Chapter FiFteen
On time and eternity in messiaen
BenediCt taylOr
i aspire towards eternity, but i’m not suffering while living in
time, all the less so since time has always been at the centre
of my preoccupations. as a rhythmicist, i’ve endeavoured
to divide this time up and to understand it better by dividing
it. Without musicians, time would be much less understood.
Philosophers are less advanced in this ield. But as composers,
we have the great power to chop up and alter time.1
messiaen’s interest in time and eternity is frequently cited,
and approaches to understanding his music from the perspective of
its temporality are all-pervasive. One might justiiably claim that
to appreciate his music at all one must understand it in light of its
relationship with time, a relationship which arguably differs from that of
much earlier Western music.2 yet such a complex and multifaceted topic
as time does not admit easy consideration, and the precise nature of the
time and eternity invoked in messiaen scholarship is not always clear.
Both terms, for instance, have multiple, often quite distinct deinitions,
and as a result commentary on his music from this perspective is liable
to become confusing if these concepts are insuficiently deined. It is
also unclear as to what extent this musicological discourse is based on
demonstrable attributes of messiaen’s music, or draws rather upon his
own comments on it, and if from the latter, the epistemological validity
of these. the present chapter appraises the views on time messiaen
professed, their relationship to his music, and to subsequent accounts
of his music. it does not seek to provide a detailed analysis of his
music from a temporal perspective (a topic already covered in some
detail), but focuses rather on the use of philosophical conceptions of
time and their applicability to messiaen’s music.
Chapter FiFteen
257
I Conceptions of Time and Eternity
Messiaen’s views
Given how ubiquitous discussions of messiaen’s music from
the perspective of its temporality are, one might expect to ind within
them a reasonably clear deinition of the notion of time. Such a demand
is on one level unjust, as time is a concept notoriously intractable to
deine. “What is time?”, St Augustine famously mused–“Provided
that no one asks me, i know. if i want to explain it to an inquirer,
I do not know”–and Messiaen himself left the pointed remark cited
above as to the superiority of a musical, as opposed to philosophical,
understanding of time.3 the topic may be approached from differing
philosophical, theological, physicist and psychological perspectives,
and even within each discipline (let alone between them) there is
no overall consensus as to a correct viewpoint. yet it is relatively
straightforward to align the composer’s own understanding of time
to the philosophical position termed reductionist or relational. this
position, taken by messiaen primarily from aquinas, sees time after
Aristotle’s deinition as “the measure of motion”, “the number of
movement in respect of the before and after”.4 time is not the same
as movement, but the two are interdependent; by implication, without
any movement or change in the universe there can be no time. this
deinition is traditionally opposed to an absolute conception (such
as that found in classical newtonian physics), which sees time as
an external, independent entity.5 messiaen’s reductivist temporal
perspective certainly lends itself more immediately to the possibility
of a musical manipulation of time, in that (putting to one side for the
moment potentially problematic niceties of cognitive perception)
differing types of rhythmic movement or stasis would, on the face
of it, appear to have a higher epistemological status as constituting a
genuine manipulation of time within a conception which sees time as
dependent upon movement.
Growing out of this conception of the contingent nature of
time is the particular notion of eternity that messiaen holds. eternity
is not something often considered as a concept, and thus it is not
always appreciated that there are two quite distinct notions that can
be indicated by this word. First, eternity may imply ininity of time,
everlasting duration, something without beginning or end. this may be
contrasted with timeless, unchanging extra-temporal being, something
258
On time and eternity in messiaen
outside and not measurable by time. despite the etymological root of
the term eternity implying the irst concept (aevum, time or age), the
term “sempiternity” is often used to distinguish the former notion of
ininite duration from the second one of timeless eternity. This second
deinition of eternity is characteristic especially of religious and
mystical thought, and is that with which messiaen concerns himself.
