Social and Personality Psychology Compass 8/6 (2014): 263–274, 10.1111/spc3.12108
The Case for Mixed Emotions
Jeff T. Larsen1* and A. Peter McGraw2
1
2
University of Tennessee
University of Colorado
Abstract
How do people feel when they experience bittersweet events comprised of pleasant and unpleasant
aspects (e.g., good news accompanied by bad)? Just as acids immediately neutralize bases, some have
suggested that bittersweet events’ pleasant aspects might neutralize their unpleasant aspects, thereby
resulting in fairly neutral emotional reactions. Some contemporary theorists also contend that
happiness and sadness are mutually exclusive. We review research on the alternative possibility that
bittersweet events can elicit pairs of opposite-valence, mixed emotions, with particularly close
attention to the growing body of evidence that people can feel happy and sad at the same time while
watching films, listening to music, and experiencing meaningful endings. We also review evidence
that people sometimes experience other types of mixed emotions, including disgust accompanied
by amusement and fear by enjoyment. Taken together, these data indicate that positive and negative
affect are separable in experience.
On June 29, 2009, Kassim Bakari learned that the airliner carrying his daughter, Bahia, had
plunged into the Indian Ocean. All aboard were believed to have perished. The next day,
Bakari learned that Bahia had managed to survive by clinging to a piece of debris for 12 hours.
The story, however, does not have an entirely happy ending for Bakari. His wife had also been
aboard the flight and did not survive. A complete understanding of emotion must include an
understanding of emotional reactions to events like those faced by Bakari, yet for centuries
theorists have disagreed about how such bittersweet events make people feel.
Mixed Emotions of Happiness and Sadness
We define mixed emotions broadly as the co-occurrence of positive and negative affects.
Mixed emotions represent a subset of emotion blends, which we define as the co-occurrence
of any two or more same-valence or opposite-valence emotions (Scherer, 1998). Positive
emotions come in any number of fairly discrete varieties (e.g., excitement, hope, happiness),
as do negative emotions (e.g., fear, sadness, disgust), which raises the possibility that mixed
emotions will also come in any number of varieties. We will cast a wider net later, but we
begin with a particularly provocative question that has sparked the sharpest theoretical
disputes and has the broadest implications for the nature of emotional experience: Can
people feel happy and sad at the same time?
The case against mixed emotions of happiness and sadness
Early psychologists doubted the possibility of mixed emotions. Bain (1859) argued that
pleasure and displeasure neutralize one another “as an acid neutralizes an alkali [i.e., base]”
(p. 441). Wundt (1896) concurred. He maintained that, “all the partial feelings present at a
given moment unite, in every case to form a single total feeling” (p. 187; emphasis in original).
© 2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
264
Mixed Emotions
Some contemporary theorists also concur. Most notably, the circumplex model (Russell &
Barrett, 1999) conceptualizes valence as a “basic building block of emotional life” (Barrett,
2006, p. 35), a psychological primitive (Barrett & Bliss-Moreau, 2009). To say that valence is a
psychological primitive is to say that the experience of valence cannot be decomposed into
its constituent parts (e.g., some combination of pleasant and unpleasant feelings) any more than
a chemical compound can be both an acid and a base. On this view, when good fortune is
coupled with misfortune, only the net difference between pleasure and displeasure reaches
conscious experience; the underlying pleasures and displeasures themselves are lost along the
way. Consequently, the circumplex model contends that happiness and sadness, which anchor
the two ends of the valence dimension, are mutually exclusive in experience.
The case for mixed emotions of happiness and sadness
Other scholars have proposed that people can experience a variety of mixed emotions,
including happiness and sadness. In Plato’s Philebus (trans. 1975), Socrates posited that when
people appear to be “midway between the two” states of pleasure and pain, they might
actually be experiencing mixed emotions. David Hume (1739/2000) argued that people
can experience mixed emotions in response to events with a “mixt nature”. In contrast to
Bain’s chemical analogy, Ebbinghaus (1902; cited in Wolgemuth, 1919) put forth a thermal
analogy in support of his contention that people can experience mixed emotions: “Just as we
may sense cold in our feet and warmth in our hands at the same time, so we may experience the
pleasantness of a tasty dish and the unpleasantness of a severe headache side by side” (p. 540).
Different analogy, different conclusion.
Few contemporary theories hold that all positive and negative emotions are mutually
exclusive. In fact, the circumplex model contends that only happiness and sadness and other
pairs of polar opposite emotions (e.g., relaxed and stressed) are mutually exclusive (Russell &
Carroll, 1999). It makes the further contention that highly arousing positive emotions
(e.g., excitement) and negative emotions (e.g., stressed) can co-occur. A second leading
contemporary model of the structure of affect, Watson and Tellegen’s (1985) model, goes so far
as to contend that two broad classes of such high-arousal affective states termed Positive
Activation and Negative Activation are largely independent of another in experience, which
suggests that intense excitement can occur alongside intense levels of stress. The evaluative space
model goes even further by contending that the operation of the positive and negative substrates
underlying the valence dimension are separable in experience (Cacioppo & Berntson, 1994;
Cacioppo, Larsen, Smith, & Berntson, 2004). This raises the possibility that any pair of
opposite-valence emotions can co-occur, even happiness and sadness (Larsen, McGraw, &
Cacioppo, 2001). Thus, the circumplex and evaluative space models make competing
predictions about mixed emotions of happiness and sadness.1
Initial empirical tests
At first blush, testing the circumplex and evaluative space models’ competing hypotheses
seems fairly straightforward. If Eratosthenes (c. 276 BCE–c. 195 BCE) had the wherewithal
to approximate the earth’s circumference by comparing the length of shadows cast in
Alexandria with those cast nearly 1000 km to the south in Syene, contemporary psychologists
should have the wherewithal to figure out whether someone is feeling happy and feeling sad.
