophy and underfunction
of the anterior lobe results in infantilism, acromikria (diminution of
extremities, i. e. hands, feet, head), obesity, and genital dystrophy (i. e.
suppression of secondary sexual characters). The posterior lobe of the
pituitary body constitutes, with the pars intermedia, a second endocrine
gland, which generates a stimulatory hormone called pituitrin. This
hormone stimulates unstriated muscle to contract, and thereby regulates
the discharge of secretions from various glands of the body, e. g. the
mammary glands, bladder, etc. Hence the hypophysis, far from being a
useless organ, is an indispensable one. Moreover, it is an integral and
important part of the cryptorhetic system.
The same story may be repeated of the thyroid glands. These consist
of two lobes located on either side of the windpipe, just below the larynx
(Adam’s apple), and joined together across the windpipe by a narrow
band or isthmus of their own substance. Gaskell homologized them with
a gland in scorpions, and Mathew says that, if his surmise is correct, “the
thyroid represents an accessory sexual organ of the invertebrate.” (Op.
cit., p. 654.) They are, however, endocrine glands, that generate a
hormone known as thyroxin, which regulates the body-temperature,
growth of the body in general, and of the nervous system in particular,
etc., etc. Atrophy or extirpation of these glands causes cretinism in the
young and myxoedema in adults. Without a sufficient supply of this
hormone, the normal exercise of mental powers in human beings is
impossible. The organ, therefore, is far from being a useless vestige of
what was formerly useful.
George Howard Parker, the Zoölogist of Harvard, sums up the case
against the Darwinian interpretation of the endocrine glands as follows:
“The extent to which hormones control the body is only just beginning to
be appreciated. For a long time anatomists have recognized in the higher
animals, including man, a number of so-called ductless glands, such as
the thyroid gland, the pineal gland, the hypophysis, the adrenal bodies,
and so forth. These have often been passed over as unimportant
functionless organs whose presence was to be explained as an
inheritance from some remote ancestor. But such a conception is far from
correct. If the thyroids are removed from a dog, death follows in from
one to four weeks. If the adrenal bodies are excised, the animal dies in
from two to three days. Such results show beyond doubt that at least
some of these organs are of vital importance, and more recent studies
have demonstrated that most of them produce substances which have all
the properties of hormones.” (“Biology and Social Problems,” 1914, pp.
43, 44.)
Even the vermiform appendix of the cæcum, which since Darwin’s
time has served as a classic example of a rudimentary organ in man, is,
in reality, not a functionless organ. Darwin, however, was of opinion that
it was not only useless, but positively harmful. “With respect to the
alimentary canal,” he says, “I have met with an account of only a single
rudiment, namely, the vermiform appendage of the cæcum. ... Not only is
it useless, but it is sometimes the cause of death, of which fact I have
lately heard two instances. This is due to small hard bodies, such as
seeds, entering the passage and causing inflammation.” (“Descent of
Man,” 2nd ed., ch. I, pp. 39, 40.) The idea that seeds cause appendicitis
is, of course, an exploded superstition, the hard bodies sometimes found
in the appendix being fecal concretions and not seeds—“The old idea,”
says Dr. John B. Deaver, “that foreign bodies, such as grape seeds, are
the cause of the disease, has been disproved.” (Encycl. Americana, vol.
2, p. 76.) What is more germane to the point at issue, however, is that
Darwin erred in denying the utility of the vermiform appendix. For,
although this organ does not discharge in man the important function
which its homologue discharges in grain-eating birds and also in
herbivorous mammals, it subserves the secondary function of lubricating
the intestines by means of a secretion from its muciparous glands.
Darwin gives the semilunar fold as another instance of a vestigial
organ, claiming that it is a persistent rudiment of a former third eyelid or
membrana nictitans, such as we find in birds. “The nictitating
membrane, or third eyelid,” he says, “with its accessory muscles and
other structures, is especially well developed in birds, and is of much
functional importance to them, as it can be rapidly drawn across the
whole eyeball. It is found in some reptiles and amphibians, and in certain
fishes as in sharks. It is fairly well developed in the two lower divisions
of the mammalian series, namely, in the monotremata and marsupials,
and in some higher mammals, as in the walrus. But in man, the
quadrumana, and most other mammals, it exists, as is admitted by all
anatomists, as a mere rudiment, called the semilunar fold.” (Op. cit., ch.