This is clariied at the start of the Traité de Rythme, de Couleur et
d’Ornithologie, through citation of aquinas’ consideration of the
distinction between time and eternity: “Eternity and time are two
absolutely different measures of duration.” “Eternity is simultaneously
whole. But time has a ‘before’ and an ‘after’.”6 Similarly, in the
conversations with Claude Samuel, this viewpoint is ampliied:
all of God’s creations are enclosed in time, and time is one of
God’s strangest creatures since it is totally in conlict with his
eternal nature, he who is without beginning, without end, without
succession.7
And speaking of the Quatuor pour la in du Temps, messiaen
elaborates
i did not want in any way to make a commentary on the book
of revelation, but only to justify my desire for the cessation of
time.…for the ending of concepts of past and future: that is, for the
beginning of eternity….my initial thought was of the abolition of
time itself, something ininitely mysterious and incomprehensible
to most of the philosophers of time, from plato to Bergson. 8
It is clear then, that the notion of ininite time is antithetical
to messiaen’s own thought. time has a beginning and an end, being
created (and ultimately ended) by God, who exists outside time,
unchanging and immutable.
Problems of mixed temporal conceptions in scholarship
messiaen’s own position, particularly with regard to his
conception of timeless eternity, is often recognised by commentators
on his music. it should be emphasised that this perspective on time
is not necessarily the only one applicable to his music, indeed that
it is not necessarily correct as a theory, but it is certainly what the
composer professes, and any account that seeks to interpret his music
Chapter FiFteen
259
in terms of his own beliefs should take account of this. yet even given
the well-known statements by messiaen aligning his conception of
eternity with atemporal, timeless being, messiaen scholars are at
times liable to mix the two conceptions without further clariication of
the differences involved. Paul Grifiths, in the introduction to a work
that thematicises messiaen’s relationship to time, speaks in the same
paragraph of the stasis and iconic being of messiaen’s music and then
of the “image of eternity” produced by “the long time it must take” for
the completion of rhythmic cycles and the possibility of their “constant
repetition”.9 the temporal sempiternity of the latter, however, has little
in common with the atemporal eternity implied by the former and
messiaen’s religious beliefs. timothy Koozin, too, after contending
that “it is important to understand Messiaen’s rhythmic processes in
the context of his religious thought”, goes on to speak of “Time itself,
undifferentiated and ininite”–a conception that Messiaen could not
have shared.10 Even Robert Sherlaw-Johnson, who correctly notes the
distinction between these two types of eternity, similarly conlates the
idea of endless repetition of long temporal cycles with the timeless
eternal.11
these accounts cited are generally sensitive explorations
of messiaen’s music, and the conceptions of time and eternity that
underlie these statements are not necessarily false, but it is undeniable
here that conceptions of time that are inimical both to messiaen’s
stated beliefs and to each other are often mixed or at least unclearly
interchanged. the sense of extremely long durations (approaching a
sense, negatively perceived, of potential everlastingness) can be used
metaphorically for sempiternity, but this is not strictly speaking the
eternity that messiaen’s religious belief can sustain.
part of the problem lies with messiaen’s own statements,
which do seem liable for confusion.
When we say ‘God is eternal’, do we think about the signiicance
of these words? ‘God is eternal’ signiies not only that he
will never end, but that he never had any beginning. here is
where the temporal notions of ‘before’ and ‘after’ encumber
us. to conceive of something without a beginning absolutely
overwhelms us.12
this is not actually incompatible with timelessness, but
260
On time and eternity in messiaen
certainly gives more the impression of speaking of everlasting time.
