Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                
materialisierungen 4 Edited by Louis Schreel Pathology &Aesthetics Andrea von Hülsen-Esch, Ricarda Bauschke-Hartung, Vittoria Borso, Reinhold Görling, Hans Körner, Achim Landwehr, Roger Lüdeke, Eva Schlotheuber, Timo Skrandies, Jürgen Wiener (Hg.) Essays on the Pathological in Kant and Contemporary Aesthetics 1 1 1 1 1 1 i 1 1 1 11 !1 .-„ ' 1# graduiertenkolleg セL@ materialität und produktion .• „. 1 iJFCi セWイM HEINRICH HEINE UNlVERSITÄT DÜSSELDORF dlulp Table of Contents Bibliografische Infonnation der Deutschen Nationalbibliothek Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek verzeichnet diese Publikation in der Deutschen Nationalbibliografie; detaillierte bibliografische Daten sind im Internet über http://dnb.dnb.de abrufbar. Louis Schreel Preface: Pathology and Aesthetics 7 Wolfram Bergande Kant' s Apathology of Compassion 11 Claudio Rozzoni Literature and Health: Proust as Symptomatologist 49 Sjoerd van Tuinen Painting versus Theatre: Hysteria of the Hand 69 Stefan Kristensen On the Figuration of Drives, or Duchamp as an Outsider © düsseldorf university press, Düsseldorf 2016 http://www.dupress.de Redaktion: Louis Schreel Lektorat: Marnie Slater & Liz Allen Titelbild: Ema ©Petra Poggenpohl Satz, Layout und Umschlaggestaltung: Hannah Reller Herstellung: docupoint GmbH, Barleben Der Fließtext ist gesetzt in Adobe Garamond Pro ISBN: 978-3-95758-032-0 99 Louis Schreel Animating Ideas: Pathology and the Aesthetic Idea in Kant and Deleuze .. .. . . 121 List of Contributors ...................................................................................... 167 Kant's Apathology of Compassion Wolfram Bergande Now reason's ability eo become mascer over all ehe inclinacions striving against ic chrough ehe mere idea of a law is absolucely inexplicable, hence it is also incomprehensible how ehe senses could have ehe ability co become master over a reason which commands wich such authority on ics side. For if all the world proceeded in accordance wich ehe precepc of ehe law, we would say chat everything occurred according co ehe order of nature, and nobody would think even of inquiring afcer ehe cause. -Immanuel Kant, Religion within the boundaries of mere reason' Christianity has assuredly taught men eo pay litrle attention co God's jouissance, and this is how Kant makes pass his volunrarism ofLaw-for-Law's-sake, which is something that cops, one might say, the ataraxia of the Scoic experience. -Lacan, Kant with Sade2 1. Tue Moral Pleasure of Respect In his critical works, e. g. in the Critique ofPractical Reason, Kant employs the weilknown and seemingly clear-cut distinction between sensuousness, Sinnlichkeit, on the one hand and undcrstanding, Verstand, respectively reason, Vernunft, on the other, hence between thc "physical" (Kant 1889, pp. 122, 133) laws governing human nature and the moral law, the categorical imperative, which ought to govern the individual's will and thence, at least in principle, his or her acts, too. 3 Kant's moral philosophy accordingly seems to divide into two aspects: into what on the one hand could be called a pathology, taking care of reason as it tends to get heteronomously, i. e. sensuously affected or even passionately so; and, on the other, into what could not unjusdy be called an 'apathology' which secures the grounds for an unaffected and dispassionate morality. This apathology comes close to a praxeology; even if Kant, unlike the Stoies or the Aristotelian-Thomistic tradition, does not Kant 1996, p. 102f. (Footnote t); cf. Kant 2007, 06: 059. Lacan 2006a, p. 651 f. (Translation modified.) Cf. Wood 2015, 132ff. 1 11 Wolfram Bergande Kant'.< Apathology o/Compassion depart from an absolute Other (an almighty God) but only postulates his existence pleasure, too. No, bccause the feeling of respect actually suggests itself as exemplary and his eventual afterworldly reward for a moral life. for the "moral pleasure [moralischen Lust]" (Kant 2007, 06: 378, 391; Kant 1889, For Kant, feelings, Gefühle, respectively sentiments, Empfindungen, almost invariably fall under physical laws, hence under the aspect of pathology. "[E]very feeling pp. 289, 301) of which Kant writes in 1797 in the Metaphysic ofEthics; and as 'moral pleasure' respect is far from being a pleasure in the ordinary sense of the term. generally" (Kant 1889, p. 167) is "pathological" (ibid.), writes Kant in the second This is because the dctermination of the will by the "practical law" (Kant 1889, Critique, literally so because feelings ultimately derive from the subject's pathe, from p. 112), which occasions the feeling of respect, makes a very special case for Kant. its physical nature, and critically because they tend to encroach upon the autonomy Even if one insisted on calling respect a 'pleasure', namely a 'moral pleasure', it ne- of moral reason. However, already in the second Critique there is one-although only vertheless would not involve any kind of 'pathological' pleasure, neither in the sense one single-exception to this rule: the "singular" "moral feeling" of "respect'', Ach- of presupposing it, nor of feeding on it, nor of aiming at it. As Kant claims in the tung (Kant 1889, p. 169). Being "produced simply by reason" (Kant 1889, p. 169), Critique of Practical Reason: ir is a case sui generis, even if compared with the somewhat similar aesthetic feelings Reason, with its practical law, determines rhe will immediately, not by means of an intervening feeling of pleasure or pain, not even of pleasure in the law itself [nicht vermittelst eines dazwischen kommenden Gefohls der Lust und Unlust, selb.rt nicht an diesem Gesetze], and it is only because it can, as pure reason, be practical, that it is possible for it eo be legislative (ibid.; Kant 2007, 05: 025). which Kant will introduce only later in the Critique ofjudgement. 4 Standing out as an exceptionally "practical" (Kant 1889, p. l 72f.) feeling, respect accompanies those Nor is respect itself, as seems to go without saying at this point in Kant's text, a and only those wills which are morally good because they would be grounded in pure pathological 'pleasure in the law itself' eithcr. All of this holds true for Kant even reason. Practically, this means that the will in question would be absolutely clcansed though the determination of the will, as he admits, implies a somewhat painful feeeven of the "slightest admixture" (Kant 1889, p. 112) of pathological (sentimental, as ling of "humiliation" of one's "self-conceit" (Kant 1889, p. 167) 6 , a feeling of pain it were) causaliry. As a matter of fact, later, in thc Critiquc of Judgement, Kant will which, although it is not a pleasure, would have to count as "pathological" (ibid.) explicate thar actually "any determination of the will" as such would carry a "state in equal measure, if only it was not indeed the negative reverse of the feeling of resof mind which accompanies" it; and that this state of mind "is in itsclf a feeling of pcct and thus, according to Kant, another major "effect of the consciousness of the plcasure and identical with it" (Kant 1914, p. 70). 5 So is respect,Achtung, then a moral law" (ibid.). 7 pleasure? Kanr's answer must appear somewhat paradoxical: yes and no. Yes, because So not only is it that the moral feeling of respect would not in any way involve given that respect is a determination of the will, it must be idenrical with a feeling of or imply 'pathological' feelings. What is more, it "cannot be compared to any patho4 Cf. Kant 1886, p. 115: Ir "is encirely of irs own kind". 5 Cf. Kant 1914, p. 53: "Bur ro will somerhing, and ro have a sadsfaction in irs exisrence, i. e. ro rake an imerest in ir, are idemical." 12 1 6 Cf.Kantl889,p.173. Cf. Kant 1889, p. 213. 13 1 Wolfram Bergande Kants Apathology of Compassion logical feeling" (ibid., p. 169) in the first place, !et alone itselfbe "reckoned either as feeling that applies merely to what is practical, and depends on the conception of a [ ... ] which cannot be called happiness, because it does not depend on the positive concurrence of a feeling, nor is it, strictly speaking, bliss, since it does not include complete independence on inclinations and wants, but ir resembles bliss in so far as the determination of one's will at least can hold itself free from their inAuence; and thus, at least in its origin, this enjoyment is analogous to the self-suf!iciency which we can ascribc only ro the Supreme Being (ibid„ p. 215). law, simply as to its form, not on account of any object [„.]" (ibid.). lt is "produced For the worldly human being who seeks to practically emulatc this self-sufficient by an imellecrual cause" only (Kam 1889, p. 166). And that is also why it "is the only Supreme Being, comentment spells out as the moral virtue of "apathy" (Kam 2006, one that we know quite a priori, and the necessity of which we can discern [einsehen p. 152) or "equanimiry" (Kam 2006, p. 131), rarely also as: "ataraxia, Ataraxia" kännen]" (ibid.). 8 So much does respect grow from purely reasonable grounds alone (Kam 2006, p. 154; Kam 2007, 07: 256). 