Religious Studies (2013) 49, 439–458
doi:10.1017/S0034412513000164
© Cambridge University Press 2013
Winner of the Religious Studies Postgraduate Essay Prize
Moral critique and defence of theodicy
SAMUEL SHEARN
Faculty of Theology and Religion, University of Oxford, 34 St Giles, Oxford,
OX1 3LD, UK
e-mail: samuel.shearn@theology.ox.ac.uk
Abstract: In this essay, moral anti-theodicy is characterized as opposition to
the trivialization of suffering, defined as the reinterpretation of horrendous evils in
a way the sufferer cannot accept. Ambitious theodicy (which claim goods emerge
from specific evils) is deemed always to trivialize horrendous evils and, because
there is no specific theoretical context, also harm sufferers. Moral anti-theodicy is
susceptible to two main criticisms. First, it is over-demanding as a moral position.
Second, anti-theodicist opposition to least ambitious theodicies, which portray
God’s decision to create as an ‘all-or-nothing’ scenario, requires a moral
commitment to philosophical pessimism. Thus anti-theodicists should not be
quick to take the moral high ground. However, this should not encourage
theodicists, since theodicies may well be self-defeating in so far as they attempt to
provide comfort.
Introduction
This is an essay about moral anti-theodicy – objections to the practice of
theoretical theodicy on moral grounds. Such objections have been presented by
both atheists and theists. Therefore, this essay is not concerned with the attempt to
solve or prove the problem of evil. Rather its aim is to assess anti-theodicy as a
moral argument.
I have not given a fine-grained account of the great variety of theodicies on offer.
The most important distinction in the essay is that of most or least ambitious
theodicies, since this refers to the sort of explanation or reasons a theodicy tries to
give (see Trakakis (), f.). Thus Hick and Plantinga are in the same ‘lowambition’ category, although they disagree in several important ways. It turns
out that the morality of theodicy depends significantly on how ambitious a
theodicy is.
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 54.157.246.241, on 09 Jan 2017 at 13:32:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034412513000164
SAMUEL SHEARN
In part one I evaluate moral anti-theodicy with reference to some recent papers,
exploring the critique of theodicies by assessing the charge that theodicies
trivialize suffering. The argument leads us to consider in part two whether
there can be a defence of theodicy as a sufficiently moral project, if there are good
reasons for the sort of detachment from suffering such trivialization entails.
Finally, in part three, a consideration of the qualitative difference between
ambitious and less ambitious theodicies leads us to ask whether an anti-theodicist
rejection of least ambitious theodicies (having significant parallels with Ivan
Karamazov’s ‘mutiny’) implies a moral commitment to philosophical pessimism.
My conclusions are that, first, ambitious theodicies always trivialize the
experience of those who have suffered horrendously. Second, this (trivializing)
detachment from suffering which such theodicies entail is partially defendable as
an intellectual pursuit, yet self-defeating if pursued with the aim of helping others
with religious doubt. This leads to a third conclusion, that anti-theodicy which too
easily impugns the motives of theodicists is wrong, although theodicists who aim
to help doubters do unwittingly harm those who suffer acutely. Fourth, antitheodicy is over-demanding. Fifth, for the case of least ambitious theodicies, antitheodicy demands pessimism and is therefore unacceptable as a moral principle.
Sixth, even least ambitious theodicists who are theists should consider the further
question whether giving reasons for God’s permission of evil is likely to
undermine theism’s attraction and ability to offer comfort to those who suffer.
Part one: does theodicy trivialize suffering?
In what follows we shall characterize moral anti-theodicy generally as a
charge about the trivialization of suffering, which seems to refer to a set of
complaints regularly made against theodicy, such as that theodicy makes light of
suffering, does not give horrific experiences due weight, and fails to take the
devastating impact of great evils seriously. The heart of the issue is the nature of
the relationship between the theoretical (‘third-person’) explanation of evil and
the ‘first-person’ experience of evil.
Theodicists insist that they attempt to give God’s reasons for allowing evil in
good faith, and with a desire never to trivialize the suffering of others (see Hick
(), ). Both theodicists and anti-theodicists would agree that trivializing
suffering is bad. However, they disagree about whether theodicy is an instance of
such trivialization. Claiming that God has good reasons for allowing suffering, the
theodicist says, does not have to entail a trivialization of suffering. Given this
disagreement, we should explore what trivialization amounts to.
Trivialization as reinterpretation
To understand trivialization, consider this example: if a person makes
considerable sacrifices and works hard to gain an apprenticeship with a
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 54.157.246.241, on 09 Jan 2017 at 13:32:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034412513000164
Moral critique and defence of theodicy
manufacturing company, she will feel a sense of pride at having achieved
her goal. However, if we imagine her overhearing a company boss talking
about the vocational qualifications necessary to start an apprenticeship being ‘two
a penny nowadays – you have to try hard to fail them’ then the apprentice would
feel much put down. She would find the reinterpretation of her effort as having
been – from another person’s perspective – insignificant, very hurtful.
We could therefore understand a trivialization of someone’s experience of effort
or suffering as a reinterpretation of that experience in ways the person does not
endorse. One could argue from here that theodicy trivializes suffering if it
reinterprets suffering in a way the sufferer cannot accept.
However, there is an obvious objection to this move, since it would
seem to commit us to a strict perspectivism which does not admit of any intersubjective judgements. We would have to say that everyone’s version of events is
true. This is an unacceptable consequence. We shall call this the perspectivism
objection.
Furthermore, a hypersensitive person could, on undergoing mild and generally
insignificant discomfort (for example the feeling of hunger before dinner), insist
that her daily experience was terrible and could not be reinterpreted as on balance
good or worthwhile. This is also an unacceptable consequence. This is the
hypersensitivity objection.
The claim that theodicy trivializes if it reinterprets suffering in a way the sufferer
cannot accept is vulnerable to both objections. In that manufacturing company,
there may be vacancies because few young people have completed the very basic
technical courses required. The boss may remember the days when qualifications
necessary for an apprenticeship were higher and competition for places was
tough. He might talk about the fall in standards when speaking to a colleague in
Human Resources, and not intend the apprentice to overhear. It is doubtful we
would consider him immoral.
If there are cases (according to the hypersensitivity objection) where we think it
is right to discount a hypersensitive person’s perspective to a degree and we also
do not want to accept a strict perspectivism, then we are implying that some
common-sense account of the gravity of experiences of suffering should be
included in an account of which trivialization is immoral. But might then the
debate between theodicists and anti-theodicists be characterized as a debate
between people on a spectrum of empathy, with some opting for tough, honest
words and others opting for silence?
This would be too simple. If we make use of some generally agreed account of
how grave various experiences are, then there will be no disagreement that the
subjective experience of horrendous evils can never be discounted or trivialized.
