Imagining in the Public Sphere
Robert Asen
Contemporary public sphere scholarship has been motivated significantly
by a concem to overcome historical and conceptual exclusions in public
spheres. Recent theory and criticism has investigated direct and indirect
exclusions. Direct exclusions expressly prevent the participation of particular individuals and groups in public discussions and debates. Prohibitions against women speaking in public, for example, have served
historically to inhibit women's participation in various forums (see, e.g.,
Landes 1998). Indirect exclusions function tacitly through discursive norms
and practices that prescribe particular ways of interacting in public forums. Indirect exclusions compel participants to conform to established
modes of discourse that effectively negate the perspectives and contributions of previously directly excluded individuals and groups. Calls for "objective" and "dispassionate" debate, for instance, sometimes have restricted
public agendas by portraying culturally specific forms of address as universally practiced (see, e.g., Wamer 1993). Indirect exclusions may regulate discourse in various forums even when direct exclusions have been
counteracted. Scholarship seeking to overcome these exclusions has proceeded on two levels. On one level, scholars have recounted the efforts of
excluded persons to participate in public life despite restrictions by developing altemative modes of publicity (see, e.g., Ryan 1990; Zaeske 2002).
On a second level, theorists have proposed more inclusive conceptual
models ofthe public sphere that may overcome historical exclusions ofthe
bourgeois public sphere while retaining a commitment to critical publicity
(see, e.g., Asen 1999; Benhabib 1996; Hauser 1999; Mouffe 2000).
Practicing democratic discourse fairly and justly depends indispensably on enabling inclusion. Proponents of deliberative democracy argue
that political legitimacy arises from processes of inclusive public debate.
Seyla Benhabib asserts that "legitimacy in complex societies must be
Philosophy and Rlietoric, Vol. 35, No. 4,2002. Copyright © 2002 The Pennsylvania State
University. University Park, PA.
345
346
ROBERT ASEN
thought to result from the free and unconstrained public deliberation of all
about matters of common concern" (1996, 68). Others regard inclusive
public discourse as crucial for the formation of affirmative individual and
collective identities. Craig Calhoun faults bourgeois notions of publicity
for treating "identity formation as essentially private and prior to participation in the idealized public sphere of rational-critical discourse" (1993,
274). Identity formation entails mutual recognition among members of diverse cultures, yet theorists have observed that truncated discursive processes may inhibit mutual recognition. Charles Taylor writes that practicing
a politics of recognition requires an openness toward other cultures—a presumption of value tested through sustained engagement so that "what we
have formerly taken for granted as the background to valuation can be situated as one possibility alongside the background of the formerly unfamiliar culture" (1994, 67). Inclusiveness is also important for individuals and
groups seeking to advance self-fashioned interpretations of their interests
and needs against interpretations imposed by others. Nancy Fraser explains
that self-fashioning is necessary because in public debates and controversies "vt7io gets to establish authoritative thick definitions of people's needs
is itself a political stake" (1989, 164).
Although inclusion is indispensable, exclusion is never total. Sometimes, people force their way into public forums and agendas. For example,
participation by activists in discussions of AIDS research and treatment
often has been limited by researchers' assertions of expert privilege in investigating scientific matters. Valeria Fabj and Matthew J. Sobnosky (1995)
detail how .A.IDS activists have responded by engaging in discursive acts
of redefinition and translation to gain entry into previously circumscribed
forums. At other times, people surreptitiously access public arenas. Prison
writing is one way that those officially banished from public view nevertheless continue to participate in oppositional discourses and movements.
Gerard A. Hauser (2001) considers how dissident Adam Michnik remained
a vibrant voice in Polish civil society through his writings even after his
imprisonment in the 1980.S by an authoritarian regime. At still other times,
typically excluded people may be invited to participate in public discussions. Members of the AIDS activist group ACT UP occasionally have testified in the traditional setting of the congressional committee hearing as
invited witnesses. Daniel C. Brouwer (2001) maintains that politically sympathetic committee chairs facilitated ACT UP's "official" appearances before members of Congress. Whether invited or insisted, participation in
wider publics by previously excluded individuals and groups runs the risk
IMAGINING IN THE PUBLIC SPHERE
347
of co-optation—wider publics may attempt to recuperate dissident appeals
by creating an institutionally sanctioned and politically innocuous space
for the expression of opposition. Still, advocates and theorists alike regard
inclusion as crucial for reasons of political legitimacy, identity formation,
cultural diversity, and needs interpretation.
Exclusion also is never total because the dynamics of inclusion and
exclusion operate on multiple levels. Participation in public discussions
does not proceed only through voice and body; inclusions and exclusions
also occur in the perceptions of others—the imagining of others. Sometimes, individual and groups "appear" in debates from which they are physically absent as images (linguistic and/or visual representations) circulate
in public discourse. For instance, as members of Congress debated various
welfare reform proposals throughout the 1980s and 1990s, fewer than 4
percent of the witnesses testifying before participating House and Senate
committees identified themselves as current or former welfare recipients
(Asen 2002). Yet poor people were by no means absent from the debates;
vivid, disabling images of current and potential public assistance recipients elicited intense scrutiny from most debate participants. In the early
1980s, policymakers told tales of deceitful "welfare queens" who lived
lavishly on govemment benefits. Images of prodigality receded as the debates proceeded, but in their place arose images of recipients as unwed
teenage mothers who engaged in promiscuous sexual activity knowing that
the federal government would support their liaisons.
This essay seeks to draw critical attention to processes of imagining
as important aspects of the dynamics of inclusion and exclusion in public
spheres. I argue that imagining affects participants in public discussions
differently, often disadvantaging socially and historically marginalized
people and groups while tacitly aiding the appeals of others. I develop this
argument in three sections. The first section elucidates a concept of imagining as a collective, constitutive, and active force that forms part of our
shared social world. The second section unpacks connections between imagining and representation. Imagining enacts a politics of representation and
deploys multiple modes—linguistic and visual—of representation. The third
section amplifies the varying advantage that imagining affords to individuals
and groups by linking imagining with recent scholarship in public sphere
studies that has developed under the heading of "counterpublic." I maintain that critical attention to imagining may complement existing
counterpublic theory and criticism, which explicitly considers questions
of inclusion and exclusion and alternative publicities. The examples to
348
ROBERT ASEN
which I refer to illustrate my conceptual argument address a common topic:
U.S. welfare policy. This is an area of public discourse with an extensive
history of marginalization of and negative imagining about its putative
beneficiaries: poor people. Public debates over U.S. welfare policy offer a
dramatic example of how actual processes of imagining create advantages
for some and disadvantages for others.
