For Routledge Companion to Evidence, (eds.) M. Lasonen-Aarnio & C. Littlejohn, (Routledge).
EPISTEMOLOGICAL DISJUNCTIVISM AND EVIDENCE
DUNCAN PRITCHARD
University of California, Irvine
dhpritch@uci.edu
ABSTRACT. An overview of epistemological disjunctivism is offered, including its
relationship to metaphysical disjunctivism. Particular focus is then placed on how such a
thesis might be cast specifically in terms of evidence. Two issues in particular are
discussed: (i) how to locate the proposal within the epistemic externalism/internalism
distinction; and (ii) how one might motivate the viability of the proposal.
KEYWORDS: Disjunctivism; Epistemic Externalism/Internalism; Epistemological
Disjunctivism; Epistemology; Evidence.
BIO: Duncan Pritchard is UC Distinguished Professor of Philosophy and Director of the
Center for Knowledge, Technology & Society at the University of California, Irvine. His
monographs include Epistemic Luck (Oxford UP, 2005), The Nature and Value of Knowledge
(co-authored, Oxford UP, 2010), Epistemological Disjunctivism (Oxford UP, 2012), and
Epistemic Angst (Princeton UP, 2015).
1. INTRODUCTORY REMARKS
Disjunctivist views about the content of perceptual experience have been defended for some time,
often as part of a broadly naïve realist account of perception. Very roughly, such views hold that
there is no common metaphysical component of both ordinary veridical experience (the ‘good
case’), and corresponding indistinguishable experiences involving hallucination, such as when one
is brain-in-a-vat (BIV) being ‘fed’ one’s experiences by supercomputers (the ‘bad case’).1 Rather,
such experiences are on this view different in kind, in that the content of the former experience is
at least partly determined by it being a veridical perception in a way that the content of the latter
experience cannot be determined. (Of course, there is a negative epistemological property that is in
common to both experiences, which is that they are indistinguishable, but the point is that this
2
property doesn’t pick out a significant metaphysical property).
Call disjunctivism of this kind metaphysical disjunctivism. Given that the content of one’s
experiences can have a bearing on the evidential or rational support that is available for one’s
perceptual beliefs, then there is a direct connection between metaphysical disjunctivism and the
epistemic support one’s perceptual beliefs enjoy. In particular, we should not conclude that just
because a pairing of good/bad case experiences are indistinguishable to the agent concerned that
the epistemic support offered by the experience in the good case can be no better than the
epistemic support offered by the experience in the bad case. Instead, if metaphysical disjunctivism
is true, then it may well be that the epistemic support one’s experiences generate in the good case
is significantly better than the epistemic support generated by the indistinguishable experiences
had in the corresponding bad case.2
In what follows, we will focus our attention not on metaphysical disjunctivism, but rather
on its sister position, epistemological disjunctivism. The core difference between the two is that whereas
metaphysical disjunctivism offers a metaphysical position from which one might be able to extract
some surprising epistemological consequences, epistemological disjunctivism offers an
epistemological position that delivers those surprising epistemological consequences directly. With
the two proposals differentiated, we can then ask what the logical relationships are between
metaphysical and epistemological disjunctivism. Does the former entail the latter? Does the latter
entail the former? Or is the relationship between the two views less a matter of logical entailment
and more one of dialectical affiliation? For example, one might plausibly contend that it is hard to
make sense of the philosophical motivation for epistemological disjunctivism without a prior
commitment to metaphysical disjunctivism. In any case, these further questions are largely
orthogonal to the purposes of this piece. On the one hand, if metaphysical disjunctivism doesn’t
have interesting epistemological consequences, then it’s bearing on evidence won’t be of concern
to us. On the other hand, if epistemological disjunctivism is true, then it has ramifications for the
nature of evidence regardless of whether this position entails (or otherwise leads to) metaphysical
disjunctivism. It follows that our proper concern here is directly with the evidential ramifications
of epistemological disjunctivism.
2. EPISTEMOLOGICAL DISJUNCTIVISM
There is a standard version of epistemological disjunctivism in the contemporary epistemological
literature. It is derived from earlier work by John McDowell (e.g., 1995), but the main presentation
of the view is due to myself.3 According to this proposal, in epistemically paradigm cases of
3
perceptual knowledge, one’s knowledge is supported by rational support that is both factive and
reflectively accessible. In particular, in such cases one’s reflectively accessible rational support for
knowing that p is that one sees that p, where seeing that p entails p (and hence is factive).