Unfortunately, emotions are hypothetical constructs rather than objective entities, which
makes them considerably more difficult to measure than shadows.
© 2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Social and Personality Psychology Compass 8/6 (2014): 263–274, 10.1111/spc3.12108
Mixed Emotions
265
Carroll and Russell (1998; cited in Russell & Carroll, 1999) were the first to test the
circumplex model’s contention that happiness and sadness are mutually exclusive. They
asked undergraduates in a classroom setting whether they felt happy and whether they felt
sad. Most participants reported feeling happy and some reported feeling sad. Only 10%
reported feeling both happy and sad, but it is quite likely that some participants were
acquiescent (i.e., they simply responded “yes” to most questions even if they were not
experiencing the emotion) or simply responded randomly. With allowance for these and
other sources of measurement error that might yield overestimates of the incidence of mixed
emotions, Carroll and Russell’s findings are consistent with the circumplex model’s
contention that happiness and sadness are mutually exclusive (Russell & Carroll, 1999).
However, sitting in a university classroom filled with other students completing questionnaires is a pallid event. As Russell and Carroll noted, stronger tests of the circumplex and
evaluative space models’ competing predictions require investigating how people feel in
more evocative, bittersweet events containing both pleasant and unpleasant aspects.
Larsen et al. (2001) provided one of the first investigations of how bittersweet situations make
people feel by capitalizing on the remarkably evocative film Life Is Beautiful (Benigni, 1997).
The tragicomedy Life Is Beautiful depicts a father’s attempts to keep his son unaware of their
plight during their imprisonment in a World War II concentration camp. We surveyed
moviegoers as they entered the theater to watch Life Is Beautiful. Like Carroll and Russell
(1998), we simply asked people to indicate whether they were feeling a number of emotions,
including happiness and sadness. Not surprisingly, most of these individuals indicated feeling
exclusively happy. (A few, perhaps partners who would have preferred to be on their way to
watching another film, indicated feeling exclusively sad.) Most important, only 10% reported
mixed emotions of happiness and sadness, which represents a conceptual replication of Carroll
and Russell’s (1998) evidence that happiness and sadness tend to be mutually exclusive.
We also collected data from moviegoers on their way out of the theater, just after they had
watched Life Is Beautiful. These data painted a very different picture. Many respondents
reported feeling exclusively happy, and many others felt exclusively sad, but some 44%
reported mixed emotions of happiness and sadness.2 The finding that moviegoers were four
times more likely to report mixed emotions of happiness and sadness after the film than
before is inconsistent with the circumplex model’s contention that polar opposite emotions
such as happiness and sadness are mutually exclusive but consistent with the evaluative space
model’s contention that happiness and sadness can co-occur in bittersweet situations.
Addressing alternative interpretations
At first blush, Larsen et al.’s (2001) findings might seem to lie to rest a question about the
experience of emotion that had vexed scholars for centuries. It has become clear that the Life
Is Beautiful study failed to address any number of alternative interpretations. It did provide
evidence against at least one alternative interpretation, though. Specifically, one possibility
is that moviegoers were simply more acquiescent after the film than before. Perhaps they
quickly and thoughtlessly said “yes” to most questions because they were eager to finish
the survey and get on with their evenings. If moviegoers were simply more acquiescent after
the film, we would expect them to be more likely to report experiencing other pairs of polar
opposite emotions than those who completed the survey before the film, but this was not the
case. They were no more likely to report feeling both calm and tense, excited and depressed,
or other pairs of polar opposite emotions. These data provide evidence against the possibility
that acquiescence can account for our evidence for mixed emotions, but others remained.
© 2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Social and Personality Psychology Compass 8/6 (2014): 263–274, 10.1111/spc3.12108
266
Mixed Emotions
Reactive measurement. Eratosthenes’ measurement of shadows had no influence on the length
of those shadows, but psychologists’ measurement of emotions may very well influence those
emotions. When we asked people whether they felt happy, we may have inadvertently
elicited happiness by prompting them to recall pleasant scenes (e.g., the boy’s reunion with his
mother). Similarly, when we asked people whether they felt sad, we may have inadvertently
elicited sadness by prompting them to recall unpleasant scenes (e.g., the father’s death).
According to this reactive measurement hypothesis, our participants only experienced mixed
emotions because we put words in their mouths by asking them whether they felt happy and
whether they felt sad.
We tested the reactive measurement hypothesis by showing undergraduates a 20-min clip
from the English-subtitled version of Life Is Beautiful in the context of a study that they were
led to believe dealt with foreign language comprehension (Larsen & McGraw, 2011; Study 4).
After watching a clip containing bittersweet scenes from the film, participants wrote (or rather,
typed) about the emotions they were feeling. The prompt did not mention happiness or
sadness; some 24% of the participants wrote that they felt both happy and sad. In contrast,
not one in a group of people who had watched a clip that began with unambiguously pleasant
scenes and ended with unambiguously unpleasant scenes wrote that they felt both happy and
sad. These findings provided evidence against the reactive measurement hypothesis. People
sometimes report mixed emotions of happiness and sadness even if they have not been asked
whether they feel happy and whether they feel sad.
Demand characteristics. The shadows that Eratosthenes measured were indifferent to any
hypothesis that he may have had about their length, but people sometimes tell psychologists
what they think the psychologists want to hear. To address the possibility that such demand
characteristics (Orne, 1962) lead participants to report mixed emotions (Schimmack, 2005),
we conducted another experiment in which participants completed open-ended measure
of emotions after watching the bittersweet clip from Life Is Beautiful (Larsen & McGraw,
2011; Study 5). Some participants then read that we had “predicted that people CANNOT
feel both happy and sad at the same time” and completed a measure of the time course of
their emotional reactions. These participants were just as likely to report mixed emotions
as a group who watched the bittersweet clip and were told nothing about our hypothesis.