I, pp. 35, 36.) Here Darwin is certainly wrong about his facts; for the so-
called third eyelid is not well developed in the two lower divisions of the
mammalian series (i.e. the monotremes and the marsupials) nor in any
other mammalian type. “With but few exceptions,” says Remy Perrier,
“the third eyelid is not so complete as among the birds; (in the mammals)
it never covers the entire eye. For the rest, it is not really perceptible
except in certain types, like the dog, the ruminants, and, still more so, the
horse. In the rest (of the mammals) it is less developed.” (“Elements
d’anatomie comparée,” Paris, 1893, p. 1137.) Moreover, Darwin’s
suggestion leaves us at sea as to the ancestor, from whom our
“rudimentary third eyelid” has been inherited. His mention of birds as
having a well developed third eyelid is not very helpful, because all
evolutionists agree in excluding the birds from our line of descent. The
reptiles are more promising candidates for the position of ancestors, but,
as no trace of a third eyelid could possibly be left behind in the imperfect
record of the fossiliferous rocks (soft parts like this having but slight
chance of preservation), we do not really know whether the palæozoic
reptiles possessed this particular feature, or not. Nor can we argue from
analogy and induction, because not all modern reptiles are equipped with
third eyelids. Hence the particular group of palæozoic reptiles, which are
supposed to have been our progenitors, may not have possessed any third
eyelid to bequeath to us in the reduced and rudimentary form of the plica
semilunaris. If it be replied, that they must have had this feature, because
otherwise we would have no ancestor from whom we could inherit our
semilunar fold, it is obvious that such argumentation assumes the very
point which it ought to prove, namely: the actuality of evolution.
Rudiments are supposed to be a proof for evolution, and not, vice versa,
evolution a proof for rudiments.
Finally, the basic assumption of Darwin that the semilunar fold is
destitute of function is incorrect; for this crescent-shaped fold situated in
the inner or nasal corner of the eye of man and other mammals serves to
regulate the flow of the lubricating lacrimal fluid (which we call tears).
True this function is secondary compared with the more important
function discharged by the nictitating membrane in birds. In the latter,
the third eyelid is a pearly-white (sometimes transparent) membrane
placed internal to the real eyelids, on the inner side of the eye, over
whose surface it can be drawn like a curtain to shield the organ from
excessive light, or irritating dust; nevertheless, the regulation of the flow
of lacrimal humor is a real function, and it is therefore entirely false to
speak of the semilunar fold as a functionless rudiment.
The coccyx is likewise cited by Darwin as an example of an inherited
rudiment in man. “In man,” he says, “the os coccyx, together with certain
other vertebræ hereafter to be described, though functionless as a tail,
plainly represents this part in other vertebrate animals.” (Op. cit., ch. I, p.
42.) That it serves no purpose as a tail, may be readily admitted, but that
it serves no purpose whatever, is quite another matter. As a matter of
fact, it serves for the attachment of several small muscles, whose
functioning would be impossible in the absence of this bone. Darwin
himself concedes this; for he confesses that the four vertebræ of the
coccyx “are furnished with some small muscles.” (Ibidem.) We may,
therefore, admit the homology between the human coccyx and the tails
of other vertebrates, without being forced to regard the latter as a useless
vestigial organ. It may be objected that the attachment of these muscles
might have been provided for in a manner more in harmony with our
ideas of symmetry. To this we reply that Helmholtz criticized the human
eye for similar reasons, when he said that he would remand to his
workshop for correction an optical instrument so flawed with defects as
the human eye. But, after all, it was by the use of these selfsame
imperfect eyes that Helmholtz was enabled to detect the flaws of which
he complained. When man shall have fully fathomed the difficulties and
obstructions with which organic morphogeny has to contend in
performing its wonderful work, and shall have arrived at an elementary
knowledge of the general laws of morphogenetic mechanics, he will be
more inclined to admire than to criticize. It is a mistake to imagine that
the finite works of the Creator must be perfect from every viewpoint. It
suffices that they are perfect with respect to the particular purpose which
they serve, and this purpose must not be narrowly estimated from the
standpoint of the created work itself, but from that of its position in the
universal scheme of creation. All such partial views as the Helmholtzian
one are false views.