We can see why the position is an epistemological form of disjunctivism by seeing how it
plays out in a pairing of experiences in a good case (i.e., a scenario where the conditions are
epistemically paradigmatic) and a corresponding indistinguishable bad case (e.g., a radical sceptical
scenario, such as the BIV case). One might naturally suppose that since one is unable to
distinguish between the experiences had in the good and the bad case, then the rational support
enjoyed by one’s beliefs in the good case can be no better than the rational support enjoyed by
one’s belief in the bad case.4 After all, for all one can tell, one might be in the bad case, so how is
one to have rational support for one’s beliefs that would be unavailable in the bad case?
Epistemological disjunctivism runs directly counter to this thought, however, since it maintains
that there is rational support reflectively available to the subject that is unavailable to the subject’s
counterpart in the bad case. After all, since the subject is radically deceived in the bad case, she can
hardly be in a position to see that p, not least because p is almost certainly false, but even if it does
happen to be true, the subject in our bad case is not going to stand in the robust epistemic
relationship to p of seeing that p.5 At best, the rational support reflectively available to the subject
in the bad case is going to be that of seeming to see that p, which is obviously a non-factive rational
standing.6
The upshot is that rather than one’s rational support in the good case being no better than
it is in the corresponding bad case, it can instead be significantly superior. Moreover, proponents
of epistemological disjunctivism maintain that there is no common rational core to the rational
standing of the subject’s belief in the good and bad cases, as if one could simply understand the
rational standing in the good case as being the rational standing available in the bad case
supplemented by some additional rational support. Rather, the difference in rational support is one
of kind. Seeing that p cannot be decomposed into, say, merely seeming to see that p plus some
other additional rational support. The difference between the two rational standings is thus one of
kind and not merely of degree. We thus have the disjunctive aspect of epistemological
disjunctivism: either one is in the good case and enjoys factive rational support, or one is in the bad
case and enjoys, at best, non-factive rational support (with there being no significant common core
of rational support which applies to both cases).7
There are a few things to note about our characterization of epistemological disjunctivism.
First, in common with metaphysical disjunctivism, the thesis is primarily about perception. That
said, the view might well be extendable to other sources of knowledge—such as memory,
testimony, and so on—though we will not be exploring these possibilities here.8 Second, this is a
4
thesis only about epistemically paradigm cases of perceptual knowledge, and not a thesis about
perceptual knowledge in general.9 Third, epistemological disjunctivism is explicitly cast in terms of
rational support rather than evidence. This last point requires further discussion, given the
evidential focus of this piece.
Can we straightforwardly translate claims about reasons into claims about evidence? I
think many in contemporary epistemology would regard such a replacement as largely harmless.
Aren’t one’s reasons one’s evidence? That is, if my reason for believing that my car has been stolen
is that the policewoman testified to this effect, then isn’t such testimony also the evidence I have
for believing that my car is stolen? Moreover, doesn’t one’s evidence have to be available to one in
order for it to count as one’s evidence? If so, then isn’t it as available to one as one’s reasons are?
For example, the policewoman’s testimony is only your evidence because you are aware of it; had
you not been, then it wouldn’t be your evidence at all. But, insofar as you are aware of it, then it
can also function as your reasons for believing the target proposition.
For what it is worth, my own view on these matters is that reasons and evidence play such
different roles in our epistemic economy that replacements of this kind are usually far from
harmless. But it will take us too far afield to explore these issues here.10 Accordingly, I will follow
the mainstream and straightforwardly translate the rational support in play in epistemological
disjunctivism into evidential terms. We thus get the view that in epistemologically paradigm cases
of perceptual knowledge one’s belief in the target proposition is supported by reflectively
accessible factive evidence.11 We also get a corresponding account of what is disjunctive about
epistemological disjunctivism, so characterized. Either one is in the good case, and hence enjoys
reflectively accessible factive evidence (provided by one seeing that p), or one is in the
corresponding indistinguishable bad case and only enjoys, at best, reflectively accessible nonfactive evidence (e.g., provided by one seeming to see that p). Moreover, there is no significant
common core to the evidential standing in the good case and the corresponding evidential
standing in the bad case, such that one cannot decompose the factive evidential standing in the
good case into the non-factive evidential standing in the bad case supplemented by additional
evidence. Rather, the evidential difference in play here is one of kind rather than degree.