1° Kam repeatedly recommends or even that even though for the sake of convenience one might call it a 'moral pleasure' it commands apathy (e. g.: the "dury of apathy" (Kam 1886, p. 226) in the Metaphy- nevertheless and strictly speaking "comains no pleasure" (Kam 1889, p. 173) at all sics of Ethics ( 1797)), usually with an explicit reference to anciem Sroicism, like in (nor pain, at least if we leave its negative reverse, humiliation, aside). the following passage from the Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point oJView (1798): pleasure or pain" (ibid., p. 173) in the ordinary, 'pathological' sense, for it "[„.] is a What the feeling of respect actually does consist of phenomenologically speaking is, according to Kam, a cerrain kind of"selfapprobation" which "contains something 'Ihe principle of aparhy-namely that the wise man must never be in a state of affect, not even in that of compassion with the misfortune of his best friend, is an entirely correct and sublime moral principle of the Stoic school; for affect makes us (more or less) blind (Kant 2006, p. 152). elevating' (ibid.), a kind of"inward peace" (Kam 1889, p. 181). 9 More prccisely, it If the twin feelings of humiliation-and-respect together make up the moral con- is a "comentment, which is primarily contentment with one's own person" (ibid., temmem of the human being, then we could say that something like countenance p. 215), however far from it's opposite double: complacency, Behaglichkeit. This con- (like 'comemmem' deriving from the Latin continere, 'to hold together, to enclose') tentmem or self-comemmem may cerrainly amoum to some kind of "enjoymem" is the respective practical disposition of an individual's "moral ascetics" (Kam 2005, (ibid.), as Kam admits. However, "comemmem (acquiesceritia)" in the full meaning p. 597; Kam 2007, 6: 484). In thc Metaphysics ofEthics, Kam refers this "cultivati- of the term is "unattainable" for human beings "during life" (Kam 2006, p. 130). on of virtue" (ibid.) to "the old watchword of the Stoa[. „], bear andforbear. bear, And, what is more, the comemmem that is evemually attainable for humans is only cndure the evils of lifc without complaim; forbear, abstain from its superfluous en- "a negative satisfaction with onc's state" (Kant 1889, p. 215). lt yields an only ne- joymems [überflüssigen Ergätzlichkeiten]" (Kant 1886, p. 304). The virtuous human gative enjoyment, one which has "nothing to do with enjoymem of life" (ibid., p. being ought to stay apathctic in the face of pathology, i. e. in the face of any senti- 183) in the ordinary sense and mems/fcelings, affccts and passions, whether pleasurable or painful. This is bccause they constantly threaten to infringe upon the purely moral determination of the will. 8 14 Transla(ion modified. IO Kant also writes of a "Vernunftliebe seiner selbst", foornote *'in Kam 2007, 06: 045. Colleg über Anthropologie aus den 70er und 80er Jahren" (Kant 2007, p. 15: 854). 1 Cf. "Ataraxia" in Kant 2007, 07: 256. On "ataraxia" as "Gleichmtithigkeit" (equanimiry) see: "Entwürfe zu dem 1 15 Wolfram Bergande Kants Apathology of Compassion Sure enough, rhis does nor mean w be "dull" or "indifferent" (Kant 2006, p. 131 ), 06: 456). 13 Here, these two feelings, Mitfreude (compassionate joy, so to speak) and as Kant hasrens ro add in ehe Anthropology. Mitleid (compassion), appear under the category of ''sympathia moralis" (Kant 2007, However, ir can lead w quire exrrcme consequences. Kant's nororious example, 06: 456), which is somewhat paradoxical given that Kant maintains that we are und- which appears in borh ehe Anthropology (Kant 2007, 07: 253; Kant 2006, p. 152) oubtedly dealing with sensuous feelings, ''sinnliche Gefühle", thus obviously not with and ehe Metaphysics ofEthics (Kant 2007, 06: 457; Kant 1886, p. 276), is ehe re- moral but instead with aesthetical, 'ä'sthetisch" (ibid.), i. e. with ultimately patholo- jection of compassion, Mitleid, as a form of parhological suffering. Kant's referee in gical feelings. This paradox notwithstanding, Kant infers from the 'predisposition the Metaphysics is again the Stoic "sage" who "rejected compassion [Mitleidenschaft]" of nature' to have such sympathetic feelings if not a direct 'obligation to act kindly even in "the case ofhis friend" because he could not "allow" himself-and as to Kant out of compassion' (which, as we just have learned, cannot be) then nevertheless an indeed he ought not to allow himself-"to be infected by his [friend's] sorrow" and "indirect duty [„.] to cultivate the [se] sympathetic affections" (Kant 1886, p. 276). thus to "augment the evils in the world" (ibid.) by suffering rogerher wich him. 11 For So surprisingly here we are called on by Kant not to repress the naturally pa- the Kant of the Metaphysics rhis is tantamount to saying that as a maner of princip- thological feeling of Mitleid, compassion. Instead we are to cultivate it. To allow for le "rhere can be no obligation to act kindly our of compassion [Mitleidj" (ibid.). 12 this cultivation, Kant is led to introduce a further distinction between a natural and a cultivated kind of sympathy; this distinction temporarily resolves the paradoxical 2. Compassion as Surrogate of Reason categorization just mentioned, it is true, but only at the cost of reapplying the prima- But this is not the whole story. For in the Anthropology, Kant continues the above ry distinction between morality and pathology, i. e. between Achtung (respect) and quoted passage about the 'principle of apathy' with an important reservation: Mitleid (compassion or sympathy, respectively), within the subsphere of pathology itself, i. e. within the subsphere of compassion (respectively sympathy). So within this Nevertheless the wisdom of nature has planred in us the predisposit'ion to compassion in order to handle the reins provisionally, unril reason has achieved the necessary strengrh; that is to say, for rhe purpose of enlivening us, nature has added the incentive of pathological (sensible) [pathologischen (sinnlichen}] impulse to the moral incentives for the good, as a temporary surrogate of reason [einstweiliges Surrogat der Vernunft] (Kant 2006, p. 152). subsphere we face again the second Critique's primary distinction between morality 0/ the Duty ofSympathy, Kant is 'participating' ( ''theilnehmend" (Kant 2007, 06: 456) and "seated in the will and continues the discussion of this "predisposition of nature", namely of the natural the ability to communicate to one another" and which "depends on practical reason" predisposition "to have a fellow-feeling with the joys and sorrows [Mitfreude und (Kant 1886, p. 276) 14, if however, as we will learn, not on practical reason alone- Mitleid (sympathia moralis)] of others [Anderer]" (Kant 1886, p. 275; Kant 2007, and a slavish, ''servilis" (Kant 2007, 06: 457), and pathologically admixed or soaked 11 Translarion modified. 13 Translation modified. 12 Translation modified. Cf Denis 2000. 14 Translation modified. And in the Metaphysics of Ethics, in a section titled 16 1 and pathology: namely between a "free" and morally cultivated compassion which 1 17 Wolfram Bergande Kants Apathology of Compassion compassion, a "Mitleidenschaft" (ibid.), which by contrast is "seated in that physical thetically in tune with the feelings of others, thus allowing oneself to be affected in susceptibility, which nature has implanted in us, for feeling in common the delights a merely passive way, is silly and childish" (Kant 2006, p. 132). or misery of our neighbour" (Kant 1886, p. 275f.). This latter Mitleidenschaftcom- Still this is not the end of what can be termed Kant's apathology of compassi- municates itselfby itself. By itself it is ''mittheilend" (Kant 2007, 06: 457). lt 'spreads on. If the Metaphysics calls on us to cultivate natural compassion, i. e. the sensuous in a natural way', ''sie sich ... natürlicher Weise verbreitet", comparable to 'warmth', sympathy with others: "humanitas aesthetica" (Kant 2007, 06: 456), and to trans- "W'firme'', or 'contagious diseases', "ansteckender Krankheiten" (ibid.). By contrast to form it into truly humane compassion: "humanitas practica" (ibid.) as it 'depends its counterpart, it is not a duty, not even an indirect one, but must remain repressed on practical reason', then this is not so much because, as Kant considers, "we might and avoided by all means. be unable to repress" (Kant 1886, p. 277) it anyway; nor is it only because com- So if there is, as we have learned in the Anthropology, 'the incentive of pathologi- passion can function as a temporary surrogate impulse for the possibly deficitary cal (sensible) impulse to the moral incentives for the good, as a temporary surrogate 'strength' of practical reason; rather, and this is astonishing, compassion can help us of reason', then we can conclude from the Metaphysics ofEthics that this surrogate "to do what the representation of duty on its own might be unable to accomplish impulse is not straightforwardly pathological but the result of cultivation. And the [dasjenige zu tun, was die Pflichtvorstellung.für sich allein nicht ausrichten würde]" Metaphysics seems to agree with the Anthropology as (ibid.) 15 , as Kant surprisingly concedes towards the end of the Metaphysics' section to why at all we should cultiva- te 'compassionate natural (aesthetical) affections', ''mitleidige natürliche (ästhetische) on the Duty ofSympathy: Neither ought we to desert the chambers of the sick nor the cells of the debtor, in order to escape the painful sympathy we might be unable to repress, this emotion being a spring implanted in us by nature, prompting us to do what the representation of dury on its own might be unable to accomplish (Kant 1886, p. 276f.). 