Another consideration which Darwin and his partisans have failed to
take into account is the possibility of an ontogenetic, as well as a
phylogenetic, explanation of rudimentary organs. That is to say,
rudimentary organs might, so far as a priori reasons are concerned, be
the now useless vestiges of organs formerly developed and functional in
the fœtus, and need not necessarily be interpreted as traces of organs that
functioned formerly in remote racial ancestors. That there should be such
things as special fœtal organs, which atrophy in later adult life, is a
possibility that ought not to excite surprise. During its uterine existence,
the fœtus is subject to peculiar conditions of life, very different from
those which prevail in the case of adult organisms—e.g. respiration and
the digestive process are suspended, and there is a totally different kind
of circulation. What, then, more natural than that the fœtus should
require special organs to adapt it to these special conditions of uterine
life? Such organs, while useful and functional in the earlier stages of
embryonic development, will, so soon as birth and maturity introduce
new conditions of life, become superfluous, and therefore doomed, in the
interest of organic economy, to ultimate atrophy and degeneration, until
nothing is left of them but vestigial remnants.
The thymus may be cited as a probable instance of such an organ. This
organ, which is located in front of the heart and behind the breastbone, in
the region between the two lungs, consists, at the period of its greatest
development in man, of a two-lobed structure, 5 cm. long and 4 cm.
wide, with a thickness of 6 mm. and a maximum weight of 35 grams. It
is supplied with numerous lymphoid cells, which are aggregated to form
lymphoid follicles (cf. Gray’s “Anatomy,” 20th ed., 1918, pp. 1273,
1274; Burton-Opitz’ “Physiology,” 1920, p. 964). This organ is a
transitory one, well developed at birth, but degenerating, according to
some authors, after the second year of life (cf. Starling’s “Physiology,”
3rd ed., 1920, p. 1245); according to others, however, not until the period
of full maturity, namely, puberty. (Cf. Gray’s “Anatomy,” loc. cit.) W. H.
Howell cites both opinions, without venturing to decide the matter (cf.
his “Physiology,” 8th ed., 1921, pp. 869, 870). It was at one time
classified as a rudimentary or functionless organ. Later on, however, it
was thought by certain observers to be an endocrine gland, yielding a
secretion important for the growth of young mammals. This took it out
of the class of useless vestigial organs, but the recent discovery that it is
indispensable to birds as furnishing a secretion necessary for the
formation of the tertiary envelopes (egg membrane and shell) of their
eggs, has tended to revive the idea of its being a vestigial organ inherited
from the lower vertebrates.
Thus Dr. Oscar Riddle, while admitting that the thymus gland in man
has some influence on the growth of the bones, contends that the newly-
discovered function of this gland in birds is much more important, since
without it none of the vertebrates, excepting mammals, could reproduce
their young. “It thus becomes clear,” he says, “that though the thymus is
almost without use in the human being, it is in fact a sort of ‘mother of
the race.’ The higher animals could not have come into existence without
it. For even while our ancestors lived in the water, it was the thymus of
these ancestors which made possible the production of the egg-envelopes
within which the young were cradled and protected until they were ready
for an independent life.” (Science, Dec. 28, 1923, Suppl. XIII, XIV.)
This conclusion, however, is far too hasty. For, even if we disregard as
negligible the minor function, that Riddle assigns to the thymus in man,
there remains another possibility, which H. H. Wilder takes into account,
namely, that the thymus may, in certain cases, be a temporary substitute
for the lymphatic vessels. Having called attention to certain determinate
channels found in some of the lower vertebrates, he tells us that these
“can well be utilized as adjuncts of the lymphatic system until their
function can be supplied by definite lymphatic vessels.” He then resumes
his discussion of the lymph nodules in mammals as follows: “Aside from
the solitary and aggregated nodules, both of which appear to be centers
of origin of lymphocytes, there are numerous other places in which the
cellular constituents of the blood are developed. Many of these, as in the
case of the aggregated nodules of the intestines, are developed within the
wall of the alimentary canal and are therefore endodermic in origin.