and surely the notion of something existing outside time is more
overwhelmingly dificult to comprehend than something without
a beginning?13 Similarly, speaking of the Quatuor, the composer
blends spatial and temporal metaphors and the eternal, ininite and
atemporal:
its musical language is essentially immaterial, spiritual and
Catholic. modes which achieve a kind of tonal ubiquity,
melodically and harmonically, here draw the listener towards
eternity in space or the ininite. Special rhythms, beyond metre,
contribute powerfully in dismissing the temporal.14
The recourse to symbol
a noticeable feature of writing on messiaen and time is,
indeed, how often particular features are spoken of through metaphors
or attributed symbolic qualities, where the precise nature of the
relationship is not clear. a result of this lack of clarity is that the
metaphors or symbols used do not always it the purported meaning as
much as is sometimes assumed. a case in point is the connection often
made between eternity and the circle (or more precisely, something
of which circular properties are predicated). Circular movement,
even its everlasting repetition, does not necessarily imply timeless
eternity; the relational view of time taken from aristotle and aquinas
sees time as generated from the circular rotation of the heavens, and
indeed Aristotle’s account, the irst extended consideration of the topic
in Western philosophy, views this as sempiternal, without beginning
or end.15 Only in a weak sense in the latter is the cosmos as a whole
eternal in a non-temporal sense, as being immutable.16 Still, it has been
suggested that circular or cyclical processes may be in some sense
akin to messiaen’s eternity in that before and after, or cause and effect,
appear mixed.17 as messiaen claimed concerning nonretrogradable
rhythms, this creates “a certain unity of movement…where beginning
and end are confused because identical”.18 and at one level, since
the movement described in a circle is complete and self-contained,
one could argue at a symbolic level that such circular movement
might imply a view of the totality of time from the perspective of an
atemporal observer (God) outside time and space, without being itself
strictly timeless. however, the connection here is still weaker than is
Chapter FiFteen
261
often assumed.
Such use of metaphor and symbol in discussing Messiaen’s
music is well established, and arguably appropriate concerning
its relation to an intended religious meaning, as a relection of the
impossibility of speaking directly of things above and beyond our
limited standpoint.19 as aquinas argued, it is in the nature of God and
eternity to be deined negatively: “As God, although incorporeal, is
named in Scripture metaphorically by corporeal names, so eternity,
though simultaneously whole, is called by names implying time
and succession.”20 after all, messiaen’s endeavour in such works as
the Quatuor pour la in du Temps is rather paradoxical–attempting
to express the inexpressible, representing the unrepresentable, the
atemporal through a medium that is essentially concerned with time.
in eternity there can be no music.21
What our experience of an unchanging eternity might
actually be like, and whether this is indeed a desirable state, is also
not self-evident. messiaen speaks of the duration of consciousness in
eternity:
regular time moves towards the future–it never goes
backwards. psychological time, or time of thought, goes in all
directions: forward, backwards, cut in pieces, at will…in the
life of the resurrection we will live in a duration malleable and
transformable. the ability of the musician, who retrogrades and
permutes his durations, prepares us, in a small way, for that
state.22
the psychological duration spoken of by messiaen (considered
at greater length in the next section) implies at least some internal
change, which suggests the passing of time–itself incompatible with
the eternity posited. yet the alternative, duration without change, also
presents conceptual dificulties.23 the writer and philosopher miguel
de Unamuno, a Catholic and proto-existentialist, considered at length
the idea of eternity, concluding that although the idea of annihilation
was terrifying, the only idea of a changeless eternity one could conceive
from our worldly terms of reference was almost equally frightening in
its apparent deadly boredom.24 it would, perhaps, be uncharitable to
messiaen to suggest that the effect of some of his music gives rise
to a similar feeling, yet the apparent virtue of changelessness seems
262
On time and eternity in messiaen
in need of reconsideration when presented within the terms of time
and space. nevertheless for a religious believer we should withhold
logical objections to this idea of eternity drawn from the phenomenal
world, to the extent that such a hypothetical state transcends any
conceptualisation. aquinas himself (against the beliefs of most
philosophers, prior and subsequent), attempted to argue that emotions
such as delight were not in their essence temporally contingent, and by
implication that participation in the eternity of the resurrected could
be one of enduring joy.25
Such contradictions are neatly encapsulated in Messiaen’s
oft-quoted “charm of impossibilities”.26 roberto Fabbi puts it nicely in
his claim that “all of Messiaen’s work is profoundly characterised by a
yearning of something, which is the music, towards something else…
‘the leap outside time’…unobtainable for the living…. Since music is
the stuff of the living, it is what it is, precisely because what it yearns
for is unobtainable–the charm of a metaphysical impossibility.”27
however, our inability to conceptualise fully such religious claims and
the recourse to metaphor and symbol does not mean that all metaphors
and symbols are appropriate to this music or the religious truths it is
claimed to convey.