16 Gefühle" (Kant 2007, 06: 457). We should do so because we can "[. „] make them serve as instruments enabling us to discharge the offices of a humane mind, upon ethical principles [sie als so viele Mittel zur lheilnehmung au/moralischen Grundsätzen und dem ihnen gemäßen Gefühl zu benutzen]" (Kant 1886, p. 276). Particularly, we may use them in cases where practical reason is in need of support; for instance, as we read in the Anthropology, 'provisionally, until reason has achieved the necessary strength'. However, only insofar as they effectively serve such purposes should we cultivate them, that is, only insofar as they are directed to an active end. Otherwise There are-as Kant lets his readers know in what is a rather passing albeit concluding remark-actions commanded as duties by practical reason, and, as can be presumed, strengthfully so. Nevertheless, 'the representation of duty alone' does not suffice to determine the will effectively-presumably regardless of the support of the concomitant feeling of Achtung, respect. So obviously it is not only, as the An- thropology suggests, some temporary and hence sooner or later remediable deficit of they are useless, as Kant warns in the Anthropology: " [... ] the ineffectual sharing of one's feelings [die thatleere lheilnehmung seines Gefühls] in order to appear sympa- 18 1 15 Translation modified. 16 Translation ュッ、ゥヲセN@ 1 19 Wolfram Bergande Kants Apathology of Compassion 'rhe strength of reason' which compassion, the 'pathological surrogate of reason', is Be this as it may, the remarkable resu!t is that Kant seems to allow for cases where supposed to supplement in a however culrivated form. Rather, the Metaphysics seems rhe 'representation of dury on its own' [die Pflichtvorstellung.für sich allein], obviously to point here to a fundamental problem one might have with doing one's dury as it because it is on its own, is not enough to determine the will; not just factually, e. g. is commanded by the practical law alone. Can we not suspect that in extreme cases because it would be overpowered by other pathological motives, "Triebfedern" (Kant this problem might indeed become irremediable without the 'positive concurrence' 2007, 06: 036), or because it would lack the experience which enlivens or enhances of a cultivated 'pathological feeling'? And would not rhis consequendy pur the self- its strength (and even granted that the effective outcome is always indeterminable contentment of rhe virruous agent in danger, together with the ideal of supreme because empirical), but principally-namely, as one may suspect, because without self-sufficiency that orientates it? intuition the Pflichtvorstellungwould be just as void, "leer" (Kant 2007, 03: 075) as One must be very precise here. Kant writes that "[ ... ] although it is no direct it would then become "blind" or rather blinded under the rule of an uncultivared duty to rake apart in the joy or grief of others", it neverrheless "is a dury not to avo- "affect" (Kant 2006, p. 152). Is rhis an overinterpretation? Certainly, Kant would id" the occasions and places where such feelings are usually triggered: "rhe chambers have rejected any such interpretation, just like his Metaphysics explicitly opposes any of the sick" or the "cells of the debror" (Kant 1886, p. 276). Even so, the feeling of such view. For if, according to Kant, "the power of mastering every opposing excite- the 'joy or grief of others' must remain problematic for Kant, like any of the other ment of the sensory can, and indeed must, be absolurely postulated [das Vermögen "inner and ourer enjoyments" of everyday life: "only inasmuch as they are innocent (facu!tas) der Überwindung aller sinnlich entgegenwirkenden Antriebe seiner Freiheit in themselves, i. e., not contrary to moraliry, and present themselves spontaneously, halber schlechthin vorausgesetzt werden kann und muß'J" (Kant 1886, p. 2 l 4f.; Kant may we adopt rhem, but never go in pursuit of them" (Kant 2001 b, p. 397), as we 2007, 06: 397), then in principle reason must be rhe absolute master. Yet the ques- learn from rhe notes taken by Johann Friedrich Vigilantius from Kant's lectures on tion remains wherher Kant's systematic treatment of compassion does not point to ethics in 1793-94. Otherwise, Kant warns, they indeed might be "injurious to our a fundamental problem wirh reason's principally absolute mastery, particularly in self-contentment" (ibid.). As a consequence, it seems as if cases where cultivared regard to Kant's famous coordination of freedom and constraint ('you can becausc compassion is asked for must neither actively be sought nor actively be avoided. If you must'). The first epigraph to this text, taken from Kant's Religion within the compassion arises, it must arise spontaneously, unintentionally. This probably also Boundaries ofMere Reason, is one of a small number of scattercd marginalia in Kant's implies rhat such cases must not be passively sought nor be passively avoided eit- corpus which appear to reflect such a problematic. her, i. e.: negligently or secretly. A perfectly balanced state of neirher activity nur passiviry is obviously what is at stake when it comes to the morally obligatory selfcontentment of Kant's virtuoso of virtue. 20 1 1 21 Wolfram Bergande Kants Apathology of Compassion And yet recent secondary literature on Kant often appcars to ignore this prob- accomplishment of the moral dury of charity [nicht hinreichend zur Erfüllung der lematic. To give an example: lt certainly is not altogether wrong to interpret Kant's moralischen Pflicht zur Wohltätigkeit]" (Mieth 2015, p. 413). 18 Natural compassion is text-as has been clone-in the conventional sense that "only ehe moral feeling of a condition of cultivated compassion, so much is true. Just like "[ ... ) the sensible fee- Achtung, which is exclusively triggered by the practical law and which has an inner ling which is at the bottom of all our inclinations is the condition of chat impression causal relation to the practical law, can guarantee that it only motivates to moral which we call respect, Achtung' (Kant 1889, p. 168; Kant 2007, 05: 075) according actions" (Goy 2007, p. 352). lt is not wrong, bur it understates the case, because, as to has just been evidenced in Kant's text, there seem to be at least imaginable cases in that "painful sympathy [schmerzhaften mゥエァ・ヲィセ@ which a 'temporary surrogate impulse' not only "may later facilitate our doing our Antriebe] implanted in us by nature" (Kant 1886, p. 277): lt is one of ehe springs to dury" (Carcwright 1984, p. 87 Fn. 11) or cases in which it "can be of instrumental do good, einer der Antriebe, not the only one. Hence compassion (Mitleid respec- importance" (Denis 2000, p. 65), as other interpreters of Kant have it; but also cases tively Mitgefühb, whether in natural or cultivated form, cannot be a necessary, i. e. a in which such a surrogate impulse might be indispensable for doing our duties in general condition of charity; nor can any other feeling be such a necessary condition, ehe first place. A 'temporary surrogate impulse' then may be principally indispen- except Achtung. In the second Critique, Kant leaves no doubt about it: "There is here sable for a 'representation of duty' which, 'on its own' as it in some cases obviously in the subject no amecedem feeling tending ro morality. For this is impossible, since is, without such an im pulse, without an as it were Fichtean '/tnstoß" (Fichte 2013, every feeling is sensuous, and the motive of moral intention must be free from all p. 37) avant la lettre, cannot perform its moral duty. 17 (And then again, if chere in- sensuous conditions [die Triebfeder der sittlichen Gesinnung aber muß von aller sinn- dccd are such exceptional cases in which moral reason principally cannot dispense of liehen Bedingung.frei sein]" (Kant 1889, p. 168). 