These include the tonsils, the thymus, and thyroid glands, the associated
epithelial bodies, and, perhaps, the spleen.... In their function as
formative nidi for the cellular elements of the blood these organs form
physiologically important auxiliaries to the vascular system as a whole,
but belong elsewhere in their anatomical developmental affinities.”
(“History of the Human Body,” 2nd ed., 1923, p. 395—italics mine.)
This being the case, it is much more reasonable to interpret the thymus
as an ontogenetic (embryonic), rather than a phylogenetic (racial)
rudiment. It has been observed that, in the case of reptiles which lack
definite lymphatic glands (which function in man as formative centers of
lymphocytes or white blood corpuscles), the thymus is extraordinarily
developed and abounds in lymphoid cells. It has also been observed that
the formation of lymphocytes in the lymphatic glands is regulated by the
digestive process; for, after digestion, the activity of these glands
increases and the formation of leucocytes is accelerated. Since, then, the
lymphatic glands appear to require the stimulus of the digestive process
to incite them to action, it is clear that in the fœtus, which lacks the
digestive process, the lymphatic glands will not be stimulated to action,
and that the task of furnishing lymphocytes will devolve upon the
thymus. After birth, the digestive process commences and the lymphatic
glands become active in response to this stimulus. As the function of
forming lymphocytes is transferred from the thymus to the lymphatic
glands, the former is gradually deprived of its importance, and, in the
interest of organic economy, it begins to atrophy, until, at the end of the
child’s second year, or, at latest, when the child has reached sexual
maturity, nothing but a reduced vestige remains of this once functional
organ. “The thymus,” says Starling, “forms two large masses in the
anterior mediastinum which in man grow up to the second year of life
and then rapidly diminish, so that only traces are to be found at puberty.
It contains a large amount of lymphatic tissue and is therefore often
associated with the lymphatic glands as the seat of the formation of
lymph corpuscles.... In certain cases of arrested development or of
general weakness in young people, the thymus has been found to be
persistent.” (“Physiology,” 3rd ed., 1920, p. 1245.)
In the light of these facts, it is utterly unreasonable to regard the
thymus as a practically useless rudiment inherited from the lower
vertebrates. “That they have an important function in the young animal,”
says Albert Mathews, “can hardly be doubted.” (“Physiological
Chemistry,” 1916, p. 675.) In fact, the peculiar nature of their
development in the young and their atrophy in the adult forces such a
conclusion upon us. The thymus, therefore, is, in all probability, an
ontogenetic, and not a phylogenetic, rudiment. It might conceivably be
exploited as a biogenetic recapitulation of a reptilian stage in man, just as
the so-called fish-kidney of the human embryo is exploited for
evolutionary interpretation. The principles by which such a view may be
refuted have been given previously. But, in any case, it is folly to
interpret the thymus as a rudiment in the racial, rather than embryonic
sense. Moreover, the possibility of an ontogenetic interpretation of
rudiments must not be restricted to the thymus, but must be accepted as a
general and legitimate alternative for the phylogenetic interpretation.
In the last place, it remains for us to consider the Darwinian argument,
based upon so-called rudimentary organs, from the standpoint of the
science of genetics. Darwin, as we have remarked elsewhere, was
ignorant of the non-inheritability of those inconstant individual
variations now known as fluctuations. He was somewhat perplexed,
when Professor L. Meyer pointed out the extreme variability in position
of the “projecting point” on the margin of the human ear, but he still
clung to his original contention that this “blunt point” was a surviving
vestige of the apex of the pointed ears found in donkeys and horses, etc.
“Nevertheless,” he says, “in some cases my original view, that the points
are vestiges of the tips of formerly erect and pointed ears, still seems to
be probable.” (“Descent of Man,” 2nd ed., ch. I, p. 34.) Darwin, as
Ranke points out, was mistaken in homologizing his famous “tubercule”
with the apex of bestial ears. “The acute extremity of the pointed animal
ear,” says this author, “does not correspond to this prominence
designated by Darwin, but to the vertex of the helix.” (“Der Mensch,” II,
p. 39.) The feature in question is, moreover, a mere fluctuation due to the
degree of development attained by the cartilage: hence its variability in
different human beings. In very extreme cases, fluctuations of this sort,
may be important enough to constitute an anomaly, and, as anomalies are
often interpreted as atavisms and reversions to a primitive type, it may be
well to advert to this subject here.