Moreover, both groups were more likely to report simultaneously mixed emotions than a
third group who had watched the control clip. These findings suggest that people did not tell
us what they thought we wanted to hear; they did their best to tell us how they actually felt.
Lay theories of mixed emotions. Shadows hold no beliefs about how long they are, but
people have lay theories about how emotions work, and these lay theories can be
inaccurate (e.g., Barrett, Robin, Pietromonaco, & Eyssell, 1998). Most people think that
people can feel happy and sad at the same time (Larsen & McGraw, 2000, February), which may
lead them to think they are experiencing simultaneously mixed emotions even when they are
not (E. Harmon-Jones, personal communication; April, 2004). To address this possibility, we
identified students who we termed non-endorsers: people who did not think that (or did not know
whether) people can feel happy and sad at the same time (Larsen & McGraw, 2011; Study 6).
Later in the semester, open-ended measures revealed that these students were just as likely to
report mixed emotions of happiness and sadness as other students who watched the bittersweet
clip. More important, they were more likely to report mixed emotions than other students who
had watched our control clip from Life Is Beautiful. These findings suggest that people report
mixed emotions not because they erroneously think they can simultaneously feel happy and
sad but because they actually simultaneously felt happy and sad.
© 2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Social and Personality Psychology Compass 8/6 (2014): 263–274, 10.1111/spc3.12108
Mixed Emotions
267
Vacillation. The shadows cast by the sun did not change in the course of the time that it took
Eratosthenes to measure them. In contrast, emotions can come and go in less than a second
(Ekman, 1992). Such instability raises what is perhaps the thorniest alternative explanation for
initial evidence for mixed emotions. Even when asked to indicate how they feel “right now,
at this very moment” (Larsen et al., 2001; p. 688), people may simply summarize the
emotions they had experienced during the previous few seconds or even minutes (Barrett
& Bliss-Moreau, 2009; Barrett et al., 2010; Larsen, McGraw, Mellers, & Cacioppo, 2004).
If so, people may report mixed emotions of happiness and sadness even when they merely
vacillated between happiness and sadness.
Carrera and Oceja (2007) addressed this vacillation hypothesis by asking undergraduates to
draw one curve to chart how their happiness had changed moment-to-moment over the
course of a bittersweet 6-min film and another curve to chart how their sadness had changed.
The floor of the chart represented the absence of the emotion, and the ceiling represented
maximum intensity. Carrera and Oceja identified those who had experienced mixed
emotions as those whose curves both cleared the floor at any one point in time. The finding
that these participants were nearly twice as likely to report mixed emotions (47%) as those
who watched a control clip (25%) provides evidence against the vacillation hypothesis.
Carrera and Oceja’s (2007) measures require participants to recall the emotions they had
experienced over the course of an evocative event, but recalling emotions can be difficult
(Thomas & Diener, 1990), and recalling mixed emotions can be especially difficult (Aaker,
Drolet, & Griffin, 2008). We have asked participants to report moment-to-moment changes
in their emotions as they watched scenes from Life Is Beautiful (Larsen & McGraw, 2011;
Study 1a). Specifically, we handed them a computer mouse and asked them to press the left
button whenever they felt happy, the right button whenever they felt sad, neither button if
they felt neither happy nor sad, and both buttons if they felt both happy and sad. Participants
who watched the bittersweet clip were several times more likely to spend some amount of
time simultaneously pressing both buttons (67%) than another group of participants who
watched the control clip (18%). Additional studies with moment-to-moment measures
revealed that both (a) people who had been told that we did not think that people can feel
happy and sad at the same time and (b) people who had earlier indicated that they did not
think or did not know whether people could feel happy and sad at the same time reported
more mixed emotions during the bittersweet clip than did people who watched the control
clip. In another study, the instructions for the button press measures made no mention of
happiness and sadness, and participants were only prompted to report whether they felt
happy and whether they felt sad on one occasion (Larsen & Green, 2013). Participants
who were prompted to report their emotions during bittersweet scenes, as opposed to
unambiguously unpleasant scenes, spent more time reporting simultaneously mixed
emotions. All of these studies provide evidence against the hypothesis that people in earlier
studies simply vacillated quickly between happiness and sadness.
Summary. Popper (1927/1999) noted that, “The theory ‘All ravens are black’ rules out the
existence of white ravens; and observation of a white raven refutes the theory” ( p. 19).
The occurrence of mixed emotions of happiness and sadness represents one of psychology’s
few white ravens. Indeed, few psychological theories preclude the very existence of a
phenomenon, which makes Russell and Carroll’s (1999) contention that happiness and
sadness cannot co-occur especially remarkable. With the broad question of whether the
experience of valence is a psychological primitive at stake, the narrow question of whether
people can feel happy and sad at the same time is hardly an idle quest for a mere curiosity.
Numerous studies including our own suggest that happiness and sadness rarely co-occur.
© 2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Social and Personality Psychology Compass 8/6 (2014): 263–274, 10.1111/spc3.12108
268
Mixed Emotions
In Larsen and McGraw’s (2011) button press study described above, the median participant
spent precisely 0 sec reporting mixed emotions during the control clip and only 24 sec
reporting mixed emotions during the bittersweet clip even though it was nearly 20 min long.