II Issues concerning the phenomenology of time
Messiaen’s theoretical positions
an important question not yet addressed concerning
messiaen’s understanding of time is whether it is an external, objective
aspect of the world or an internal aspect of consciousness. From this
question stem wider issues concerning the phenomenology of certain
temporal characteristics he attributes to his music–in other words, to
what extent they are available to audible perception, or, as seen with
the symbolic aspects discussed above, are intellectual conceits that
speak more to the composer or analyst than listener.
a statement messiaen makes early in the Traité suggests a
broadly Kantian view of time as being, with space, a necessary form
of apprehending the world: subjective in the sense that it is within us,
objective in that it is an a priori condition of perception–we can never
have access to anything without it.
Chapter FiFteen
263
time and space are intimately related. their perception is of great
importance for the construction of human consciousness. they
are the two intellectual instruments that permit our construction
of the world. For the musician and rhythmician, the perception of
time is the source of all music and all rhythm. a musician must
be a rhythmician….He should reine his sense of rhythm by a
more intimate knowledge of experienced duration, by the study
of different concepts of time and different rhythmic styles.28
this demonstrates as well how messiaen views time
from multiple perspectives–in the Traité running successively
through biological, relative (einsteinian), superimposed, quantum,
physiological and psychological time. With the exception of the brief
foray into quantum time (that conlicts with much else), the general
emphasis is on the relative nature of all these times, largely consistent
with the reductionist interpretation indicated before. Such plurality is
an accurate relection of the complexity and multifaceted nature of the
topic, yet is also rather confusing in trying to grasp messiaen’s beliefs
and justiications more precisely. Such an assortment of theories
inevitably contains internal inconsistencies and mutually incompatible
viewpoints, and messiaen’s exegetical writing, both in his substantial
consideration of time in the Traité and throughout his life, relects
these tensions.
at the largest level, messiaen aligns himself with the theories
of henri Bergson, who assumes in the Traité an importance greater
than any other philosopher (including aquinas). Following Bergson,
messiaen divides time into subjective durée réel or durée vécue–“real”
time, heterogeneous, qualitative, immeasurable; and objective temps
espace or mathematique–homogenous, quantitative, measurable,
seen after Bergson as an abstraction or spatialisation of real time.
On one occasion (pp. 11-12) messiaen suggests the former should
be called duration (durée) and the latter time (temps), though this is
inconsistently applied and indeed conlicts with much of his writing
elsewhere. despite the composer’s (and Bergson’s) focus on the
former, it is the latter that is most important for realising many of the
temporal properties messiaen attributes to his music. it is arguable,
indeed, that messiaen confuses Bergson’s two types of time throughout
his consideration of musical temporality; at the very least, he uses
incompatible terms interchangeably, and readily subsumes subjective,
264
On time and eternity in messiaen
experienced time into its opposite, abstract time, with problematic
consequences for attempting to make sense of his pronouncements on
music’s temporality.
Problems of rhythmic perception in Messiaen’s theories
We recall that for Messiaen, “the perception of time is the
source of all music and all rhythm”; Andrew Shenton has called this
“both a statement of fact and a statement of compositional philosophy,
and as such it is of paramount importance to any engagement with
Messiaen’s music.”29 it is also clear that for the composer such
perception is equivalent to Bergsonian experienced time: the idea
messiaen proposes that the silence after a note sustains its duration
is evidently not an objective feature of music, and he spends some
time detailing how different modes of attack or articulation may affect
the perception of chronometrically equal durations. “Experienced
duration is not measurable” he concludes, following Bergson.30
messiaen’s entire theory of rhythm, however, depends upon an
abstract, homogenous, measurable and numerable time. and rhythm,
as the composer is keen to stress, is “the irst, essential element in
music”. If musical perception, as occurring in heterogeneous durée
vécue, is free from measure, messiaen’s conception of rhythm can
play no part in our audible experience of his music.