19 Otherwise there could actually as to how Achtung should be no cases at all in which, as Kant claims, moral "[r]eason, wich its practical law, be able to 'guarantee that it only motivates to moral actions' in all the other cases.) determines the will immediately, not by means of an intervening feeling of pleasure Now on ehe other hand it is not only to overstate the case but just wrong to argue or pain, not even of pleasure in the law itself, [... )" (ibid., p. 112). And according (as has been clone by one interpreter in the recenrly published Kant-Lexikon) chat to Kant "practical pure reason" does determine ehe will, not only immediately but "the natural feelings of compassion [die natürlichen Gefühle des Mitleids]" would be also effectively. lt is not only ehe "objective determining principlc of ehe objects of "necessary conditions of the accomplishment of charity [notwendigen Bedingungen action as called good and evil" but also the "subjective determining principle, that zur Erfüllung der Wohltätigkeit]", even granted that they are "not sufficient for the is, a motive [Triebfeder] to this action [ ... )" (ibid., p. 168; Kant 2007, 05: 075). 18 My uanslation. 17 19 Translation rnodified. this Surrogate im pulse, then of course the question arises 22 Cf Honneth 2001. 1 the Critique of Practical Reason. But in the Metaphysics Kant is quite clear about [ ... ) being a spring [einer der ... 1 23 Wolftam Bergande Kants Apathology ofCompassion As a result, compassion, i. e. the pathological affection, if not infectedness, by on its own' and eo not only will but eo also act according co ehe categorical impera- somebody else's feelings, appears as quite paradoxical, as quite Rousseauistic so co tive. Thence for Kant it becomes an 'indirect ducy' not co foreclose on ehe real life speak, at lease in chese cwo ultimate publications of Kant, ehe Metaphysics and ehe occasions in which compassion can possibly affect or rather infect ehe moral agent, Anthropology. Both inessential and necessary, it appears co be an undecidable in driving him towards its cultivation. ehe technical sense of deconscructive cerminology. On ehe one hand compassion is From this it follows chac, paradoxically, compassion is boch on either side and ruled out as pathological by ehe auchoricy of reason; either because it is an evil which beyond ehe Scoic dichotomy 'bear and forbear' co which Kant refers. lt is not really must not be engaged wich nor unnecessarily mulciplied, like in ehe case of a friend's concained by chac dichocomy, neither logically nor 'practically'; andin case compassi- suffering, which can only be 'endured wichout complaint' if need be; or because it on should be contained, it gets excluded from 'practical' reason, at least theoretically. would have co be classified as 'superfluous enjoyment' from which one must 'abs- Conversely, insofar as compassion should be beyond chis dichotomy, it gets never- tain', like-che example is Kanc's-che "offensive variety of chis compassion called cheless included inco 'practical' reason, needed as it is eo incite eo dfective action in mercy, by which is meant thac kind of benevolence shown eo ehe unworchy" which exceptional cases. So, paradoxically, it is boch excluded and included within 'practi- only serves co "boast" one's own "worchiness co be happy" (Kant 1886, p. 276). 20 cal', i. e. moral reason. Ics logic can chus be reconstructed as follows: Kant's concept As a merely 'added' extra, compassion seems eo add noching really necessary co ehe of moral subjectivicy firscly excludes compassion, namely either as a pathological good will, which is self-sufficient from ehe moral point of view. In any case, as Kant object of ehe will or 'as commanded'; yec it is precisely in chis excluded compassion emphasizes, one just cannot be obliged co be compassionace, just like "love", being where ehe subject, secondly, rediscovers a therewich excluded part of icself; hence it a natural "affection", simply, i. e. nacurally, "cannot be commanded" (Kant 1889, chirdly and laboriously undercakes eo recover chis part by saving compassion in ehe p. 15)-even chough as far as "love" is concerned, it may accually appear as anal- form of cultivated (albeit 'painful') sympathy (which is not a ducy but which not eo most "indispensable complement" eo ehe moral Pflichtvorstellung's "command of avoid is an 'indirect ducy'). Here one can see how Kant's concept of moral subjecti- ducy", given chac "ehe laccer as an incentive, withouc ehe contribucion of ehe former vicy becomes quite twisced as it seeks co save not ehe appearances but, so eo speak, [i. e.: oflove], is not very much eo be counted on'', as Kant concedes in The end of ehe noumena. "The subject is, as it were, internally excluded from its object [en ex- all things (Kant 2007, 08: 338; Kant 200lc, p. 230). On ehe ocher hand and 'practi- clusion interne ason objet]" (Lacan 2006b, p. 731 ), as can be stated here wich Lacan. cally' speaking, chis added surrogate seems co be essential, at least in chose particular Compassion marks ehe inner oucland of ehe subject, subjected as it is eo an allegedly cases in which compassion incices reason co leave its abscracc 'representation of dury purely rational moral law. And it is chrough cultivaced compassion chac ehe subjecc's apathy, its disposition eo will and act morally, i. e. humbly and respectfully at ehe 20 24 Translarion modified. 1 1 25 Wolfram Bergande Kants Apathology of Compassion same time, entertains an encrypted, i. e. encapsulated and hardly decipherable, com- double of the feeling of respect, Achtung, namely upon the repression of the ominous munication with the pathological feelings of the social other-and eventually with 'pleasure in the law itself'. This is because it is precisely with cultivated compassi- his or her own pathological feelings, as it would be in the case of compassion with on that Kant gets disquietingly close to such a commanded pleasure. Certainly, for oneself, i. e. of self-pity, a concept which, not surprisingly, is alien to Kant's corpus. Kant there simply is not anything like a commanded pleasure-the feeling of Ach- So if for some moment Kant may have appeared to dismiss any form of patholo- tung norwithstanding, as it is supposed to be not a 'pleasure in the law itself' but a gical feeling as supplementary to intellectual reason alone (by the way quite similar pleasure on the mere occasion of that law; and the same would apply to the "moral to Plato's Socrates who e. g. in the Republic 21 dismisses even the artistically staged pleasure (moralischen Lust)" or "moral enjoyment (moralischen Genuss)" which, as to feelings of tragedy and comedy), then it must now be clear that some rhetorical Kant's Metaphysics, may be the "reward" (Kant 1886, p. 207; Kant 2007, 06: 391) dismissals norwithstanding Kant straightforwardly accepts a more or less cultivated of virtuously charitable actions. compassion as a natural supplement to moral reason. Making solitary reason leave Yet at closer inspection Kant's scattered remarks on the ominous topic of a 'ple- its purely intellectual, i. e. unpractical (if not immoral) abstractions, truly humane asure in the law itself' and on a possibly 'commanded' feeling appear quite cont- and thus virtuously charitable compassion is attending, Gセィ・ゥャョュ、B@ (Kant 2007, radictory: On the one band it must remain true for Kant that 'any determination 06: 456), but not properly communicative, "mittheilend" (ibid.: 457). Thus it comes of the will' is a 'feeling of pleasure'.22 And the prime case for such a determination close to-but is not identical with-the communicable, mitteilbar aesthetic feeling of the will, namely the will's determination by the moral law and the concomitant of the Critique ofjudgement. feeling of Achtung, is something which even forces itself upon us, "sich für sich selbst uns aufdringt" 23 (Kant 2007, 05: 031). 24 So remarkably, Achtung results as a 'mo- 3. Morality and its Discontents ral pleasure' which the moral law forces upon us. However it is supposed to be no All things considered, compassion, Mitleiden{schaft), remains a problematical feeling 'pleasure in the law itself'. On the other band, Kant asserts in a footnote to his dis- in Kant's late theory of moral virtue, whether principally or only factually, already cussion of the sources of the aesthetic feeling in the Critique of]udgement that "[a]n because it will not always be possible to critically distinguish berween natural and obligation to enjoyment is a manifest absurdity [Eine Verbindlichkeit zum Genießen ist cultivated compassion; nor berween cultivated compassion and 'boasting mercy'; eine offenbare Ungereimtheit]." And he continues: "Thus the obligation to all actions moreover, and more imporrantly, because in order to properly function as a sup- 22 Cf Kam 2007, 06: 211; 05: 178. 23 Kant's wording here is inceresting: In the scrictest sense ehe moral law not just forces icself upon us, bur it "forces plement to reason, cultivated compassion is contingent upon the repression of the itself for itself [sich for sich selbst] upon us", as if this force would act on behalf of itself, like another subject, and not on behalf of e. g. a desired outcome, namely the subjectivation of the thus moralized individual. 21 26 24 Cf. e. g. Rep. 413a; 429c-d; 606a ff. 1 l Cf. Kant 2007, 06: 036. 