Harding 230106 230029
Harding 230106 230029
Harding 230106 230029
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content
in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Synthese.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 129.110.33.9 on Sun, 17 Aug 2014 21:34:20 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
SANDRA HARDING
"STRONG OBJECTIVITY":
A RESPONSE TO THE NEW OBJECTIVITY QUESTION
ABSTRACT. Where the old "objectivity question" asked, "Objectivity or relativism: which
side are you on?", the new one refuses this choice, seeking instead to bypass widely
recognized problems with the conceptual framework that restricts the choices to these two.
It asks, "How can the notion of objectivity be updated and made useful for contemporary
discovery for maximizing our ability to block "might makes right" in the sciences. It
does so by delinking the neutrality ideal from standards for maximizing objectivity, since
neutrality is now widely recognized as not only not necessary, not only not helpful, but,
worst of all, an obstacle to maximizing objectivity when knowledge-distorting interests
and values have constituted a research project. Strong objectivity provides a method for
correcting this kind of situation. However, standpoint approaches have their own limitations
which are quite different from the misreadings of them upon which most critics have tended
to focus. Unfortunately, historically limited epistemologies and philosophies of science are
all we get to choose from at this moment in history.
theory-laden; our beliefs form a network such that none are in principle
immune from revision; theories are underdetermined by any possible set of
evidence for them. In short, there is enough slack in scientific belief sort
ing to permit social values and interests fully to permeate these processes
and their results. This slack turns out to be not a defect but a resource
for the growth of scientific knowledge; it permits more than one theory
Synthese 104:331-349,1995.
? 1995 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.
This content downloaded from 129.110.33.9 on Sun, 17 Aug 2014 21:34:20 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
332 SANDRA HARDING
to fit any set of observations, more than one interpretation of any theory
to be reasonable, and, consequently, the growth of science in ever new
directions (van Fraassen and Sigman 1993). Interpretive methods earlier
found useful primarily in the humanities and social sciences increasingly
are providing resources for philosophies, histories, and social studies of
natural sciences. Consequently, few thinkers today are quite as confident
as heretofore concerning such central Enlightenment assumptions as the
2. OBJECTIVITY:AN ESSENTIALLYCONTESTEDCONCEPT?
Philosophers may well think that now is none too soon to define what
objectivity is for the purposes of this discussion. However, Iwant to resist
this urge. One problem is that the term has no single reference in prevail
ing discussions. Objectivity, or the incapacity for it, has been attributed
to individuals, or groups of them, as in, "Women (or feminists, marx
ists, environmentalists, Blacks, welfare recipients, patients, etc.) are more
emotional, less impartial, less capable of objective judgments." Second, it
has been attributed to knowledge claims, where it does not seem to add
anything to the assertion that a claim is better supported by evidence than
its competitors. Third, objectivity is also attributed to methods or proce
dures that are fair: statistical, or experimental, or repeated procedures are
more objective because they maximize standardization, impersonality or
some other quality assumed to contribute to fairness. Fourth, objectivity is
to certain kinds of knowledge-seeking -
attributed communities in Kuhn's
account, the kind characteristic of modern science (Kuhn 1970); in other
This content downloaded from 129.110.33.9 on Sun, 17 Aug 2014 21:34:20 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
"STRONG OBJECTIVITY" 333
is not a single idea, but rather a sprawling collection of assumptions, attitudes, aspirations
and antipathies. At best it is what the philosopher W. B. Gallie has called an "essentially
contested concept," like "social justice" or "leading a Christian life," the exact meaning of
which will always be in dispute. (Novick 1988, p. 1)
struggles over the place that science should have in society" (Proctor 1991,
p. 262).
Both Novick point out that asserting objectivity
and Proctor sometimes
has been used to advance and sometimes to retard the growth of knowledge,
and the same can be said of assertions of relativism. Thus neither position
automatically claims the scientific or rational high-ground. Nor does either
assure the political high-ground: each has been used at some times to block
social justice and at other times to advance it. As Proctor puts the point,
neutrality, the central requirement of the conventional notion, has been
used as "myth, mask, shield and sword" (Proctor 1991, p. 262).