the one place where messiaen appears to try to address this
apparent contradiction is in the inal section of the consideration of
time in the Traité (“Temps Bergsonien et Rhythme Musical”, pp. 3136). here messiaen notes Bergson’s view of the capacity of the human
mind through memory to spatialise past events heard in experienced
time, thus enabling their numeration (pp. 32-33). this, messiaen seems
to take it, suficiently justiies the unmediated turning of experienced
time into its opposite, abstract time, and thus the heterogeneous and
immeasurable into the homogenous and measurable. through this
equating of opposites, he is able to move freely between antithetical
concepts. yet the argument given by Bergson does not go as far as this
proposal would suggest.
Bergson adduces his example of the striking of a clock to
demonstrate how we can numerate the events perceived in internal
durée, thus partially spatialising it and to this extent turning our
Chapter FiFteen
265
heterogeneous, subjective real time into an abstract type of time that
approximates space.31 this is not quite the same as the retrospective
subdivision of past musical durations into multiples of a ixed smallest
unit that messiaen proposes. numeration of events is not equivalent
to ixing a durational value to each. Messiaen’s contention already
presupposes an underlying regularity of time (if not, a basic unit could
not be used to measure longer note durations), which is especially
problematic given that he himself has stated how note durations that
are equal when measured by clock-time can appear dissimilar to
perception depending upon the type of attack or articulation used.32
put simply, measuring a non-homogenous medium with a nonhomogenous unit will not result in a meaningful value.
this reducing of duration to number is evident in a wellknown comment messiaen made on the birth of time and rhythm,
which has rightly been seen as problematic. this quotation contains
several pertinent features illustrating messiaen’s views on time: on the
initude of time (its creation); its interdependence on movement (the
beat–the event that establishes change); on rhythm as the comparison
of duration.
The irst, essential element in music is Rhythm, and Rhythm is
irst and foremost the change of number and duration. Suppose
that there were a single beat in all the universe. One beat; with
eternity before it and eternity after it. a before and after. that
is the birth of time. imagine then, almost immediately, a second
beat. Since any beat is prolonged by the silence which follows
it the second beat will be longer that the irst. Another number,
another duration. that is the birth of rhythm.33
“Time and duration: two words treated as synonymous, often
used interchangeably. philosophers, however, strongly oppose this
and establish them practically as opposites.”34 After having irst
professed their difference, messiaen goes on to identify them once
again. duration here becomes interchangeable with number. For
messiaen’s listener, it appears, every subjective duration must be
spatialised, numerated, turned into what he claims is its opposite,
abstract mathematical time.
messiaen’s contention of audible rhythmic subdivision seems
only the more ambitious when it is taken into account that the listener
266
On time and eternity in messiaen
encountering his music is not presented with a simple two-note
rhythmic unit heard on its own with ample time to numerate its rhythm
(as in the Traité) but with an ongoing succession of highly complex
musical rhythms, often superimposed. even a relatively simple passage
of messiaen surely presents an information overload if needing to be
processed in the manner the composer advocates, let alone something
like the epode to Chronochromie. “Rhythm is a matter of intelligence;
the more perfect the human brain becomes, the more one will be able
to use complex rhythms”, Messiaen would claim. “One will be able
to appreciate more easily the difference between very short values of
only slight divergence, and, more dificult, between very long values
of only a slight divergence. everyone can achieve this with patience
and study.”35 this seems optimistic. to be sure, it is quite possible that
messiaen’s rhythmic irregularities may be perceived qua irregularity
by the listener, but this is likely to be in a qualitative sense as a general
feeling of metric irregularity (heard against the cultural expectations
drawn from previous metrically regular music), not as something
that can be easily quantiied and numerated in the manner Messiaen
suggests.36
Problems of Time and Symbol
the disparity between time as messiaen believes it is perceived
and how he presents it as an attribute of his music is further noticeable
in the numerous comments he left concerning the ability of a composer
to manipulate the direction of time. a typical example:
the musician possesses a mysterious power: by means of his
rhythms, he can chop up time here and there, and can even put
it together again in the reverse order, a little as though he were
going for a walk through different points of time, or as though
he were amassing the future by turning to the past, in the process
of which, his memory of the past becomes transformed into a
memory of the future.37
practically, this can be taken as referring to technical procedures
such as palindromes (“non-retrogradable rhythms”) and symmetrical
permutations that are found within messiaen’s music. a procedure
for which the term retrograde may be used evidently has something
to do with going backwards. Similarly, a non-retrogradable rhythm
Chapter FiFteen
267
is one that is the same backwards as forwards. Such orientation can
easily be represented spatially, on paper. yet the precise relationship
of these with time–especially if time is something messiaen is rather
ambiguous in deining–is more complicated.