1 27 Wolfram Bergande Kants Apathology of Compassion which have merely enjoyment for their aim can only be a pretended one; however identifies perversion as one of the major clinical structures besides neurosis/hysteria spiritually it may be conceived (or decked out), even if it is a mystical, or so-called and psychosis. In Lacanian psychoanalytical theory, these structures represent the pos- heavenly, enjoyment." (Kant 1914, p. 52 Fn. 2; Kant 2007, 05: 209, Fn. *)So whe- sible avatars (Schicksale) of the drives (Triebe) deriving from the castration complex. reas the moral law obliges the subject to the painful humiliation of its seif resulting As such they represent different ways to cope with a primally repressed "pernicious in the 'moral pleasure' of Achtung, it nevertheless does not oblige, it cannot oblige enjoyment" (Lacan 1991, p. 52) which is the necessary libidinal remainder resulting according to Kant, to enjoy pathologically, because that would be, according to this from the institution of the super-ego (Über-Ich) as inner agent and executor of the marginal assertion, manifestly absurd from a logical point of view. There is a similar moral law within the individual, i. e. from the individual's subjectivation. Thereby, argument in a passage from the Vigilantius-notes. There one can read that 'to enjoy as Freud explains in Civilization and its Discontents (Das Unbehagen in der Kultur), having duties' would be 'contrary to the nature of duty' ('nature' here metaphorically morality is based on a self-sustaining and indeed self-aggravating libido-economic in the sense of essence and not of physical quality). And one can paraphrase Kant logic: Tue super-ego parasitically feeds on the pathological satisfaction which it its- in that passage by saying that to enjoy duties would be symptomatic of 'impulses' elf prohibits. Tue super-ego derives its strength from the libidinal energy of what it standing under the inacceptable 'authority' of 'painful or despotic commands': prohibits. And so what Kant admitted as pathological 'surrogate' of moral reason, namely compassion (if only it is 'not commanded' but 'cultivated'), reveals itself as [... ] it is also certain that every obligation is forthwith associared wich a moral constraint, and thar ir is contrary to the nature of duty to enjoy having duties incumbent upon one; it is necessary, rather, that man's impulses should make him disinclined to fulfill rhe moral laws, and that these impulses should be overcome only rhrough ehe authority of ehe latter, without it being possible to say rhat these laws demand respect in ehe manner of painful or despotic commands" (Kant 200lb, p. 259). 25 apriori compassion-ofoneself (rather than with-oneself), imposed as it always alrea- Now to enjoy one's submission to a prohibitory law and to take this culpable enjoy- dy is by the social other. So from a Freudian perspective, Kant's 'strength of reason' ment as a libidinally "regressive surrogate [regressiver eイウ。セ}B@ (Freud 1973, p. 240) is in pathological deficit right from the start. Tue more pathological satisfaction the for the enjoyment of the object prohibited by that law is exemplary for the "essence super-ego prohibits, however, the stronger it gets, and the stronger it gets, the more of masochism" (ibid., p. 241) as perversion according to Sigmund Freud's seminal it prohibits, and so on. Now to conceive ofhow this spiral logic is set into motion, text A Child is Being Beaten. So obviously what Kant excludes as a double of Achtung, one must logically presuppose, firstly, a primordial moment in which the moral law throughout all these contradictory statements on the topic of a forced enjoyment, would have been originally imposed, that is forced upon the subject, and, second- and without really getting at it, is something similar to what moral masochism is for ly, a concomitant primordially prohibited enjoyment. This is the enjoyment of a Freud: pleasure in the law itself. As far as Freudian psychoanalysis is concerned, it pathological object whose only function it would be a quite unbehaglich, discontentful constituent of morality, namely in the form of an to serve the institution of this prohibitory law. Tue concomitant state of mind would be identical with the derer25 28 Cf. Baxley 2015. p. 237. 1 mination of the will by that law. 29 1 Kants Apathology of Compassion Wo/ftam Bergande In conrradistinction to simple pleasure, Lacan at one point starts to reserve the in the law itself' (Kant 2007, 07: 265). 28 Besides, with respect to the provocations term 'Jouissance" (Lacan 1967, 30.05.67, p. 274f.) for this enjoyment insofar as it in de Sade's writings one might want to follow Lacan's text on Kant with Sade and is logically, ethically and aesthetically 'extimate' (included/excluded) to a subjecti- argue that Kant's theory of evil can actually come to terms with de Sade, given that vity thence twisted by this extimacy. 26 And Lacan ranges rhe literary work of Kanr's de Sade's work would stay within an (anti-)virtue-ethical framework. As to Lacan, contemporary Marquis de Sade among rhe ancient ethical traditions in philosophy, "[h]is [de Sade's] apology for crime merely impels him to an oblique acceptance of e. g. Stoicism or Peripateticism, insofar as it would provide a noteworthy access to rhe Law. Tue Supreme Being is restored in Evil Action [le Malifice]" (Lacan 2006a, rhe experience of this enjoyment. (Lacan 2006a, p. 645) According to Freudian and p. 667). As far as Kant's Religion is concerned, it is the subject's "free power of choice Lacanian psychoanalysis some of antiquiry's ethical schools, just like various Christian [freien Willkür]" from which "depravity [Bösartigkeit]", which can also be called virtue doctrines, ultimately projected this enjoymenr onto a Supreme Being, onto "perversity [Verkehrtheit] (perversitas)" (Kant 1996b, p. 83; Kant 2007, 06: 037), a fatherlike, almighty God, onro an Other who is the, as it were, Subject Supposed ultimately derives-depraviry respectively perversiry tobe understood not as the to Enjoy. As to Lacan, de Sade's La philosophie dans le boudoir supplements Kant's simple propensiry to yield to one's natural inclinations but as rhe formal "propensity Critique ofpractical reason with its "truth" (ibid., p. 646)-and we should add: a of the power of choice [Willkür] to maxims that subordinate the incentives of rhe truth about rhe enjoyment of this supreme Other which for Lacan turns out to be moral law to others (not moral ones)" (Kant 1996b, p. 78; Kant 2007, 06: 030). the unconscious as the discourse to which the subject is subjected. In a similar vein, As a somewhat paradoxical "innate guilt [angeborene Schuld]" perversity "must no- Julia Kristeva speaks of a "logic of the intimare" which would work the Kantian netheless have originated from freedom [aus der Freiheit entsprungen]" (Kant l 996b, 'practical' rcason from wirhin and which rhe literary work of de Sade would "srage p. 84; Kant 2007, 06: 038). For Kant there is "no conceivable ground for us, there- [... ) by illustrating how the intimate of the passionate and.sensitive soul, because it fore, from which moral evil could first have come in us [kein begreiflicher Grund da, finds itself under the empire of judging Reason and his de-sensitizing and unifying woher das moralische Böse in uns zuerst gekommen sein könne]" (Kant l 996b, p. 88; power, is an intimate which is condemned to enjoy this force" 27 (Kristeva 1997, p. 76). Kant 2007, 06: 043). lt is wirh his theorem about the radical "propensity [Hang]" to do evil in Religion And even though "the concept of freedom [... ] first and foremost derives from within the Boundaries ofMere Reason thar Kant had earlier approached rhis 'pleasure this law", i. e. from the moral law as freedom's ratio cognoscendi, i. e. even though "the concept of the freedom of the power of choice [der Begriffder Freiheit der Will- kür] does not precede in us the consciousness of the moral law but is only inferred 26 , In the contexr of his concept of rhe 1hing (la Chose) Lacan speaks of an imimare exrerioricy ( ''exthioriti intime') and of extimiry ( ''extimite') (Lacan 1986, p. 167). 27 30 My rranslaüon. 1 28 Cf. Zac 1972, p. 153. 1 31 Wolfram Bergande Kants Apathology of Compassion from the determinability of our power of choice rhrough this law as unconditional reproach of the offender for not having been clever enough (since he gor caught). This command" (Kant l 996b, p. 93 Fn. *; Kant 2007, 06: 049), this for Kant cannot is obviously not a moral disposition betraying a secret perverse enjoyment. And so mean that "rhe freedom of the power of choice", "Freiheit der Willkür", and thus for Kant this just fits all roo weil with a "slavish frame of mind [sklavische Gemüths- evil would also be ontologically grounded in the consciousness of the moral law (as stimmung]" of those who, rather unambiguously, arc just "weighcd-down by fear i ts ratio essendi). and dejected" and likewise "never [... ] without a hidden hatred of the law [nie ohne Consequently, and given that for Kant there just cannot be a 'pleasure in the law einen verborgenenen Haß des Gesetzes]" (ibid.) ro which they feel themselves subjected. itself', there can be no pleasure in the opposition to the law itself either. Hence there To this analysis of Kant one would have to object roday with Lacan that at least in can be no "evil reason [boshafte Vernunft]" in which "resistance ro the law would itself the case of masochism "the masochist is not" a mere "slave [esclave]" of the law (La- be thereby elevated to incentive [Triebfeder] (for without any incentive the power can 1967, 30.05.67, p. 276f.). 