Dwight has an excellent chapter on anatomical variations and
anomalies. (Cf. “Thoughts of a Catholic Anatomist,” 1911, ch. IX.) He
tells us that “a thigh bone a little more bent, an ear a little more pointed,
a nose a little more projecting ... a little more or a little less of anything
you please—this is variation.” “An anatomical anomaly,” he says, “is
some peculiarity of any part of the body which cannot be expressed in
terms of more or less, but is distinctly new.” He divides the latter into
two classes, namely: those which consist in the repetition of one or more
elements in a series, e.g. the occurrence of supernumerary legs in an
insect, and those which consist in the suppression of one or more
elements in a series, e.g. the occurrence of eleven pairs of ribs in a man.
Variations and anomalies are fluctuational or mutational, according as
they are based on changes in the soma alone, or on changes in the germ
plasm. Variations, however, are more likely to be non-inheritable
fluctuations, and anomalies to be inheritable mutations. We shall speak
of the latter presently. In the meantime we may note that the main trouble
with interpreting these anatomical irregularities as “reversive” or
“atavistic” is that they would connect man with all sorts of quite
impossible lines of descent. “In my early days of anatomy,” says Dwight,
“I thought that I must be very ignorant, because I could not understand
how the occasional appearance in man of a peculiarity of some animal
outside of any conceivable line of descent could be called a reversion, as
it soon became the custom to call it.... It was only later that I grasped the
fact that the reason I could not understand these things was that there
was nothing to understand. It was sham science from beginning to end.”
(Op. cit., p. 209.) By way of anomaly, almost any human peculiarity can
occur in animals, and, conversely, any bestial peculiarity in man, but the
resemblance to man of an animal outside of the alleged line of human
descent represents a grave difficulty for the theory of evolution, and not
an argument in its favor.
The human body is certainly not a mosaic of heterogenetic organs, i.e.
a complex of structures inherited from any and every sort of animal,
whether extant or extinct; for such a vast number and variety of ancestors
could not possibly have coöperated to produce man. Prof. D. Carazzi, in
his Address of Inauguration in the Chair of Zoölogy and Comparative
Anatomy at the University of Padua, Jan. 20, 1906, excoriated with
scathing irony the sham Darwinian science, of which Dwight complains.
“But even in the serious works of pure science,” says the Italian
zoölogist, “we read, for example, that the over-development of the
postauricular muscles sometimes observed in man is an atavistic
reminiscence of the muscles of the helix of the ear of the horse and the
ass. And so far so good, because it gives evidence of great modesty in
recognizing as our ancestors those well-deserving and long-eared
quadrupeds. But this is not all; there appear at times in a woman one or
more anomalous mammary glands below the pectoral ones; and here,
too, they insist on explaining the anomaly as a reversion to type, that is,
as an atavistic reminiscence of the numerous mammary glands possessed
by different lower mammals; the bitch, for example....
“But the supernumerary mammary glands are not a reversion to type;
anomalous mammary glands may appear upon the median line, upon the
deltoid, and even upon the knee, regions far-distant from the ‘milk-line.’
So with regard to the postauricular muscles we must say that according
to the laws of Darwinism the cases of anomalous development are not
interpretable as reversions to type. All these features are not
phylogenetic reminiscences, but anomalies of development, of such a
nature that, if we should wish to make use of them for establishing the
line of human descent, we would have to say that man descends from the
swine, from the solipeds and even from the cetaceans, returning, namely,
to the old conception of lineal descent, that is, to Buffon’s idea of the
concatenation of creatures.” (“Teorie e critiche nella moderna biologia,”
1906.)
Darwin’s doctrine, however, on the origin and significance of
rudimentary organs has been damaged by genetic analysis in a yet more
serious fashion. In fact, with the discovery that anomalous suppression
and anomalous duplication of organs may result from factorial mutation,
this Darwinian conception received what is tantamount to its deathblow.