music is not in time, but rather time is in music…the
rhythmician…has the advantage of moving at will through the
past and the future, and of chopping time up by retrograding and
permutating it.38
at face value, this statement is consistent: if time is in
music, then rearranging musical order in some sense could be
thought of as rearranging temporal order. the idea is undoubtedly
attractive. however, as soon as one begins to question how this music
is perceived, either within the terms of reference messiaen provides
or indeed outside these, this notion rapidly becomes more fraught.
most commentators are understandably hesitant to assign too great
an audible reality to such techniques, preferring instead to focus on
their symbolic qualities.39 But Messiaen, as we have seen, ascribes an
unrealistic amount to the capacities of his listener and is somewhat
coy in acknowledging the purely metaphorical or symbolic nature of
these techniques.
Recall again that for Messiaen “the perception of time is the
source of all music”; if time perception is a precondition for music, it
now arguably becomes circular to suggest that time is in the medium
that requires it for its very perception. time is assumed to be an
internal part of consciousness in the latter quotation, yet something
external in the former. at the very least, it would be more reasonable
to suggest that if the perception of time is the source of all music,
music is to this extent in time.
the best solution to this impasse is probably to recall that
for messiaen there are different types of time–here the internal time
of consciousness (Bergson’s durée), the external time of musical
events, and an abstract, mathematical time that allows the numeration
of external events and durations for consciousness (which assumes
greater importance for his thinking than messiaen admits). musical
temporality might therefore be created from the interaction of these
different times; that the precise relationship between them is unclear
268
On time and eternity in messiaen
is understandable given the complexity of the subject. however,
messiaen does not actually say this, or clarify why he needs to cite so
many different types of time without divulging their relationship.
messiaen’s writings are also contradictory in that although
in the quotations above the word time (temps) is used, elsewhere he
uses this same idea interchangeably with duration (durée)–as we have
seen, supposedly an internal, non-measurable continuity of conscious
states. in the Traité, for instance, he states, for the musician, duration
[durée] is a weapon, by which he attacks and convinces the listener”,40
and similarly, in the passage from the Third Tome cited earlier, “The
ability of the musician, who retrogrades and permutes his durations
[durées], prepares us, in a small way, for that state [of eternal life].”41
First, if by durée messiaen means something like Bergson’s
durée vécue (as it would seem given his discussion earlier in the
Traité), this is incapable of being chopped up: it is continuous and
unique to each listener. if, rather, he implies the perception of differing
durations of external events by a perceiving subject, these are still heard
(according to Bergson’s phenomenology) as subject to successive
presentation, with no apparent indication of implied reversal. even
repetition, in the strict sense, is impossible for durée, as the internal
experience of a repeated external event is modiied the second time
in light of the irst. In our subjective, experienced time, everything is
evolving, accumulating.42 a palindrome is not heard as a palindrome.
it is only a palindrome on paper, or when removed from time by being
spatialised in consciousness.