30 Nor is it that the 'slavish frame of mind' would boil of choice cannot be determined)". This is because in being "so the subject would be down ro the simple question ofbeing clever enough or not. Rather, such a mindset made a diabolical being" which according ro Kant "is however not applicable reveals the subject-the subject of the unconscious-as being more than just de- to the human being" (Kant 1996b, p. 82; Kant 2007, 06: 035). ver. Tue masochistic subject of the unconscious is all-roo-clever, a clever-clever "old fox [un petit malin]" (ibid.) according to Lacan, since it is precisely in the act of 4. Tue Aesthetics of Rationalization: Disgust, Boredom and Humour submitting ro the law and its punishment that he or she finds enjoyment. As Lacan As Kant thus ignores or rather pushes aside the possibility of perverse enjoyment states: "the masochist knows that he is within enjoyment [le masochiste sait qu'il est within morality, he accordingly misjudges "[ ... ] rhe aesthetic constitution [ästhetische dans la jouissance]" (ibid.). Beschaffenheit], the temperament so ro speak of virtue", roo, conceiving of it as a "joy- Be this as it may, Kant's Critique ofpractical reason sides with the derided "Sroic" ous frame of mind rjröhliche Gemüthsstimmung]", a "heart joyous in the compliance who refuses to recognize anything evil in some "paroxysms of gout" which to him with its duty (not just complacency [Behaglichkeit] in the recognition of it)" (Kant must appear as a merely physical pain: 1996b, p. 73 Fn. t; Kant 2007, 06: 023 Fn. t) 29 • Kant detects, it is true, something A bad thing [Übel] it certainly was, and his cry betrayed that; but that any evil [ein Böses] attached to him thereby, this he had no reason whatever to admit, for pain did not in the least diminish the worth of his person, but only that of his condition. If he had been conscious of a single lie it would have lowered his pride, but pain served only to elevate him [ihn zu erheben], when he was conscious that he had not deserved it by any unrighteous action by which he had rendered himself worthy of punishment. (Kant 1889, p. 15lf.; Kant 2007, 05: 060) 31 "very ambiguous", i. e. some moral ambiguity within "the self-torment of a remorseful sinner". Bur this turns out ro be unproblematic because it "usually [is] only an inward reproach for having offended against prudence" (ibid.). lt is the usual seif- 29 32 CE Zac 1972. p. 147. 1 30 My translarion . .ll Translation modified. 1 33 Wolfram Bergande Kants Apathology of Compassion In contrast to the Stoies who moralized the whole of physical reality, Kant is surely Against this background it must have been unthinkable for Kant that the pain- more than critical of the tendency of "human reason [... ] to link the course of na- trodden's sage elevation, Erhebung, might secretly contain a malign (i. e. all-too-cle- ture with the laws of morality [den Laufder Natur an die Gesetze der Moralität an- verly evil) pleasure as an added extra, as a pernicious surplus enjoyment, for instance zuknüpfen]" (Kant 1996b 114 Fn. *;Kant 2007, 06: 073 Fn. *). 32 Correspondingly, a kind of elevated self-pity. But then how would Kant have judged the legendary he makes a sharp distinction between the spheres of morality and of physical reality, apathetic self-contentment of the Stoic "[ ... ] Epictetus who, when his master was i. e. pathology. Still for Kant these two extremes, the Stoic's cosmotheistic and his twisting his leg, said, smiling and unmoved, 'You will break my leg', and when it own quasi-monotheistic view, converge in the idea of an ideal elevation, Erhebung, a was broken, he added, 'Did I not teil you that you would break it?'" (Origen 2001, genuinely "moral apathy, moralische Apathie" which would be cleansed of all patholo- chap. LIII). Is not Epictetus' jovial countenance in face of a pain unjustly suffered gical activity ('lies', punishable 'unrighteous actions', etc.) as much as of all patholo- an extreme form of what Kant had in mind when he praised "contentment (ac- gical passivity ("bluntness, Fühllosigkeit", "listlessness, subjective Gleichgültigkeit" and quiescentia)" as an "enjoyment analogous to the self-sufficiency which we can ascri- "indifference, Indifferenz" (Kant 1886, p. 226; Kant 2007, 06: 408)). 33Aesthetically, be only to the Supreme Being" in the Critique ofPractical Reason? 35 Actually, it is Kant's 'moral apathy' should thus be free of the boredom (Langeweile) which cha- not. For Kant sees a limit to moral elevation beyond which man's "moral capacity" racterizes, according to Hegel's Phenomenology ofSpirit, the "general terms beyond becomes "fancifully" exaggerated and thus "nonsense" (Kant 200la, p. 32). And it which Stoicism cannot get", for instance "[t]heTrue and the Good, wisdom and is precisely some famous Stoies which Kant-as quoted by Herder-has in mind virtue". For Hegel, these Stoic terms are "lacking the fullness of life"; they are "no here: "Seneca was an impostor, Epictetus strange and fanciful." (Ibid.) 36 However, doubt elevating [erhebend], but since they cannot in fact produce any expansion of can Kant's moral apathy, the subject's countenance, based as it is on reason's practi- the content, they soon become boring rJangen sie bald arf: Langeweile zu machen]" ca! law only and on a solitary Pflichtvorstellung ('representation of duty on its own'), (Hegel 1977, p. 122).34 be said to be free of all fancies? 32 On Kant and Scoicism cf. Schneewind 1996, 292ff„ parcicularly p. 294. Cf. also Sancozki 2006, p. 508, who acgues 35 See above (Kant 1889, p. 215). chat despite many parallels Kant's critical philosophy was developed without subscanrial recourse to ancient Stoicism: 36 Schneewind 1996, p. 292 quoces ehe whole passage from which chis phrase is taken: "Man fancifully exaggerates "Wenn man ihn [Kant] überhaupt in eine antike Richtung einordnen kann, dann ist die Stoa zu nennen. Er selbst hätte sich his moral capaciry and sets before himself the most perfect goodness; ehe outcome is nonsense; but what is required of als kritischer Philosoph al/.erdings sicher gegen derartige Zuschreibungen gewehrt. [..}Negativ konnte der Gang durch die drei us? Tue Scoic's answer: 1 shall raise myself above myself, „. rise superior eo my own affiiccions and needs, and wich all Kritiken jeweils begründet zeigen, dass eine genuine Auseinandersetzung mit der Antike for die Genese der grund/.egenden my might be good, be the image of godhood. But how so, for godhood has no obligations, yet you cercainly do„. Now Prämissen der jeweiligen Theorien keine Rol/.e spielt." ehe god departs and we are lefr wich man, a poor creature, loaded with obügacions. Seneca was an impostor, Epictetus 33 Translation modified. Cf. Assmann 2003, passim, for ehe distinction berween monocheism and cosmotheism. strange and fanciful" (Cf. Kant 2001a, p. 32). Schneewind cesumes Kant's relacionship to Stoicism as follows: "Kant's 34 Tcanslacion modified. reservations about Stoicism were as pervasive as his appreciation of it" (ibid.). 34 1 1 35 Kants Apathology of Compassion Wolfram Bergande !nterestingly, for Freud's Psychopathology ofEveryday Lift section on Erroneously Here self-communication adopts the cwisted form of an acting out of an uncon- carried out actions, it is precisely the "srriking countenance [Fassung] which the pati- scious phantasy of self-punishment. Ir is rooted in what can be called a sympcomatic ents show" in the face of"apparently accidental injuries" which "in the more serious 'compassion-of-oneself'. "[!] n our present state of civilization", writes Freud in 1904, cases of psychoneuroses" may "berray the portion of unconscious intention" causally "[t]he self-inflicted injury which does not entirely tend coward self-annihilation has involved therein. An analysis of ehe respective unconscious intention regularly reveals [... ] no other choice [ ... ) than to hide itselfbehind the accidental [... ]. Formerly, it thac chese "precended accidents" in rruch "are really self-inflicced" and "sympcoms was a cuscomary sign of mourning, at other times it expressed itself in ideas of piety of ehe disease". Behind the seeming "calmness, Ruhe" we must: according eo Freud, [Frömmigkeit] and renunciation of the world [Weltentsagung]." (Ibid., p. 199 Fn. 1) suppose an unconscious and "constantly lurking tendency co self-punishment [ ... ] lt is known, of course, how Kant repeatedly denounces Schwärmerei and other which skilfully, makes use of an external situation" (Freud 1922, p. l 98f.). 