Darwin, it will be remembered, was convinced that the regression of
organs was brought about by “increased disuse controlled by natural
selection.” (Cf. “Origin of Species,” 6th ed., ch. V.) Such phenomena, he
thought, as the suppression of wings in the Apteryx and the reduction of
wings in running birds, arose from their “inhabiting ocean islands,”
where they “have not been exposed to the attacks of beasts, and
consequently lost the power of using their wings for flight.” (“Descent of
Man,” 6th ed., ch. I, p. 32.) In some cases, he believed that disuse and
natural selection had coöperated ex aequo to produce results of this
nature, e.g. the reduction of the eyes in the mole and in Ctenomys; for
this reduction, he claims, has some selection-value, inasmuch as
reduction of the eyes, adhesion of the lids, and covering with hair tends
to protect the unused and useless eye against inflammation. In other
cases, however, he is inclined to discount the idea that suppression of
organs is an “effect of long-continued disuse,” and to regard the
phenomenon as “wholly, or mainly, due to natural selection,” e.g. in the
case of the wingless beetles of the island of Madeira. “For during
successive generations,” he reasons, “each individual beetle which flew
least, either from its wings having been ever so little less developed or
from indolent habit, will have had the best chance of surviving from not
being blown out to sea; and, on the other hand, those beetles which most
readily took to flight would oftenest have been blown to sea, and thus
destroyed.” In a third class of instances, however, he assigns the
principal rôle to disuse, e.g. in the case of the blind animals “which
inhabit the caves of Carniola and Kentucky, because,” as he tells us, “it is
difficult to imagine that eyes, though useless, could be injurious to
animals living in darkness.” Hence he concludes that, as the obliteration
of eyes has no selection-value, under the circumstances prevailing in
dark caves, “their loss may be attributed to disuse.” (Cf. “Origin of
Species,” 6th ed., ch. V, pp. 128-133.)
Morgan’s comment on these elaborate speculations of Darwin is very
caustic and concise. Referring to factorial mutations, which give rise to
races of flies having supernumerary and vestigial organs, he says: “In
contrast to the last case, where a character is doubled, is the next one in
which the eyes are lost. This change took place at a single step. All the
flies of this stock, however, cannot be said to be eyeless, since many of
them show pieces of eye—indeed the variation is so wide that the eye
may even appear like a normal eye unless carefully examined. Formerly
we were taught that eyeless animals arose in caves. This case shows that
they may also arise suddenly in glass milk bottles, by a change in a
single factor.
“I may recall in this connection that wingless flies also arose in our
cultures by a single mutation. We used to be told that wingless insects
occurred on desert islands because those insects that had the best
developed wings were blown out to sea. Whether this is true or not, I will
not pretend to say, but at any rate wingless insects may also arise, not
through a slow process of elimination, but at a single step.” (“A Critique
of the Theory of Evolution,” 1916, pp. 66, 67.)
In directing attention to the fact that a permanent and inheritable
reduction of organs to the vestigial state can result from mutation, we do
not, of course, intend to exclude the possible occurrence of somatic
atrophy due to lack of exercise rather than to germinal change. Thus the
blind species of animals in caves may, in some instances, be persistently
blind, because of the persistent darkness of the environment in which
they live, and not by reason of any inherited factor for blindness. Darwin
gives one such instance, namely, that of the cave rat Neotoma. To test
such cases, the blind animals would have to be bred in an illuminated
environment. If, under this condition, they failed to develop normal eyes,
the blindness would be due to a germinal factor, and would be inherited
in an illumined, no less than a dark, environment.
In any case, a mutation which suppresses a character is not, as we
have seen, a specific change, but merely one of the varietal order, which
does not result in the production of a genuine new species. The factorial
mutant with a vestigial wing or eye belongs to the same species as its
wild or normal parent stock. Moreover, neither disuse nor natural
selection has the slightest power to induce mutations of this kind. If
mutation be the cause of the blindness of cave animals, then their
presence in such caves must be accounted for by supposing that they
migrated thither because they found in the cave a most suitable
environment for safety, foraging, etc. Darkness alone, however, could
never induce germinal, but, at most, merely somatic blindness. The
Lamarckian factor of disuse and the Darwinian factor of selection have
been definitely discredited as agents which could bring about
hereditarily-transmissible modifications.
§ 4. Fossil Links