3. CLASSICAL AND NON-CLASSICAL FORMS OF EPISTEMIC INTERNALISM
One can best appreciate the radical nature of epistemological disjunctivism by seeing how it
constitutes a non-classical form of epistemic internalism. Classical forms of epistemic internalism
tend to endorse the following three theses (here expressed, given our current concerns, in terms of
5
evidence rather than reasons or some other epistemic standing):
Accessibilism
S’s internalist epistemic support for believing that j is constituted solely by facts that S can know
by reflection alone.12
Mentalism
S’s internalist epistemic support for believing that j is constituted solely by S’s mental states.13
The New Evil Genius (NEG)
S’s internalist epistemic support for believing that j is constituted solely by properties that S has in
common with her recently envatted physical duplicate.14
There are debates amongst epistemic internalists regarding which of these theses holds the ‘whip
hand’ when it comes to determining the nature of epistemic internalism, but one can easily see
why a commitment to all three theses would tend to go together.15 Plausibly, after all, the reason
why one’s mental states play the role in determining the evidential standing of one’s beliefs that
mentalism describes is that one has the kind of reflective access to one’s mental states that is at
issue in accessibilism. Conversely, one could argue, in line with accessibilism, that we are interested
in that which is reflectively accessible when it comes to evidential standing precisely because that
relation picks out one’s mental states and they are key to determining evidential standing, in line
with accessibilism. Moreover, the path from accessiblism and mentalism to (NEG) is also fairly
straightforward. If evidential support is to be understood in terms of one’s reflectively accessible
mental states, as accessibism and mentalism maintain, then it is hard to see how the evidential
support one’s beliefs enjoys in the good case can be any better than the evidential support enjoyed
by one’s beliefs in the corresponding bad case. After all, the experiences in play in these two
scenarios are ex hypothesi indistinguishable to the subject concerned, and so presumably there
cannot be evidence that is reflectively accessible to the subject in the good case that is not also
reflectively accessible to one’s counterpart in the bad case.
Classical forms of epistemic externalism, in contrast, reject all three theses. Take process
reliabilism, for example.16 According to this proposal, it is the reliability of one’s belief-forming
processes that determine epistemic standing, and hence would be relevant to determining the
strength of one’s evidence. Such a proposal would not satisfy any of the three conditions for
classical epistemic internalism just set out. It would not satisfy accessibilism, since whether or not
a process is reliable is not something that will usually be reflectively accessible to the subject. It
would not satisfy mentalism, since the evidential support one’s beliefs enjoys is determined by the
reliability of the processes in play, and does not have anything essentially to do with one’s mental
states. And it would not satisfy (NEG), because one’s beliefs in the good case, where the beliefforming processes in play will tend to be highly reliable, will enjoy stronger levels of evidential
6
support than the beliefs of one’s counterpart in the bad case, where few, if any, of the beliefforming processes in play will be reliable.
Classical epistemic internalism thus accepts all three of these theses, while classical
epistemic externalism rejects all three. Epistemological disjunctivism is a non-classical form of
epistemic internalism in that it accepts at least one and rejects at least one of these classical
epistemic internalist theses. In particular, whereas epistemological disjunctivism explicitly endorses
accessibilism, and is compatible with mentalism, it rejects (NEG). Before explaining why this is the
case, there is an important caveat we need to add here. Recall that epistemological disjunctivism is
only a thesis about perceptual knowledge in epistemically paradigm conditions. As such, when one
says that the view endorses, for example, accessibilism, this is to be understood only in terms of
what the view is committed to with regard to epistemically paradigm cases of perceptual
knowledge. In particular, there is nothing to prevent a proponent of epistemological disjunctivism
from being an epistemic externalist about knowledge in general (and thus also about evidence,
specifically).17
With this caveat in play, we can easily see why epistemological disjunctivism is committed to
accessibilism, since it holds that one’s factive evidential support in the good case should be
reflectively accessible. Moreover, we can also see the consistency with mentalism, so long as we
allow that seeing that p is a mental state. Note, however, that this move is much more
controversial, since proponents of mentalism usually assume a conception of mental states that
involves only narrow content, and hence which would exclude factive mental states like seeing that
p.18 Still, we can at least say this much: that epistemological disjunctivism is compatible with
mentalism to the extent that we do not add this further restriction regarding types of mental state
that qualify.
What epistemological disjunctivism is committed to denying is precisely (NEG). This is
because, as seen above, it is a fundamental commitment of the proposal that one’s evidential
support in the good case is factive, and hence clearly superior to the evidential support available to
one’s counterpart in the bad case, which is at most non-factive.19 Epistemological disjunctivism
thus constitutes a non-classical form of epistemic internalism, in that while it endorses at least one
core epistemic internalist thesis, it also rejects at least one core epistemic internalist thesis.20
4. THE VIABILITY OF EPISTEMOLOGICAL DISJUNCTIVISM
One of the big questions facing epistemological disjunctivism is whether it is a viable position.
Indeed, until relatively recently it was a view that was not explicitly considered by mainstream
7
epistemologists since it was held to be completely untenable. Part of the reason for this is the
supposed inherent plausibility of (NEG), a claim that even epistemic externalists will usually grant
is constitutive of epistemic internalism.21 In particular, epistemological disjunctivism seems to be
trying to do something that is simply impossible, which is to fuse core elements of epistemic
internalism and epistemic externalism. On the one hand, epistemological disjunctivism is meant to
capture epistemic internalist insights by demanding that one’s evidential support is reflectively
accessible. But, on the other hand, the view also tries to capture epistemic externalist insights by
arguing that such reflectively accessible evidential support can nonetheless have worldly import, in
virtue of being factive. According to traditional ways of understanding the epistemic
externalism/internalism distinction, such an intermediate position is not credible¾either the
evidential support is reflectively accessible, in which case it can’t have worldly import (much less
be factive), or the evidential support is factive, in which case it can’t be reflectively accessible.
The way that proponents of epistemological disjunctivism have gone about demonstrating
the viability of this proposal is via a three-stage process. First, to show that our everyday epistemic
practices are shot-through with appeals to factive evidence. Second, to demonstrate that
epistemological disjunctivism is a view that we would want to endorse were it available.22 Finally,
third, to argue to the effect that the reasons offered for rejecting epistemological disjunctivism are
unsound, where this can be shown without appealing to anything independently controversial
(much less anything that would already commit one to epistemological disjunctivism). Note that
this is an essentially negative way of defending the view. That is, it is shown that the arguments
against epistemological disjunctivism are dubious and hence, since it is part of our everyday
epistemic practices and an otherwise attractive position to hold, that we should endorse it.23
Let’s take these three stages in turn. That our everyday epistemic practices naturally
involve appeal to factive evidence ought to be relatively unproblematic. Suppose I am on the
phone to my boss, who expresses scepticism that a colleague is in work today (perhaps because
she tends to skip work whenever the boss is away). I might well naturally respond to such
scepticism by saying that I know that she’s in work because I can see that she’s here—she’s right
in front of me. Indeed, in the circumstances it would be very odd if I backed up my claim to know
by appealing to something that fell short of this factive evidence, such as by saying that it merely
seems to me as if she in front of me right now. The more qualified latter claim would only be
appropriate in very special kinds of conditions¾such as when one has been offered grounds for
thinking that what one sees is not to be relied upon (e.g., an hallucinogenic has been slipped into
one’s coffee)¾and would make no sense at all in conditions which one takes to be epistemically
paradigm. Of course, even the opponent of epistemological disjunctivism can accept this point
8
about our everyday epistemic practices. But they will contend that we shouldn’t take such practices
at face-value.
Second, the claim that epistemological disjunctivism is an attractive position, if true. Again,
I take this to be relatively uncontroversial, in that even opponents of epistemological disjunctivism
will likely grant this claim (in that they will focus instead on whether the position is true, rather
than whether it is attractive). Part of the attraction of the view resides in the fact already noted that
it offers a way of accommodating both epistemic externalist and internalist insights. Classical
epistemic internalism seems to cut-off evidential standing from worldly import, in that, in line with
(NEG), the best kind of evidential standing that our beliefs can enjoy is nonetheless entirely
compatible with massive error in our beliefs (i.e., of a kind that would hold in a radical sceptical
bad case, such as a BIV scenario). In contrast, classical epistemic externalism ensures that the
evidential standing of our beliefs can have genuine worldly import, but does so by making such
evidence opaque to us, in that it is no longer by its nature reflectively accessible. Epistemological
disjunctivism steers a midway course between both views by ensuring that our reflectively
accessible evidence can have worldly import (indeed, worldly import of the strongest kind, in
virtue of being factive).
Moreover, if we can make sense of such a position, then it has the potential to offer new
ways of approaching age-old epistemological problems. Consider, for example, the problem of
radical scepticism, which has bedeviled philosophy for millennia (or, at least, centuries anyway, if
we confine our attention to the specifically Cartesian variety of this problem). Radical sceptical
arguments essentially trade on the fact that the evidential support our beliefs enjoy, even in the
very best cases, can be no better than that enjoyed by the beliefs held by our counterparts who are
subject to radical sceptical scenarios, such as the BIV scenario. With this claim in place, it becomes
relatively easy for proponents of radical scepticism to leverage their radical sceptical conclusions.
And yet epistemological disjunctivism, if true, offers a way of cutting off this sceptical line of
argument at source, via its rejection of (NEG).24
The case for epistemological disjunctivism thus ultimately turns on whether it can block
the arguments against its viability. It would take us too far afield to consider all of the objections
one can put to epistemological disjunctivism, so let me instead focus on what I take to be the most
serious objection.25 All parties to this debate, including epistemological disjunctivists, will grant
that good and bad cases are, ex hypothesi, indistinguishable to the subject concerned. And yet, if
epistemological disjunctivism is true, then there is something reflectively accessible to the subject
in the good case¾viz., the factive reason¾that is unavailable to the subject in the bad case. Given
that this is so, why can’t the subject in the good case reflectively access the factive reason and on
this basis come to know that she is in the good case rather than the bad case? The problem is that,
9
if this is so, then it seems that the subject in the good case can come to know that she is in the
good case rather than the bad case, and hence can in a sense distinguish between good and bad
cases, something which, ex hypothesi, she is meant to be unable to do. Call this the distinguishability
problem for epistemological disjunctivism.
The way epistemological disjunctivists respond to this problem is by arguing that there can
be ways of knowing the difference which aren’t thereby ways of telling the difference, where the
latter involves a specific discriminative capacity. Moreover, they contend that this is a distinction
that all epistemologists should accept, and hence that it is dialectically available to the
epistemological disjunctivist (i.e., it is not a thesis that in any way already presupposes a
commitment to epistemological disjunctivism).
Set aside epistemological disjunctivism for a moment, and consider a case where a subject
comes to know, via perception, that there is a zebra in the enclosure before her at the zoo. In
normal circumstances, the kind of perceptual abilities needed to identify a zebra as such are fairly
limited. In particular, one would not need to possess the rather special perceptual ability to
discriminate between zebras and cleverly disguised mules. Now imagine that someone raises the
possibility that the creature might be a cleverly disguised mule. Note that they are not offering
evidence in support of this alternative scenario, but merely raising it as an alternative scenario.
Given that one cannot discriminate between zebras and cleverly disguised mules, does one still
know that the creature before one is a zebra?
Well, if this is still known, it is not in virtue of one’s perceptual abilities alone, since they
are, by stipulation, entirely silent about this possibility. But notice that this is not the only
epistemic support that one has available in this case. In particular, at least as far as most mature
subjects go, there will be a wealth of background evidence that one can bring to bear which
collectively excludes this error-possibility, such as what one knows about well-run zoos, the
plausibility of such a deception, the likelihood that such a deception would be spotted before long,
the costs involved in undertaking such a deception, and so on.26 With this background evidence
suitably marshaled, one is in an evidential position to enable one to know that the creature before
one is a zebra rather than a cleverly disguised mule even though one cannot perceptually
discriminate between zebras and cleverly disguised mules.27
The point is that with this distinction in play, the epistemological disjunctivist can appeal
to this distinction to explain why one might be able to know that one is in the good case rather
than the bad case. Just as in the scenario we have described, the error-possibility at issue is not
evidentially motivated, but merely raised as a possibility. Moreover, with epistemological
disjunctivism in play the subject has available to her a distinctive form of evidential support that is
factive. Putting these two points together, the subject in the good case has a reflective route
10
available to her where she can rationally conclude that she is in the good case rather than the bad
case. But this is entirely compatible with the undeniable fact that one lacks a discriminative faculty
that enables one to distinguish between good and bad cases.
5. CONCLUDING REMARKS
Of course, merely showing how epistemological disjunctivism might deal with a core objection
that it faces is not the same as offering a full defence of the view. But at least it demonstrates that
epistemological disjunctivism has resources available to meet objections (and recall also that the
objection just considered is claimed to be the most difficult one facing the view). We have, then, at
least a prima facie case for the viability of the position. Given the points made above about the way
in which such a position seems rooted in our everyday epistemic practices, and the attraction of
such a position if it were true, this makes the view very worthy of our further consideration,
particularly given that it occupies such a distinctive and unorthodox position in the normal
taxonomy of epistemological proposals.28
11
REFERENCES
BonJour, L. (1985). The Structure of Empirical Knowledge, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Dretske, F. (1969). Seeing and Knowing, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Cassam, Q. (2007). ‘Ways of Knowing’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 107, 339–58.
Chisholm, R. M. (1977). Theory of Knowledge (2nd edn.), Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Cohen, S. (1984). ‘Justification and Truth’, Philosophical Studies 46, 279-95.
Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (2004). Evidentialism: Essays in Epistemology, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Goldberg, S. (2016). ‘Comments on Pritchard’s Epistemological Disjunctivism’ Journal of
Philosophical Research 41, 183-91.
Goldman, A. (1976). ‘Discrimination and Perceptual Knowledge’, Journal of Philosophy 73, 771–91.
¾¾ (1979). ‘What Is Justified Belief?’, Justification and Knowledge, (ed.) G. Pappas, 1–23,
Dordrecht: Reidel.
¾¾ (1986). Epistemology and Cognition, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
¾¾ (1988). ‘Strong and Weak Justification’, Philosophical Perspectives 2: Epistemology, (ed.) J.
Tomberlin, 51–69, Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview.
Hinton, J. M. (1967a). ‘Experiences’, Philosophical Quarterly 17, 1–13.
¾¾ (1967b). ‘Visual Experiences’, Mind 76, 217–27.
¾¾ (1973). Experiences: An Inquiry into Some Ambiguities, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Lehrer, K., & Cohen, S. (1983). ‘Justification, Truth, and Coherence’, Synthese 55, 191–207.
Littlejohn, C. (2009). ‘The New Evil Demon Problem’, Internet Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, (eds.) B.
Dowden & J. Fieser, www.iep.utm.edu/evil-new/.
¾¾ (2015). ‘Knowledge and Awareness’, Analysis 75, 596-603.
¾¾ (2016). ‘Pritchard’s Reasons’, Journal of Philosophical Research 41, 201-19.
Martin, M. G. F. (2002). ‘The Transparency of Experience’, Mind and Language 17, 376-425.
¾¾ (2004). ‘The Limits of Self-Awareness’, Philosophical Studies 120, 37–89.
¾¾ (2006). ‘On Being Alienated’, Perceptual Experience, (ed.) T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne,
354–410, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
McDowell, J. (1994). ‘Knowledge by Hearsay’, Knowing from Words: Western and Indian Philosophical
Analysis of Understanding and Testimony, (eds.) B. K. Matilal & A. Chakrabarti, 195–224,
Dordrecht: Kluwer.
¾¾ (1995). ‘Knowledge and the Internal’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55, 877-93.
Neta, R. (2016). ‘How Holy is the Disjunctivist Grail?’, Journal of Philosophical Research 41, 193-200.
Neta, R., & Pritchard, D. H. (2007). ‘McDowell and the New Evil Genius’ Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research 74, 381-96.
Pritchard, D. H. (2007). ‘How to be a Neo-Moorean’, Internalism and Externalism in Semantics and
Epistemology, (ed.) S. Goldberg, 68-99, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
¾¾ (2008). ‘McDowellian Neo-Mooreanism’, Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge, (eds.) A.
Haddock & F. Macpherson, 283-310, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
¾¾ (2010). ‘Relevant Alternatives, Perceptual Knowledge, and Discrimination’, Noûs 44, 24568.
¾¾ (2011a). ‘Epistemological Disjunctivism and the Basis Problem’, Philosophical Issues 21, 43455.
¾¾ (2011b). ‘Evidentialism, Internalism, Disjunctivism’, Evidentialism and its Discontents, (ed.) T.
Dougherty, 362-92, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
¾¾ (2012). Epistemological Disjunctivism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
¾¾ (2015a). Epistemic Angst: Radical Skepticism and the Groundlessness of Our Believing, Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press.
12
¾¾ (2015b). ‘Précis of Epistemological Disjunctivism’, Analysis 75, 589-95.
¾¾ (2015c). ‘Responses to My Critics’, Analysis 75, 627-37.
¾¾ (2016a). ‘Précis of Epistemological Disjunctivism’, Journal of Philosophical Research 41, 17581.
¾¾ (2016b). ‘Responses to My Critics’, Journal of Philosophical Research 41, 221-38.
—— (2018a). ‘Epistemic Angst’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 96 (2018), 70-90
¾¾ (2018b). ‘Epistemological Disjunctivism and the Biscopic Treatment of Radical
Scepticism’, The Factive Turn in Epistemology, (ed.) V. Mitova, 15-31, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
—— (2019). ‘Epistemological Disjunctivism and Anti-Luck Virtue Epistemology’, New Issues in
Epistemological Disjunctivism, (eds.) C. Doyle, J. Milburn & D. H. Pritchard, 41-58, London:
Routledge.
¾¾ (2023). ‘Moderate Knowledge Externalism’, Externalism About Knowledge, (ed.) L R. G.
Oliveira, 131-49, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
¾¾ (Forthcoming). ‘Shadowlands’, The New Evil Demon: New Essays on Knowledge, Justification and
Rationality, (eds.) F. Dorsch & J. Dutant, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Pritchard, D. H., & Ranalli, C. (2017). ‘Scepticism and Disjunctivism’, Skepticism: From Antiquity to
the Present, (eds.) D. Machuca & B. Reed, 652-67, London: Bloomsbury.
Schönbaumsfeld, G. (2015). ‘Epistemological Disjunctivism, by Duncan Pritchard’, Analysis 75, 604-15.
¾¾ (2016). The Illusion of Doubt, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Snowdon, P. (1980–1). ‘Perception, Vision and Causation’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (new
series) 81, 175–92.
¾¾ (1990–1). ‘The Objects of Perceptual Experience’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (suppl.
vol.) 64, 121–50.
Soteriou, M. (2014). ‘The Disjunctive Theory of Perception’, Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy,
(ed.) E. Zalta, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/perception-disjunctive/.
Turri, J. (2010). ‘Does Perceiving Entail Knowing?’, Theoria 76, 197–206.
Vogel, J. (1990). ‘Cartesian Skepticism and Inference to the Best Explanation’, Journal of Philosophy
87, 658-66.
Williamson, T. (2000a). Knowledge and its Limits, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
¾¾ (2000b). ‘Scepticism and Evidence’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60, 613–28.
Wittgenstein, L. (1969). On Certainty, (eds.) G. E. M. Anscombe & G. H. von Wright, (tr.) D. Paul
& G. E. M. Anscombe, Blackwell, Oxford.
Zalabardo, J. (2015). ‘Epistemic Disjunctivism and the Evidential Problem’ Analysis 75, 615-27.
13
NOTES
Note that for convenience I have immediately opted for an illustrative instance of the bad case that involves a
radical sceptical scenario. Bad cases needn’t be so radical, however¾a localised hallucination, for example, where
one’s perception is disturbed only in some specific respect, could also count as a bad case.
2 For some of the key defences of metaphysical disjunctivism, see Hinton (1967a; 1967b; 1973), Snowdon (1980–1;
1990–1), and Martin (2002; 2004; 2006). For an excellent survey of the range of metaphysical disjunctivist positions on
offer in the literature, see Soteriou (2014). See also Pritchard & Ranalli (2017) for a survey of disjunctivist views as
they bear on the problem of radical scepticism.
3 See especially Prichard (2012). See also Neta & Pritchard (2007), Pritchard (2007; 2008; 2011a; 2011b; 2015a; 2018a;
2018b). For two recent symposia on Pritchard (2012), see: Littlejohn (2015), Pritchard (2015b; 2015c), Schönbaumsfeld
(2015), and Zalabardo (2015); and Goldberg (2016), Littlejohn (2016), Neta (2016), and Pritchard (2016a; 2016b). See
also Williamson’s (2000a; 2000b) knowledge-first account, which has some parallels with epistemological disjunctivism,
but which is also sufficiently dissimilar that it is best to keep apart from the view (e.g., in that it is explicitly cast as a
form of epistemic externalism rather than epistemic internalism). I briefly discuss this proposal at several junctures
below¾see endnotes 11, 19 and 20. See also Pritchard (2011b).
4 Note that we are here setting aside the possibility that there might be independent rational support that could be
brought to bear which enables one to rationally conclude that one is in the good case rather than the bad case, such as
abductive reasons. See Vogel (1990) for a sophisticated defence of such a proposal. See Pritchard (2015, part 1) for a
general critique of this sort of proposal, particularly as it might function in the context of a radical sceptical bad case.
5 Indeed, on standard views of seeing that p¾see Dretske (1969), Williamson (2000a, ch. 1), and Cassam (2007), for
instance¾seeing that p actual entails knowing that p. But even on proposals that reject this entailment thesis¾e.g.,
Pritchard (2011a; 2012, part 1)¾it is still maintained that seeing that p is a robustly epistemic notion in that it
necessarily puts one in an objectively good position to know that p. For further critical discussion of the putative
entailment between seeing that p and knowing that p, see Turri (2010)
6 It’s actually far from clear what the epistemological disjunctivist should say about the subject’s rational standing in
the bad case. See Pritchard (forthcoming) for discussion of this point.
7 The point about there being no significant common core of rational support which applies to both cases is to
accommodate the point noted above with regard to metaphysical disjunctivism, which is that there is undeniably a
negative epistemological property that is common to both cases¾i.e., that the cases are indistinguishable to the
subject.
8 McDowell (1994; 1995) certainly seems amenable to this approach, even going so far as to suggest that it might
work for inductive knowledge (which is arguably the least plausible domain to introduce epistemological
disjunctivism).
9 See Pritchard (2011a; 2012, part 1) for an account of what makes a scenario epistemically paradigm.
10 Part of the issue here is that I think we in any case need a more nuanced conception of rational support, something
which a straightforward translation between reasons and evidence will obscure. See Pritchard (forthcoming) for more on
this point.
11 Interestingly, Williamson’s (2000a; 2000b) knowledge-first account¾which as noted above (see endnote 3) has
some similarities to epistemological disjunctivism¾is directly expressed in terms of evidence rather than reasons.
12 For two key defences of accessibilism, see Chisholm (1977) and Bonjour (1985, ch. 2).
13 The locus classicus when it comes to defences of mentalism is Conee & Feldman (2004).
14 For two key defences of the new evil genius intuition, see Lehrer & Cohen (1983) and Cohen (1984). See also the
excellent survey article of work on this topic by Littlejohn (2009).
15 Much of the debate is concerned with the relative merits of accessibilism or mentalism as the overarching account
of epistemic internalism. See, for example, Conee & Feldman (2004).
16 Such a position is, of course, most closely associated with Goldman’s (1976; 1979; 1986; 1988) work.
17 Indeed, that is in fact my own position. See Pritchard (2019; 2023).
18 See, for example, Conee & Feldman (2004).
19 This is yet another juncture on which epistemological disjunctivism diverges from Williamson’s (2000a; 2000b)
knowledge-first account¾which as noted above (see endnote 3) bears some noteworthy similarities¾in that the latter
always treats evidence as factive (since it has probability 1), whereas epistemological disjunctivism is not committed to
this claim.
20 Interestingly, Williamson’s (2000a; 2000b) knowledge-first approach, which as noted above (see endnote 3) bears
some similarities to epistemological disjunctivism, is in fact a non-classical form epistemic externalism. This is because,
unlike process reliabilism, it is at least consistent with one core epistemic internalist thesis, that of mentalism (at least
on a liberal construal of this thesis). See Pritchard (2011b) for discussion of this point.
21 That is, standard forms of epistemic externalism often treat the intuitions behind (NEG) as something that needs
to be accommodated by their own proposals. Consider, for example, how Goldman (1986; 1988) modifies his process
reliabilism in order to account for why there might be a sense in which a subject’s epistemic position is no better than
that enjoyed by her envatted counterpart.
1
14
22 As I rather provocatively put the point in Pritchard (2012, 1), epistemological disjunctivism is the “holy grail” of
epistemology.
23 See Pritchard (2012) for just such a negative defence of epistemological disjunctivism along this three-stage line.
See also McDowell (1995) for a similarly negative defence of the view, though as I explain in Pritchard (2012, part 3),
McDowell’s defence is allied to a broader philosophical quietism.
24 For more details regarding how epistemological disjunctivism might be marshaled against radical scepticism, see
Pritchard (2007; 2008; 2012). Note, however, that in more recent work I have argued that epistemological
disjunctivism fares much better as an anti-sceptical strategy when it is paired with the kind of hinge epistemology outlined
by Wittgenstein (1969). See, for example, Pritchard (2015a; 2018a; 2018b).
25 For a fuller list of objections against epistemological disjunctivism, and the development of counterarguments, see
Pritchard (2012, passim).
26 If such background evidence is lacking, then I think we should allow that the mere raising of this error-possibility
could defeat knowledge. After all, if one really has no evidential basis for preferring the zebra scenario over the
competing cleverly disguised mule scenario, then it is hard to see how one can have a sufficient evidential basis for
knowing the former.
27 See Pritchard (2010) for a more detailed defence of this claim, and why it undermines various kinds of
epistemological revisionism, such as certain arguments against the closure principle, epistemic contrastivism, epistemic
contextualism, and so on.
28 Thanks to Giada Fratantonio, John Greco, Ram Neta, and Michael Williams for some useful discussions about
epistemological disjunctivism and evidence/reasons.