A conception of imagining
In this section. I develop a preliminary concept of imagining as a constitutive social force. My discussion is preliminary because imagining as a social force draws its power from a capacity to represent people, objects, and
ideas—a power that, for analytic purposes. 1 address subsequently. However. I do not wish to advance an ontological or phenomenological argument. My goal is not to situate imagining as an originative social process,
nor do 1 aim to develop an account of imagining that describes objective
social phenomena. Rather, my conception is a critical one. I offer my conception of imagining as a tool that may inform critical investigations of the
ways in which included and excluded people appear in public spheres.'
Imagining may be conceived individually or collectively. As an individual concept, imagining typically has been defined as a mental faculty
capable of forming images and impressions, combining disparate ideas, or
perceiving phenomena. Yet the imagination in this view traditionally has
been regarded as subordinate to reason. According to Wolfgang Iser, "from
Aristotle through the beginnings of the modem age. imagination has been
regarded as an inferior faculty" (1993, 176). Writers .such as John Locke
described and denounced the imagination as pleasurable, mysterious, and
uncontrollable, even as they implicitly appealed to its manifold powers.
Jean-Paul Sartre departed famously from a faculty view in describing the
imagination as a constitutive act of consciousness. Sartre developed a relational view of the imagination as connecting consciousness to objects
through mental images: "The word image can therefore only indicate the
relation of consciousness to the object; in other words, it means a certain
manner in which the object makes its appearance to consciousness, or. if
one prefers, a certain way in which consciousness presents an object to
itself (1948, 8). While attributing a constitutive power to imagining, Sartre
maintained an individual conception.
IMAGINING IN THE PUBLIC SPHERE
349
An individual conception also has appeared in ostensibly unlikely
sources. In a widely cited study. Benedict Anderson examines how imagining inculcates and promotes ideas of nationhood. Anderson defines the
nation as an imagined community: "II is imagined because the members of
even the smallest nation will never know most of their fellow-members,
meet them, or even hear of them, yet in the minds of each lives the image
of their communion" (1991, 6). Anderson situates imagining within
sociopolitical processes of nationalism, and he writes of the ways in which
interactions among colonial subjects engendered notions of mutuality, yet
his definition of the nation as imagined locates this community in individual cognition. The nation resides in the "minds of each" inhabitant. As
constitutive of selves and nations, individual acts of imagination demand
critical attention. An individual conception of the imagination offers a compelling retort to deterministic theories of human thought and perception
that elevate rationality at the expense of other processes. .\n individual
conception also may elucidate, as Anderson demonstrates with nationalism, how seemingly disparate societal developments cohere in the perspectives of panicular people and attain a symbolic significance. My focus in
this article, however, is on the collective dimension of imagining.
Collective imagining does nol emerge through the aggregation of
individual thoughts and perceptions. Rather, collective imagining takes
shape through discursive engagement among interlocutors in contexts of
varying structure, scope, and formality. Discourse functions in this process
not as a vehicle for transmitting information and beliefs bul as a constitutive force. Reducing discourse to the role of transmitter would presume
that individuals enter into processes of social dialogue wiih their opinions
already formed and ordered. Sometimes this may be the case, but people
also may develop opinions only after discussing issues with others, or they
may change previously held views, or they may reorder their priorities.
Moreover, the "collective" modifying collective imagining suggests that
social dialogue enables the formation of opinions that did not exist prior to
discursive engagement. The images produced by processes of collective
imagining emerge in specific moments of interaction; they cannot be ascertained in advance. Collective imagining thus retains the relational quality of the imagination explicated by Sartre, but iis relation shifts. Rather
than describing a relationship between objects and consciousness, collective imagining refers to those images that emerge in intersubjective relations. In this way, collective imagining indicates a public process:
interlocutors engage in processes of imagining about people they regard as
350
ROBERT ASEN
similar to and different from themselves, and the processes and products of
the collective imagination are accessible to others.
In conceptualizing imagining as collective and constitutive, I do not
wish to make this process synonymous with what some theorists have termed
the '"social construction of reality." Kenneth J. Gergen defmes this latter
perspective as holding that '"what we take to be real is an outcome of social
relationships'" sustained through discourse (1999, 237). Imagining may
panicipate in constructing our shared social world, but it is not the only
participant. To be sure, some theorists have ascribed an apparently all-encompassing role to the imagination. A prominent theorist in this vein is
Cornelius Castoriadis, who attributes an originative role to the imagination in constituting self and society. He holds that the imagination constitutes the self as "a condition for all thought" (1987, 336). On the level of
society, Castoriadis develops a notion of "social imaginary significations"
to describe how imagining institutes society. He maintains that some imagined concepts—he references terms such as "citizen," "justice," "money,"
and others—sers'e a central role in structuring societies. Collective understandings of these intertwined central concepts order relationships among
the persons and objects through which they are represented. Yet he does
not regard this as a relationship between signs and their referents: "Central
significations are not significations "of something—nor are they, except
in a second-order sense, significations "attached' or "related' to something.
They constitute that which, for a given society, brings into being the cobelonging of objects, acts and individuals which, in appearance, are most
heterogeneous. They have no "referent'; they institute a mode of being of
things and individuals which relate to them" (364). From one vantage point,
Castoriadis's notion of the instituting force of the imagination stands as a
provocative statement against referential views of language. However, in
locating the symbolic action of discourse exclusively in the imagination,
Castoriadis presents a deterministic view of representation that undermines
his commitment to overdetermined signification. Moreover, his all-encompassing conception of the imaginary secures a prominent role for imagining by sacrificing its critical purchase. So long as it stands for everything,
Castoriadis's concept of imagining does not critically illuminate anything
in particular.
A more modest situation appears in the theorizing of Charles Taylor,
who locates the collective imagination between a realm of social habit and
a realm of explicit doctrine. Both distinctions, in varying degrees, are useful. Imagining should not be equated with routine behaviors or customs
IMAGINING IN THE PUBLIC SPHERE
351
even as imaginative processes sometimes may induce people to act
unreflectively. Imagining also resists the systematization connoted in doctrines. As systems of belief or articulated positions and principles, doctrines suggest a propositional structure and a susceptibility to tests of
propositional logic that do not characterize imagining. However, Taylor's
distinction becomes problematic in implying that processes of imagining
themselves may not be explicit. He describes the collective imagination as
"a level of images as yet unformulated in doctrine" (1993, 219). Insofar as
it restricts imagining to the background of public discourse, this description understates the power of imagining and neglects how imagining may
be employed to achieve specific ends.