Nonetheless, the data also reveal that people are more likely to report feeling happy and sad
in response to bittersweet scenes from films than during other scenes. This pattern is obtained
whether emotions are measured with closed- or open-ended measures and at a single point
in time or continuously over time. Taken together, the data provide evidence against the
circumplex model’s contention that valence is a psychological primitive (Bain, 1859; Russell
& Carroll, 1999; Wundt, 1896) and for those that contend that the positive and negative
affective bases underlying valence are separable in experience (e.g., Cacioppo & Berntson,
1994; Hume 1739/2000; Ebbinghaus, 1902, cited in Wolgemuth, 1919). Chemical
compounds cannot be both acidic and basic, but it appears that they can experience the
distinct pleasures and displeasures associated with bittersweet events.
Beyond Life Is Beautiful
Films such as Life Is Beautiful provide strong tests of nuanced alternative interpretations for
questions about whether people can feel happy and sad at the same time. The evidence
indicates that Life is Beautiful represents a white raven, and more recent research indicates that
it may not be the only white raven.
Different structural elements of music reliably elicit different emotional reactions. Whereas
fast tempos typically elicit happiness, slow tempos elicit sadness (e.g., Webster & Weir, 2005).
Other elements have more subtle influence on emotion. Even though most non-musicians
have difficulty distinguishing the patterns of pitch changes that distinguish major from minor
modes (Leaver & Halpern, 2004), major modes typically elicit happiness, and minor modes
elicit sadness (Webster & Weir, 2005). Many songs feature conflicting cues (Schellenberg &
von Scheve, 2012) comprising fast tempos but minor modes or slow tempos but major
modes, which raises the question of whether songs with conflicting cues elicit mixed emotions of happiness and sadness. Hunter, Schellenberg, and Schimmack (2008) had listeners indicate both how happy and how sad they felt after each of a series of songs that varied in
tempo and mode. As predicted, they found that songs with conflicting cues elicited more
mixed emotions than songs with consistent cues (see also, Hunter, Schellenberg, &
Schimmack, 2010; Ladinig & Schellenberg, 2012). A subsequent study involving momentto-moment measures (i.e., Larsen & McGraw’s, 2011, button press measures) also revealed
that songs with conflicting cues elicited more simultaneously mixed emotions (Larsen &
Stastny, 2011). A closer look at these findings indicates that even slow minor songs elicit considerable levels of mixed emotions, presumably because their sad cues were accompanied by
the array of cues (e.g., consonance, rhythm; see Juslin & Laukka, 2004) that make music
pleasant (Larsen, Hershfield, Stastny, & Hester, 2014). Additional evidence indicates that
songs that elicit feelings of nostalgia, presumably even those with no sad cues, can also elicit
mixed emotions (Barrett et al., 2010). Taken together, these findings indicate that music, like
Life Is Beautiful, represents another white raven in that it can elicit mixed emotions of happiness and sadness.
Beyond Aesthetic Emotions
Films and music have provided great insight into whether people can feel happy and sad at
the same time, but their utility is limited somewhat by the fact that they involve aesthetic
emotions (i.e., emotions elicited by works of art rather than real events). Some scholars have
challenged the very idea that aesthetic emotions are actual emotions (see Walters, 1989).
© 2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Social and Personality Psychology Compass 8/6 (2014): 263–274, 10.1111/spc3.12108
Mixed Emotions
269
At the very least, the idea that art can elicit emotions is perplexing (e.g., Ellsworth & Scherer,
2003; Frijda, 1988; Walters, 1989). All this raises the concern that mixed emotions of
happiness and sadness can only co-occur in the confines of the laboratory even though our
real objective is to understand the emotions elicited by real events in the real world.
Subsequent research indicates that people can feel happy and sad at the same time in
response to real world events. Ersner-Hershfield, Mikels, Sullivan, and Carstensen (2008)
speculated that meaningful endings can elicit poignant mixed emotions of happiness and
sadness. Initial evidence came from our evidence that undergraduates were more likely to feel
mixed emotions of happiness and sadness upon turning in the keys to their dorm rooms at the
end of their freshman year and upon their own graduation day at the end of their senior year
than during typical days on campus (Larsen et al., 2001). Ersner-Hershfield et al. investigated
the role of meaningful endings more directly by reminding some Stanford students on the
day of their graduation that “today is the last day that you will be a student at Stanford”. As
predicted, they found that these students subsequently reported more intense mixed emotions
than did other graduates who received no such reminder. Thus, meaningful endings represent
one real world event that can elicit mixed emotions of happiness and sadness.
Beyond Happiness and Sadness
The evidence that people can feel happy and sad at the same time provides a context for
thinking about mixed emotions more broadly. If such polar opposite emotions as happiness
and sadness happiness and sadness can co-occur, we can expect that a wide array of oppositevalence emotions can also co-occur.
High-arousal mixed emotions
As we mentioned above, all dimensional models allow for at least some types of mixed emotions. Russell and Carroll (1999) did contend that polar opposite emotions (e.g., happiness &
sadness) are mutually exclusive, but they stressed that all other pairs of opposite-valence
emotions can co-occur and that some will co-occur more often than others. For instance, they
shared Watson and Tellegen’s (1985) contention that high-arousal positive and negative
emotions co-occur regularly. Evidence that the Positive and Negative Affect Schedule’s
(i.e., PANAS, Watson, Clark, & Tellegen, 1988) measures of high-arousal positive
emotions (i.e., Positive Activation) and high-arousal negative emotions (i.e., Negative
Activation) tend to be uncorrelated or only weakly negatively correlated has been treated
as evidence for their co-occurrence, but logical considerations (Diener & Iran-Nejad, 1986;
Russell & Carroll, 1999; Schimmack, 2001) and empirical evidence (Larsen et al., 2014) have
made it abundantly clear that correlation coefficients are poorly suited for indexing mixed
emotions. Fortunately, the ready availability of more suitable measures of mixed emotions
(e.g., Schimmack, 2001) has allowed more insight into the co-occurrence of high-arousal
positive and negative emotions.
Types of experience known as guilty pleasures may be one source of high-arousal mixed
emotions. Mukhopadhyay and Johar (2007) investigated mixed emotional responses to
impulse purchases. They asked students to consider a scenario in which they happened upon
a sale on attractive computer software that they had not intended to buy. Participants who
indicated that they would succumb to temptation and buy the software subsequently
reported that they would feel happier than those who would resist temptation, but they also
reported that they would feel guiltier. In another study, Ramanathan and Williams (2007)
gave people a subtle opportunity to take some cookies without actually inviting them to
© 2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Social and Personality Psychology Compass 8/6 (2014): 263–274, 10.1111/spc3.12108
270
Mixed Emotions
do so. The majority of participants succumbed to temptation and were rewarded in the short
run with positive affect but punished in the long run by feelings of guilt.
Some temptations are more problematic than impulsively purchasing software or surreptitiously
helping oneself to a cookie. Though laws against pornography indicate that many people have
negative emotional reactions to pornography, the finding that as many as 13% of web searches involve erotic content (Ogas & Gaddam, 2011) is a sobering indication that many have positive
emotional reactions to it. Pornography involves a primary reinforcer that is both socially charged
(Zillmann, 1992) and physiologically arousing (Carvalho, Leite, Galdo-Álvarez, & Gonçalves,
2011), so any such mixed emotions likely include highly arousing positive and negative emotions.
Peterson and Janssen (2007) found that most participants reported experiencing at least one of four
positive emotions and one of seven negative emotions to at least some degree after viewing various
types of erotic films (see also Byrne, Fisher, Lamberth, & Mitchell, 1974). Staley and Prause (2013)
focused specifically on the effects of pornography on high-arousal positive and negative emotions.
Their change scores revealed that nearly half of men and women alike showed increases in both
Positive Activation and Negative Activation scores after watching erotic films.
Horror films also elicit high-arousal emotions (Hewig, Hagemann, Seifert, Gollwitzer,
Naumann, & Bartussek, 2005) and are acclaimed by some but reviled by others, all of which
raises the possibility that they represent another source of high-arousal mixed emotions. Andrade
and Cohen’s (2007) moment-to-moment measures of emotion provide an unsurprising explanation for why some people avoid horror films: non-fans experienced a great deal of fear during
horror films but little happiness. More interestingly, horror fans experienced simultaneously
mixed emotions of fear accompanied by happiness. The fact that horror fans seek out horror
films represents an example of the curious phenomenon of benign masochism (Rozin, Guillot,
Fincher, Rozin, & Tsukayama, 2013), which involves seeking out aversive stimuli. Andrade
and Cohen’s findings suggest that fans spend time and money being afraid in the safe confines
of the movie theater because such fear also makes them happy (Andrade & Cohen, 2007).
Humor is often associated with high-arousal positive emotions (Dienstbier, 1995), but
Socrates’ speculation that humor can come at the expense of another’s misfortune suggests
that it might also be associated with high-arousal negative emotions. Not surprisingly, a scene
from Pink Flamingos in which a character eats dog feces elicits high-arousal emotions in
general and disgust in particular (Hewig et al., 2005). A closer investigation by Hemenover
and Schimmack (2007), however, indicated that this disgust is accompanied by feelings of
amusement (Hemenover & Schimmack, 2007). Moreover, participants who had been
encouraged to view the scene from the perspective of a dispassionate observer found it
particularly amusing. That finding fits nicely with McGraw and Warren’s (2010) benign
violation hypothesis, which holds that people find humorous those events that they construct as
being both wrong and not wrong. Eating feces is a clear violation, but viewing the action from
the perspective of a dispassionate observer helps make the violation benign. More direct evidence for the benign violation hypothesis comes from McGraw and Warren’s finding that
nearly every participant in their study found a hypothetical scenario in which a man has sexual
contact with a kitten disgusting, but many also found it amusing if the kitten seemed to enjoy
the contact (McGraw & Warren, 2010). Frottage with a kitten is a violation, but frottage that
does no harm the kitten brings mixed emotions to people who construe it as a benign violation.
Low-arousal mixed emotions
In addition to contending that high-arousal opposite-valence emotions regularly co-occur,
another implication of Watson and Tellegen’s (1985) model and the circumplex model
© 2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Social and Personality Psychology Compass 8/6 (2014): 263–274, 10.1111/spc3.12108
Mixed Emotions
271
(Russell & Barrett, 1999) is that low-arousal opposite-valence emotions (e.g., tired and
relaxed) should co-occur. This possibility remains to be tested, but there is some suggestive
evidence. As would be expected, the average long-distance male runner in one study reported
feeling more tired at the end of a 20-km race than he had at the beginning (Hollandsworth &
Jones, 1979). Despite being more tired, the average runner also felt more relaxed after the race.
Unfortunately, no measures of mixed emotions were reported, so it is unclear whether the
runners who felt tired after the race also felt relaxed. Thus, despite considerable evidence for
dimensional theorists’ (e.g., Russell & Barrett, 1999; Watson & Tellegen, 1985) claim that
high-arousal positive and negative emotions can co-occur, there is little evidence bearing on
the co-occurrence of low-arousal positive and negative emotions.
Future directions. Though the evidence that people can feel happy and sad (Larsen &
McGraw, 2011) challenges the circumplex model’s strong claim that polar opposite emotions
are mutually exclusive (Russell & Carroll, 1999), both the circumplex and the Watson and
Tellegen (1985) models make broader claims that some opposite-valence emotions are more
likely to co-occur than others. The evidence that a variety of high-arousal opposite-valence
emotions (e.g., Positive Activation & Negative Activation) can co-occur is consistent with
these broader claims. Though our own evidence that happiness and sadness co-occur only
occasionally is suggestive, however, we are aware of no direct evidence bearing on the critical
contention that non-polar opposite emotions co-occur more frequently than polar opposite
emotions. One reason is that researchers have generally focused on a single pair of emotions
(e.g., happiness & sadness; Larsen & McGraw, 2011; happiness & fear; Andrade & Cohen,
2007) or averaged across several emotions (e.g., Peterson & Janssen, 2007). Studies in which
multiple opposite-valence emotions are assessed will allow greater insight into whether some
opposite-valence emotions (e.g., high-arousal emotions) co-occur more frequently than
polar opposite emotions.
Conclusion
We opened by describing how Kassim Bakari learned that his daughter had survived the
jetliner crash that had killed his wife. Rather than speculating about how Bakari felt, we
promptly retreated to safer ground by making allusions to Greek philosophers and white
ravens and by detailing abstract theories and concrete data. Psychologists have not been so
tactless as to ask Bakari how he felt, but they have asked many other people how they felt
in response to a range of other bittersweet events including films, music, and meaningful
endings. The resulting body of evidence indicates that mixed emotions of happiness and
sadness tend to be rare, albeit less rare than white ravens. Moreover, the evidence suggests
that other types of mixed emotions (e.g., amusement accompanied by disgust; McGraw &
Warren, 2010) may be fairly common and open the door to further investigations of mixed
emotions. To give but one example, Markman and McMullen (2003) suggested that the
feelings of relief elicited by narrowly averting misfortune may be accompanied by feelings
of dread at the thought of what might have been. They provided one piece of anecdotal
evidence from an American Airlines passenger who flew out of Boston’s Logan airport on
the morning of September 11, 2001. He later told a reporter that, “I felt sick in my stomach
knowing I was in the same terminal at Logan airport with these terrorists and feeling how
lucky I was to be safely on the ground” (Markman & McMullen, 2003, p. 244). Of course,
no prior or future psychological research on mixed emotions will tell us precisely how Bakari
felt on that day in June 2009, but it does indicate that whatever joy he felt upon learning that
that his daughter had survived need not have precluded him from anguishing over the fact
that his wife had not been so fortunate.
© 2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Social and Personality Psychology Compass 8/6 (2014): 263–274, 10.1111/spc3.12108
272
Mixed Emotions
Short Biographies
Jeff T. Larsen conducts research on emotion and is an expert on the study of mixed emotions.
His research has been published in Psychological Science, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Emotion, Psychophysiology, and Cognition and Emotion and has been funded by the
National Institute of Mental Health. He is an Associate Editor at Emotion and has served
on the editorial boards of Emotion, Cognition and Emotion, and Personality and Social Psychology
Bulletin. He recently moved from Texas Tech University to the University of Tennessee,
where he is an Associate Professor of Psychology and teaches courses in social psychology
and emotion. He holds a BA in Psychology from the University of California at San Diego
and an MA and PhD in Psychology from Ohio State University.
A. Peter McGraw, an associate professor at the University of Colorado Boulder, is a leading
expert in the interdisciplinary fields of emotion and behavioral decision theory. His research
examines the interrelationship of judgment, emotion, and choice. Holding appointments in
marketing at the Leeds School of Business and in social psychology in the Department of
Psychology and Neuroscience, McGraw teaches courses in decision making, consumer
behavior, and advertising. His recent book, The Humor Code, documents his global
expedition to understand what makes things funny.
Notes
* Correspondence: Department of Psychology, University of Tennessee, Knoxville, TN 37996, USA. Email:
jeff.larsen@utk.edu
1
Watson and Tellegen’s (1985) model makes the surprising contention that happiness and sadness are perfectly negatively
correlated. This prediction might appear to simply be a restatement of Russell and Carroll’s (1999) prediction that happiness
and sadness are mutually exclusive. To the contrary, it implies that people will experience some amount of sadness unless
they feel extremely happy and, by the same token, some amount of happiness unless they feel extremely sad (Russell &
Carroll, 1999). The prediction that happiness and sadness are perfectly negatively correlated also implies that people cannot
feel neutral (i.e., neither happy nor sad). As we have noted (Larsen & McGraw, 2011), these predictions seem highly unlikely
and are inconsistent with a wide variety of data (e.g., Larsen & McGraw, 2011; Larsen et al., 2001; Russell & Carroll, 1998;
Schimmack, 2001), so we set aside Watson and Tellegen’s treatment of the relationship between happiness and sadness.
2
All comparisons that we mention were statistically significant.
References
Aaker, J., Drolet, A., & Griffin, D. (2008). Recalling mixed emotions. Journal of Consumer Research, 35(2), 268–278.
DOI: 10.1086/588570
Andrade, E. B., & Cohen, J. B. (2007). On the consumption of negative feelings. Journal of Consumer Research, 34, 283–300.
DOI: 10.1086/519498
Bain, A. (1859). The Emotions and the Will. London, England: Parker. DOI: 10.1037/10617-000
Barrett, L. F. (2006). Valence is a basic building block of emotional life. Journal of Research in Personality, 40, 35–55. DOI:
10.1016/j.jrp.2005.08.006
Barrett, L. F., & Bliss-Moreau, E. (2009). Affect as a psychological primitive. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.). Advances in
Experimental Social Psychology, 41, 167–218. DOI: 10.1016/S005-2601(08)00404-8
Barrett, F. S., Grimm, K. J., Robins, R. W., Wildschut, T., Sedikides, C., & Janata, P. (2010). Music-evoked nostalgia:
Affect, memory, and personality. Emotion, 10(3), 390–403. DOI: 10.1037/a0019006
Barrett, L. F., Robin, L., Pietromonaco, P. R., & Eyssell, K. M. (1998). Are women the “more emotional” sex? Evidence
from emotional experiences in social context. Cognition and Emotion, 12, 555–578. DOI: 10.1080/026999398379574
Benigni, R. (Director). (1997). La Vita è Bella (Life is Beautiful) [Motion Picture]. Italy: Miramax.
Byrne, D., Fisher, J. D., Lamberth, J., & Mitchell, H. E. (1974). Evaluations of erotica: Facts or feelings? Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 29, 111–116. DOI: 10.1037/h0035731
Cacioppo, J. T., & Berntson, G. G. (1994). Relationship between attitudes and evaluative space: A critical review, with emphasis
on the separability of positive and negative substrates. Psychological Bulletin, 115, 401–423. DOI: 10.1037/0033-2909.115.3.401
© 2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Social and Personality Psychology Compass 8/6 (2014): 263–274, 10.1111/spc3.12108
Mixed Emotions
273
Cacioppo, J. T., Larsen, J. T., Smith, N. K., & Berntson, G. G. (2004). The affect system: What lurks below the surface
of feelings? In A. S. R. Manstead, N. H. Frijda, & A. H. Fischer (Eds.), Feelings and Emotions: The Amsterdam Conference
(pp. 223–242). New York, NY: Cambridge.
Carrera, P., & Oceja, L. (2007). Drawing mixed emotions: Sequential or simultaneous experiences? Cognition and
Emotion, 21, 422–441. DOI: 10.1080/02699930600557904
Carvalho, S., Leite, J., Galdo-Álvarez, S., & Gonçalves, Ó. F. (2011). Psychophysiological correlates of sexually and
non-sexually motivated attention to film clips in a workload task. PLoS ONE, 6, e29530. DOI: 10.1371/journal.
pone.0029530
Diener, E., & Iran-Nejad, A. (1986). The relationship in experience between various types of affect. Journal of Personality
and Social Psychology, 50, 1031–1038. DOI: 10.1037/0022-3514.50.5.1031
Dienstbier, R. A. (1995). The impact of humor on energy, tension, task choices, and attributions: Exploring hypotheses
from toughness theory. Motivation and Emotion, 19, 255–267.
Ekman, P. (1992). An argument for basic emotions. Cognition and Emotion, 6, 169–200. DOI: 10.1080/
02699939208411068
Ellsworth, P. C., & Scherer, K. R. (2003). Appraisal processes in emotion. In R. J. Davidson, K. R. Scherer, &
H. H. Goldsmith (Eds.), Handbook of Affective Sciences (pp. 572–595). New York, NY: Oxford.
Ersner-Hershfield, H., Mikels, J. A., Sullivan, S. J., & Carstensen, L. L. (2008). Poignancy: Mixed emotional experience
in the face of meaningful endings. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 94, 158–167. DOI: 10.1037/00223514.94.1.158
Frijda, N. H. (1988). The laws of emotion. American Psychologist, 43, 349–358. DOI: 10.1037/0003-066X.43.5.349
Hemenover, S. H., & Schimmack, U. (2007). That’s disgusting! …, But very amusing: Mixed feelings of amusement and
disgust. Cognition & Emotion, 21, 1102–1113. DOI: 10.1080/02699930601057037
Hewig, J., Hagemann, D., Seifert, J., Gollwitzer, M., Naumann, E., & Bartussek, D. (2005). A revised film set for the
induction of basic emotions. Cognition and Emotion, 19, 1095–1109. DOI: 10.1080/02699930541000084
Hollandsworth, J. G., & Jones, G. E. (1979). Perceptions of arousal and awareness of physiological responding prior to
and after running 20 kilometers. Journal of Sport Psychology, 1, 291–300.
Hume, D. (1739/2000). A Treatise of Human Nature. New York, NY: Oxford.
Hunter, P. G., Schellenberg, E. G., & Schimmack, U. (2008). Mixed affective responses to music with conflicting cues.
Cognition and Emotion, 22, 327–352. DOI: 10.1080/02699930701438145
Hunter, P. G., Schellenberg, E. G., & Schimmack, U. (2010). Feelings and perceptions of happiness and sadness induced
by music: Similarities, differences, and mixed emotions. Psychology of Aesthetics, Creativity, and the Arts, 4, 47–56. DOI:
10.1037/a0016873
Juslin, P. N., & Laukka, P. (2004). Expression, perception, and induction of musical emotions: A review and a
questionnaire study of everyday listening. Journal of New Music Research, 33, 217–238. DOI: 10.1080/
0929821042000317813
Ladinig, O., & Schellenberg, E. G. (2012). Liking unfamiliar music: Effects of felt emotion and individual differences.
Psychology of Aesthetics, Creativity, and the Arts, 6, 146–154. DOI: 10.1037/a0024671
Larsen, J. T., & Green, J. D. (2013). Evidence for mixed feelings of happiness and sadness from brief moments in time.
Cognition & Emotion, 27, 1469–1477. DOI: 10.1080/02699931.2013.790782
Larsen, J. T., & McGraw, A. P. (2000, February). Evidence for the co-occurrence of happiness and sadness. Poster
presented at the annual convention of the Society for Personality and Social Psychology, Nashville, TN.
Larsen, J. T., & McGraw, A. P. (2011). Further evidence for mixed emotions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
100, 1095–1110.
Larsen, J. T., & Stastny, B. J. (2011). It’s a bittersweet symphony: Simultaneously mixed emotional responses to music
with conflicting cues. Emotion, 11, 1469–1473. DOI: 10.1037/a0024081
Larsen, J. T., Hershfield, H. E., Stastny, B. J., & Hester, N. R. (2014). How (and how not) to measure mixed emotions.
Manuscript under review. University of Tennessee, Knoxville.
Larsen, J. T., McGraw, A. P., & Cacioppo, J. T. (2001). Can people feel happy and sad at the same time? Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 81, 684–696. DOI: 10.1037/0022-3514.81.4.684
Larsen, J. T., McGraw, A. P., Mellers, B. A., & Cacioppo, J. T. (2004). The agony of victory and thrill of defeat: Mixed
emotional reactions to disappointing wins and relieving losses. Psychological Science, 15, 325–330. DOI: 10.1111/
j.0956-7976.2004.00677.x
Leaver, A. M., & Halpern, A. R. (2004). Effects of training and melodic features on mode perception. Music Perception,
22, 117–143. DOI: 10.1525/mp.2004.22.1.117
Markman, K. D., & McMullen, M. N. (2003). A reflection and evaluation model of comparative thinking. Personality
and Social Psychology Review, 7, 244–267. DOI: 10.1207/S15327957PSPR0703_4
McGraw, A. P., & Warren, C. (2010). Benign violations: Making immoral behavior funny. Psychological Science, 21,
1141–1149. DOI: 10.1177/0956797610376073
© 2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Social and Personality Psychology Compass 8/6 (2014): 263–274, 10.1111/spc3.12108
274
Mixed Emotions
Mukhopadhyay, A., & Johar, G. V. (2007). Tempted or not? the effect of recent purchase history on responses to affective advertising. Journal of Consumer Research, 33, 445–453. DOI: 10.1086/510218
Ogas, O., & Gaddam, S. (2011). A Billion Wicked Thoughts: What the Internet Tells us about Sexual Relationships.
New York, NY: Plume.
Orne, R. A. (1962). On the social psychology of the psychological experiment: With particular reference to demand
characteristics and their implications. American Psychologist, 17, 776–783. DOI: 10.1037/h0043424
Peterson, Z. D., & Janssen, E. (2007). Ambivalent affect and sexual response: The impact of co-occurring positive and
negative emotions on subjective and physiological sexual responses to erotic stimuli. Archives of Sexual Behavior, 36,
793–807. DOI: 10.1007/s10508-006-9145-0
Plato. (1975). Philebus. (J.C.B. Gosling, Trans.) New York, NY: Oxford.
Popper, K. (1927/1999). All Life is Problem Solving. (P. Camiller, Trans.) London: Routledge.
Ramanathan, S., & Williams, P. (2007). Immediate and delayed emotional consequences of indulgence: The moderating influence of personality type on mixed emotions. Journal of Consumer Research, 34, 212–223. DOI: 10.1086/
519149
Rozin, P., Guillot, L., Fincher, K., Rozin, A., & Tsukayama, E. (2013). Glad to be sad, and other examples of benign
masochism. Judgment and Decision Making, 8, 439–447.
Russell, J. A., & Barrett, L. F. (1999). Core affect, prototypical emotional episodes, and other things called emotion:
Dissecting the elephant. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 76, 805–819. DOI: 10.1037/0022-3514.76.5.805
Russell, J. A., & Carroll, J. M. (1999). On the bipolarity of positive and negative affect. Psychological Bulletin, 125, 3–30.
DOI: 10.1037/0033-2909.125.1.3
Schellenberg, E. G., & von Scheve, C. (2012). Emotional cues in American popular music: Five decades of the Top 40.
Psychology of Aesthetics, Creativity, and the Arts, 6, 196–203. DOI: 10.1037/a0028024
Scherer, K. R. (1998). Analyzing emotion blends. In Proceedings of the 10th Conference of the International Society for Research
on Emotions (pp. 142–148). Wurzburg, Germany: ISRE Publications.
Schimmack, U. (2001). Pleasure, displeasure, and mixed feelings? Are semantic opposites mutually exclusive? Cognition
and Emotion, 15, 81–97. DOI: 10.1080/0269993004200123
Schimmack, U. (2005). Response latencies of pleasure and displeasure ratings: Further evidence for mixed feelings.
Cognition and Emotion, 19, 671–691. DOI: 10.1080/02699930541000020
Staley, C., & Prause, N. (2013). Erotica viewing effects on intimate relationships and self/partner evaluations. Archives of
Sexual Behavior, 42(4), 615–624. DOI: 10.1007/s10508-012-0034-4
Thomas, D. L., & Diener, E. (1990). Memory accuracy in the recall of emotions. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 59, 291–297. DOI: 10.1037/0022-3514.59.2.291
Walters, K. S. (1989). The law of apparent reality and aesthetic emotions. American Psychologist, 44, 1545–1546. DOI:
10.1037/0003-066X.44.12.1545
Watson, D., & Tellegen, A. (1985). Toward a consensual structure of mood. Psychological Bulletin, 98, 219–235. DOI:
10.1037/0033-2909.98.2.219
Watson, D., Clark, L. A., & Tellegen, A. (1988). Development and validation of brief measures of positive and negative
affect: The PANAS scales. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 54, 1063–1070. DOI: 10.1037/0022-3514.54.6.1063
Webster, G. D., & Weir, C. G. (2005). Emotional responses to music: Interactive effects of mode, texture, and tempo.
Motivation and Emotion, 29, 19–39. DOI: 10.1007/s11031-005-4414-0
Wolgemuth, A. (1919). Pleasure-unpleasure: An experimental examination of the feeling elements. British Journal of
Psychology, Monograph Supplements, 6, 1–250.
Wundt, W. (1896). Outlines of Psychology. Leipzig, Germany: Engelmann.
Zillmann, D. (1992). Pornography research, social advocacy, and public policy. In Suedfeld, P., & Tetlock, P. E. (Eds.),
Psychology and Social Policy (pp. 165–178). Washington, DC: Hemisphere Publishing Corp.
© 2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
Social and Personality Psychology Compass 8/6 (2014): 263–274, 10.1111/spc3.12108