As we have seen, operation is a key concept in Simondon’s work and unifies his ontology and his epistemology. He further defines an operation as “what makes a structure appear and what modifies a structure” [
96, p. 661], in which a structure refers to an individuated being (such as a brick, a machine, a flower, a human). In classical ontology as in technical systems, the operations that make beings remain hidden. Technical mentality is the attitude that seeks to manifest and understand these operations and recognizes them as the proper site of being. In order to understand technical mentality, therefore, we must start with Simondon’s ontological critique which, as we will see, has implications for how HCI researchers and designers might apprehend the ethics of the systems they design and study.
4.1 ‘Blackboxing’ the Operations of Being
Simondon’s work starts with a critique of the hylomorphic schema, the ontological model proposed by Aristotle, which states that beings come from the combination of form and matter [
3]. The critique of hylomorphism is not new to HCI: drawing from Ingold [
52], several scholars have reported on the influence of hylomorphism in digital fabrication. Devendorf et al. [
25] show that the design of 3D printers embraces a hylomorphic model through the imposition of a form (in this case, a mathematical description of geometry) onto matter (thermoplastic filaments). As a response to this model, Torres proposes
Crafting Proxies as intermediaries to support the manipulation and intervention of materials in digital fabrication workflows [
105], emphasizing the agency of matter in design and fabrication processes. Twigg-Smith et al. [
107] highlight the hylomorphic nature of the canonical digital fabrication workflow and demonstrate that despite this authoritative account of fabrication processes, makers and artists using plotters embrace how technical and material constraints shape the art and artifacts they produce. As Devendorf et al. [
25] put it: “While a designer’s imagined workflow of 3D printing may be hylomorphic, the reality of 3D printing is anything but: 3D printing, like all craft, forces the maker to contend with stubborn recalcitrance and unpredictability of the material world.”
Simondon’s critique is aligned with this observation that hylomorphism is in fact an
external assessment of a technical operation. Aristotle’s example is brick making but the process he describes is—like the ‘designer’s imagined workflow—severed from the reality of making bricks. Hylomorphism remains external to the actual principle of individuation, which is neither form nor matter but the
operation that puts them in relation.
For Simondon, Aristotle’s description of brick making focuses only on the structures: the visible, already realized elements that form the brick—the clay, the mold—whereas the process that brings them together is never explained. The hylomorphic schema obscures the ‘true mediation’ that links matter and form, which is the operation [
96, p. 32]. To illustrate this, Simondon describes the process of brick making by carefully unpacking the ‘chains of operations’ that prepare the clay and the mold themselves (see Figure
2).
The brick does not result from the combination of an “unspecified matter and an unspecified form” but from the
preparation of clay and the
fabrication of the mold [
96, p. 22]. The labor required to prepare clay and mold not only enables the combination of form and matter, it is what makes the dirt in the marsh into malleable clay and transforms the pile of wood and nails into a mold. The form of the mold is also not arbitrary, but selected according to the properties of materials, already bearers of forms. The mold is built in such a way that it can be opened or closed without breaking its content; its interior might be prepared so as to avoid (or facilitate) the absorption of the water in the clay. Similarly, the clay homogeneous enough for brick making does not happen spontaneously in nature, but is lifted from the earth as raw matter: “it’s what the shovel raises to the surface at the edge of the marsh with roots of rush and gravel grains” [
96, p. 23]. This matter is then dried, crushed, sifted, wetted, shaped, and kneaded to arrive at the homogenous dough that is plastic enough to be able to embrace the contour of the mold and “firm enough to conserve this contour long enough for this plasticity to disappear.”
Simondon pays close attention to all the processes that allow the convergence of form and matter: the first chain goes from the abstract geometry to the physical mold and the second from the raw dirt in the marsh to the prepared clay. These operations are absent from the hylomorphic account of brick making which, according to Simondon, reveals classical ontology’s substantialist premises, i.e. the assumption that substances are a fundamental ontological category. Instead, Simondon argues that
relations are what constitute substances, which can never be fully apprehended as discrete, complete and finished. The principle of individuation, the process by which individuals come to be, is to be found neither in form nor matter but in their relation—or rather, in the process that puts them in relation: “The veritable principle of individuation is genesis itself in the course of being carried out, i.e. the system in the course of becoming while energy is actualized [...] The principle of individuation is an
operation” [
96, p. 32, our emphasis].
As Simondon’s detailed description of the process of brick making illustrates, matter’s plasticity and form’s structuring action are only actualized in the process of individuation. Beings are not the reunion of fully actualized principles; rather, it is the very process of beingess—of becoming, of individuation—that actualizes and realizes the principles of form and matter—that makes form informing and matter plastic, able to express its ’implicit forms’ [
96, p. 38]. The ontological ‘method’ proposed by Simondon consists in “considering every [...] relation as having the status of being” [
96, p. 12]. To use an analogy, an individual is not simply the sum of its ‘ingredients’ but rather “the totality of its production” [
50], including all the steps, labor, potential energy and tribulations required to make it.