Collective imagining may function as a background process or it may
be engaged actively. As a background process, the collective imagination
constitutes a constellation of shared assumptions, values, perceptions, and
beliefs for matters identified explicitly as topics of discussion. For instance,
present-day beliefs regarding private enterprise as more innovative and
efficient than government institutions condition debates about the future
of public programs such as social security retirement benefits. Likewise,
commitments to ""family values" tacitly inform debates over appropriate
public policy remedies for teen pregnancy (see Cloud 1998). Nancy Fraser
invokes the background functioning of the collective imagination when
she sets out to analyze the "political imaginary of social welfare" by considering "various taken-for-granted assumptions about people's needs and
entitlements" (1993, 9). Active engagement of the collective imagination
occurs in situations where advocates explicitly call upon their audiences to
rethink relations to one another. At these moments, participants in public
discussions explicitly reflect on the rights, responsibilities, and obligations
granted, entitled, and owed to one another. Active engagement proceeds,
for example, when policymakers heed the frequent calls of their colleagues
to reevaluate and to reorient the demands that govemment agencies place
on adult welfare recipients.
Processes of collective imagining may be most active in public debates and controversies. Controversy unsettles taken-for-granted values and
beliefs and raises the stakes of public discourse for participants and excluded others who nevertheless may be affected by the outcomes of particular debates (Olson and Goodnight 1994). Controversial issues often are
highly visible issues that rally widespread support and opposition and stir
strong feelings. Contestation accompanies controversy: advocates have to
advance particular images against competing constructions as they engage
352
ROBERT ASEN
interlocutors in the public sphere. Understood this way, controversy resists
traditional scholarly treatments that view controversy as something to be
avoided because it putatively departs from or perverts formal rules of disputation or reason. Instead, as G. Thomas Goodnight contends, controversy
may be seen as a practice that pushes and expands the available limits of
communication. Goodnight characterizes controversy as a "site where the
taken-for-granted relationships between communication and reasoning are
open to change, reevaluation, and development by argumentative engagement" (1991, 5). This view of controversy broaches the fluid and unstable
quality of collective imagining. Collective imagining does not proceed
ihrougb fixed, teleoJogical processes of discursive engagement; its images
are not constant and eternal. Imaginings change. Controversy engenders
moments especially amenable to changes in imagining by unsettling background understandings and engaging imagining as an active force.
A comparative example may serve to illustrate the conception of
imagining I have developed thus far. A number of scholars have held that
the bifurcation of the U.S. welfare state into social insurance and public
assistance programs sustains a two-tiered, gendered structure (see, e.g..
Fraser 1989; Gordon 1994; Mink 1995; Orloff 1991). Social insurance programs that tie participation to paid labor, distribute generous and geographically uniform grants, and require no further actions from recipients
historically have served men and their dependents. Such programs have
been celebrated in political discourse and their benefits have been characterized as "money owed." Images of elderly recipients circulate in public
discourse as honored senior citizens to whom politicians have binding obligations. By contrast, public assistance programs such as, until its 1996
repeal. Aid to Families with Dependent Children (AFDC) historically have
occupied an inferior position in the U.S. welfare state. These programs
generally serve mothers with young children, tie participation to household income, disperse meager grants that vary geographically, and require
the satisfaction of various corollary conditions by recipients. Public assistance programs have been vilified in political discourse and their benefits
often denounced as wasteful govemment spending. Adult recipients of public assistance have been portrayed as clients benefiting from public charity. These contrasting images of recipients have circulated despite the
operational similarities of social insurance and public assistance programs.
Although the structural inequities of social insurance and public assistance date back to the 1935 Social Security Act, the contrasting images
of recipients have transformed over time. Policymakers initially portrayed
IMAGINING IN THE PUBLIC SPHERE
353
adult female welfare recipients as valued and virtuous nurturers and
caregivers forced by circumstances beyond their control to assume the role
of breadwinner for their families. Policymakers believed Aid to Dependent
Children (ADC), as AFDC was then called, would allow poor mothers to
resume their important domestic responsibilities; they did not disparage
ADC recipients. In its report to the president, the U.S. Committee on Economic Security, the chief architectural body of the Social Security Act,
asserted that "we are strongly of the opinion that these families should be
differentiated from the permanent dependents and unemployables" (1935,
6). Similarly, images of social insurance recipients have changed. When
the Social Security Act was enacted, social insurance for the elderly was a
smaller and decidedly less popular program than Old Age Assistance, which
distributed more generous and more widespread benefits. Wishing to attract public suppon for its newly created social insurance program, the
Social Security Board began a public relations campaign to promote social
insurance as an honored entitlement for citizens (Gordon 1994, 282-83).
This campaign proceeded in part by denigrating all forms of public assistance—whether or not such assistance served an elderly population (Cates
1983, 104-35).
Imagining and representation
Imagining engages a particular power of discourse: a power of representation. In this section, I consider the relationship between imagining and representation by addressing the politics and modalities of representation.
Representing is not a disinterested process, but one that implicates social
judgments and relations of power, ln this way, representing enacts a politics of representation. Representing does not proceed exclusively through
one mode of communication, but may employ linguistic and visual symbols simultaneously and complementarily. In doing so, representing functions as a multimodal process.
To say that representation enacts a politics is to say that all representation is tendentious. When participants in public discourse describe themselves and others, they do not engage in a value-neutral and transparent
process. Rather, representational processes implicate participants in (often
unacknowledged) choices regarding how people should be portrayed. As
Linda Hutcheon explains, these processes do not "reflect society as much
354
ROBERT ASEN
as grant meaning and value within a particular society'" (1989, 24-25).
Representing does not occur outside of history and society, but works with
the symbolic materials of specific cultures. In this way, representing invokes social values and beliefs as well as the interests of panicipants in
public discourse. Representing engages relations of power and social hierarchies. Further, the politics of representation produces consequences—
both for those representing and those represented. Our attitude toward and
treatment of others depends crucially on how we imagine others, and representations express our collective imagination (see Dyer 1993; Scarry
1996).
The intimate connection between representations and social values,
beliefs, and interests indicates that representational processes may frame
public debates, identify proper objectives for collective action, and suggest appropriate remedies. One can note unobjectionably that the percentage of eligible people receiving AFDC increased nearly three-fold from
the early 1960s through the early 1970s (Patterson 1994, 179). Disagreements arise, however, as soon as one offers an interpretation of this trend.
Some commentators view this rise in AFDC receipt as evidence of a misguided federal policy subsidizing pathological behavior and thus encouraging family break-up and the dissolution of the work ethic among poor
people. Conservative social critic Charles Murray characterizes this trend
as a "generous revolution." He argues that the federal government changed
the system of punishments and rewards facing poor people "to make it
more profitable for the poor to behave in the short term in ways that were
destructive in the long term" (1994, 9). Others see this same development
as the successful outcome of efforts by community activists and poverty
lawyers seeking to transform a situation in which a minority of eligible
poor people participated in programs ostensibly designed for them to one
in which the vast majority did. The scholar/activists Frances Fox Piven
and Richard A. Cloward describe the rise in welfare roles as an act of resistance. They insist that "the great rise in relief insurgency can be understood as a rebellion by the poor against the circumstances that deprived
them of both jobs and income" (1979, 265). Both interpretations offer images that link up with larger political programs. From one perspective, the
poor person appears as a naive subject led astray by arrogant government
officials. From another perspective, the poor person appears as a triumphant agent holding state officials to their word.