Here are cases where the distinction between an over-sensitive or under-sensitive
person pales into insignificance and their account of their experience is given
priority and credence.
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 54.157.246.241, on 09 Jan 2017 at 13:32:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034412513000164
SAMUEL SHEARN
Therefore the focus of an anti-theodicy argument has to be specifically directed
to the worst cases, including a reference to horrendous evils as the worst sorts of
suffering in our world, ‘prima facie ruinous to the participant’s life’ (Adams (),
). A person unacceptably trivializes suffering if she reinterprets horrendous evils
in a way the sufferer cannot accept.
This defends the right of victims of extreme suffering to have the last word – for
their account to be taken seriously. This sort of objection to theodicies is well
expressed by Adorno: ‘The need to lend a voice to suffering is a condition of all
truth’ (Adorno (), f.; cited by Surin (), ).
In the next section, we shall explore whether theodicies can be defended by the
argument that the moral status of theodicies, whether it is the case that theodicies
are insensitive and trivialize suffering, is contingent on their truth.
Simpson on not assuming implausibility
Simpson argues that a theodicy trivializes suffering if it is false. An agnostic
about theodicies, open to the possibility that there may be a true or plausible
theodicy, must also see that it is possible that a theodicy is not insensitive, which
means it does not trivialize horrendous evils (see Simpson (a), ).
Simpson considers examples of a family friend who offers a sort of theodicy
by suggesting putative goods which occur as the result of some suffering.
I summarize two of them below (see ibid.):
Putative
good
Suffering
(A)
Child with mumps
(B)
Child with diabetes
Better to have mumps as a child
than as an adult
Long-term benefit for child
True?
Insensitive?
Yes
No
No
Yes
Simpson assumes for the sake of argument that in all examples the ‘theodicist’
might offer the ‘theodicy’ (putative goods) tactfully and at an appropriate
moment, so that only the insensitivity of the content is considered. In example
(B), assuming there is a more appropriate moment to mention the putative good,
the theodicist’s response is ‘false, and all the more insensitive for being false’
(ibid.). Therefore, says Simpson, the insensitivity is dependent upon the falsehood
of the putative good.
Simpson wants to relate these examples of a friend offering consolation to
another example closer to theodicies and suggests the example (C):
(C)
Suffering
Putative good
True?
Insensitive?
Terminal illnesses
Improved gene pool
No
Yes
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 54.157.246.241, on 09 Jan 2017 at 13:32:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034412513000164
Moral critique and defence of theodicy
Simpson comments: ‘even if it is couched in the nicest possible terms it remains
appalling, because the content of the view itself is beyond the pale (and obviously
untrue)’ (ibid.).
Simpson’s response is revealing. The falsehood of the putative good seems to be
a secondary consideration. The ‘view itself’ is appalling, i.e. inherently insensitive.
The anti-theodicist would agree. Some theodicists would also agree, if they insist
that theodicies must be ‘patient-centred’, i.e. the putative goods must benefit the
sufferer, and not merely future generations or humanity’s average utility. I suspect
that this is why Simpson finds the view itself repugnant, although he does not
elaborate.
However, Simpson insists that those who believe in the inherent insensitivity
of such theodicies cannot say that all theodicies are inherently insensitive
because there may still be a theodicy ‘that is more like the mumps example’ (ibid.,
–) – which I note is patient-centred. Anti-theodicists must make the
assumption that even future theodicies are incapable of being plausible (ibid.,
).
Simpson asks ‘which features of theodical discourse . . . could provide a suitable
focus for a global argument against the plausibility of theodicies’ (ibid.). Under
the next heading we will turn to consider this possibility, and it will be argued
that for certain types of theodicies it is fair to assume they are inherently
implausible.
A Humean argument from implausibility
In the examples Simpson to which refers, the difference between a sensitive
and insensitive theodicy is contingent upon its plausibility. Simpson does not
distinguish between the truth of a putative good and the plausibility of a putative
good, because the plausibility is a measurement of the intersubjective judgement
(common knowledge) of the veracity of such a good. Thus the mumps example is
plausible and the diabetes example implausible.
Therefore the plausibility of putative goods said to emerge from evils is a matter
of degrees. We can imagine a scenario somewhere between examples () and ()
where there is uncertainty whether a putative good emerges from a particular evil.
The plausibility of that putative good would rest on the evidence offered by the
medical community. This seems to be the assumption behind Simpson’s train of
thought. We could characterize this as a Humean argument, since it assigns
plausibility to theodicies according to whether the putative goods are evident.
Presumably, the prima facie plausibility of a ‘theodicy’ in this medical analogy
would also depend on the particular evil. It would be easier to convince people of
a putative good if it emerged from the common cold than if it were said to emerge
from cancer.
Simpson is claiming that the anti-theodicist has to assume that there are and will
be no theodicies whose reinterpretations of horrendous evils the sufferer will
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 54.157.246.241, on 09 Jan 2017 at 13:32:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034412513000164
SAMUEL SHEARN
accept. However, since we are talking about horrendous evils, this seems sure.
It beggars belief that there is a good entailed in a person’s horrific experience, such
that it is overall good and better (or at least not worse) for having undergone that
suffering.
It might be objected that there is a theodicy which is true – whereby, through
some logical connection between certain evils and goods emerging from that life
of suffering, the person’s life would be better overall than if her life had been
spared the suffering. However, within this Humean (evidential) framework of
plausibility, a theodicy which claimed to know of putative goods (as yet not
evident in the life of the sufferer) which emerged from horrendous evils must be
judged to be most certainly implausible. In a world containing horrendous evils,
ambitious theodicies are inherently implausible for the sufferer and she
experiences this theodicy as a trivialization of her suffering.
Søvik on not communicating theodicies
Søvik, like Simpson, thinks the attempt to morally discredit all theodicy
already assumes theodicy’s falsehood (see Søvik (), ). However, he also
says that if theodicies are in danger of trivializing the sufferer’s experience, it is
crucial that theodicies are offered in the right contexts; ‘it is a matter of practical
wisdom to find out what is needed when’ (ibid., ).
Even if, in some situations, theodicies trivialize suffering, it does not follow that
they trivialize in every situation. Theodicists should not offer theodicies in situations where someone could be hurt, but there is nothing wrong with theodicies
generally: ‘the statements themselves are not immoral; in some settings they are
right to communicate, in others they are wrong to communicate’ (ibid., ).
Søvik makes the distinction between the theory and the misuse of a theory. If a
theodicy has such trivializing effects when communicated in an inappropriate
situation, then it is not the fault of the theodicy or the theodicist. Søvik gives the
example of misused theories: how social Darwinism and nuclear weapons are
misuses of biology and physics (see ibid.).
However, putting theodicy into the category of misused theories will not do.