37 This ambiguous forms of moral pathology like e. g. bigotry. And it has been evidenced self-punishment resulcs in a pernicious enjoyment through which ehe subject (of the above how much Kanc's moral subject is supposed co differ from that through its unconscious) communicates wich itself. Freud's exemplary case in the Psychopathology 'joyous frame of mind' etc. Yet in Kant's later philosophy traces of a symptomatic is a young married woman who enjoyment at ehe roots of moral subjectivity can be detected, coo. A comparison wich [... ] broke her leg below the knee in a carriage accidenr so that she was bedridden for weeks. Tue striking part of it was ehe lack of any manifestation of pain and ehe calmness [Ruhe] wich which she bore her misforcune. 1his calamity ushered in a long and serious neurotic illness, from which she was finally cured by psychotherapy. During ehe treatment 1 discovered ehe circumstances surrounding ehe accident, as well as certain impressions which preceded it. Tue young woman with her jealous husband spent some time on ehe farm of her married sister, in company wich her numerous orher brothers and sisters wich their wives and husbands. One evening she gave an exhibition of one of her talenrs before this intimate circle; she danced artistically ehe 'cancan', eo ehe great delight of her relatives, but to ehe great annoyance of her husband, who afterward whispered to her, 'Again you have behaved like a prostitute'. Tue words took effect; we will leave it undecided whecher it was just on account of ehe dance. That night she was restless [unruhig] in her sleep, and ehe ncxt forcnoon she decided to go out driving. She chose ehe horses herself, refusing one team and demanding another. Her youngest sister wished to have her baby wich its nurse accompany her, but she opposed this vehemently. During ehe drive she was nervous; she reminded ehe coachman that ehe horses were getting skittish, and as ehe fidgety [unruhigen] animals really produced a momentary difficulty she jumped from ehe carriage in fright and broke her leg, while those remaining, in the carriage were uninjured. Although afrer ehe disclosure of these details we can hardly doubt that this accidenr was really contrived, we cannot fail to admire ehe skill which forced the accident to mete out a punishment so suicable to the crime. For as it happened 'cancan' dancing with her became impossible for a long time" (ibid., p. l 99f.). 37 36 de Sade is helpful here, following Lacan's cexc on Kant with Sade, for it suggests that the elevated and self-content enjoyment of the virtuous subject would turn into, so CO speak, 'moral' disgust under de Sadean conditions: "Imagine a revival of Epic- tetus in Sadean experience: 'You see, you broke it', he says, pointing to his leg. To reduce jouissance co ehe misery of an effect in which one's quest stumbles-doesn't this transform it into disgust?" (Lacan 2006a, p. 651) And as Jacques Derrida suggests in Economimesis, "ehe experience of disgust" cogether with "the scheme of vomiting" (Derrida 1981, p. 21) mark ehe blind spot of Kant's rationalistic moralism. Or rather it occupies "[ ... ] wichin ehe Kantian system a strategic point that unites Translation modified. 1 1 37 Wolfram Bergande Kants Apathowgy of Compassion all faculcies'', as Winfried Menninghaus convincingly argues (Menninghaus 2003, with nature". lt cannot be forborn because it cuts through any kind ofimaginary or p. 114). 38 lt is in Kam's own concepcion of disgusc indeed where his contradictory symbolic distancing. Disgust is a formation of ehe 'real' in Lacan's sense. Therefore Statements on ehe paradoxical copic of a 'commanded feeling', a 'pleasure in ehe law it ruins ("zu Grunde zu richten") "all aesthetical satisfaction [ästhetische Wohlgefal- itself' or an 'enjoyment of duties' converge-statements like: that ehe determinati- len] and consequencly artificial beauty [Kunstschönheit]" (ibid.). As disgust collapses on of the will by ehe moral law 'imposes itself (sich au/dringt)' and thac Achtung is ehe difference between sensation and representation, it also tends to collapse the the 'moral pleasure' resulcing from this imposition; thac it is 'contrary co the nature difference between ehe subject and the disgustful object-be it a suffering human of duty to enjoy having duties incumbent upon one'; chat 'an obligation co enjoy- being. From an aesthetical point of view, it thus marks ehe blind spot of the ethi- ment is a manifest absurdiry', just like it 'cannot be commanded' co have a certain cally and logically necessary self-implication of ehe morally judging subject into his 'affection' like e. g. 'love'. own systematized rationalizations. Through disgust, ehe moral subject is blinded and This is not least because disgusc (including possible variants) is the only form of thus beyond good and evil. Yet at the same time, we may presume, disgust is just forced enjoyment that Kant openly admics (again Achtung and its reverse, humilia- the extreme reverse side of compassion and chus is related to ehe very possibility of tion, notwithstanding). In ehe Critique ofjudgement, § 48 dealing wich ehe Relation practical reason; as surrogate or supplement of moraliry's truth, it kicks ehe solitary of Genius to Taste, Kant defines disgust, Ekel, as ehe"[ ... ) peculiar sensation, which Pflichtvorstellung into ehe fullness oflife. Moreover, we can conclude that in analogy rests on mere imagination, [in which) ehe object is represented as [if) it were impo- to sing itself for our enjoyment [all ob er sich zum Genusse aufdränge] while we strive (einsehen)", in the case of disgust it is necessity as such, i. e. the necessity of subjecti- against icwich all our mighc" (Kant 1914, p. 195; Kant 2007, 05: 312). 39 As itwere, vation, i. e. moraliry's ultima ratio, which becomes an object of aesthetic experience. disgust is a feeling which commands itself to us. Tue aestfietic resulc according to Thus it appears that in Kant's moral philosophy disgust is the-ugly-truth of ehe Kant is that in disgusc, Ekel, "the artistic representation of ehe object is no longer "necessiry, indeed urgency" of "a demand of moraliry itself", namely of "finding a distinguished from ehe nature of ehe object itself in our sensation", which is to say sensible representation ofmorality" (Guyer 1993, p. 178). 40 thac an imaginary !et alone symbolic distancing of ehe object is impossible. Thus disgust is the singular "kind of ugliness which cannot be represented in accordance ° 4 ehe feeling of Achtung, which is a feeling "ehe necessity of which we can discern Cf. Menninghaus: "While virmally all pertinem scholarly work on Kant focuses on the duality of the sublime and the beautiful, rhe Kamian sysrem is in fact distinguished by a triad-that of'the feelings of the sublime, rhe beautiful, and the disgusting'. This triad proves tobe highly functional with regard to the paradigm ofphilosophical organa. [... ] Tue beautiful and sublime positively compensate for theoretical deficits of foundation and practical deficits of motiva- 38 On Kam's concept of disgusr cf. Menninghaus 2003, panicularly pp. 103-120. Menninghaus observes that „[t] tion; the feeling of disgust warns us away, and shelters us in negative-apotropaic fashion, from giving in to what would he sensation of disgusr judges, as it were, on physical, aesrhetic, and moral levels, thus occupying-very much like rhe be opposite sensation ofbeauty-within the Kancian sysrem a srrategic poinc that unites all faculties. lt supplemencs the purely the- desirable achievements do not constitue a miraculous natural phenomenon,-proving chat the human being is namrally oretical critique with a test of taste-with a dietetic organon judging all sorrs of 'food for the incellect'." (lbid„ p. l 14f.) good in essence. Rather: to speak with Freud, in the end these positive functions of disgusr are instituted by the supere- 39 go" (Menninghaus 2003, p. 116). 38 Translation modified. 1 to the (groundless) good or the (unknowable) purposiveness of nature. As an effect of cultivation, such 39 1 Wolfram Bergande Kants Apathology of Compassion Aesthetically speaking again, this ultimate necessity appears here in a most 'acci- sed action 'as possible by his or her own will' 41 • This is because it is precisely disgust/ dental' (Freud) form, namely in a form which, in everyday experience, is as pervasive boredom which masks boch ehe self-implication of ehe subjecc's will into ehe moral as it is unpredictable: boredom. And just as disgust is ehe reverse side of compassion, law (conceived of in analogy co a 'system of nature') and ehe unconscious (quasi- Mitleid, and by the same coken ehe discontentful double of respect, Achtung, so ana- natural, quasi-pathological) "pre-determinism" of ehe will resulting from it; how such logously is boredom ehe discontentful (unbehaglich) double ofKant's moral apachy. pre-determinism could possibly "co-exist wich freedom" is something which, as co For it is "disgusc" chac, in Kant's Anthropology, essentially defines "boredom". Bore- Kant's Religion, "we want eo discern [einsehen], but we never shall" (Kant 2006, p. 94, dom, lange Weile, wrices Kant, boils down co disgusc or nausea, given thac boredom Fn. *;Kant 2007, 06: 049). is ehe "disgust [Anekelung] wich one's own existence, which arises when ehe mind