This reformulation of classical ontology bears on HCI in important ways. First, it highlights the various forms of labor—human, material, energetic—that are central to the existence of technical (including digital, [
41,
50]) objects. For instance, AI-generated text and images are the results of not only algorithms and data but especially of the (hidden) labor of data collection, formatting, annotation, and labeling [
22,
47,
57,
65]. In the context of digital fabrication, it suggests that the essential aspect of fabrication that needs to be supported is not the realization of form but the material and human operations that make things, of which form-taking is only one dimension. Systems research should support, in other words, the
conditions of production and not just the realization of computational designs. In their empirical study of nine different digital fabrication workflows in professional contexts, Hirsch et al. [
45] show that the design decisions made by professionals included not just the selection of form and pattern, but the negotiation between material constraints, resource management, access to tools and skill acquisition, among others. Yet, these ‘details’ of production tend to be abstracted or overlooked as too specific, contextual or mundane to enter the official accounts of fabrication that prevail in HCI. According to Simondon, these ‘details’—the labor that is simultaneously technical, material, scientific, domestic and logistical—are the crux of beingness, both for living beings and technical objects. But this labor is blackboxed in the hylomorphic schema as in technical systems, because material and situated labor is historically dismissed as irrelevant to discourse.
4.2 The Ethics of Blackboxing
Hylomorphism is an ontological account that stems from a specific time and place: Athens, in Ancient Greece, where slave labor was instrumental to running the democratic city-state [
32,
54]. While Aristotle based his ontological model on a technical operation (brick making), he was not the brick maker; slaves were. Simondon writes that the ‘dark zone’ of the hylomorphic schema, i.e. the indifference or ignorance of the operations and labor that make bricks, is the expression of those specific exploitative labor relations, namely, slavery [
96, p. 35-36].
The passivity of matter supposed by the hylomorphic schema is therefore a reflection of the exploitative human relations that coordinate the labor of brick making. Form is expressible and expressed as an order coming from the free man, the citizen (and philosopher), whereas matter is mute, handled by slaves—individuals who have no say in the matters of the polis, the discussions on collective becoming.
Coiled deep within the dark zone of classical Western ontology are therefore not just operations and mechanisms but what Rancière calls a ‘distribution of the sensible’: a particular configuration of matter and discourse that reveals “who can have a share in what is common to the community” [
85]. This configuration of matter and discourse is concealed in the black box of technology as well. The mechanisms of machines, as well as socio-political technologies such as race and capitalism, are concealed and therefore naturalized [
12,
79]: technology becomes deterministic, and exploitation systemic.
Technical mentality starts with paying attention to the labor, decisions, and operations that articulate material and socio-political technologies. The development of technical mentality is intimately linked with a shift in the relationships humans have with technology. The same way classical ontology is an expression of alienating and exploitative labor relations, for Simondon the current relationship with technology in the contemporary world is the expression of an alienation of the human labor present in technical systems: “What resides in the machines is human reality, human gesture fixed and crystallized into working structures [...].” [
95, p. 16]. The essence of technicity is human labor, effort, and invention, but it remains unacknowledged and unknown, ‘trapped’ in the black boxed machine. Technical mentality orients culture towards a direct knowledge of technicity, and this knowledge can be supported by developing ‘open’ systems, in the sense of systems that reveal their mechanisms, are flexibly composed, and integrate in their design the possibility of their extension and reconfiguration.
This direct knowledge, however, is not easily acquired. Simondon often comments on the need for the machine “user to become the builder” of machines. In an article written in 1954 for an education journal, Simondon writes that educators can instill in children a respectful attitude towards machines by teaching them to build, repair and maintain technical systems [
94, p. 233-253]. This avenue has, of course, been explored: initiatives to teach physical computing and programming skills to children are too numerous to list here (an entire paper could be written about the relationships between Simondon’s philosophy, constructionism and the maker movement. See [
2]). Another approach, discussed by Guchet [
40], is to recover the “affective content” of technical systems. Simondon describes in various essays [
94] the evolution from the magical to the technical regime in Western societies, and the progressive loss of the symbolic and imaginal power of technical objects as they move from one to the other. He writes that affectivity and emotion “bring their dimension of collective participation to tools and technical objects” [
94, p. 104] and have therefore the power to be the vectors of more respectful and companionable relationships with technology.
How can technologists and designers restore this affective content in technical systems? Simondon mentions aesthetics and art as domains in which technical mentality can be further developed. We discuss this point in section
6.4.
In the next section, we give an example of technical mentality through the discussion of a fabrication system called Imprimer, a machine infrastructure for direct control of a CNC mill from a computational notebook [
106]. This example is not an exemplar but rather a case study to illustrate how the ontological and ethical commitments of technical mentality might be expressed in systems.