A closer comparison between scientific research and theodicy would be to ask
whether certain types of biological research ensured animal welfare, or whether
the research at CERN was good for the citizens of Geneva. Just as some scientific
research might harm animals and humans, so theodicy impacts upon humans.
Theodicy does not stay in a university laboratory, sealed off from those who have
suffered horrendous evils. Theodicy is written and spoken in the public arena, in
the world of ideas, and to propagate a theodicy is to communicate it at once to
potentially everyone, because the theodicy of academic journals finds its way to
the pulpits and popular religious books, providing religious communities with
theodical narratives for interpreting horrendous evils. Therefore, contra Søvik,
there is no strictly ‘theoretical context’ (Søvik (), ) to which one can turn
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 54.157.246.241, on 09 Jan 2017 at 13:32:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034412513000164
Moral critique and defence of theodicy
and safely do theodicy. It follows from this that for ambitious theodicies, ‘if we
would think it shamefully foolish and cruel to say such things in the moment when
another’s sorrow is most real and irresistibly painful, then we ought never to say
them’ (Hart (), ).
Do the least ambitious theodicies trivialize suffering?
John Hick points out that his own theodicy does not judge horrendous
sufferings to be good as Phillips would charge. Regarding the horrendous evils of
the twentieth century, Hick calls them ‘wrongs that can never be righted, horrors
which will disfigure the universe to the end of time’ (Hick (), ) and thinks
no soul-making effect issues from such circumstances (see Hick (), f.).
The theodicist, according to Hick, makes the far less ambitious claim that ‘the
entire person-making process, in this life and beyond, will ultimately have a fully
justifying value to all’ (ibid., ). Therefore, the theodicy is not a reinterpretation
or justification of horrendous evils which individuals experience. Rather, it is
the claim that those individuals, having experienced the unfathomable good of the
eschaton, will be able to say that their life was good overall and feel that the
creation of a world wherein horrendous suffering is a possibility is justified.
Much that we have said about the implausibility of theodicies for those suffering
is rather relativized by the recognition of Hick’s distinction. Asking about the
plausibility of a putative good emerging from a particular evil is one thing. Asking
about the plausibility of a positive judgement concerning human life considered
as a whole is a question of a different order – an ultimate question!
Since a theodicy like Hick’s holds on to a non-teleological understanding of
horrendous suffering, it does not reinterpret suffering in a way directly at odds
with the experience of suffering. Therefore it appears Hick escapes the charge of
trivialization on one count. However, it still seems to be the case that one could
characterize this as trivialization, because the meta-narrative is made central and
the horrendous evils not attended to in the way that sufferers might demand. If the
theodicist’s attention is drawn away from the horrific experiences of evil towards
‘an overwhelming tide of “positive experience” that can be guaranteed to swallow
up any and all specific negative experiences’ (Williams (), ), then the
horrendous evils could be said to be reinterpreted in a way the sufferer cannot
accept. Even the least ambitious theodicy is in danger of trivializing suffering,
because it places that suffering within a larger positive framework. We will explore
this possibility in part three. However, for now, let us survey our conclusions so far.
Conclusion: ambitious theodicies trivialize suffering
We started with the claim that theodicies do inherently trivialize suffering
because theodicy entails the reinterpretation of suffering which a sufferer cannot
accept. We upheld this conclusion against several objections: Simpson rightly
recognizes the connection between anti-theodicy and plausibility, but he should
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 54.157.246.241, on 09 Jan 2017 at 13:32:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034412513000164
SAMUEL SHEARN
concede that no theodicy claiming that goods will emerge from evils will be
plausible to sufferers of horrendous evils.
Søvik suggests that theodicy, not being intended for practical contexts, should
not be blamed when it is misused there. However, since theodicy is done in
public, the theoretical/practical distinction is not relevant. Therefore, we concluded that ambitious theodicies, which claim God has good reason for allowing
horrendous evils because he intends greater goods to emerge from those evils, will
be implausible to people suffering acutely and therefore always be a trivialization
of their experience – a reinterpretation they cannot accept.
Less ambitious theodicies do not reinterpret suffering as being advantageous in
itself but promise that, from the perspective of the eschaton, life will be judged to
be overall good. Whether this also amounts to a trivialization of evils – and, if so,
whether this is immoral, will be explored in part three.
However, in part two we shall attend to a significant objection to the charge of
trivialization, namely, that there is such a thing as a legitimate detachment from
suffering which, despite its trivialization of suffering, cannot be said to be wholly
immoral.
Part two: is theodicy a legitimate and useful detachment?
Some theodicists might defend their practice by claiming that such
detachment is legitimate as an intellectual duty, and as a service to those seeking
theoretical orientation.
Detachment as intellectual duty
Søvik says one can legitimately search for a true answer even though
communicating a truth may not be the right thing to do in a certain situation.
Since theodicy is about the search and not the communication, theodicy is not
immoral (see Søvik (), ). Similarly, John Hick says that since the problem
of evil presents itself as an intellectual problem, it belongs to the intellectual
duty of a philosopher or theologian to think hard about the problem and seek to
find a successful theodicy (see Hick (), f.). Peter van Inwagen goes beyond
the defence of theodicy and accuses anti-theodicists of ‘intellectual dishonesty’
(van Inwagen (), ), demonstrated in a reluctance to think hard. Van
Inwagen warns that since moral scorn for another’s position gives one a feeling of
being in the right, one can feel one is right without having made a good
argument.
The theodicist insists that it is her moral and intellectual duty to pursue an
objective, third-person, description of reasons why God might allow evil. The antitheodicist believes it is her moral and intellectual duty to give the first-person
perspective of sufferers credence and therefore stop explaining. It seems that the
theodicist and anti-theodicist stand in very different philosophical traditions.
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 54.157.246.241, on 09 Jan 2017 at 13:32:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034412513000164
Moral critique and defence of theodicy
Might it be possible to reduce this disagreement to saying that theodicists prefer
the third-person, scientific approach, while anti-theodicists prefer the first-person,
subjective approach?
We can test whether the anti-theodicist’s position is indicative of such a wider
set of assumptions by seeing if the anti-theodicist approves of a more general
critique of the inappropriateness of scientific (third-person) discourse to give a
true account of horrendous evils. The theodicist might object that the antitheodicist would have no moral difficulties with a scientific account of a disease,
even if the affliction was horrific. While it is clear that there are bad times to give a
patient a scientific explanation, it does not preclude the scientific study of the
disease in medical journals. Furthermore, sometimes a scientific explanation
helps the person suffering to understand what is happening to him. Theoretical
theodicy is no different, says the theodicist.
Proscribing scientific discourse generally because of the insensitivity a scientific
explanation would entail in a specific context seems inadmissible. Might not the
theodicist therefore legitimately suggest that theodicy is justified when confined to
the right contexts?