My concerns here are primarily with scientific methods. They arise from
widespread criticisms in feminist, anti-racist, postcolonial, environmental
and other movements for social justice that systematically distorted results
of research in the natural and social sciences are the consequence not only of
carelessness and inadequate rigor in following existing methods and norms
for maximizing objectivity in research practices, but also of inadequacies in
how those methods and norms are conceptualized. The prevailing standards
This content downloaded from 129.110.33.9 on Sun, 17 Aug 2014 21:34:20 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
334 SANDRA HARDING
for good procedures for maximizing objectivity are too weak to be able
to identify such culture-wide assumptions as androcentric or Eurocentric
ones.
provide a kind of method for maximizing our ability to block "might makes
right" in the sciences. Maximizing objectivity is not identical to maximiz
ing neutrality, as conventional understandings have assumed. Nor, I argue,
does it always require it; in a certain range of cases, maximizing neutrality
is an obstacle to maximizing objectivity. Though developed as such in
feminist theory, central insights of this kind of epistemology/philosophy
of science have been expressed far more broadly. This is so in spite of its
clear limitations, which, I shall conclude by showing, are significant, but
are not those due to the misreadings of it upon which most critics have
tended to focus, and which I address in Section 5.
In some ways, the fate of science parallels that of bourgeois democracy: both were born as
exuberant forces for liberation against feudalism, but their very successes have turned them
into caricatures of their youth. The bold, antiauthoritarian stance of science has become
docile acquiescence; the free battle of ideas has given way to a monopoly vested in those
who control the resources for research and publication. Free access to scientific information
has been diminished by military and commercial secrecy and by the barriers of technical
by specialization and bureaucratization, allows them to work on all sorts of dangerous and
harmful projects with indifference to the human consequences. The idealized egalitarianism
of a community of scholars has shown itself to be a rigid hierarchy of scientific authorities
into the general class structure of the society and modeled on the corporation.
integrated
And where the pursuit of truth has survived, it has become increasingly narrow, revealing
a growing contradiction between the sophistication of science in the small within the
laboratory and the irrationality of the scientific enterprise as a whole. (Levins and Lewontin
This content downloaded from 129.110.33.9 on Sun, 17 Aug 2014 21:34:20 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
STRONGOBJECTIVITY" 335
This content downloaded from 129.110.33.9 on Sun, 17 Aug 2014 21:34:20 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
336 SANDRA HARDING
It is certainly true that, in one important sense, the Nazis sought to politicize the sciences
.... Yet in an important sense the Nazis indeed be said to have "depoliticized"
might
science (and many other areas of culture). The Nazis depoliticized science by destroying
the possibility of political debate and controversy. Authoritarian science based on the
"Fuhrer principle" replaced what had been, in the Weimar period, a vigorous spirit of
politicized debate in and around the sciences. The Nazis "depoliticized" problems of vital
human interest by reducing these to scientific or medical problems, conceived in the narrow,
reductionist sense of these terms. The Nazis depoliticized questions of crime, poverty, and
sexual or political deviance by casting them in surgical or otherwise medical (and seemingly
terms ... in the name of science or health a powerful
apolitical) politics pursued provided
weapon in the Nazi ideological arsenal. (Proctor 1988, pp. 290, 293)
This content downloaded from 129.110.33.9 on Sun, 17 Aug 2014 21:34:20 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
"STRONG OBJECTIVITY" 337
regularities of nature that make possible healing a body, charting the stars,
or mining ores may be explained in ways permitting extensive (though
not identical)prediction and control within radically different and even
conflicting, culturally local, explanatory models. The kinds of explanations
favored by modern science have not always been the most effective ones
for all projects - for example, for achieving balance or
environmental
preventing chronic bodily malfunctions. "It works" is no guarantee of
cultural neutrality,
The neutrality ideal functions more through what its normalizing pro
cedures and concepts implicitly prioritize than through explicit directives.
This kind of politics requires no informed consent by those who exercise
it, but only that scientists be "company men" (and women), following the
prevailing rules of scientific institutions and their intellectual traditions.
This normalizing politics frequently defines the objections of its victims
and any criticisms of its institutions, practices, or conceptual world as agi
tation by special interests that threatens to damage the neutrality of science
and its "civilizing mission", as an earlier generation saw the matter. Thus,
when sciences are already in the service of the mighty, scientific neutrality
ensures that "might makes right".