Despite their political power (or, perhaps, as an augmentation of their
political power), representations purport to be natural, universal, and es-
IMAGINING IN THE PUBLIC SPHERE
355
sential renderings of objective phenomena. Frank Lentricchia refers to the
tendency of representations to hide their constructed character as the "coercive power" of representations. He explains that representations assert
"an ontological claim, used like a hanuner, that some part of the whole
really does stand in for the whole" (1983, 153). Created in particular
sociopolitical contexts, representations may draw attention away from these
contexts. In these cases, their persuasive power arises in important respects
from their ability to appear detached from political struggles. Representing thus becomes a "cover-up" by concealing itself as "an agency of specific political power" and by obscuring "social and cultural difference and
conflict" (153). Representations are at their most political when they appear to be non-political.
A fundamental tension in representation between absence and presence, between standing for something and embodying that something, bolsters this political power. Representation historically has meant both
standing for something absent and making something present (see Williams 1983). Representation as absence informs theories of representative
democracy whereby elected officials in parliamentary or legislative bodies
speak on behalf of their constituents. Representation as presence orients
theories of aesthetic realism that judge artworks by their ability to portray
the elements of our physical world in a lifelike manner (Derrida 1982; Pitkin
1967). Yet each notion of representation implicates the other: standing for
something absent may create a sense of presence, and making something
present may overcome its absence. Employing the terms "speaking for"
and "speaking about," Linda Alcoff situates this mutual implication of absence and presence in the context of participants and non-participants in
public discourse. She observes that "when one is speaking for others one
may be describing their situation and thus also speaking about them." Similarly, "when one is speaking about others, or simply trying to describe their
situation or some aspect of it, one may also be speaking in place of them,
that is, speaking for them" (1991-92,9). As Alcoff notes, neatly separating
these two senses may be possible only analytically. Absence and presence
create an irreducible tension in representing: the representation is and is
not the person, object, or idea represented.
This tension between absence and presence in representation critically influences collective imagining by interacting with dynamics of inclusion and exclusion in public spheres to operate on participants and
excluded others. Imagining can make those present absent and those absent present. Negative circulating images may lead some people to self-
356
ROBERT ASEN
censor their contributions to public debates, and negative images may
prompt other participants to disregard their contributions. People affiliated
with historically marginalized groups seem especially susceptible to both
outcomes, since they often are subjected to negative imagining. Iris Marion
Young notes that participatory norms of discourse "are powerful silencers
or evaluators of speech in many actual speaking situations where culturally differentiated and socially unequal groups live together" (1996, 124;
see also Young 2000, 53-55). Imagining may effectively silence and make
absent some debate participants. The reverse process of making present
those absent typifies the relation of poor people to welfare policy debates.
Negative images of poor people as members of a dangerous "underclass,"
for example, have often attained an ominous presence in media and policy
forums. In his popular 1982 book The Underclass, journalist Ken Auietta
grouped long-term welfare recipients with street thugs, hustlers, drifters,
mental patients, and others as comprising the underclass. Tying these figures together through a singular focus on deviance, he asserted that the
"underclass usually operates outside the generally accepted boundaries of
society. They are often set a p a r t . . . by their deviant or antisocial behavior,
by their bad habits, not just by their poverty" (28). The image of a fearsome underclass spurred subsequent reform efforts. In a 1987 U.S. House
Education and Labor Committee hearing. Representative Harris Fawell
expressed his desire for welfare reform legislation in starkly pragmatic
terms: "We are scared, too. I mean the whole problem is terrible. . , . We
have communities sitting by watching [their] own community go to hell,
so to speak" (339). As Fawell's apprehension reveals, the "underclass" did
not need to participate directly in the debates to attain a presence.
Representing may enact a politics through multiple communicative
modes. Thus far I have focused on imagining as a linguistic process. When
witnesses appear before congressional committees to tell stories of increased
illegitimacy, unemployment, or crime among poor people, they do so principally through written and oral testimony. When editorialists, opinion columnists, and talk show hosts censure poor people for perpetuating a
deleterious "underclass," they do so chiefly through the printed or spoken
word. The same can be said for less formal and more prevalent forms of
vernacular exchange that constitute the public sphere as a multiplicity of
diverse and partially overlapping discursive venues: When suburbanites
gathered at a neighborhood picnic decry the expenditure of tax dollars on
"undeserving" poor people, the primary medium they employ is talk. And,
when poor people join together to confront negative images about them
IMAGINING IN THE PUBLIC SPHERE
357
circulating in politics, media, and middle-class society, they sometimes
invent and disseminate alternative vocabularies to express their interests,
identities, and needs. But imagining should not be limited to its linguistic
manifestations.
Processes of collective imagining may employ both linguistic and
visual modes of representation. The polysemic character of "image"—which
denotes a physical likeness, optical reflection, mental representation, figure of speech, and public perception—suggests the multimodality of imagining. Visual artifacts and linguistic texts may work together to produce
compelling circulating images. Along these lines, Cara A. Finnegan cautions critics against viewing visual and linguistic elements of a rhetorical
artifact as self-contained and binary. She argues instead that "the goal of
analyzing the imagetext [a synthetic combination of visual image and linguistic text] is not simply to compare images to texts, but rather to recognize the inherent tensions in the marriage of image and texts and investigate
how those tensions make or negotiate meaning" (2000, 340; see also
Mitchell 1994). Similarly, Catherine Helen Palczewski (2002) considers
how public debates may proceed through the mutual invocation of visual
and verbal elements.- In a revealing study, Martin Gilens considers how
visual images have appeared in print media to project racial images of poor
people. Analyzing pictures of poor people that appeared in the national
newsweeklies Time, Newsweek, and U.S. News and World Report between
the years 1950 and 1992, Gilens (1999, 122-25) reaches two troubling conclusions. First, blacks were overrepresented among pictures of poor people.
They appeared in 53.4 percent of the pictures though their proportion among
the poor during this period was 29.3 percent. Second, as the negative tone
of the coverage of poverty increased, so too did the percentage of blacks
pictured, and as the negative tone of the coverage decreased, so too did the
percentage of blacks among pictures of the poor. So, for example, in the
years 1972-73, as public concerns about rising welfare costs and caseloads
waxed and as the optimism of the 1960s waned, the percentage of blacks
pictured topped 70 percent. However, as an economic downturn developed
in the 1970s and a focus on unemployment increasingly occupied magazine articles, the percentage of blacks pictured dropped to 49 percent.
In the objects investigated by Gilens, linguistic and visual elements
worked together to engender processes of imagining. In the periods when
the articles primarily portrayed poverty as a result of behavioral deficiencies, presaging contemporary concerns about an urban "underclass," pictures of blacks helped construct a racially coded image of poor people. Yet
358
ROBERT ASEN
when the main focus of the articles shifted from behavior to environment,
partially absolving poor people of blame for their economic woes, more
racially diverse pictures invited connections between the subjects of the
articles and the magazines' mostly white readership. Gilen's study contains two implications for considering the relationship between linguistic
and visual modes of representation. First, whether linguistic, visual, or both
modes of representation are functioning and, in the latter case, whether
one mode predominates depends crucially on context. In certain forums in
the public sphere, such as the formal site of the congressional committee
hearing room and the vernacular sites of neighborhood gatherings, linguistic modes may function primarily. In other forums, such as the mass mediated site of television campaign advertising or news coverage of political
demonstrations, visual modes may function primarily. And still in other
forums, neither mode may predominate and instead create irresolvable tensions. Second, the point is not to assert the primacy of either mode but, in
those moments when processes of imagining engage both linguistic and
visual representation, to explore their interaction.
Imagining and counterpublics
I have touched on the theme of the advantages and disadvantages afforded
to participants in multiple public spheres through processes of imagining
by discussing how the politics of representation engages dynamics of inclusion and exclusion to make those present absent and those absent present.
In this section. 1 connect these dynamics to counterpublic theory and criticism. I suggest through examples some specific ways in which imagining
creates varj'ing degrees of advantage: by impugning the credibility of
counterpublic agents, by concentrating historical animosities in negative
images, and by creating a cumulative imaginary field that constrains the
choices of successive participants.
Counterpublic theory explicitly addresses acts of inclusion and exclusion in multiple public spheres (see, e.g., Dawson 1995; Doxtader 2001;
Fraser 1992; Squires 2001). As a critical term, "counterpublic" refers to
those publics that form through mutual recognition of exclusions in wider
publics, set themselves against exclusionary wider publics, and resolve to
overcome these exclusions. Recognition of exclusion is crucial for the formation and investigation of counterpublics. Counterpublic loses its criti-
IMAGINING IN THE PUBLIC SPHERE
359
cally illuminating force if it refers to excluded people per se. Individuals
do not necessarily recognize exclusions and resolve to overcome them by
virtue of their location in a social order. Invoking counterpublic in this
manner would reduce the term to the identity of particular participants and
presume a shared set of interests among people who may not see themselves as allies. One does not participate in a counterpublic formed around
issues of poverty simply through receipt of public assistance. For example,
former AFDC recipient Nancy Peterson appeared before the Human Resources Subcommittee in 1996 to support the punitive tone of the debates
and to endorse strict time limits and unequivocal work requirements. Evaluating reforms adopted in her home state, she judged that "the changes that
Michigan has made have been positive changes. We do not need to be as
soft as it has been. I am motivated. But other people are not. There needs to
be a little bit of a push to motivate people to work, to get a feel of what that
is like, to make them responsible" (U.S. House 1995, 58). In casting doubt
on the work habits of other recipients, Peterson did not call into question
disabling discursive practices, but reaffirmed larger themes informing the
debates. Moreover, critical attention to recognition facilitates exploration
of counterpublics constituted not only by persons excluded from wider
publics, but by coalitions of people of varied social, economic, and political status dedicated to overcoming exclusions.
As explicitly articulated alternatives to wider publics that neglect
the interests of their participants, counterpublics contest direct and indirect exclusions. Overcoming direct exclusions enables counterpublic agents
to access previously restricted forums. Yet counterpublic agents often must
continue their struggle to reconstitute these forums so that contributions
from diverse participants may not only be permitted but also appreciated.
Contestation draws attention to discursive norms and practices: how exclusions prevent participation by some people, how exclusions defiect attention from certain discussion topics, and how exclusions circumscribe
particular ways of speaking. Invoking the absence and presence of representation, imagining may function as a discursive practice that disadvantages counterpublic agents in moments of interaction among multiple
publics.
Imagining in a multiple public sphere is multidirectional. Wider publics may imagine themselves (as, for example, patriotic and hard-working
Americans) and actual or potential counterpublics. Wider public imagining may spur counterpublicity. Regarding wider processes of imagining as
a source of grievance, social actors may join together to resist objection-
360
ROBERT ASEN
able images circulating in public discourse. For iheir part, counterpublic
agents may imagine themselves and others. Imagining appears to function
crucially for counterpublicity insofar as recognition of exclusion invokes
an image of wider forums unfairly and unjustly closed off to outside participation and populated by ideologically driven and/or mean-spirited
people.^ In this imaginary realm, counterpubiic agents stand as indignant
social reformers seeking to uphold a greater good. Processes of imagining,
then, may be inwardly and outwardly directed both for counterpublics and
wider publics. My concem in this section is those interactive moments
among publics and counterpublics when some counterpublic agents have
gained access to wider forums but have not yet reconstituted the discursive
exclusions of wider publics.
In such interactive moments, counierpublics suffer from what I call
the doubly disabling tendencies of representation. Counterpublics often
struggle to gain access to the very forums in which others are imagining
them, often in ways objectionable to counterpublic agents. The doubly disabling tendencies of representation arise from this dynamic: Voices and
bodies largely absent from public discourses may be made present through
disabling images. The various goods that theorists associate with inclusive
public deliberation suggest that the consequences of the doubly disabling
tendencies of representation implicate issues of political legitimacy, identity formation, cultural diversity, and needs interpretation. Moreover, these
consequences affect counterpublic participation even after some agents have
entered particular forums. Negative imagining constitutes a symbolic hurdle
that counterpublic agents—but not other participants—have to overcome.
Negative images circulating in wider forums impugn the character
of counterpublic agents participating in these forums." Negative images
compel counterpublic agents to engage the statements of others from multiple vantage points: counterpublic agents may wish to assert their interests and identities as they see them, and yet they may need to counteract
negative images representing counterpublics. Christine Pratt-Marston confronted this discursive obstacle when she testified before the U.S. House
Public Assistance and Unemployment Compensation Subcommittee in 1981
to object to proposed budget cuts in AFDC and other social programs. PrattMarston explained to the subcommittee that low-wage labor required her
to receive AFDC benefits. Yet she refused to be seen as an "AFDC recipient" in the pejorative sense of the term—as someone choosing to live comfortably on government aid while avoiding the demands of paid labor.
Instead, Pratt-Marston sought to complicate simplistic representations of
IMAGINING IN THE PUBLIC SPHERE
361
poor people's lives. She introduced herself to the subcommittee as a single
parent, a foster parent, a taxpayer, and a disabled person. She shared with
committee members the aspirations of many poor people—and the frustrations they experienced in the low-wage labor market. Connecting her own
experiences to others, she explained, "when we try to become employed,
we find that we cannot make it. We cannot pay for daycare, we do not have
health services for our children, and we cannot pay the rent to feed our
children. So we find ourselves going back on welfare" (84). As PrattMarston's references to daycare and medical care demonstrate, she sought
to advocate a policy agenda capable of ameliorating the lives of poor people.
Yet she also had to confront negative images of welfare recipients that may
have raised doubts about her credibility among committee members. As
Pratt-Marston explained, negative images of welfare recipients often arose
from confounding and contradictory social expectations: "When I am home
taking care of my four children and two foster children, I am a lazy welfare
broad. And when I go across the street and take care of my neighbor's one
child, I am employed. And I fail to understand the rationale of that" (84).
Pratt-Marston could not ignore negative circulating images if she wished
to advance positive interpretations of her identities and interests.
Competing societal expectations of child rearing and paid employment intimate another obstacle that imagining creates for counterpublic
agents: negative images may invoke historical animosities and concentrate
these animosities in conflicts over representation. After completing her testimony, Pratt-Marston responded to questions from various subcommittee
members. Representative John Rousselot appeared especially skeptical of
her claims regarding the inadequacy of AFDC and its connection to the
low-wage labor market. He asked Pratt-Marston: "Now, what do you suppose the problem is in going back to work?" Without waiting for an answer, Rousselot shared his own view: "What we are really saying, then, is
that they are not able to get a job to encourage them to go back to work that
is [at] a level of pay that can compete with what they are getting" (U.S.
House 1981, 95). His answer invoked an image of welfare recipients as
comfortable individuals insufficiently motivated to seek paid employment.
Pratt-Marston's reply advanced an alternative image: "I would not say it is
a matter of competing with what they are getting. 1 would say it is a matter
of a level of pay that allows them to survive and feed their children and pay
their rent" (95). In her reply, Pratt-Marston imagined welfare recipients—
including herself—as valiant but struggling parents desperately attempting to provide for their children. Rousselot retorted that he too wanted
362
ROBERT .AiSEN
poor people to survive, but reiterated, "they are not able to get something
in the employment field that is competitive with what they are receiving"
(95). Pratt-Marston in turn highlighted welfare recipients' lack of training,
which prompted a discussion of federal job training programs launched in
the 1960s. Rousselot labeled these programs a failure. Pratt-Marston pointed
to a lack of jobs for program participants and countered that these programs had provided social ser\'ices and offered an irreplaceable supplement to poor people's incomes. Beginning with the relationship of public
assistance and low-wage labor. Rousselot and Pratt-Marston proceeded to
an evaluation of Great Society programs. Their differing judgments reflected
divergent political outlooks that placed varying emphasis on the proper
role of government as an ameliorative social force. In this way, they entered into a long-standing and wide-ranging debate, and their points of entr>'
and critical judgment relied significantly on contrasting images of poor
people.
Informing particular interactions between counterpublic agents and
others, circulating images do not disappear when specific discussions conclude. Some images linger in the public imagination. These images constitute a cumulative imaginary field that constrains the choices of successive
participants; they shape subsequent rhetorical situations. Calls for budget
cuts in social programs in 1981 gained strength from earlier charges of
waste and fraud in public assistance programs. In his unsuccessful 1976
presidential campaign, Ronald Reagan repeatedly relayed the alleged exploits of the "Chicago welfare queen." At many campaign appearances, he
enraged audiences with the stor\' of a woman in Chicago who "has 80 names,
30 addresses. 12 Social Security cards and is collecting veterans' benefits
on four nonexisting decea.sed husbands. And she's collecting Social Security on her cards. She's got Medicaid, getting food stamps and she is collecting welfare under each of her names. Her tax-free cash income alone is
over $150,000." (quoted in "Welfare Queen" 1976, 51; see also Weiler 1992,
232). By 1981. images of fraud had become so widespread that they elicited parodies from policymakers who supported public assistance programs.
Pete Stark, chairperson ofthe Public Assistance and Unemployment Compensation Subcommittee and a longtime advocate of federal anti-poverty
programs, solicited one witness's help in locating a particularly notorious
welfare cheat who roamed his district. He wanted to track down "this
woman, and for some reason it is a woman, who is ahead of each one of my
constituents in the checkout line at a supermarket and has bought a tremendous amount of Perrier and chickens. Actually, they are never chickens;
IMAGINING IN THE PUBLIC SPHERE
363
they are Cornish game hens stuffed with wild rice. A whole carton of these
go into the trunk o f . . . a new Cadillac." Fed up with her behavior. Stark
announced a plan to stop this woman and others who may have been tempted
to follow her example: "I have a bill that I am about to introduce that would
make it a felony for a Cadillac salesman to accept food stamps in full or
partial payment for the Cadillac" (U.S. House 198L 74). To call attention
to the cumulative force of imagining is not to ascribe a determinative force
to imagining. Circulating images and other aspects of collective imagining
may be only one element informing specific discursive engagements in the
public sphere. And discourse may be constrained variously and to varying
degrees. Still, prominent images compel an accounting from future participants. As welfare reform debates continued throughout the 1980s and 1990s,
participants had to address the question of whether the non-needy had been
vanquished from the welfare rolls.
Conclusion
Hoping to redeem a promise of critical publicity, contemporary' public sphere
scholarship has drawn critical attention to direct and indirect exclusions in
multiple public spheres. I have sought to contribute to this effort by considering the interrelationship of exclusions operating on multiple levels.
Specifically, I have considered how dynamics of inclusion and exclusion
may be engaged at the level of the imagination. Imagining proceeds importantly in this regard as a collective process that participates in constructing
a shared social world. Collective imagining draws its power as a representational process, one that enacts a politics and utilizes linguistic and visual
modalities. In interactive moments between counterpublics and wider publics, collective imagining functions as a symbolic hurdle for counterpublic
agents insofar as it circulates negative images that undermine their credibility and concentrates historical animosities in conflicts over representation. Moreover, prominent circulating images constitute a cumulative
imaginarj' field that constrains the choices of successive participants.
Attention to imagining reveals that including more and more voices
in multiple public spheres—a form of direct inclusion—is an indispensable but by itself insufficient reformulation of critical models of the public
sphere. As with other discursive norms and practices, imagining may inform interactions even in ostensibly accessible forums. The consequences
364
ROBERT ASEN
of collective imagining appear in the doubly disabling tendencies of representation that absent some people from public discourse and yet present
them through disabling images. Counterpublic agents encounter these negative images as they enter previously foreclosed forums. Yet disabling tendencies of representation should not prompt a scholarly flight from
imagining and its representational power. A flight of this sort would retum
public sphere scholarship to a reconstructed bourgeois public sphere as a
singular public forum in which everyone—at least in principle—is free to
participate. Existing scholarship has demonstrated that such a sphere would
most likely betray its legitimating discourses at the level of direct exclusions. A flight from representation also would require a renunciation of
poiiticai legitimacy, identity formation, cultural diversity, and needs interpretation as appropriate topics of public discourse, for these are social goods.
More hopefully, representation ought not to be disavowed because imagining need not be disabling. Counterpublics may interact with wider publics
to construct affirmative images of themselves and others that may engender discourses capable of advancing the multiple aims of discourse in the
public sphere. Scholars may contribute to this process by elucidating how
various forums may exclude potential participants in voice, body, and imagination.
Departrr^enl
Institution
Notes
1. Michael Osbom has developed a notion of "'rhetorical depiction" to explain how rhetors
may prompt visualization in their audiences. He observes that 'contemporary rhetoric seems
dominated by strategic pictures, verbal or nonverbal visualizations that linger in the collective memory of audiences as representative of their subjects when rhetoric has been successful" (1986. 79). He quotes George Campbell's view of significant metaphor to describe depiction as "an allegory in miniature" (1986. 80). Though "depiction" resonates with "imagining." Osbom's invocation of allegory suggests a more directed symbolic process. Moreover. Osborn does not consider depiction as a collective process, nor does he explore the
political dimension of representation.
2. See also Lake and Pickering 1998. Scholarly attention to the communicative qualities
of visual images has produced a provocative, growing field of inquiry (see. e.g.. Biesecker
1998; DeLuca 1999; DcLuca and Demo 2000; Lucaites 1997). Sometimes, however, statements asserting the prominence of visual modes of communication extend into the hyperbolic. For instance, although he initially describes political messages as 'complex composites of multiple discourses created in verbal, visual, and acoustic languages" (1995. 219).
Bruce Gronbeck stresses the visual as the primary mode of discourse in the contemporary
public sphere. He writes: "The telespectacle, for better or worse, is the center of public
politics, of the public sphere. . . . We must recognize that the conversation of the culture is
centered not in the New York Review of Books but in the television experience" (235).
IMAGINING IN THE PUBLIC SPHERE
365
Gronbeck's characterization of the contemporary public sphere is problematic on several
counts. First, his remarks betray a desire to locate a center, while the public sphere may be
better appreciated as a multiplicity with no primary focal point. Second, he sets up two
overly restrictive options for discourse between the "telespectacle" on the one hand and
detached proto-academic discussion on the other. Most di.scourse in the public sphere likely
lies between these two poles. Third. Gronbeck privileges mass-mediated discourse over more
vernacular forms of political communication. Although thousands of people appear each
year on television, many millions more do not—yet they nevertheless engage in '"public
politics" that participates in constituting a multiple public sphere.
3. I invoke ideology here in its classical sense as the false representation of the interests
ofthe few as the interests ofthe many. On the diverse and sometimes contradictory ways in
which theorists have understood ideology, see Eagleton 1991.
4. This potential obstacle appears e.specially harmful in light of the role that character
{ethos) plays in adjudicating tensions of dissent and consensus in a multiple public sphere.
Erik Doxtader explains that "the ethos of an advocate marks these oppositions [expressions
of dissent] with a concession: the merit of the dissident's proposal turns on whether an audience is able to see why and how the speaker is willing to bear the risk of her own transgression" (2000. 360). Ethos functions as a constitution of the self that permits recognition of an
other: "Ethos is a figure of accountability (a mean) that offers some insight into the relation
between the improvisation of creative reasoning and the procedures of intersubjective dialogue" (360). Negative imagining precludes this assertion of responsibility insofar as it circumscribes how one may appear.
Works cited
Alcoff. Linda. 1991-92. "The Problem of Speaking for Others." Cultural Critique 20: 5-32.
Anderson, Benedict. 1991. Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of
Nationalism, rev. ed. London: Verso.
Asen. Robert. 1999. "Toward a Normative Conception of Difference in Public Deliberation." Argumentation and Advocacy 35: 115-29.
. 2002. Visions of Poverty: Welfare Policy and Political Imagination. East Lansing:
Michigan State UP.
Auletta. Ken. 1982. The Underclass. New York: Random House.
Benhabib. Seyla. 1996. "Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy." In Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries ofthe Political, ed. Seyla Benhabib.
Princeton. NJ: Princeton UP.
Biesecker. Barbara. 1998. ""Rhetorical Ventriloquism: Fantasy and/as American National
Identity." In Argument in a Time of Change, ed. James F. Klumpp. Annandale. VA: National Communication Association.
Brouwer. Daniel C. 2001. "'ACT-ing UP in Congressional Hearings." In Counterpublics and
the State, ed. Robert Asen and Daniel C. Brouwer. Albany: State U of New York P.
Calhoun. Craig. 1993. "'Civil Society and the Public Sphere." Public Culture 5: 267-80.
Castoriadis. Cornelius. 1987. The Imaginary Institution of Society. Trans. Kathleen Blamey.
Cambridge: MIT P.
Cates, Jerry R. 1983. Insuring Inequality: Administrative Leadership in Social Security,
1935-54. Ann Arbor: U of Michigan P.
Cloud. Dana L. 1998. "The Rhetoric of <Family Values>: Scapegoating, Utopia, and the
Privatization of Social Responsibility." Western Journal of Communication 62: 387419.
Dawson. Michael C. 1995. "A Black Counterpublic?: Economic Earthquakes. Racial
.Agenda(s), and Black Politics." ln The Black Public Sphere, ed. Black Public Sphere
Collective. Chicago: U of Chicago P.
DeLuca, Kevin Michael. 1999. Image Politics: The New Rhetoric of Environmental Activism. New York: Guilford P.
DeLuca. Kevin Michael, and Anne Teresa Demo. 2000. "'Imaging Nature: Watkins. Yosemite.
and the Birth of Environmentalism." Critical Studies in Media Communication 17: 241-61.
366
ROBERT ASEN
Derrida, Jacques. 1982. "Sending: On Represenlalion." Social Research 49: 294-326.
Doxtader. Erik. 2000. "Character.s in the Middle of Public Life: Consensus. Dissent, and
Ethos." Philosophy and Rhetoric 33: 336-69.
. 2001. "In the Name of Reconciliation: The Faith and Works of Counterpublicity." In
Counterpublics and the State, ed. Robert Asen and Daniel C. Brouwer. Albany: State U
of New York P.
Dyer, Richard. 1993. The Matter of Images: Essays on Representation. New York: Routledge.
Eagleton. Terry. 1991. Ideology: An Introduction. London: Verso.
Fabj, Valeria, and Matthew J. Sobnosky. 1995. "AIDS Activism and the Rejuvenation of the
Public Sphere." .Argumentation and Advocacy 31: 163-84.
Finnegan. Cara A. 2000. "Social Engineering. Visual Politics, and the New Deal: FSA Photography in Survey Graphic." Rhetoric & Public Affairs 3: 333-62.
Fraser, Nancy. 1989. Unruly Practices: Power, Discourse, and Gender in Contemporary
Social Theory. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P.
. 1992. "Rethinking the Public Sphere: A Contribution to the Critique of Actually
Existing Democracy." In Habermas and the Public Sphere, ed. Craig Calhoun. Cambridge: MIT P.
. 1993. "Clintonism, Welfare, and the Antisocial Wage: The Emergence of a Neoliberal
Political Imaginary." Rethinking Marxism 6.1: 9-23.
Gergen. Kenneth J. 1999. An Invitation to Social Construction. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
Gilens, Martin. 1999. Why Americans Hate Welfare: Race, Media, and the Politics of Antipoverty Policy. Chicago: U of Chicago P.
Goodnight, G. Thomas. 1991. "Controversy." \n Argument in Controver.iy.ed. Donn W. Parson. Annandale, VA: Speech Communication Association.
Gordon, Linda. 1994. Pitied hut not Entitled: Single Mothers and the History of Welfare.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP.
Gronbeck, Bruce E. 1995. "Rhetoric, Ethics, and Telespeclacles in the Post-everything Age."
In Postmodern Representations: Truth, Power, and Mimesis in the Human Sciences and
Public Culture, ed. Richard Harvey Brown. Urbana: U of Illinois P.
Hauser, Gerard A. 1999. Vemacttlar Voices: The Rhetoric of Publics and Public Spheres.
Columbia: U of South Carolina P.
. 2001. "Prisoners of Conscience and the Counterpublic Sphere of Prison Writing:
The Stones that Start the .Avalanche." )n Coumerpuhlics and the State, ed. Robert Asen
and Daniel C. Brouwer. .Albany: State U of New York P.
Hutcheon. Linda. 1989. "The Politics of Representation." Signature: A Journal of Theory
and Canadian Literature 1: 23^4.
Iser, Wolfgang. 1993. The Fictive and the Imaginary: Charting Literary Anthropology. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP.
Lake. Randall A., and Barbara A. Pickering. 1998. "Argumentation, the Visual, and the Possibility of Refutation: An Exploration." Argumentation 12: 79-93.
Landes, Joan B. 1998. "The Public and the Private Sphere: A Feminist Reconsideration." In
Feminism. The Public & The Private, ed. Joan B. Landes. New York: Oxford UP.
Lentricchia, Frank. 1983. Criticism and Social Change. Chicago: U of Chicago P.
Lucaites. John Louis. 1997. "Visualizing 'the People': Individualism vs. Collectivism in Let
Us Now Praise Famous Men." Quarterly Journal of Speech 83: 269-88.
Mink. Gwendolyn. 1995. The Wages of Motherhood: Inequality in the Welfare State, 19171942. Ithaca. NY: Cornell UP.
Mitchell, W. J. T. 1994. Picture Theory: Essays on Verbal and Visual Representation. Chicago: U of Chicago P.
Mouffe, Chantal. 2000. The Democratic Paradox. London: Verso.
Murray, Charles. 1994. Losing Ground: American Social Policy, 1950-1980. 10th Anniversary ed. New York: Basic Books.
Olson. Kathryn M., and G. Thomas Goodnight. 1994. "Entanglements of Consumption, Cruelty. Privacy, and Fashion: The Social Controversy over Fur." Quarterly Journal of Speech
80: 249-76.
IMAGINING IN THE PUBLIC SPHERE
367
Orloff, Ann Shola. 1991. "Gender in Early U.S. Social Policy." Journal of Policy History 3:
249-81.
Osbom. Michael. 1986. "Rhetorical Depiction." In Form, Genre, and the Study of Political
Discourse, ed. Herbert W. Simons and Aram A. Aghazarian. Columbia: U of South Carolina P.
Palczewski, Catherine Helen. 2002. "Argument in an Off Key: Playing with the Productive
Limits of Argument." In Arguing Communication & Culture, ed. G. Thomas Goodnight.
Washington, D.C: National Communication Association.
Patterson, James T. 1994. America's Struggle Against Poverty 1900-1994. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard UP.
Pitkin, Hanna Fenichel. 1967. The Concept of Representation. Berkeley: U of California P.
Piven, Frances Fox. and Richard A. Cloward. 1979. Poor People's Movements: Why They
Succeed, How They Fail. New York: Vintage Books.
Ryan, Mary P. 1990. Women in Public: Between Banners and Ballots, 1825-1880. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP.
Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1948. The Psychology of Imagination. Trans. B. Frechtman. New York:
Philosophical Library.
Scarry, Elaine. 1996. "The Difficulty of Imagining Other People." In For Love of Country:
Debating the Limits of Patriotism, ed. Martha C. Nussbaum. Boston: Beacon P.
Squires, Catherine. 2001. "The Black Press and the State: Attracting Unwanted (?) Attention." In Counterpublics and the State, ed. Robert .Asen and Daniel C. Brouwer. Albany:
State U of New York P.
Taylor, Charles. 1993. Modernity and the Rise of the Public Sphere, Tanner Lectures on
Human Values, voi. 14. Salt Lake City: U of Utah P.
. 1994. "The Politics of Recognition." In Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of
Recognition, ed. Amy Gutmann. Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP.
U.S. Committee on Economic Security. 1935. Report to the President of the Committee on
Economic Security. Washington. DC: U.S. Government Printing Office.
U.S. House. 1981. Committee on Ways and Means. Subcommittee on Public Assi.stance and
Unemployment Compensation. Administration's Proposed Savings in Unemployment
Compensation, Public Assistance, and Social Sen'ices Programs. 97th Cong.. 1st sess.
11 March.
. 1987. Committee on Education and Labor. Hearings on Welfare Reform: H.R. 30,
Fair Work Opportunities Act of 1987 and H.R. 1720, Family Welfare Reform Act of 1987.
100th Cong., 1st sess. 5 May.
-. 1995. Committee on Ways and Means. Subcommittee on Human Resources. Welfare
Reform Success Stories. 104th Cong.. 1st sess. 6 December.
Wamer, Michael. 1993. "The Mass Public and the Mass Subject." In The Phantom Public
Sphere, ed. Bruce Robbins. Minneapolis: U of Minne.sota P.
Weiler, Michael. 1992. "The Reagan Attack on Welfare." In Reagan and Public Discourse
in America, ed. Michael Weiler and W. Barnett Pearce. Tuscaloosa: U of Alabama P.
"'Welfare Queen' Becomes Issue in Reagan Campaign." 1976. New York Times. 15 February, late city edition.
Williams, Raymond. 1983. Keywords: .4 Vocabulary of Culture and Society, rev. ed. NewYork: Oxford UP.
Young, Iris Marion. 1996. "Communication and the Other: Beyond Deliberative Democracy." In Democracv and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, ed.
Seyla Benhabib. Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP.
. 2000. Inclusion and Democracy. New York: Oxford UP.
Zaeske, Susan. 2002. "Signatures of Citizenship: The Rhetoric of Women's Antislavery Petitions." Quarterly Journal of Speech 88: 147-68.