We have already emphasized that theodical discourse is unlikely to be confined
to academia and that it will shape the narratives of religious communities and
thus their responses to horrendous evils. However, the same is true of medical
explanations of terrible diseases. These explanations will shape the general
knowledge concerning disease in public life. Yet, the theodicist might argue, noone worries about the insensitivity of medical explanations. Generally opposing
the detachment necessary to attempt to understand God’s putative reasons for
allowing evil would be as intellectually obtuse as opposing scientific research – a
gross negligence of intellectual duty.
If the theodicist were to argue so, it might be objected that no-one worries about
the intellectual pursuit of description of disease in medical research because the
whole aim of the enterprise is to serve patients. In contrast, theoretical theodicy
does not help sufferers. The theodicist’s reply might be that theodicy can indeed
be of help to people.
Detachment as benevolent existential orientation
According to many theodicists, theoretical theodicies are a comfort to
believers. Forrest envisages a religious apologist pastorally motivated by concern
for those whose doubts would rob them of religious comfort. For example, Forrest
believes that while ‘insensitive theodicy insults the sufferer . . . sensitive theodicy
can endow suffering with meaning’ (Forrest (), ).
Moreover, the theodicist might continue, to deny those suffering a theoretical
explanation for the existence of evil – and to deny the existence of God, who gives a
reason to hope that human life is not meaningless – could be said to be a great evil,
leaving people stranded and alone with their suffering (see Davis (), f.).
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 54.157.246.241, on 09 Jan 2017 at 13:32:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034412513000164
SAMUEL SHEARN
Assuming that religious beliefs make metaphysical claims, and noting that these
claims are attacked philosophically, it is a disservice to those who gather comfort
from their religious beliefs not to defend those religious beliefs from attack and to
refuse to devise a theoretical theodicy (see Forrest (), ). ‘[M]aybe the person
in sorrow did ask a theoretical question because she had some existential questions concerning whether she could still believe in God . . . . a theoretical
answer . . . may have the good consequences of bringing comfort and hope’
(Søvik (), ).
It is true that many people find comfort in their religious beliefs. If one is able to
believe that one’s difficulties, illnesses, crises, and even impending death are part
of a divine plan for personal flourishing, then this framework fosters optimism
concerning the course of one’s life and is arguably very empowering. If ‘God exists
and A good eschaton is in the offing . . . then telling people those facts . . . is about as
helpful a thing as we can do for them’ (Davis (), , cited in Simpson (a),
). Might not the theodicist’s desire to be helpful to those seeking orientation
justify her project?
Theodicy as self-defeating detachment
The anti-theodicist could argue that the detachment is self-defeating, i.e.
theodicy, by virtue of being detached, is not able to deliver the existential
assistance it aimed to provide. This undermines the theodicist argument made
under the previous heading.
A case can be made that the existential benefits of a theodicy are contingent
upon the nature of the God whose existence is supposedly vindicated by theodicies. Simpson imagines amoral theodicies which take God’s Schadenfreude to be
the reason for allowing evil and insists these would be instances of such a
universally insensitive theodicy (see Simpson (b), ). Such a theodicy will
have offered a reason for God’s permission of evil, and thus a framework of
meaning within which one could understand evil, but this framework of meaning
would offer no existential comfort. Obviously, in that amoral theodicy, God would
not be considered benevolent, and so this would not be a theodicy proper.
However, similar difficulties occur in some theodicists’ attempts to justify God.
For example, Forrest describes God as a tough-minded utilitarian, a moral
monster by human standards, very unlike a loving heavenly father (see Forrest
(), f.). The existential comfort gained would have to be gained from the
knowledge that the sufferings one experiences are part of the plan or permission of
a thoroughgoing utilitarian deity with a detailed knowledge of all the variables
of the hedonistic calculus. Perhaps some find security in such a perspective.
However, in the face of horrendous examples of evil, it is hard to imagine this
theodicy being comforting to the sufferer. As David Hart says, ‘It is a strange thing
indeed to seek peace in a universe rendered morally intelligible at the cost of a
God rendered morally loathsome’ (Hart (), ).
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 54.157.246.241, on 09 Jan 2017 at 13:32:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034412513000164
Moral critique and defence of theodicy
Davis says he would only worship a God who is perfectly good and abhors
theodicies which claim all evils are ‘disguised goods’. However, he thinks that
theodicies which do ‘belittle’ suffering are good, and should be communicated to
those suffering as ‘the best possible news that sufferers could hear’ (see Davis
(), ). However, while one can agree that the message, that ‘evil is not the
whole story . . . and suffering will one day come to an end’ (ibid., ), is good
news for many sufferers of lesser evils, for those undergoing severe suffering, this
good news may not help.
One might think of parents witnessing their child suffer greatly, daily, due to a
chronic illness for which doctors can find no conceivable treatment or cure. For
that child and those parents, the only story they can see is the horrendous one,
and the end of the suffering is not in sight. Even the best news does not give
meaning, for the daily struggle with the reality of that suffering engulfs and
destroys any seeds of meaning.
The detachment of theodicy which finds a third-person explanation involves a
God who finds (or is confined by) a logical reason for permitting evil. Therefore,
borrowing Martin Buber’s terminology (see Buber (), f.), in theoretical
theodicy, God’s relationship with sufferers is portrayed as an Ich–Es relation,
rather than an Ich–Du relation. Buber’s schema distinguishes between the way we
talk of people as objects (referring to them as he or she) and the way we talk to a
person and say ‘you’ to them. He argues plausibly that only the Ich–Du relation is
spoken with one’s whole being, by which he means with emotion and full
attention. There is a great difference between talking about someone and talking
to them, addressing them. We can use this distinction to analyse the debate about
anti-theodicy.
In the case of horrendous evils, as theodicists would agree, it is only the practical
help and personal comfort in the heat and aftermath of severe suffering which is
appropriate. It is only the personal attending to and companionship of other
people (an Ich–Du relation) which could help at all.
In a theodicy, evils become ‘things’ for which God has reasons. God, having his
reasons, must be portrayed as relating to evil in that detached, Ich–Es way, not fully
attentive to the personal predicament of the sufferer. Any theoretical ‘help’, in the
case of horrendous evils, does not become good news for the sufferer, because it
will not comfort. Theodicy, even if it is legitimate as an intellectual enterprise, is
self-defeating if it aims to be beneficial to sufferers.
Theodicy as selfish comfort
It follows from these observations about the lack of comfort theodicy can
offer to sufferers of horrendous evils that the supposed benevolence could be
portrayed as a selfish attitude on the part of those who suffer only minor or lesser
evils. As we have seen, while theodicies might offer comfort to those suffering the
discomforts of western life, it is difficult to see how theodicies can offer any
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 54.157.246.241, on 09 Jan 2017 at 13:32:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034412513000164
SAMUEL SHEARN
comfort to those who have undergone horrific and degrading suffering, and such
theodicies may be distressing to them. Therefore the theodicist, disregarding this
(unintended) effect of theodicy, harms the sufferer of horrendous evils by her
unthoughtfulness, even as she seeks to comfort her contemporaries.