it is the same with his claims of chopping up and reordering
time. messiaen proceeds as if each differentiable musical event had its
own ordinal position according to a hypothetical regulative diachronic
succession, which remains with the recurrence of this event, even when
this succession is reordered. i.e., for the events that can be ordered:
{1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8}
when subject to symmetrical permutation from the centre, are
subsequently heard as:
{5, 4, 6, 3, 7, 2, 8, 1}
But it is highly questionable whether musical events are
Chapter FiFteen
269
audibly marked as bearing an order like this. this is particularly
the case with messiaen’s music, in distinction to that of earlier
composers. as a consequence of having excluded such features as
metre, functional harmony, thematic development and other culturally
determined tropes of phrasal position (such as generic opening
or closing gestures) from playing a signiicant role in his musical
language, and by further dissociating rhythm from other musical
parameters through the use of isorhythm, messiaen’s music is largely
without potential aural markers of temporal position.43 in other words,
there is little sense of an underlying putative true temporal order to
have as a reference against which to judge the temporal reordering,
in the way that previous common-practice Western music arguably
had, or indeed literary and cinematic narrative has.44 messiaen quite
effectively removes the sense of causality and temporal progression
from his music, but as a consequence cannot easily play it off against
any perception of reordering.
the only real means for determining such a referential order is
by allotting a numerical order to the musical events in the score and
following their manipulations. this chops up time in a symbolic way,
but at such an abstracted level that it has more or less nothing to do
with time as most of us understand it, and certainly not how (and as)
we experience it. how the listener can be attacked, let alone convinced
by these procedures, remains unclear. essentially, despite professing
his allegiance to Bergson, the reality of the internal experience of
time and its relative, qualitative nature (both subjectively and across
nature), messiaen appears to reduce time and duration here to no more
than a spatialised quantum, an abstract pattern of semiotic relationships
on paper. Stefan Keym, in a thorough and detailed survey, concludes
that “Messiaen’s mirror-image reversal of time is a purely symbolic
art and represents a clear-cut paradigm of the surrender to spatial
categories that Bergson denounced, which are irreverent for subjective
experience.”45 ironically the time messiaen manipulates has little to
do with real time.
III Audible and Abstract aspects of musical time in
Messiaen’s music
despite the inconsistencies of his claims for the audible
apprehension of certain temporal conceits in his music, messiaen
270
On time and eternity in messiaen
also leaves a more realistic admission of their probable perceptual
feasibility. in the Traité he notes the changing importance of different
modes of temporal understanding dependent upon the manner of his
music’s perception. the cognition of duration for the listener in a
concert hall is a mixture of mathematical and psychological time, he
holds, whereas the score-reader, able to repeat the music at will, is able
to “overcome all dificulties.”46 Following this distinction, one may
distinguish between temporal features that form part of the listening
experience and those that are more abstract, symbolic, accessible
largely or indeed wholly through study of the musical score.47
the compositional techniques messiaen uses to convey an
audible sense of temporality different from that of much preceding
Western music have been amply documented in scholarship.48 these
include the enlargement of harmonic vocabulary accompanied by
the weakening of harmonic grammar (i.e., the non-functional use
of harmonic progressions); a sense of melodic/harmonic stasis
emanating from the equidistance resulting from the use of symmetrical
pitch collections (Messiaen’s “modes of limited transposition”);
the downplaying of thematic working characteristic of culturally
embedded notions of development and organic growth; heterophony
or the superimposition of different rhythmic layers in place of
counterpoint; freedom from metre and other hierarchical systems
of temporal ordering; the construction of non-progressive forms
emphasising symmetry and enclosedness; and the seeming arbitrary
succession of sections characteristic of what would later be termed
“moment form”.
many of these features make their effect in conjunction; for
instance, the freedom from metre, functional harmony and thematic
development all contribute to downplaying the sense of temporal
directionality obtained in previous Western music through the fusion
of these different parameters.49 though much attention has been
devoted in this paper to appraising theoretical claims of eternity
and timelessness, one should note how much of messiaen’s music
is actually concerned with the expression and defamiliarisation of
different senses of time, rather than the impossible search for eternity.50
Andrew Shenton recognises this quality in quoting Rowan Williams’
observation that if music “is the most contemplative of the arts, it is
not because it takes us to the timeless, but because it obliges us to
Chapter FiFteen
271
rethink time.”51
Abstract or symbolic aspects of musical time
Operations such as the retrograding and symmetrical permutation
of musical material are perfectly reasonable ways of reordering
temporal events, but their relationship with time is only present at a
purely intellectual, abstract level.
