Engineering Ethics: Lecture by Md. Raihan Goni Southeast University
Engineering Ethics: Lecture by Md. Raihan Goni Southeast University
Engineering Ethics: Lecture by Md. Raihan Goni Southeast University
Lecture by
Md. Raihan Goni
Southeast University
Introduction
• One of the main differences between science and engineering is that
engineering is not just about better understanding the world but also
about changing it. Many engineers believe that such change improves,
or at least should improve, the world. In this sense engineering is an
inherently morally motivated activity. Changing the world for the
better is, however, no easy task and also not one that can be
achieved on the basis of engineering knowledge alone. It also
requires, among other things, ethical reflection and knowledge. This
book aims at contributing to such reflection and knowledge, not just
in a theoretical sense but also more practically.
• There is an increasing attention to ethics in the engineering curricula.
Engineers are supposed not only to carry out their work competently and
skillfully, but also to be aware of the broader ethical and social implications
of engineering and to be able to reflect on these. According to the
Engineering Criteria 2000 of the Accreditation Board for Engineering and
Technology (ABET) in the US, engineering graduates must have “an
understanding of professional and ethical responsibility” and “the broad
education necessary to understand the impact of engineering solutions in a
global and societal context” (Herkert 1999).
• The ethical cycle is intended as a didactical tool to deal with these
problems. It provides a guide for dealing with ethical issues which is
systematic without assuming an instrumental notion of ethics. By applying
the ethical cycle, the moral competencies will be acquired that are needed
for dealing with ethical issues in engineering and technology (see Figure).
Responsibility
• Responsibility is often linked to the role that you have in a particular situation.
You often have to fulfil a number of roles simultaneously such as those of
friend, parent, citizen, employee, engineer, expert and colleague. In a role you
have a relationship with others, for instance, as an employee you have a
relationship with your employer, as an expert you have a relationship with your
customers and as a colleague you have relationships with other colleagues.
Each role brings with its certain responsibilities. A parent, for example, is
expected to care for his child. In the role of employee it is expected that you
will execute your job properly, as laid down in collaboration with your
employer; in the role of expert it will be presumed that you furnish your
customer with information that is true and relevant and in the role of colleague
you will be expected to behave in a collegial fashion with others in the same
work situation. An engineer is expected to carry out his work in a competent
way.
• Professional responsibility is the responsibility that is based on your
role as professional engineer in as far it stays within the limits of
what is morally allowed. Professional responsibilities are not just
passive but they also contain an active component (see next reading).
We will examine the content of the professional responsibility of
engineers in more detail.
Passive responsibility
• Typical for passive responsibility is that the person who is held
responsible must be able to provide an account why he followed a
particular course of action and why he made certain decisions. In
particular, the person is held to justify his/her actions towards those
who are in a position to demand that the individual in question
accounts for his/her actions. We will call this type of passive
responsibility accountability. Passive responsibility often involves not
just accountability but also blameworthiness. Blameworthiness means
that it is proper to blame someone for his/her actions or the
consequences of those actions. You are not always blameworthy for
the consequences of your actions or for your actions themselves.
Usually, four conditions need to apply:
• 1. Wrong-doing. Whenever one blames a person or institution one usually
maintains that in carrying out a certain action the individual or the
institution in question has violated a norm or did something wrong. This can
be a legal or moral norm, or that is common in the organization.
• 2. Causal contribution. The person who is held responsible must have
made a causal contribution to the consequences for which he or she is held
responsible.
• 3. Foreseeability. A person who is held responsible for something must
have been able to know the consequences of his or her actions. The
consequences are the harm actually arising from transgressing a norm.
• 4. Freedom of Action. The one who is held responsible must have had
freedom of action, i.e. he or she must not have acted under obligation.
Individuals are either not responsible or are responsible to a lesser degree
if they are, for instance, forced to take certain decisions.
Active responsibility and the ideals of engineers
• We considered above questions of responsibility when something has gone wrong. Responsibility is
also something that comes into play beforehand, if nothing has yet gone wrong or if there is the
chance to realize something good. We will refer to this as active responsibility. If someone is
actively responsible for something, he is expected to act in such a way that undesired consequences
are avoided as much as possible and so that positive consequences are being realized.
• One way in which the active responsibility of engineers can be understood is by looking at the ideals
of engineers. Ideals, as we will understand the notion here, have two specific characteristics. First
ideals are ideas or strivings which are particularly motivating and inspiring for the person having
them. Second, it is typical for ideals that they aim at achieving an optimum or maximum. Often,
therefore, ideals cannot be entirely fulfilled but are strived for. Some of these ideals are directly
linked to professional practice because they are closely allied to the engineering profession or can
only be aspired to by carrying out the profession of engineer. We call such ideals professional
ideals. As professional ideals, these ideas are part of professional responsibility in as far they stay
within the limits of what is morally allowed. Examples of these professional ideals of engineers are:
1. Technological enthusiasm. This pertains to the ideal of wanting to
develop new technological possibilities and take up technological
challenges.