It ismany decades since it has been reasonable to think of modern nat
ural and social sciences as small-scale, weak, guerilla warriors for truth,
This content downloaded from 129.110.33.9 on Sun, 17 Aug 2014 21:34:20 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
338 SANDRA HARDING
design of the research project, and therefore select the methods. Of course
in the "mangle of practice" (Pickering 1991) during scientific research,
hypotheses, nature, and research technologies are adjusted to each other
such that a certain element of objectivity is produced without the promise of
total neutrality. Nature constrains our beliefs without uniquely confirming
them. The most science can hope for is results that are consistent with "how
nature is", not ones that are uniquely coherent with it, as the objectivist
goal intended (Hayles 1992). Even the U.S. National Academy of Sciences
- not a den of - now that the notion
certainly wild-eyed radicals argues
of research method should be enlarged beyond its familiar meaning of
techniques to
This content downloaded from 129.110.33.9 on Sun, 17 Aug 2014 21:34:20 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
"STRONG OBJECTIVITY" 339
include the judgments scientists make about or reliability of data, ... the
interpretation
decisions scientists make about which problems to pursue or when to conclude an investi
... the scientists work with each other and exchange information.
gation, ways (Nat. Acad.
Sei. 1989, pp. 5-6)
I do not intend to contrast evil determinists who stray from the path of scientific objectivity
with enlightened antideterminists who approach data with an open mind and therefore see
truth. Rather I criticize the myth that science itself is an objective enterprise, done properly
only when scientists can shuck the constraints of their culture and view the world as it
really is.... Science, since people must do it, is a socially embedded activity. It progresses
This content downloaded from 129.110.33.9 on Sun, 17 Aug 2014 21:34:20 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
340 SANDRAHARDING
by hunch, vision, and intuition. Much of its change through time does not record a closer
approach to absolute truth, but the alteration of cultural contexts that influence it so strongly.
Moreover, Gould's reflection makes clear that not all cultural interests
and values ("contexts") retard the growth of knowledge. Some advance
it, he is saying: science has often progressed because of changes in its
cultural contexts. So
it is problematic that objectivism is supposed to
enable the elimination of all social values and interests. Weak objectivity
is unable to discriminate between those interests and values that enlarge
our understanding and those that limit it.
objectivity-as-neutrality.8
Yet another response has been to retain the neutrality criterion for
This content downloaded from 129.110.33.9 on Sun, 17 Aug 2014 21:34:20 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
STRONGOBJECTIVITY" 341
So where might one find a method for maximizing objectivity that has
the resources to detect (a) values and interests that constitute scientific
projects, (b) ones that do not vary between legitimated observers, and (c)
the difference between those values and interests that enlarge and those that
limit our images of nature and social relations? This is where standpoint
has resources are not - at least,
theory provided useful that available or,
not easily available - from other epistemologies.
4. STANDPOINTAPPROACHES:SYSTEMATICPROCEDURESFORMAXIMIZING
OBJECTIVITY
How could biological and social science research that clearly was guided
by feminist politics manage to be producing empirically and theoretically
more adequate accounts of nature and social relations? This is the question
standpoint theorists set out to answer. Here I shall only review the main
outlines of this theory of knowledge and philosophy of science since it
has been developed, refined and critically discussed now for close to two
decades.9
daily activities of people in the ruling groups tend to set distinctive limits
on their thought, limits that are not created
by the activities of the subju
gated groups. Administrative-managerial activities, including the work of
the natural and social sciences, is the form of "ruling" in our contempo
rary modern societies, and the conceptual frameworks of our disciplines
are shaped by administrative-managerial priorities, just as pre-scientific
observations of nature are shaped by other cultural priorities. Such pri
orities do enable gaining the kinds of information administrators need to
function effectively, but they also distort and limit our understanding of just
This content downloaded from 129.110.33.9 on Sun, 17 Aug 2014 21:34:20 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
342 SANDRA HARDING
what brings about daily social relations and interactions with nature, and
they make it difficult to think possible any different kind of interactions. In
order to gain a causal critical view of the interests and values that consti
tute the dominant conceptual projects, one must start one's thought, one's
research project, from outside those conceptual schemes and the activities
that generate them; one must start from the lives excluded as origins of
-
their design from "marginal lives."