Alternatively, the anti-theodicist may say that theodicies are ‘a lie told principally for our own comfort, by which we would try to excuse ourselves for believing
in an omnipotent and benevolent God’ (Hart (), ). Theodicy is thus seen to
be a relief for those experiencing justificatory pressure from their non-religious
peers. If we grant that theodicy makes the comfort of philosophical assurance
available to western Christians suffering discomfort and setbacks, that same
theodicy can be counted as selfish, since it compounds the suffering of those who
have suffered horrendous evils.
The anti-theodicist making this sort of argument is suggesting that the
theodicist (or grateful recipient of a theodicy) is herself detached from suffering
so as to suspect a disregard for those who suffer horrendously. The theodicist
insists that her motives are to provide comfort. Thus the anti-theodicist implies the
moral dishonesty (or at least unthoughtfulness) of the theodicist.
Is anti-theodicy over-demanding?
Even if we grant that the motives for producing theoretical theodicies, like
anyone’s motives for anything, are somewhat mixed, it does seem that a
theodicist’s declared aim to be a help is not obviously made in bad faith. If antitheodicists were to insist on a hermeneutic of suspicion, theodicists might equally
claim that anti-theodicists cannot take the moral high ground. Perhaps antitheodicists are not being entirely honest with themselves, since anti-theodicy’s
moral maxim is over-demanding.
The anti-theodicist claims to be opposed to trivializing the suffering of others.
Horrendous evils should be given their due weight. However, it might be objected,
if we are to give horrendous evils their due weight, then this is over-demanding. To
give truly horrendous evils their due weight, we should be constantly reminding
ourselves of the weight of suffering involved. There would be no end to reading
first-person accounts of the Holocaust, Rwanda, Srebrenica, and the most
disturbing abuses. There would be no end to the stunned sadness such reading
and remembering occasions. Presumably we would find it impossible ever to be
content and enjoy life. Taking pleasure in something as insignificant as a favourite
meal, or a special landscape, enjoying art or music, compared with the weight of
the most horrendous evils, would be immoral. The most moral person would then
be the most saddened, moved and even depressed (see Gawronski & Privette
() for the connection between empathy and depression).
This seems unacceptable – it must be that a certain amount of self-interest,
expressed in a degree of detachment from others’ suffering, is legitimate. We need
detachment to survive emotionally – we cannot be moved by everything. A moral
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 54.157.246.241, on 09 Jan 2017 at 13:32:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034412513000164
Moral critique and defence of theodicy
principle which would demand a vast, indefinite amount of our attention, and
thus conceivably leave no room for anything else in life, is an over-demanding
principle which should not be accepted.
Furthermore, the theodicist might point out that the anti-theodicist does not
take her own advice seriously. If theodicists are to be characterized as comfortably
detached academics, aloof from the real needs of sufferers of horrendous evils,
then anti-theodicists are no less comfortable, detached academics with the leisure
to write at length about the immorality of theodicy. The anti-theodicist makes loud
demands to give suffering its due weight, but it is a demand which she herself
could never fulfil.
Conclusion: moral demands in conflict
Having considered these objections and counter-objections to the
detachment which theoretical theodicy entails, we are faced with conflicting
moral demands.
Anti-theodicy seems to rest on the moral rule that one should not trivialize evils
but give the sufferer’s experience due weight, and also that one should not seek
one’s own existential comfort without regard for the consequences such
theoretical theodicy has for those undergoing suffering. The anti-theodicist calls
us not to be selfish but to practise empathy.
The theodicist, in a charitable reading of her motives, practises the virtue of
intellectual rigour in seeking to understand what God’s reasons might be,
believing him to have reasons for his actions. Furthermore, if the theodicist
believes that theodicies will help people, then she is also morally motivated to find
a successful theodicy.
The theodicist’s virtues carry with them the danger of discounting the plight of
those suffering worst, for the sake of helping the existentially disoriented or being
intellectually rigorous. The anti-theodicist’s virtues seem to carry with them the
danger of being over-demanding because horrendous evils are what one might
call a black hole for empathy – one could arguably never plumb the depths of
the terror some people experience, and any attempt to do this would surely
commit oneself to unceasing despair. In all this, both parties seek the moral high
ground.
Having surveyed these conflicts it is clear that a moral valuation of the detachment of the theodicist is less than straightforward. Therefore, anti-theodicists
should be wary of making easy and lazy criticisms of theodicists without considering that the positive motives expressed are genuine and their own motives
complex, given the over-demandingness of the anti-theodicist position. However,
the self-defeating nature of the detachment which theodicies entail when faced
with horrendous evils, and the absence of a discernible theoretical context in
which theodicies do not also, indirectly, address those suffering horrendously,
should advise theodicists that their benevolently minded attempts to provide
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 54.157.246.241, on 09 Jan 2017 at 13:32:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034412513000164
SAMUEL SHEARN
reasons for God’s permission of evil are misguided, and, given their effect on those
suffering acutely, harmful.
Part three: does moral anti-theodicy entail philosophical pessimism?
Let us recall that in part one, following the claim that ambitious theodicies
always trivialize suffering, we considered the possibility that the least ambitious
theodicies might escape the charge of trivialization. We asked whether there might
be a qualitative difference between justifying horrendous suffering and justifying
the creation of the world as a place containing conditions which make horrendous
evils possible (as in the free-will defence). The latter case can be characterized as a
justification of human life (if, for example, freedom is a necessary condition of
human life).
The theodicist might insist that the onus is on the anti-theodicist to give reasons
why our attention should be held captive by the experiences of horrendous evil, to
the exclusion of recognizing the beauty and goodness of the world as a whole. Why
should it not also be reprehensible to trivialize good experiences, by not giving
them due weight?
Thus far it seems there are grounds for considering this conflict as about
competing visions of the world. The overall positive or negative ‘picture’ within
which one interprets evils is not merely a matter of evident goods which emerge
from those evils, or a counting up of goods and evils, but a way of seeing the world.
The theodicist insists that the good outweighs the bad. The anti-theodicist insists
the bad is so weighty it could never be matched or overcome. This seems like an
aesthetic impasse, and not simply a moral issue.
To test this possibility, we should pay attention to a classic moral anti-theodicy,
expressed by Dostoevsky’s character Ivan Karamazov, and explore its parallels
with the free-will defence and with Schopenhauerian pessimism.
Ivan Karamazov’s moral anti-theodicy
Ivan Karamazov recounts a series of examples of horrendous suffering,
involving children, to his believing brother Alyosha with the purpose of exposing
that faith to be inappropriate. One example imagines a young girl enduring her
days in imprisonment and degrading abuse. Ivan challenges Alyosha to agree that
if this child’s suffering were the price necessary to make possible a heavenly
paradise for all, accepting that price would be immoral. To agree to build a cosmos
which, even though it ended in bliss, involved such innocent suffering would be to
agree to undertake an immoral task:
Tell me yourself directly, I challenge you – reply: imagine that you yourself are erecting the
edifice of human fortune with the goal of, at the finale, making people happy, of at last
giving them peace and quiet, but that in order to do it it would be necessary and
unavoidable to torture to death only one tiny little creature, that same little child that beats
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 54.157.246.241, on 09 Jan 2017 at 13:32:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034412513000164
Moral critique and defence of theodicy
its breast with its little fist, and on its unavenged tears to found that edifice, would you agree
to be architect on those conditions, tell me and tell me truly? (Dostoevsky (), )
Alyosha admits that he would not agree to be such an architect. Ivan sees himself
therein justified: a moral person would not accept the job, yet the believer would
worship the God who does that same job. Thus the believer’s position is
untenable, at once approving and disapproving of the architect’s plan. There is no
doubt that this moral objection has been powerful and influential, (see Sutherland
() ).
Ivan Karamazov and the free-will defence
Ivan’s moral objection is related to the free-will defence since in the latter,
God’s creation of free creatures is claimed to necessarily entail such a logical
limitation of his omnipotence (since creatures cannot be simultaneously free and
determined) that the creation of humans entails the possibility that they will
choose to do evil.
Thus conceived, God’s decision to create the cosmos, including humans,
entailed the possibility of horrendous moral evils. In Ivan’s words, he chose to be
that architect. There is a difference between Ivan’s account and the free-will
defence, since Ivan’s characterization of God’s decision involves the direct
instrumentalization of a horrendous evil. However, in the free-will defence,
(granting a weak characterization of omniscience with regard to future events), the
horrendous evil is not ‘necessary and unavoidable’, but rather a possibility.
Nevertheless, one might argue this difference is not significant. If we imagine that
Ivan’s attack in the passage quoted above talked of a bliss bought with the
price of the state of affairs such that the torture of a child was a possibility, then
God, portrayed as an architect taking risks into account, might equally well be
deemed to have taken an immoral risk. The structural parallel between moral
rejection of the free-will defence and Ivan’s rejection of the architect’s job is
therefore nevertheless strong. Ivan rejects the architect’s job and believes we
should therefore reject the God who supposedly took on that job – for moral
reasons.
Ivan Karamazov and Schopenhauer
Given the parallel between God’s reasons in the free-will defence and
in Ivan’s characterization, it follows that Ivan shows great affinity with
Schopenhauer. It is not that Ivan necessarily accepts Schopenhauer’s glum
description of pleasure as the mere absence of suffering or would agree with his
striking claim that even any amount of suffering would mean it would be better if
we humans had never been (see Janaway () ). However, by rejecting the
architect’s job, Ivan effectively endorses a similar pessimism about this world as it
is, since, according to Ivan, given the existence of one child who endured
horrendous suffering, it would be better that the world had never been.
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 54.157.246.241, on 09 Jan 2017 at 13:32:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034412513000164
SAMUEL SHEARN
It is clear that Ivan, on the basis that the connection between humanity’s bliss
and horrendous evils could be a necessity, rejects humanity’s bliss. Therefore, he
would also, on the basis of a connection between humanity’s existence and
horrendous evils, reject humanity’s creation.
If our analysis thus far has been correct, moral anti-theodicy is equivalent to
philosophical pessimism. If the anti-theodicist is to criticize least ambitious
theodicies on moral grounds, she should take this corollary into consideration.
The morality of moral anti-theodicy
The further question remains whether (assuming the free-will defence is
true) the pessimism which moral anti-theodicy entails is itself moral.
Since moral anti-theodicy rejects the affirmation of life on moral grounds
(we might call it ‘moral pessimism’, a morally demanded pessimism), two objections are pertinent. First, moral pessimism is over-demanding, asking that the
moral outrage at incidences of suffering so colour our perception of all of reality as
to render human existence on balance harm. This is analogous to the overdemandingness we identified earlier: the sorrows of horrendous evils become a
black hole for any joys we may experience. But why should such a moral maxim be
justified in determining our way of seeing the world?
Second, a moral commitment to pessimism undermines the basis of that said
commitment to pessimism. The moral position which objects so strongly to the
horrendous evils which befall any child must be grounded in the deep conviction
that that child’s life should go well and that it is otherwise worth living. The antitheodicist, to be so opposed to the suffering, must affirm the value of life greatly. Yet
she would appear to jettison that value as soon as she expresses moral pessimism.
It cannot be immoral to affirm life. This deconstruction is a sort of reductio
against moral anti-theodicy. It follows from this that it is self-contradictory for
humans morally to criticize a theodicy which invokes an ‘all-or-nothing’ scenario
and imagines God to be faced with the choice between creation (including the
possibility of horrendous evils) and no creation. We might also argue that we have
no reason to imagine that we should be able to pass judgement upon the morality
of the creation of the universe, since such a judgement would encompass an
estimation of all value in the universe, which is far beyond our capabilities.
This is not to say that least ambitious theodicies which posit an ‘all-or-nothing’
scenario are necessarily true, or that these are the only low-ambition theodicies
available. However, it does suggest that for this sort of theodicy, a commitment to
anti-theodicy could be better described as aesthetic rather than as straightforwardly moral, expressing different ways of seeing the world.
Theodicy as personal navigation
This is illustrated well by considering Hick’s response to Ivan’s challenge.
Hick recognizes the weight of the objection that the horrendous suffering of one
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 54.157.246.241, on 09 Jan 2017 at 13:32:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034412513000164
Moral critique and defence of theodicy
child would be too high a price to pay for the eschatological perfection of all
things. He concedes that, being faced with horrendous evils himself, he might find
himself sharing Ivan’s response (see Hick (), ). Nevertheless (writing in
), Hick says he has not faced such tragedy which causes despair and thus his
experience makes credible for him a way of seeing the world which lets him believe there is hope and that life is ‘part of a long and slow pilgrim’s progress’ (ibid.).
One could argue that Hick neglects to meet Ivan’s challenge directly and see the
implications for the project of theodicy it entails. Ivan does not give his negative
answer as a result of his own suffering, but on account of reports of the severe
sufferings of children quite unrelated to him. It is the possibility of human
empathy, of beginning to understand the depths of an innocent child’s sufferings,
which precludes Ivan’s acceptance of a cosmic redemption of suffering. Yet Hick
does not bring this to bear in his theodicy, which, by his own admission, only
makes sense of his personal experience.
This could be characterized by an anti-theodicist as selfish disregard of others.
However, given what we have said about the over-demandingness of antitheodicy, we should reject the condition that to be moral, we must enter into every
other person’s experience of suffering and give it due weight, since this is an
impossible duty to fulfil.
Mark Scott, in conversation with sociologists of religion, characterizes theodicy
as a ‘meaning-making’ activity (Scott (), ), ‘the pursuit of cosmic coherence
and personal meaning in the face of evil’ (ibid., ). He emphasizes that theodicy
is a personal process of navigation which is as unique as each person’s biography
(see ibid., ).
The claim that one’s personal navigation of evil and way of seeing the world
should be dominated and determined by horrendous evils is over-demanding,
and overlooks the fact that we are all personally involved in our theorizing and
have vested self-interest. If we give credence to Scott’s characterization, a religious
anti-theodicist response such as Phillips’s is no less a pursuit of coherence and
meaning for the theorist before God than Hick’s.
In defence of the anti-theodicist project, it would indeed be callous not to begin
to give the sufferings of others due weight. We would not consider a person moral
who gave the anti-theodicist imperative against the trivialization of suffering no
serious thought and application. However, this does not make (least ambitious)
theodicies immoral, for the reasons we have explored above.
Conclusion
My conclusions concerning ambitious theodicies are that such theodicies
necessarily trivialize suffering – the putative goods said to emerge from evils are
unacceptable to the sufferer because they are not evident and the notion of a
separate theoretical context for theodicies is inconceivable.
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 54.157.246.241, on 09 Jan 2017 at 13:32:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034412513000164
SAMUEL SHEARN
Although it may be an intellectual virtue to be detached and pursue reasons for
God’s allowing particular evils, the ambitious theodicist who undertakes her study
with the aim of assisting those made unsure of their religious beliefs by the
problem of evil might find her benevolent effort to be in vain. While anti-theodicist
suspicion of theodicist motives is uncharitable and backfires because it is morally
over-demanding, ambitious theodicists do unwittingly cause sufferers harm by
trivializing their suffering and therefore should consider desisting from the
production of ambitious theodicies.
When considering least ambitious theodicies, which portray God’s decision to
create as an ‘all-or-nothing’ scenario, the moral parallel between anti-theodicy
and pessimism renders anti-theodicy untenable as a moral position and means
anti-theodicy might be better characterized as a way of seeing the world.
With a view to future work, I conclude that despite these theoretical considerations which morally vindicate least ambitious theodicists, such theodicists
who agree with the arguments made in this essay should nevertheless consider
exploring the question whether portraying God as a moral agent with reasons
might not ultimately undermine theism’s moral and aesthetic attraction and
render the procured religious comfort unrecognizable to the sufferer.
References
ADAMS, M. M. () Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God (Ithaca NY: Cornell University Press).
() ‘Ignorance, instrumentality, compensation and the problem of evil’, Sophia (forthcoming), [online].
Available at: http://link.springer.com/article/./s--- [accessed on March ].
ADORNO, T. W. () Negative Dialectics, E. B. Ashton (tr.) (London: Routledge).
BENATAR, D. () Better never to have been: The Harm of Coming into Existence (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
BUBER, M. () I and Thou, rd edn, W. Kaufmann (tr.) (Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark).
DAVIS, S. T. () ‘Critique of D. Z. Phillips’, in S. T. Davis (ed.) Encountering Evil: Live Options in Theodicy new edn
(Louisville KY: Westminster John Knox), –.
() ‘Truth and action in theodicy: a reply to C. Robert Mesle’, American Journal of Theology and Philosophy,
, –.
DOSTOEVSKY, F. () The Karamazov Brothers, tr. with an Introduction and Notes by D. McDuff (London: Penguin).
FORREST, P. () ‘Why Richard Swinburne won’t “rot in hell”: a defense of tough-minded theodicy’, Sophia,
, –.
GAWRONSKI, I. & PRIVETTE, G. () ‘Empathy and Reactive Depression’, Psychological Reports , –.
GOODIN, R. E. () ‘Demandingness as a virtue’, Journal of Ethics, , –.
HART, D. B. () The Doors of the Sea: Where was God in the Tsunami? (Grand Rapids MI: Eerdmanns).
HICK, J. () ‘D. Z. Phillips on God and evil’, Religious Studies, , –.
() Evil and the God of Love, Reissue (London: Palgrave Macmillan).
JANAWAY, C. () ‘Schopenhauer’s pessimism’, in C. Janaway (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Schopenhauer
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), –.
LACAPRA, D. () ‘Trauma, absence, loss’, Critical Inquiry, , –.
MCDUFF, D. () ‘Introduction’, in F. Dostoevsky, The Karamazov Brothers, tr. with an Introduction and Notes by
D. McDuff (London: Penguin), xiii–xxix.
MACKIE, J. L. () ‘Evil and omnipotence’, in M. M. Adams & R. M. Adams (eds) The Problem of Evil (Oxford:
Oxford University Press), –.
MARQUARD, O. () ‘Entlastungen: Theodizeemotive in der neuzeitlichen Philosophie’, in O. Marquard (ed.)
Zukunft braucht Herkunft: Philosophische Essays (Stuttgart: Reclam), –.
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 54.157.246.241, on 09 Jan 2017 at 13:32:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034412513000164
Moral critique and defence of theodicy
NIELSEN, K. () ‘Linguistic philosophy and “the meaning of life” ’, in E. D. Klemke & S. M. Cahn (eds) The Meaning
of Life: A Reader, nd edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press), –.
PHILLIPS, D. Z. () The Problem of Evil and the Problem of God (London: SCM Press).
PLANTINGA, A. () ‘God, evil, and the metaphysics of freedom’, in M. M. Adams & R. M. Adams (eds) The Problem of
Evil (Oxford: Oxford University Press), –.
SACHS, C. B. () ‘The acknowledgement of transcendence: anti-theodicy in Adorno and Levinas’, Philosophy and
Social Criticism, , –.
SCHEFFLER, S. () ‘Morality’s demands and their limits’, The Journal of Philosophy, , –.
SCOTT, S. M. () ‘Theorizing theodicy in the study of religion’, in The Religion and Culture Web Forum, Chicago
Divinity School. [online]. Available at: www.divinity.uchicago.edu/martycenter/publications/webforum//
Theorizing%Theodicy%.pdf [accessed March ], –.
SIMPSON, R. M. (a) ‘Moral antitheodicy: prospects and problems’, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion,
, –.
(b) ‘Some moral critique of theodicy is misplaced, but not all’, Religious Studies, , –.
SØVIK, A. () ‘Why almost all moral critique of theodicies is misplaced’, Religious Studies, , –.
() ‘More on moral critique of theodicies: reply to Robert Simpson’, Religious Studies, , –.
STIVER, D. R. () ‘Still too high a price? Ivan’s question in the light of contemporary theodicy’, in J. E. Barnhart (ed.)
Dostoevsky’s Polyphonic Talent (Lanham MY: University of America Press), –.
SURIN, K. () Theology and the Problem of Evil (Oxford: Blackwell).
SUTHERLAND, S. () Atheism and the Rejection of God: Contemporary Philosophy and ‘The Brothers Karamazov’
(Oxford: Blackwell).
TRAKAKIS, N. () ‘Theodicy: the solution to the problem of evil, or part of the problem?’, Sophia, , –.
VAN INWAGEN, P. () ‘The problem of evil’, in W. Wainwright (ed.) The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Religion
(Oxford: Oxford University Press), –.
WILLIAMS, R. () ‘Redeeming sorrows’, in D. Z. Phillips (ed.) Religion and Morality (London, Palgrave Macmillan),
–.
Notes
. Simpson, writing in defence of theodicies, distinguishes three arguments for the immorality of theodicy:
‘insensitivity’, ‘detachment’, and ‘harmful consequences’. These correspond broadly to Kantian, virtue
ethical, and consequentialist concerns respectively. (Simpson (a), ). However helpful the
distinction may be, these are all complementary perspectives on the same issue, as Simpson recognizes.
Therefore the charge of trivialization shall function as our characterization of anti-theodicy in the
understanding that it captures that which is at the heart of all three perspectives.
. Another way of describing the moral at the heart of the charge of trivialization is that suffering should
be acknowledged, rather than merely known about (see Sachs (), f.).
. I submit that this thought-experiment is flawed in this regard, since there would be no appropriate
moment to offer an obviously false theodicy.
. Peter Forrest makes a related claim, misconstruing anti-theodicists as somehow objecting to talking
about suffering because it is too recent or graphic (see Forrest (), ). This is impossible, since
anti-theodicists refer at length to the horrendous experiences of physical and mental suffering in the
past. The insensitivity rebuked by anti-theodicists concerns not giving the experience of those suffering
central place. Forrest does nothing to address this concern.
. Another objection might be made that a moral proscription of theodical discourse would make
determining the moral status of theodicies impossible, because in order to ban something one would
have to be able to describe it. At least some theoretical discussion of the problem of evil seems
unavoidable, even if one is to ascertain the immorality of theodical discourse.
. It is worth noting that in this judgement, Simpson’s argument resembles some of Phillips’s arguments.
Phillips also argues that many theodicies present God as an immoral agent by human standards and
are thus immoral to endorse. Søvik disagrees; he thinks that only God, and not the theodicist, would be
immoral (see Søvik (), ).
. There is also a logical reason for thinking that the quest for meaning does not admit a third-person
explanation as an answer, but is rather an example of a ‘limiting question’ (see Nielsen (), –)
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 54.157.246.241, on 09 Jan 2017 at 13:32:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034412513000164
SAMUEL SHEARN
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
whose only ‘answer’ could be the help and comfort of another agent. Unfortunately I cannot explore
this further here.
Odo Marquard argues that theodicy, as a product of the modern era, was only made possible by being
suitably distanced from suffering. In the presence of suffering, ‘theodicy is never the problem; the only
important thing is the ability to stand the suffering and sympathy – the condition of being able to bear
with, help and comfort’ (Marquard (), ).
Scheffler argues that when a moral theory presents itself as being over-demanding, we should defer to a
less demanding theory which is liveable, given the limitations of human psychology (see Scheffler
(), ). Goodin is sceptical about such a general response; moral demands should not be
diminished: this would make morality dependent upon our behaviour, instead of being its critical
instance. However, most relevant to our concerns about anti-theodicy, even Goodin concedes that there
are limitations on the human psyche which should be taken into account, since a moral theory ‘can be
“too demanding of our strictly limited attention”, leaving no scope for attending to the projects, plans
and purposes that comprise our own lives’ (Goodin (), ).
The depth of Dostoevsky’s feelings about children’s suffering is underlined when one considers that
during his planning of the novel Dostoevsky’s two-year-old son died of epilepsy (see McDuff (),
xiii).
Mackie claims that God could have created free humans who nevertheless always choose the good (see
Mackie (), ), but we will assume for the sake of argument that the free-will defence overcomes
this objection, as Plantinga claims (see Plantinga (), ). Furthermore, we have not mentioned
natural evils, which present a challenge to the free-will defence. However, we are not concerned with
the veracity of the free-will defence, or a thorough account of it. We are merely exploring its moral
structure, assuming it is true.
This point is also made by Stiver, albeit without reference to Schopenhauer or philosophical pessimism
(see Stiver (), f.).
D. Z. Phillips spends some time considering the conceptual confusion of the free-will defence (see
Phillips (), and ), but if he also rejects it morally (while granting its coherence for argument’s
sake), then this would appear to commit Phillips to ‘denying God’s justification for creating the human
race’ (Hick (), f.), i.e. to pessimism. However, Phillips is happy to talk about a morally legitimate
religious response being ‘gratitude for existence’ (Phillips (), ). Adams also picks up on this
‘pragmatic tension’ (Adams (), ).
There is a related debate amongst those reflecting on the work of reconciliation following genocidal
trauma. Some would resist the notion of reconciliation and ‘working-through’ as not doing justice to
individuals’ experiences. Yet, as Dominick LaCapra writes, ‘[i]t is dubious to identify with the victim to
the point of making oneself a surrogate victim who has a right to the victim’s voice or subject-position’
(LaCapra (), ). Anti-theodicists might consider whether they are as equally opposed to
post-genocidal reconciliation narratives for not giving due attention to the terrible suffering involved.
For a recent defence of such pessimism, arguing that it would have been better if humans had never
existed (and thus favouring human extinction for moral reasons), see Benatar ().
Peter Forrest’s objection to moral critique of God finds no error in proposing a ‘tough-minded theodicy’
(Forrest (), ), since God, omnisciently recognizing the partial ordering of morality as a brute fact,
cannot have regrets ‘if some are sacrificed for others. By human standards . . . God is a moral monster
and not to be imitated’ (ibid., ). He then makes a repeated moral appeal against the supposed
human hubris of imitating God (ibid., , f., , ). Our objection here is related, but different. We
are not objecting theologically, but epistemologically.
Here I am using the terms ‘aesthetic’ and ‘moral’ in distinction from each other and suggest that a
certain way of seeing the world cannot be labelled immoral in a deontological sense. However, I realize
that it is not straightforward to make such a clear distinction between morality and aesthetics.
As Rowan Williams remarks, ‘theology can only point to its fundamental belief in a God who is faithful
and eternal, and say, “if there is hope, it lies there”. If it knows its business, it will not want to go much
further’ (Williams (), ).
Downloaded from https:/www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 54.157.246.241, on 09 Jan 2017 at 13:32:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https:/www.cambridge.org/core/terms. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034412513000164