lt cannoc be discerned, in any case, unless ehe subject stops ignoring his or her is empty of ehe sensations coward which it incessancly strives [aus der Leerheit des as it were 'moral' disgust, which is compassion in its mosc extreme, namely ics most Gemüths an Empfindungen, zu denen es unaufhörlich strebt, der langen Weile]" (Kant debased form. If, as Kant claims, in disgust 'ehe artistic representation of ehe object 2006, p. 43; Kant 2007, 07: 152). In ocher words: boredom is ehe disgust, Ekel, feie is no langer distinguished from the nature of ehe object itself in our sensation', i. e. on the occasion of a permanencly frustrated striving for sensations. As we have eve- if not even the artistic representation can temper disgust, chen a fortiori we may con- ry reason co suspect here, boredom or disgust become morally relevant precisely in clude chat accually any representation of ehe (disgusting) object 'is no langer distingu- cases where ehe 'representation of duty on its own', emptied as it is of all 'pachologi- ished from ehe nature of ehe object icself in our sensation'. Such 'moral' disgust thus cal' determinations, would not accomplish ehe practical decermination of ehe will. makes it impossible co decide whether a sympathetic affect springs from intuition So we can furcher presume that it is through ehe aesthetical (i. e. ultimately: or racher from reason, i. e. whecher from 'pathological' infection by a social ocher pachological) feelings of disgust and/or boredom that "[t]he rule of ehe Judgement ('humanitas aesthetica') or racher from the subject's 'practical' free will ('humanitas according to laws of pure practical reason" (i. e. ehe categorical imperative) can in- practica'). Thus in ehe experience of disgust ehe subject can no langer decide whether deed get suspended, a rule which obliges eo "ask yourself whecher, if ehe accion you its 'represemation of dury', Pflichtvorstellung, is 'pathological' or 'practical'. For it is propose were to take place by a law of the system of nature of which you were your- only in pure "chinking" chac 1 can imagine chac "I amfree, because 1 am not in an self a parc, you could regard it as possible by your own will. Everyone does, in fact, other, but remain simply and solely in communion with myself [schlechthin bei mir decide by chis rule whether actions are morally good or evil" (Kant 1889, p. 161; selbst bleibe], [„ .)"; nothing buc "[„ .) my activity in conceptual thinking is a mo- Kant 2007, 05: 069). Affected by disgusc/boredom, ehe Kantian subject, like ehe vement wichin myself [meine Bewegung in Begriffen ist eine Bewegung in mir selbst]", s」セゥL@ simply cannot ask him- or herself whether he or she 'could regard' ehe propo41 40 1 Cf. Cooper 1996, p. 266. 1 41 Wolfram Bergande Kants Apathology ofCompassion as Hegel remarks in the Phenomenology wich respect to (not only) ancient Stoicism. While the Pflichtvorstellung tends to become indiscernible in the experience of dis- As Hegel explains, this is because "[ ... ] in the case of a representation [Vorstellung], gust, and despite Kant's verdict about the impossible artification of disgustful objects, [ ... ] consciousness still has specially to bear in mind that this is its representation there are nevertheless artistic srrategies to counter the symptomatic knot interlacing [Vorstellung]; on the contrary, the concept [Begrif.ß is for me srraighraway my concept disgust, apathetic boredom and painful compassion. David Lynch's The Amputee of [Begrif.ß" (Hegel 1977, p. 120).42 Disgust breaks up this rational self-communion. 197 4 artistically stages and exposes such symptomatic feelings as they eventually So besides veiling the self-implication of the moral subject into its object and be- mask an unconscious over-determinarion. Tue objective humor involved in Lynch's sides blurring the distincrion between pathological and moral compassion, disgust short film communicates something unfathomable which cannot be discerned, it is lastly makes it impossible even to discern whether the Pflichtvorstellung really is the rrue, but which can be enjoyed and thus sensed. subject's very own representation or not, and whether it is a representation of a concept or a representation in the sensuous, aesthetic sense. Screenshot from The Amputee (1974) directed by David Lynch 42 42 Translation modified. 1 1 43 Kant'.1 Apathology of Compassion References Baxley, A. M. 2015, "Virtue, self-mastery and the autocracy of practical reason" in: L. Denis et al., Kant's Lectures on Ethics. A critical guide, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 223-238. Borges, M 2008, "Physiology and the Controlling of Affects in Kant's Philosophy" in: Kantian review, Vol. 13, issuc 2, pp. 46-66. Cartwright, 0. E. 1984, "Kant, Schopenhauer, and Nietzsche on the Morality of Pity" in: Journal of the Histoty of Ideas, Vol. 45, No. 1 (Jan. - Mar., 1984), pp. 83-98. Cooper, J. M. 1996, "Eudaimonism, the Appeal to Nature, and Moral Duty" in: S. Engstrom, and J. Whiting, Aristotle, Kant and the Stoies, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 261-284. Denis, L. 2000, "Kant's Cold Sage and the Sublimity of Apathy" in: L. Denis, Kantian Review, Vol. 4, University ofWales Press, Cardiff, pp. 48-73. Derrida, J. 1981, "Economimesis" in: Diacritics, The Ghost of Theology: Readings of Kant and Hegel, Vol. 11, No. 2, pp. 2-25. Fichte, J. G. 2013, Grundlagen des Naturrechts, Ausgewählte Werke in sechs Bänden. Zweiter Band, WBG, Darmstadt. Freud, S. 1922, Psychopathology ofeveryday life, 9'h edition. T. Fisher Unwin, London. Freud, S. 1973, "Ein Kind wird geschlagen" in: Zwang, Paranoia und Perversion. Freud-Studienausgabe, Bd. 7. Hg. von Alexander Mitscherlich, Fischer, Frankfurt a. M., pp. 229-254. Gay, !. 2007, "Immanuel Kant über das moralische Gefühl der Achtung" in: Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung, Bd. 61, H. 3 (Jul.- Sep., 2007), pp. 337-360. Guyer, P. 1996, Kant and the experience offreedom essays on aesthetics and morality, Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge. 1 45 Wolfram Bergande Kants Apathology of Compassion Hegel, G. W F., Miller, A. V. & Findlay J. N. 1977, Phenomenology ofspirit, Oxford University Press, Oxford. Lacan, J. 1967, Le Seminaire Livre XIV: La logique du phantasme ( 1966-67), LacanArchive, Bregenz. Honneth, A. 2001, "Die transzendentale Notwendigkeit von lntersubjektivität (Zweiter Lehrsatz: § 3)" in: J .-C. Merle, Johann Gottlieb Fichte. Grundlage des Naturrechts, Akademie-Verlag, Berlin, pp. 63-80. Lacan, J. 1986, Le Seminaire Livre VII: L 'Ethique de La psychanalyse (1959-60), Seuil, Paris. Lacan, J. 1991, Le Seminaire XVII: L'envers de La psychoanalyse (1969-70), Seuil, Paris. Kant, 1. 1886, The metaphysic ofethics, 3rd edition, T. & T. Clark, Edinburgh. Kant, 1. 1889, Kant's Critique ofPractical Reason and other \%rks on the Ethics, Translated by Thomas Kingsmill Abbott, Longman's, London. Kant, 1. and Bernard, J. H. 1914, Kant's Critique ofjudgement, 2"d edition, Macmillan Press, London. Kant, 1. 1996, "Religion within the boundaries of mere reason", in: Wood, di Giovanni: Immanuel Kant. Religion and Rational Theology, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 39-216. Kant, 1. 2006, Anthropology ftom a pragmatic point of view, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Kant, 1. 2007, Akademie-Ausgabe, Universität Duisburg-Essen, Essen. Available from; <https://korpora.zim.uni-due.de/Kam/>. [l 0 January 2016] Kant, 1. 200la, "Kant's practical philosophy: Herder's lecture notes (selections)" in: 1. Kant & P. L. Heath, Lectures on ethics, Cambridge University Press., Cambridge, pp. 1-36. Lacan, J. 2006a, "Kant with Sade" in Ecrits [1966], Translated by Bruce Fink, Norton, New York/London, pp. 645-670. Lacan, J. 2006b, "Science and truth" in Ecrits [1966], Translated by Bruce Fink, Norton, New York/London, pp. 726-745. Menninghaus, W 2003, Disgust. Theory and history ofa strong sensation, Stare University of New York Press, Albany. Mieth, C. 2015, entry for "Liebe" in M. Willaschek et al., Kant-Lexikon, de Gruyter, Berlin/ Boston, pp. 1412-1414. Molina, E. 2013, „Kant y el ideal del sabio", in: ideas y valores, Vol. LXII · suplemento n.o 1, pp. 171-183. Origen 2001, Contra Celsum, chap. LIII. Available from: <http://www.earlychristianwritings.com/text/origen l 67>. [10 January 2016] Wood, A 2015, "Kant's history of ethics" in L Denis et al. Kant's Lectures on Ethics: A critical guide, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 120-137. Kant, 1. 200lb. "Johann Friedrich Vigilantius: Notes on the lectures ofMr. Kanton the Metaphysics of Ethics" in: 1. Kant & P. L. Heath, Lectures on ethics, Cambridge University Press., Cambridge, pp. 249-452. Zac, S 1972, "Kant, !es sto"iciens et le christianisme" in Revue de Metaphysique et de Morale, No. 2, pp. 137-165. Kant, 1. 2001 c, "The end of all things" in: 1. Kant, Religion and rational theology, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge pp. 217-232. Filmography The Amputee 1974, Lynch, 0, [film], USA: Criterion Collection. 46 1 1 47