The fundamental features of the standpoint proposal can be grasped
most quickly looking at what it is not. Those constrained
by by the old
objectivity question will tend to distort standpoint theory by perceiving it
only through the conceptual choices offered by "Objectivity or relativism:
which side are you on?" They often construct it as just a variant of empiri
cism or, alternatively, as a kind of gynocentrism, special pleading, or unrea
sonably claimed privileged positionality. On such a reading, empiricism is
politics-free, and standpoint theory is asserting epistemological/scientific
privilege for one group at the expense of the equally valuable/distorted
This content downloaded from 129.110.33.9 on Sun, 17 Aug 2014 21:34:20 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
"STRONG OBJECTIVITY" 343
lives of women and men, our activities and beliefs, end up in the forms
that they do.
sought elsewhere than in women's experiences, since the latter are shaped
This content downloaded from 129.110.33.9 on Sun, 17 Aug 2014 21:34:20 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
344 SANDRA HARDING
This content downloaded from 129.110.33.9 on Sun, 17 Aug 2014 21:34:20 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
"STRONG OBJECTIVITY" 345
This content downloaded from 129.110.33.9 on Sun, 17 Aug 2014 21:34:20 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
346 SANDRA HARDING
This content downloaded from 129.110.33.9 on Sun, 17 Aug 2014 21:34:20 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
"STRONG OBJECTIVITY" 347
Objectivity is an important value for cultures that value sciences, and its
value spreads to other cultures as they import Northern forms of democracy,
their epistemologies and sciences. This is not to say that Northerners
are particularly good at democracy or maximizing objectivity, or have
any corner on the ideals. And, of course, Northern forms of these ideals
are widely criticized by many Third World intellectuals, as they are by
feminists, as ideologies that have justified excluding and exploiting the
already less powerful. Nevertheless, 'objective' defines for many people
today how they think of themselves; we are fair; we make decisions by
principle, not by whim or fiat; we are against "might makes right"; we are
rational; we can find ways to live together that value our cultural diversity
... and so forth. I am not
saying that everyone who claims objectivity in
fact maximizes it, but that such an ideal is deeply embedded in the ethic
and rhetoric of democracy at personal, communal, and institutional levels.
The notion is centered in natural and many social science discourses, in
jurisprudence, in public policy, in many areas where decisions about how
to organize social relations are made.
Thus, while the diverse arguments
for abandoning the notion are illuminating and important to keep inmind,
to do so is to adopt a "bohemian" strategy; it is to do "something else"
besides try to struggle on the terrain where philosophies, science projects
and social policies are negotiated. Why not, instead, think of objectivity
as an "indigenous resource" of the modern North? It needs updating,
rehabilitation, so that it is capable of functioning effectively in the science
based society that the North has generated and that many now say is its
major cultural export (cf. Harding 1994).
What of the epistemological status of this strong objectivity program
itself? What limitations arise from the particular historical projects from
which it started off? No doubt there are many such limitations, but four
easily come to mind. First, the strong objectivity program is, indeed, a sci
ence project. It relegitimates scientific rationality (and a modern European
form of it) in a world where many think the power of this rationality should
be limited. Now the "context of discovery" and the values and interests
shared within a research community are to be added
to the phenomena to
be analyzed with scientific rationality.
Second, this strong objectivity program and the standpoint theory that
supports it originate in the North, and draw upon the historical and cultural
This content downloaded from 129.110.33.9 on Sun, 17 Aug 2014 21:34:20 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
348 SANDRA HARDING
NOTES
1
Or, in the nineteenth century formulation that has left problematic residues in contem
maximizing objectivity, reserving the term 'objectivity' for the "strong objectivity", shorn
of the neutrality requirement, that I have proposed.
3
For reasons to be recounted below, claims to less falsity are preferable to those for truth
or verisimilitude. See Megill (1991) for a related account of four senses of objectivity
This content downloaded from 129.110.33.9 on Sun, 17 Aug 2014 21:34:20 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
"STRONGOBJECTIVITY" 349
(1987).
8
I cannot take space to review
these important arguments here. See Bordo (1987) and
Critique of Sociology', reprinted in my (1987). For other important statements of this the
ory see Hartsock (1983), Jaggar (1983), Rose (1983), Smith (1987), (1990). See also my
discussions of it in ( 1986b), ( 1991 ), ( 1993b). For two of themany innovative and clarifying
recent developments of it, see Collins (1991) and Hennessy (1993).
10
This claim parallels those for experimental method where, also, what the scientist does
both enables and limits (but does not determine, since our theories are always underdeter
mined by their evidence) what we can know.
Department of Philosophy
University of Delaware
Newark, DE 19716
U.S.A.
Department of Philosophy
This content downloaded from 129.110.33.9 on Sun, 17 Aug 2014 21:34:20 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions