tripleC 11(2): 294-309, 2013
http://www.triple-c.at
Why and How to Read Marx’s “Capital”? Reflections on Johan Fornäs’ book “Capitalism. A Companion to Marx’s Economy Critique”. London: Routledge, 2013. ISBN 978-0-41582342-5 (hbk), 978-0-203-5515-6 (ebook). 360 pages.
Christian Fuchs
*University of Westminster, UK;
christian.fuchs@uti.at, www.fuchs.uti.at
Abstract: This paper presents reflections on Johan Fornäs’ book “Capitalism. A Companion to Marx’s
Economy Critique”.
Keywords: Karl Marx, Das Kapital Volumes 1/2/3, Capital Volumes 1/2,/3, Critique of Political Economy, Johan
Fornäs, capitalism
Context
The new world economic crisis that started in 2008 has created a renewed interest in Karl
Marx’s works, especially his main work Das Kapital. There seems to be the hope that one
can better understood the roots of the crisis by reading capitalism’s most profound critic. This
circumstance has resulted in the publication of guides to Marx, including Elmar Altvater’s
(2012) Marx neu entdecken (Rediscovering Marx), Terry Eagleton’s (2012) Why Marx Was
Right, David Harvey’s A Companion to Marx’s Capital (Harvey 2010) and A Companion to
Marx’s Capital Volume 2 (Harvey 2013), Wolfgang Fritz Haug’s Das „Kapital“ lesen – aber
wie? Materialien (Reading Capital – But How? Materials), the English translation of Michael
Heinrich’s (2012) introductory book to Capital (An Introduction to the Three Volumes of
Marx’s Capital, originally published in German in 2004), Eric Hobsbawm’s (2010) How to
Change the World. Tales of Marx and Marxism, Frederic Jameson’s (2011) Representing
Capital: A Reading of Volume One, Jonathan Sperber’s (2013) biography Karl Marx: A Nineteenth-Century Life. Hobsbawm’s book is a political history of Marxism, Sperber’s work a
biography and Eagleton’s intervention a powerful defence of Marx’s works against common
criticisms that are exposed as being false. The remaining books are all introductions to Marx,
but fall short of this goal because they tend to advance very specific interpretations of Capital
to which the authors are committed. They therefore only have limited value for readers who
want to have an accompanying guide that makes understanding Capital easier.
The return of the interest in Marx’s works also manifested itself in the field of Media and
Communication Studies, as the large number of submissions to and the large interest in tripleC’s special issue Marx is Back – The Importance of Marxist Theory and Research for Critical Communication Studies Today (Fuchs and Mosco 2012) has shown. A further development is signified by the publication of the book Capitalism. A Companion to Marx’s Economy
Critique: its author Johan Fornäs is a well-established Media and Cultural Studies scholar
who now published a general book about Marx. He has over the years published many important contributions to theory and research in Critical Media and Cultural Studies. His new
book is an introductory companion to all three volumes of Marx’s Capital. Fornäs takes an
approach different from many other contemporary Marx books in that he does not want to
give a specific narrow interpretation of Marx that is disguised as introductory book, but wants
to provide a broad introduction: “The guiding principle has been to understand what Marx
actually wrote leave the elaboration of that meaning in relation to later theories maximally
open” (p. 5).
CC: Creative Commons License, 2013.
295
tripleC 11(2): 294-309 2013
Method and Logic of Presentation
For the author, Marxism “is a method designed for investigating the inner complexities of
capitalism and offering tools to comprehend and criticise the social reality we live in” that
connects “theoretical understanding and political action” (p. 2). He points out that political
economy “denotes the whole system of capitalist society” and “the self-understanding of this
society according to leading capitalist ideologies” (p. 3). Marx developed a critique of capitalism and bourgeois ideologies that justify this system. So his approach is a Critique of Political
Economy. At the same time one can add that Marx in developing this twofold critique worked
through existing political economic theories and also the history of capitalism by reviewing
the available empirical data with rigour. This allowed him not only to formulate a twofold critique, but to also his own alternative political-economic theory that consists of categories that
are grounded in classical political economy, but at the same time go beyond them and the
limits they pose for critically understanding capitalism.
Fornäs stresses that Marx’s method is focused on understanding “capitalism as a totality”
(p. 13) and that today’s academia is (not just in economics!) so much dominated and shaped
by business and management studies that “[n]obody looks at the totality anymore” (p. 8).
Marx reminds us of the importance to critically engage with the large power structures that
shape our lives. Fornäs stresses that dialectics is a “form of thought” that “helps us understand the inner tensions of capitalism” (p. 26). The question that arises in this respect is if
dialectics is a method of thought, critical understanding, analysis and investigation or if it is
also a principle that is immanent in the development of reality itself: contradictions are not
just human thought-forms, but exist in the dynamic reality of capitalism itself. Crises are the
factual proof of this circumstance. Dialectics is a principle that structures human experiences
and social reality, it is the science of totality that wants to understand the dialecticity of the
totality itself and of all its constituting interconnected moments (Holz 2005, 2011; Fuchs
2011, chapter 2.4). This means that dialectics exists as dialectic of the dialectics of the subjective world and the dialectics of the objective world (Fuchs 2011, section 2.4.3; Holz 2005,
9-18).
The book consists of 15 chapters: the introduction (chapter 1) is followed by chapters on
Marx’s method (2), commodities and money (3), capital (4), surplus (5), production (6), accumulation (7), primitive accumulation (8), circulation of capital (9), reproduction of the total
capital (10), the rate of profit (11), crises (12); trade, banks and land (13), mystifying realities
(14), futures (15). A postscript points out further discussion questions. The book structure is
accessible, but the reader of Marx’s Capital faces the problem that it is not immediately clear,
which chapters of the three volumes are discussed in which chapter of Fornäs’ book. A structure of chapters and sections that discusses all of Marx’s chapters sequentially and includes
references to the chapter numbers of Marx’s three volumes in the chapter and section titles
and the table of contents would be helpful. If this for some reasons cannot be achieved, then
at least a table that lists all of Marx’s chapters and maps them to the sections and chapters in
the book would be helpful. My own experience in teaching Marx has been that what students
most look for when engaging with Capital is an accompanying text that is organized chapter
by chapter. So the structure of the book is not immediately clear. This is somewhat offset by
the fact that the introductory paragraphs of each chapter describe very well what is covered
in it and how this relates to the broader context of Marx’s works. For teaching purposes,
books that have the chapter numbers of Marx’s works in the chapter and section titles tend to
however work better. Table 1 provides a mapping of Marx’s chapters to the chapters in Johan Fornäs’ book. The perfect, well-structured introduction to all three volumes of Capital
would have 106 main chapters, one for each chapter in Marx’s three books. David Harvey
(2010, 2013) attempts to structure his companions to Capital this way, but the problem of
these books is that they tend to be more David Harvey than Karl Marx, i.e. they are attempts
to promote a quite specific (although interesting and important) interpretation of Marx. One of
the merits of Fornäs‘ introduction is that it largely resists such transmogrifications of Marx
into something and somebody different.
Chapter 15 in Fornäs’ book summarizes the overall logic and content of Capital’s three vol-
CC: Creative Commons License, 2013.
Christian Fuchs
296
umes. Inspired by Ernst Bloch’s Marxist principle of hope it argues that capitalism not just
has a negative reality, but produces the foundations of its own abolition and for alternative
futures. Therefore “Marxist theory never ends, as long as capitalism continues” (p. 276).
Marxism is future-oriented. Johan Fornäs engages in this context with the notions of communism and socialism and shows how Marx used them. “Communism derives from the Latin
word communis, which means something shared that belongs to everybody, whereas socialism comes from the Latin socius, for companion. Both thus point at something owned or
made collectively together with others” (p. 281). The chapter also points out sources of and
influences on Marx’s thinking, gives a brief overview of readings of Marx and discusses ambivalences in Marx’s works. The book’s postface contains 170 questions for discussion and
further reflection. They are organized chapter-wise.
Fornäs
Chapter 3
Marx’s Capital
Volume 1: chapters 1-3
Chapter 4
Vol. 1: chapters 4-6
Chapter 5
Vol. 1: chapters 7-12
Chapter 6
Vol. 1: chapters 13-22
Chapter 7
Vol. 1: chapters 23-25
Chapter Titles in Marx’s Capital
Part One: Commodities and Money
Chapter 1: Commodities
Chapter 2: The Process of Exchange
Chapter 3: Money, or the Circulation of Commodities
Part Two: The Transformation of Money into Capital
Chapter 4: The General Formula for Capital
Chapter 5: Contradictions in the General Formula
Chapter 6: The Sale and Purchase of LabourPower
Part Three: The Production of Absolute SurplusValue
Chapter 7: The Labour Process and the Valorization Process
Chapter 8: Constant Capital and Variable Capital
Chapter 9: The Rate of Surplus-Value
Chapter 10: The Working-Day
Chapter 11: The Rate and Mass of Surplus-Value
Part Four: The Production of Relative SurplusValue
Chapter 12: The Concept of Relative SurplusValue
Chapter 13: Co-operation
Chapter 14: The Division of Labour and Manufacture
Chapter 15: Machinery and Large-Scale Industry
Part Five: The Production of Absolute and Relative
Surplus-Value
Chapter 16: Absolute and Relative Surplus-Value
Chapter 17: Changes of Magnitude in the Price of
Labour-Power and in Surplus-Value
Chapter 18: Different Formulae for the Rate of
Surplus-Value
Part Six: Wages
Chapter 19: The Transformation of the Value (and
Respectively the Price) of Labour-Power into Wages
Chapter 20: Time-Wages
Chapter 21: Piece-Wages
Chapter 22: National Differences in Wage
Part Seven: The Process of Accumulation of CapiCC: Creative Commons License, 2013.
tripleC 11(2): 294-309 2013
297
Chapter 8
Vol. 1: chapters 25-33
Chapter 9
Vol. II: chapters 1-17
Chapter 10
Vol. II: chapters 18-21
Chapter 11
Vol. III: chapters 1-12
tal
Chapter 23: Simple Reproduction
Chapter 24: The Transformation of Surplus-Value
into Capital
Chapter 25: The General Law of Capitalist Accumulation
Part Eight: So-Called. Primitive Accumulation
Chapter 26: The Secret of Primitive Accumulation
Chapter 27: The Expropriation of the Agricultural
Population from the Land
Chapter 28: Bloody Legislation against the Expropriated since the End of the Fifteenth Century. The
Forcing Down of Wages by Act of Parliament
Chapter 29: The Genesis of the Capitalist Farmer
Chapter 30: Impact of the Agricultural Revolution
on Industry. The Creation of a Home Market for
Industrial Capital
Chapter 31: The Genesis of the Industrial Capitalist
Chapter 32: The Historical Tendency of Capitalist
Accumulation
Chapter 33: The Modern Theory of Colonization
Part One: The Metamorphoses of Capital and their
Circuit
Chapter 1: The Circuit of Money Capital
Chapter 2: The Circuit of Productive Capital
Chapter 3: The Circuit of Commodity Capital
Chapter 4: The Three Figures of the Circuit
Chapter 5: Circulation Time
Chapter 6: The Costs of Circulation
Part Two: The Turnover of Capital
Chapter 7: Turnover Time and Number of Turnovers
Chapter 8: Fixed Capital and Circulating Capital
Chapter 9: The Overall Turnover of the Capital
Advanced. Turnover Cycles
Chapter 10: Theories of Fixed and Circulating Capital. The Physiocrats and Adam Smith
Chapter 11: Theories of Fixed and Circulating Capital. Ricardo
Chapter 12: The Working Period
Chapter 13: Production Time
Chapter 14: Circulation Time
Chapter 15: Effect of Circulation Time on the Magnitude of the Capital Advanced
Chapter 16: The Turnover of Variable Capital
Chapter 17: The Circulation of Surplus-Value
Part Three: The Reproduction and Circulation of
the Total Social Capital
Chapter 18: Introduction
Chapter 19: Former Presentations of the Subject
Chapter 20: Simple Reproduction
Chapter 21: Accumulation and Reproduction on an
Expanded Scale
Part One: The Transformation of Surplus-Value
into Profit, and of the Rate of Surplus-Value into
CC: Creative Commons License, 2013.
Christian Fuchs
298
Chapter 12
Vol. III: chapters 13-15
Chapter 13
Vol. III: chapters 16-47
the Rate of Profit
Chapter 1: Cost Price and Profit
Chapter 2: The Rate of Profit
Chapter 3: The Relationship between Rate of Profit
and Rate of Surplus-Value
Chapter 4: The Effect of the Turnover on the Rate
of Profit
Chapter 5: Economy in the Use of Constant Capital
Chapter 6: The Effect of Changes in Price
Chapter 7: Supplementary Remarks
Part Two: The Transformation of Profit into Average Profit
Chapter 8: Different Compositions of Capital in
Different Branches of Production, and the Resulting Variation in Rates of Profit
Chapter 9: Formation of a General Rate of Profit
(Average Rate of Profit), and Transformation of
Commodity Values into Prices of Production
Chapter 10: The Equalization of the General Rate
of Profit through Competition. Market Prices and
Market Values. Surplus Profit
Chapter 11: The Effects of General Fluctuations in
Wages on the Prices of Production
Chapter 12: Supplementary Remarks
Part Three: The Law of the Tendential Fall in the
Rate of Profit
Chapter 13: The Law Itself
Chapter 14: Counteracting Factors
Chapter 15: Development of the Law's Internal
Contradictions
Part Four: The Transformation of Commodity Capital and Money Capital into Commercial Capital and
Money-Dealing Capital (Merchant’s Capital)
Chapter 16: Commercial Capital
Chapter 17: Commercial Profit
Chapter 18: The Turnover of Commercial Capital.
Prices
Chapter 19. Money-Dealing Capital
Chapter 20: Historical Material on Merchant's Capital
Part Five: The Division of Profit into Interest and
Profit of Enterprise
Chapter 21: Interest-Bearing Capital
Chapter 22: Division of Profit. Rate of Interest.
"Natural" Rate of Interest
Chapter 23: Interest and Profit of Enterprise
Chapter 24: Interest-Bearing Capital as the Superficial Form of the Capital Relation
Chapter 25: Credit and Fictitious Capital
Chapter 26: Accumulation of Money Capital, and
its Influence on the Rate of Interest
Chapter 27: The Role of Credit in Capitalist Production
Chapter 28: Means of Circulation and CApital. The
Views of Tooke and Fullarton
CC: Creative Commons License, 2013.
tripleC 11(2): 294-309 2013
299
Chapter 14
Vol. 3: chapters 48-52
Chapter 29: Banking Capital's Component Parts
Chapter 30: Money Capital and Real Capital: I
Chapter 31: Money Capital and Real Capital: II
(Continuation)
Chapter 32: Money Capital and Real Capital: III
(Conclusion)
Chapter 33: The Means of Circulation under the
Credit System
Chapter 34: The Currency Principle and the English Bank Legislation of 1844
Chapter 35: Precious Metal and Rate of Exchange
Chapter 36: Pre-Capitalist Relations
Part Six: The Transformation of Surplus Profit into
Ground-Rent
Chapter 37: Introduction
Chapter 38: Differential Rent in General
Chapter 39: The First Form of Differential Rent
(Differential Rent I)
Chapter 40: The Second Form of Differential Rent
(Differential Rent II)
Chapter 41: Differential Rent II - First Case: Price
of Production Constant
Chapter 42: Differential Rent II - Second Case:
Price of Production Falling
Chapter 43: Differential Rent II - Third Case: Rising
Price of Production. Results
Chapter 44: Differential Rent Even on the Poorest
Land Cultivated
Chapter 45: Absolute Ground-Rent
Chapter 46: Rent of Buildings. Rent of Mines. Price
of Land
Chapter 47: The Genesis of Capitalist GroundRent
Part Seven: The Revenues and their Sources
Chapter 48: The Trinity Formula
Chapter 49: On the Analysis of the Production Process
Chapter 50: The Illusion Created by Competition
Chapter 51: Relations of Distribution and Relations
of Production
Chapter 52: Classes
Table 1: A mapping of chapters (sources: Fornäs 2013; Marx 1867, 1885, 1894)
Marx’s presentation style is not linear, although readers of course tend to read his books in a
linear manner. Fornäs is aware of the interconnectedness of concepts and of the networked
and interlinked structure of Marx’s theory. He therefore in a helpful manner cross-references
other chapters, other of Marx’s works and secondary literature. The book avoids jargon and
is easily accessible to the reader. The author is a very well-versed Marx-expert and understands how to explain Marx’s concepts and theory in a way that does not confuse the reader
of Marx’s Capital, but rather can help her/him to find clarification of the unclarities that can
easily arise while engaging with Marx. Marx’s Capital is not an easy read. It is a demanding
book whose concepts and language pose challenges for the reader. Accompanying literature
should therefore try to be as clear and accessible as possible. Johan Fornäs’ book achieves
this very well and is an accessible and extensive guide to Marx’s critical theory of capitalism
CC: Creative Commons License, 2013.
Christian Fuchs
300
that was elaborated in the three volumes of Capital. The book is very well suited as accompanying literature for reading Marx’s Capital.
Fornäs does not conceal his own sympathies with unorthodox interpretations of Marx,
especially the Frankfurt School, the importance he gives to ideology critique, the definition of
ideology as false consciousness and the importance of Marx’s fetish chapter, but he never
imposes his own preferred Marxist approach and interpretation of Marx on the reader. There
“is no single, ‘correct’ reading of Marx!” (p. 302). Ideology critique is particularly important for
Fornäs, as chapter 14 shows, but it does not substitute the engagement with basic economic
structures in the book. In contrast, Fornäs shows how ideology has its foundations in the
structures of capitalism. Ideology would mystify capitalism (p. 255) in a series of fetishisms:
the fetishism of commodities, money, wages, capital, circulation, unproductive labour, profit,
average profit and prices, commercial capital and land (pp. 255f). Bourgeois ideology would
take on specific forms that are all figures of capital fetishism (pp. 257-262). Fornäs’ longstanding interest in studying culture may be an expression of his special interest in ideology.
Political power and culture would have a relative autonomy from the economy (p. 305). Coming to grips with culture, communication, gender, ethnicity and age would require combining
Marx with other theorists, such as Habermas, Bourdieu, Stuart Hall or Nancy Fraser (p. 305).
The Logical and the Historical in Marx’s Works
Fornäs stresses that Capital is largely a logical text (p. 23) that conceptually develops the
system of capitalism by advancing from the abstract to the concrete, adding ever more categories and levels of analysis. Capital would however also contain historical passages that
deal with the history of capitalism, such as the ones on primitive accumulation (p. 139). Wolfgang Fritz Haug (1974, 2006, 2013) argues for a historical interpretation of Capital that he
terms genetic reconstruction: Marx would in the dialectical analysis of capitalism take social
forms characteristic for pre-capitalist societies and the early stage of capitalism into account
in order to describe the emergence of specifically capitalist categories (Haug 2006, 41; Haug
1974, 191). Haug (2013) interprets Marx’s (1867, chapter 1.3) value-form analysis as a historical process, whereas for Michael Heinrich (2012, 56) the value-form analysis does not
show “the historical emergence of money, but rather a conceptual relationship of development”. Heinrich is a representative of a school of Marxist thought known as the “New Reading of Marx”-School (Neue Marx-Lektüre) that was formed in Germany and is grounded in the
works of Hans-Georg Backhaus (2011) and Helmut Reichelt (2001, 2008), who interpret
Marx’s value-form analysis in a logical way, oppose a historical interpretation and have argued for a monetary value theory. Heinrich (2012, 63) in his introductory book to Marx’s three
volumes of Capital even claims that “Marx’s value theory is rather a monetary theory of value”. He thereby deceives the readers and wants to create the impression that a specific interpretation of Marx – the one advanced by Backhaus, Reichelt, Heinrich and their colleagues – is Marx’s original and own version of the labour theory of value and that other interpretations are mistaken. The problem of this reading of Marx is that it implies that it splits
off the entire concept of value from Marx and thereby assumes that no exploitation takes
place if a commodity is not sold (Fuchs 2014a, chapter 2; Haug 2013). “Marx’s value formanalytical theory of money is inverted into a money-theoretical (‘monetary’) theory of value”
that is ahistorical (Haug 2013, 153).
Haug is critical of the New Reading of Marx-School, but the problem of his approach (see
Haug 1974, 2006, 2013) is that he opposes the logical to the historical and rejects any systematic reading and presentation of Marx. There is not much more in his reading of Marx
than the insight that dialectics means that capitalism and society are historical, that time is an
important category for dialectical philosophy and for understanding capitalism and that he
stresses a philosophy of praxis, where dialectics is lived in class struggle. The focus on political praxis substitutes for any systematic reconstruction of the dialectical logic in Marx’s
works, which becomes already apparent if one takes a look at the table of contents of Haug’s
(1974, 2006) Lectures on the Introduction to “Capital”. Systematic dialectical thinking is the
best tool of thought for strengthening the systematic development of class struggle strate-
CC: Creative Commons License, 2013.
301
tripleC 11(2): 294-309 2013
gies. Systematic dialectics is therefore not detached from praxis: successful class struggle
requires systematic dialectical thinking. And this is exactly what one can best learn from
Marx. Reading Marx’s Capital is helpful today because a) it allows us to understand how capitalism works in general and to think about how it works now and b) Capital is grounded in a
systematic-dialectical mode of thinking that can help readers of Marx to understand how to
develop systematic and dialectical strategies of struggle.
David Harvey (2010, 86) argues that he has “preferred the logical reading to the historical
one, even though there may be important historical insights to be gained in considering the
circumstances necessary to facilitate the rise of a capitalist mode of production”. Wolfgang
Fritz Haug (2013, 183-188, 223) argues that Harvey says that he gives a logical interpretation, although his approach is much more genetic-reconstructive and oriented on human
praxis. Haug (2013, section 10.2) discusses how Harvey treats the question of the logical
and the historical in Marx’s chapter on Machinery and Large-Scale Industry (Marx 1867,
chapter 15), which is the longest part of Capital Volume 1. Haug (2013, section 10.2) criticizes that Harvey (2010, 189) says on the one hand that the chapter’s sections “are logically
ordered” and stresses on the other hand that it is “a critical history of technology”. He says
that Harvey understands the logical simply as “everything not historical” and as “conceptual”
(Haug 2013, 228). Haug (2013) himself does however also not provide an analysis of the
longest chapter in Capital Volume 1 that could clarify the relationship of the dialectical-logical
and the historical. Chapter 15 is in the English version is almost 150 pages long and is of
particular interest for a critical sociology of technology and the media. It is also one of the
chapters in Volume 1 that contains the most historical elements. I can here not give a detailed analysis of the entire chapter, but want to point out some aspects of the relationship of
the historical and the dialectical-logical in it.
Marx (1867, 494) defines three components of machinery that he introduces in chapter
15’s first section: the motor mechanism, the transmitting mechanism and the working machine. Whereas in a manufactory many physical labour processes were sequentially executed in order to create a product, in the machine system many individual production steps are
combined in the working machine and many working machines operate in parallel:
A real machine system, however, does not take the place of these independent
machines until the object of labour goes through a connected series of graduated
processes carried out by a chain of mutually complementary machines of various
kinds. Here we have again the co-operation by division of labour which is peculiar
to manufacture, but now it appears as a combination of machines with specific
functions. The tools peculiar t o the various specialized workers, such as those of
the beaters, combers, shearers, spinners, etc. in the manufacture of wool, are now
transformed into the tools of specialized machines, each machine forming a special organ, with a special function in the combined mechanism (Marx 1867, 501).
Each particular machine supplies raw material to the machine next in line; and
since they are all working at the same time, the product is always going through
the various stages of its formation, and is also constantly in a state of transition
from one phase of production to another (Marx 1867, 502).
CC: Creative Commons License, 2013.
Christian Fuchs
302
Figure 1: Marx’s dialectical concept of the machine system in Capital Volume 1’s chapter 15.
For Marx, production means that a subject (labour power) uses objects (means of production) to create a labour product (a subject-object) (see Fuchs 2014a, chapter 2). Each working machine is a dialectical system that creates a product. In a machine system, working
machines are dialectically connected to each other so that the labour-product created in one
stage enters as object of labour into the labour process that is part of another working machine in the next stage. Figure 1 shows the dialectic of the machine system. It visualizes the
cooperation of three working machines WM1, WM2, WM3 at three temporal stages of production t1, t2, t3 so that changing products P1, P2, P3 that pass from one working machine
to the next are created.
Chapter 15’s first section is a dialectical combination of historical and dialectical elements:
Marx describes the historical development of the predominance of physical labour towards
machines and machine systems. At the same time this historical transition changes the logic
of how the productive forces are organized, which Marx describes by making use of dialectical reasoning. The historical is itself dialectical because the machine system dialectically
sublates (aufheben) physical labour and simple machines. In chapter 15, Marx describes in
detail which effects the machine system has on society. He does so by logically and dialectically characterizing phenomena such as the prolongation of the working day, the intensification of labour, the inversion of subject and object and of means and ends of production as
process of alienation, etc. Marx characterizes and theorizes these phenomena dialectically
and shows based on reports of factory inspectors how these dimensions of capitalist industry
shaped the life of workers in Great Britain in the 19th century. The historical dimension is a
detailed analysis of the bad working conditions wageworkers were facing. It is coupled to a
dialectical analysis of technology in capitalism and its effects on everyday life.
A crucial theoretical aspect of chapter 15 is that Marx argues that technology in capitalism
does not serve human needs, but is a means of domination and relative surplus-value production that puts the logic of profit above human interests. Marx expresses this circumstance
as inversion of means and ends and of subject and object, i.e. an antagonism between
worker and technology that is caused by class relations into which both are embedded:
These two descriptions are far from being identical. In one, the combined collective worker appears as the dominant subject [übergreifendes Subjekt], and the
mechanical automaton as the object; in the other, the automaton itself is the
CC: Creative Commons License, 2013.
303
tripleC 11(2): 294-309 2013
subject, and the workers are merely conscious organs, co-ordinated with the
unconscious organs of the automaton, and together with the latter subordinated
to the central moving force. The first description is applicable to every possible
employment of machinery on a large scale, the second is characteristic of its
use by capital, and therefore of the modern factory system (Marx 1867, 544f).
Factory work exhausts the nervous system to the uttermost; at the same time, it
does away with the many-sided play of the muscles, and confiscates every atom of freedom, both in bodily and in intellectual activity. Even the lightening of
the labour becomes an instrument of torture, since the machine does not free
the worker from the work, but rather deprives the work itself of all content. Every
kind of capitalist production, in so f a r as it is not only a labour process but also
capital's process of valorization, has this in common, but it is not the worker who
employs the conditions of his work, but rather the reverse, the conditions of
work employ the worker. However, it is only with the coming of machinery that
this inversion first acquires a technical and palpable reality. Owing to its conversion into an automaton, the instrument of labour confronts the worker during the
labour process in the shape of capital, dead labour, which dominates and soaks
up living labour-power. The separation of the intellectual faculties of the production process f r om manual labour, and the transformation of those faculties into
powers exercised by capital over labour, is, as we have already shown, finally
completed by large-scale industry erected on the foundation of machinery (Marx
1867, 548f).
Figure 2 shows the inversion of subject and object typical for capitalism that Marx theorizes
and analyzes in chapter 15. It presents this process dialectical-logically. There is however
also a historical dimension to it: independent craftsman in pre-capitalist economies controlled
their means of production and their labour power, they were not alienated from both. In capitalism there is a tendency of the commodification of labour power and the private ownership
of the means of production by a dominant class that makes others work for a wage.
Figure 2: The inversion of subject and object: technology as capitalist means of domination
CC: Creative Commons License, 2013.
Christian Fuchs
304
Marx in chapter 15 also uses Hegel’s dialectic of essence and appearance for arguing that
modern technology has a dialectical character. He does not oppose modern technology, but
only its class character and therefore argues that a lot of modern technologies have positive
potentials, but under class relations turn into destructive forces. Figure 3 visualizes this dialectic of the essence and appearance of modern technology. It lists the most important contradictions of modern technology that Marx mentions. He expressed this dialectic the following way:
It is an undoubted fact that machinery is not as such responsible for 'setting
free' the worker from the means of subsistence. It cheapens and increases production in the branch it seizes on, and at first leaves unaltered the quantity of
the means of subsistence produced in other branches. Hence, after the introduction of machinery, society possesses as much of the necessaries of life as
before, if not more, for the workers who have been displaced, not to mention the
enormous share of the annual product wasted by non-workers. And this is the
point relied on by our economic apologists! The contradictions and antagonisms
inseparable from the capitalist application of machinery do not exist, they say,
because they do not arise out of machinery as such, but out of its capitalist application! Therefore, since machinery in itself shortens the hours of labour, but
when employed by capital it lengthens them; since in itself it lightens labour, but
when employed by capital it heightens its intensity; since in itself it is a victory of
man over the forces of nature but in the hands of capital it makes man the slave
of those forces; since in itself it increases the wealth of the producers, but in the
hands of capital it makes them into paupers, the bourgeois economist simply
states that the contemplation of machinery in itself demonstrates with exactitude
that all these evident contradictions are a mere semblance, present in everyday
reality, but not existing in themselves, and therefore having no theoretical existence either. Thus he manages to avoid racking his brains any more, and in addition implies that his opponent is guilty of the stupidity of contending, not
against the capitalist application of machinery, but against machinery itself
(Marx 1867, 567f).
CC: Creative Commons License, 2013.
305
tripleC 11(2): 294-309 2013
Figure 3: The dialectic of essence and appearance of modern technology
The antagonisms between the essence and appearance of modern technology are not just
dialectical-logical constituents of capitalism, but potentially express themselves historically in
conflicts and struggles. Marx especially described the Luddite movement’s destruction of
machines (Marx 1867, 554f), but such struggles can also express themselves in different
conflicts. So Marx’s logical and historical presentation pushes towards a philosophy of praxis,
in which we think about the role and contradictions of technology today and how they relate
to struggles. This brings also up the question what technologies we need in a free society.
Just like Marx described the contradictions of 19th century industrial technology, we can inspired by him today e.g. think about the contradictions of Facebook and Google and use his
thought as inspiration for understanding that these platforms have potentials for social production and creativity, under capitalist conditions exploit users and that struggles should not
question the existence of search engines and social networking sites, but their capitalist
ownership and operation, which brings up the idea of how to socialize and communalize these “social” media so that they become fully social (Fuchs 2014b).
So my own view is that Capital is a logically and a historical organized text, that these two
dimensions are interconnected and strive towards being connected to political praxis. Capital
Volume 1’s chapters 23-25 that Fornäs characterizes as historical chapters present the historical development of capitalism as the result of its logical structure. The logic of Capital is
not just based on the principle of ascendance from the abstract to the concrete (new levels
and categories are added and drive the analysis into an ever more specific direction and give
it a processual systemic character), but Marx was also guided by Hegel’s dialectics when
writing. Dialectical logic has been more or less systematically applied in Capital. Engels finished volumes 2 and 3 after Marx’s death based on drafts, which results in a more fragmented character of these two books. Volume 1 in contrast contains much clearer elements of
dialectical logic that some authors have aimed to reconstruct (see: Arthur 2004, Bidet 2005,
Sekine 1998; Smith 1990, 1993). Haug (2013, 255) characterizes systematic-dialectical interpretations of Marx (especially Arthur, but also Smith) as metaphysical and neglecting human agency. He seems to be allergic to any attempt to read Marx in a systematic and systemic way. It is incomprehensible why such an interpretation should in principle not be compatible with a focus on practical struggles. It seems that Haug (2013) has to dismiss virtually
all contemporary Marx-interpretations in order to be able to argue that there is just one corCC: Creative Commons License, 2013.
Christian Fuchs
306
rect reading of Marx – the Haug-orthodoxy. The same move to install Marx orthodoxies is
made by Heinrich and others, who try to argue that there is one correct Marx reading – their
own – and that others are false, simplistic, deterministic, short-sighted, etc. The main problem of those who publish about reading Marx is their frequent attempt to define a dominant
reading as orthodoxy and to disguise it as Marx’s original approach. They are in this respect
true Stalinists at the level of theory. The problem is not to publish interpretations of Marx,
which we all should, but to disguise such interpretations as introductory books or companions to Marx’s Capital (or other of his works). Johan Fornäs’ book in contrast resists such a
creation of orthodoxies and catechisms and tries to give an general introduction to Marx’s
Capital.
From Karl to Adolf Marx in German Marxist Theory?
Many representatives of the “New Reading of Marx”-School (Neue Marx-Lektüre) that is
grounded in the works of Hans-Georg Backhaus (2011) and Helmut Reichelt (2001, 2008)
prefer to publish in German, which means that this discourse has stayed very Germanic in
character. This Deutschtümelei (German jingoism) also has to do with the circumstance that
these authors think that the widely read edition of Capital Volume 1 that is grounded in
Marx’s second German edition from 1872 and Engels’ third and fourth editions, is undialectical, a regression behind the status of the first German edition and contains a popularized and
wrong version of the value-form analysis. They therefore think that studies of Marx’s critique
of the political economy should be limited to the first German edition of Capital, the
Grundrisse and a fragment known as the Urtext that Marx wrote at the time when he put together A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy in 1858. Wolfgang Fritz Haug
(2013, chapter 8) argues that Harvey’s (2010) Marx-interpretation contains theoretical mistakes that stem from incorrect translations of Marx into English. This would be connected to
the circumstance that Harvey “reads no German” (Haug 2013, 176). Haug (2013, 178) asks
how Harvey can claim to read Marx “on his own terms” if “he disregards the original”? Marx
wrote in Das Kapital, Band 1: “Im graden Gegenteil zur sinnlich groben Gegenständlichkeit
der Warenkörper geht kein Atom Naturstoff in ihre Wertgegenständlichkeit ein” (MEW 23,
62). For the widely-used Penguin translation, Ben Fowkes translated this passage the following way: “Not an atom of matter enters into the objectivity of commodities as values; in this it
is the direct opposite of the coarsely sensuous objectivity of commodities as physical objects”
(Marx 1867, 138). Harvey based on this passage says that “value is immaterial” and that
“values, being immaterial, cannot exist without a means of representation” (Harvey 2010,
33). Haug (2013, 189-191) criticizes that Harvey sees the non-physical as immaterial and
stresses that there is a difference between Stoff, Ding, Sache and Materie. He does himself
however not suggest alternative translations that can avoid confusion. Haug (2013, 198)
concludes his chapter about David Harvey by bemoaning that “Anglo-American is the lingua
franca of international Marxism”.
German-speaking authors who constantly stress that Marx wrote in German, that one
needs to speak German to understand Marx and who tend not to publish in English themselves try to turn Karl Marx into Adolf Marx: Out of every belittlement of non-Germanspeaking Marx readers speaks not just Teutonic arrogance, but also the ideology of superior
humans and Aryanism. This ideology presents the German Marxist as the real Marxist who
has a monopoly of definition and is the only one who has by his origin and language skills the
legitimacy to write about Marx. As a consequence this ideology also assumes a linguistically
determined superiority of the quality of German books about Marx. It opposes German Marxism to the perceived sub-humanity of non-German Marxist thought that according to this ideology not only does not understand Marx, but also produces bad books about Marx. It is not
feasible to assume that German speakers have a better understanding or interpretation of
Marx. Adolf Marx is an ideology. Marx was an internationalist who learned and spoke many
languages and would have never assumed that only Germans can correctly understand his
works. Universal struggle needs universal intellectual discourse, universal communication
and therefore a universal language – for historical reasons this language should not be Ger-
CC: Creative Commons License, 2013.
307
tripleC 11(2): 294-309 2013
man.
Visualization
Figures and tables can be helpful pedagogical means for explaining a complex theory. Many
introductions to Marx’s Capital fail on this point. There are books on Capital that do not use a
single figure or table (e.g. Haug 1974, 2006, 2013; Heinrich 2008, 2012). These texts neglect
the basic pedagogical principle that good visualizations can support learning. They are based
on a philosophical and theoretical tyranny of visual structurelessness. Haug’s introductions
furthermore are also based on textual structurelessness. Altvater et al.’s (1999) introduction
to Capital Vol. 1 in contrast contains many figures that are overloaded with information and
do not contain any dialectical logic. The presentation mode of these figures is not based on
dialectical logic, but on the logic of a multitude of information. The book’s advantage is that it
strictly follows the structure of Marx’s book: there is one chapter for each of Marx’s chapters.
When I have tried to use this book as secondary literature for teaching Marx, the complex
figures in combination with the employment of language that students do not find much accessible have shown that a tyranny of too much information is just as problematic as the tyranny of structurlessness that other authors employ. David Harvey (2010) employs four figures in his Companion to Marx’s Capital. This number is small. Three of the four images (pp.
23, 26, 109) are helpful visualizations of Marx’s work, whereas the figure on page 195 is just
a display of Harvey’s own interpretation of Marx that derives an argument that fills an entire
chapter from a footnote in Marx’s book.
Johan Fornäs uses 6 figures and 9 tables for explaining some key dimensions of Marx’s
works such as the production processes M-C-M, M-C-M’, necessary and surplus labour-time,
absolute and relative surplus-value production, the dimensions of turnover time, the reproduction schemas or the trinity formula. In contrast to many other introductory books to Capital
that lack visualizations or overload figures with information, the figures and tables in Fornäs’
book are well thought-out and pedagogically feasible.
Crises
Chapter 12 in Johan Fornäs’ book deals with crises of capitalism and positions one specific
reading of Marx against others, namely that overaccumulation and the tendency of the rate of
profit (TRPF) to fall form the root cause of capitalist crises. This explanation is put against
explanations that privilege overproduction, underconsumption, disproportionalities, profitsqueeze, ecological limits of capital or a combination of several factors as root causes of
capitalist crises. Johan Fornäs argues that such explanations are problematic (p. 219) and
that following “Marx more closely” shows that “the falling rate of profit” is “the dominant motor
behind the crises of capitalism” (p. 220). It is certainly true that in Capital Volume III the role
of part three (chapters 13-14) that describes the tendency of the rate of profit to fall privileges
this explanation of the crisis. But alternative Marxist explanations of crisis also frequently
refer to Marx’s Capital for arguing that Marx also saw other factors as crucial for crisis. Mentioning other elements than the TRPF as crucial can also be grounded in what Marx wrote in
Capital.
So for example Marx stresses in Volume 2 that wage increases prepare crises, which is
more in line with a profit-squeeze theory than with the law of the TRPF: “crises are always
prepared by a period in which wages generally rise, and the working class actually does receive a greater share in the part of the annual product destined for consumption. […] It thus
appears that capitalist production involves certain conditions independent of people's good or
bad intentions, which permit the relative prosperity of the working class only temporarily, and
moreover always as a harbinger of crisis” (Marx 1885, 486f). In Volume 3, Marx speaks of a
constant tension and immanent barrier posed by the disarticulation of production and consumption, which speaks more for overproduction and underconsumption theories of crises
than for the TRPF: “Since capital’s purpose is not the satisfaction of needs but the production
of profit, and since it attains this purpose only by methods that determine the mass of production by reference exclusively to the yardstick of production, and not the reverse, there
CC: Creative Commons License, 2013.
Christian Fuchs
308
must be a constant tension between the restricted dimensions of consumption on the capitalist basis, and a production that is constantly striving to overcome these immanent barriers“
(Marx 1894, 365).
Michael Heinrich (2012) in his introduction to Marx’s three volumes of Capital in contrast
to Johan Fornäs contests the central role of the TRPF for crisis theory: He says that the rate
of profit depends on the organic composition of capital c/v and the rate of surplus value m/v,
which becomes evident if one divides the numerator and denominator of the rate of profit by
v:
m / (c + v) = (m/v) / (c/v +1).
“If both the rate of surplus value s/v and the value-composition of capital c/v increase,
then the profit rate only falls if c/v + 1 (the denominator of our fraction) increases faster than
s/v (the numerator). In order to prove that the rate of profit necessarily falls, it is not sufficient
to prove that c/v increases. One must also show that c/v increases by a certain degree that
the condition just named is fulfilled. And here lies the fundamental difficulty for every proof of
the ‘law of the tendency of the rate of profit to fall’: a general statement about the degree of
increase for c/v is not possible” (Heinrich 2012, 151f). Heinrich (2012, 154) argues that
“Marx’s crisis theory does not require this ‘law’”. In chapter 9 of the same book, Heinrich provides a reading of Marx that sees the source of capitalist crises in a combination of the overproduction of commodities and the overaccumulation of capital.
I neither agree with Fornäs nor Heinrich, but rather have my own interpretation on the
question what the sources of capitalist crises are. But I have only mentioned this difference in
order to show that two books that provide introductions to all three volumes of Marx’s Capital
differ quite substantially on this point. My point here is not that I want to defend a specific
crisis interpretation, but rather that Marx’s crisis theory is multifaceted and not always consistent. There are elements in the three volumes of Capital that speak for different crisis theories and different authors have appropriated different passages in order to argue that Marx
supported their specific interpretation. The law of the TRPF features prominently in Volume 3
as crisis explanation, which cannot be doubted. In an introductory book to Marx’s Capital one
should in my view however better point out that there are different elements that speak for
different interpretations and that Marxist crisis theory has therefore been contested instead of
privileging one specific Marxist crisis theory. Overall, Fornäs sticks with the exception of the
presentation of crises in chapter 12 strictly to his self-set goal not to provide one specific interpretation of Marx, but to present his theory of capitalism on a more general level.
Read this Book!
Johan Fornäs has overall produced an accessible, well-written, pedagogically smart accompanying guide to Marx’s three volumes of Capital that will help readers to better understand
and make sense of these books. We live in a time, where more and more people have become interested in Marx, which requires good introductory texts such as this one. It also important to note that a Media and Cultural Studies scholar has published a general introduction to Marx, which reminds scholars in the fields of Media/Communication Studies and Cultural Studies that media, communication and culture are framed by larger political-economic
questions and that we require engagement with Marx for understanding media, communication and culture. In the persistent situation of crisis, reading Marx is more important than ever. Johan Fornäs’ book can be a way into the world of Marx that every student and scholar
should enter in order to interpret and change the world.
A specific structural constraint to accessing the book is that it is thus far only available in
an expensive hardcover and ebook edition, which has to do with the circumstance that
Routledge’s monograph-business model is based on selling primarily to libraries. In this
case, this is however a miscalculation on part of the publisher because Capitalism. A Companion to Marx’s Economy Critique is a highly student-friendly and student-relevant textbook
that should immediately be made available in a cheaper paperback edition.
CC: Creative Commons License, 2013.
309
tripleC 11(2): 294-309 2013
References
Altvater, Elmar. 2012. Marx neu entdecken. Hamburg: VSA.
Altvater, Elmar, Rolf Hecker, Michael Heinrich and Petra Schaper-Rinkel. 1999. Kapital.doc. Das
Kapital (Bd. 1) von Marx in Schaubildern mit Kommentaren. Münster: Verlag Westfälisches
Dampfboot.
Arthur, Christopher J. 2004. The New Dialectic and Marx’s Capital. Leiden: Brill.
Backhaus, Hans-Georg. 2011. Dialektik der Wertform. Untersuchungen zur Marxschen
Ökonomiekritik. Freiburg: ça ira. Second edition.
Bidet, Jacques. 2005. The Dialectician’s Interpretation of Capital. Historical Materialism 13 (2): 121146.
Eagleton, Terry. 2012. Why Marx Was Right. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Fuchs, Christian. 2014a. Digital Labour and Karl Marx. New York: Routledge.
Fuchs, Christian. 2014b. Social Media. A Critical Introduction. London: Sage.
Fuchs, Christian. 2011. Foundations of Critical Media and Information Studies. London: Routledge.
Fuchs, Christian and Vincent Mosco, eds. 2012. Marx is Back – The Importance of Marxist Theory and
Research for Critical Communication Studies Today. tripleC: Communication, Capitalism & Critique
10 (2): 127-632.
Harvey, David. 2010. A Companion to Marx’s Capital. London: Verso.
Harvey, David. 2013. A Companion to Marx’s Capital: Volume 2. London: Verso.
Haug, Wolfgang Fritz. 1974. Vorlesungen zur Einführung ins „Kapital”. Köln: Pahl-Rugenstein.
Haug, Wolfgang Fritz. 2006. Neue Vorlesungen zur Einführung ins „Kapital”. Hamburg: Argument.
Haug, Wolfgang Fritz. 2013. Das „Kapital“ lesen – aber wie? Materialien. Hamburg: Argument.
Heinrich, Michael. 2008. Wie das Marxsche Kapital lessen? Hinweise zur Lektüre zum Anfang von
„Das Kapital”. Stuttgart: Schmetterling.
Heinrich, Michael. 2012. An Introduction to the Three Volumes of Marx’s Capital. New York: Monthly
Review Press.
Hobsbawm, Eric. 2012. How to Change the World. Tales of Marx and Marxism. London: Little, Brown.
Holz, Hans Heinz. 2005. Weltentwurf und Reflexion. Versuch über die Grundlegung der Dialektik.
Münster: Metzler.
Holz, Hans Heinz. 2011. Dialektik. Problemgeschichte von der Antike bis zur Gegenwart. 5 Bände.
Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.
Jameson, Frederic. 2011. Representing Capital: A Reading of Volume One. London: Verso.
Marx, Karl. 1867. Capital. Volume 1. London: Penguin.
Marx, Karl. 1885. Capital. Volume 2. London: Penguin.
Marx, Karl. 1894. Capital Volume 3. London: Penguin.
MEW. Marx-Engels-Werke. Berlin: Dietz.
Reichelt, Helmut. 2001. Zur logischen Struktur des Kapitalbegriffs bei Karl Marx. Freiburg: ça ira.
Reichelt, Helmut. 2008. Neue Marx-Lektüre. Zur Kritik sozialwissenschaftlicher Logik. Hamburg: VSA.
Sekine, Thomas T. 1998. The Dialectic of Capital: An Unoist Interpretation. Science & Society 62 (3):
434-445.
Smith, Tony. 1990. The Dialectical Logic of Marx’s Capital. Replies to Hegelian Criticisms. Albany, NY:
State University of New York Press.
Smith, Tony. 1993. Dialectical Social Theory and its Critics from Hegel to Analytical Marxism and
Postmodernism. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
Sperber, Jonathan. 2013. Karl Marx: A Nineteenth-Century Life. New York: N.N. Norton & Company.
About the Author
Christian Fuchs
is professor at the University of Westminster’s Communication and Media Research Institute and the
editor of tripleC: Communication, Capitalism & Critique: Open Access Journal for a Global Sustainable
Information Society, chair of the European Sociological Association’s Research Network 18 – Sociology of Communications and Media Research and co-founder of the ICTs and Society Network.
CC: Creative Commons License, 2013.