regular time moves towards the future–it never goes backwards.
psychological time, or time of thought, goes in all directions:
forward, backwards, cut in pieces, at will.52
This “psychological time” uses the intellectual capacity for
memory to reorder events occurring (or conceived) within a regulative
diachronic series. By spatialising in a mental conception events that
may be played in diachronic time, a synoptic view of the music is
obtained in which all events are rendered synchronic, to the extent that
they are equally present to the imagination, in which connections can
be formed based on criteria other than temporal succession, and which
therefore to this extent also lies outside time.
these views on the intellectualisation of music, its use to
deny its own time, recall Claude lévi-Strauss’s famous claim that
music is an instrument for the “obliteration of time.” “It follows that
by listening to music, and while we are listening to it, we enter into
a kind of immortality.”53 there is the embrace of a certain platonic
quality here that suits messiaen’s theoretical ideas better than Bergson
does (who strives against this platonic spatialising, though never
denies its existence). however, one must note that what messiaen
does is not quite as intriguing as that which is observed in the music
considered by his contemporary; lévi-Strauss is here speaking of the
spatialisation of something perceived through temporal experience,
that which appears in time being transformed into something supratemporal. these conceits of messiaen’s are, on the other hand, not
audibly perceptible in the irst place, being far more abstract; a more
relevant paradigm is of something perceived non-temporally being
viewed supra-temporally.
For the philosopher J.E. mctaggart, notions of change with
272
On time and eternity in messiaen
respect to an event being successively in the future, present and past,
are fundamental to what we mean as time; by implication, any account
of time that does not include these features does not speak of time.54
mctaggart goes on to suggest that, given internal inconsistencies in
any adequate deinition of time, time is unreal. (This thesis remains
controversial; however, despite over a century of debate, it has not been
satisfactorily refuted.) it is dangerous to insist on a comprehensive
deinition of time, but the intellectual apprehension of Messiaen’s
palindromes and permutations certainly has little to do with the low
of time mctaggart speaks of. in claiming that the perception of time
is the source of all music, messiaen is in danger of negating part of his
own music’s claim to being music. From this statement, if something
is not to do with time, it is to this extent not music. to the extent
then that messiaen’s music is to do with time, these procedures have
little to do with either time or hence his music’s musicality. although
a sceptic could easily argue that messiaen’s ideas on time are
confused and his claims for his music’s mastery over time are often
devoid of any demonstratable meaning, we could, however, choose
conversely to connect this very lack of temporal characteristics with
the timelessness he ardently seeks, just as mctaggart understands the
purported unreality of time not in a negative light but as part of a long
line of mystical, religious and philosophical thought that views time
as the phenomenal appearance of a supra-temporal nouminal reality.55
Just as we have seen that there can be no music in eternity, to the
extent that this part of messiaen’s music is not temporal, is it therefore
eternal?
the answer is not necessarily so: the non-temporal is not eo
ipso identiiable with the eternal. To claim that non-temporal attributes
can be predicated of messiaen’s music does not necessarily mean that
it is to this extent eternal. a lack of distinct temporal characteristics
need not indicate God’s eternity so much as something that simply
has nothing to do with time, such as the proposition that the internal
angles of a triangle add up to 180°, though they certainly can be
viewed from this perspective if one wishes. But for Messiaen, the
existence of properties belonging to an essentially temporal object
that demonstrate a freedom from being tied to concepts of before and
after might just constitute the eternity in which he believes.
lévi-Strauss, in his consideration of music, concludes that “the
Chapter FiFteen
273
musical creator is a being comparable to the gods, and music itself the
supreme mystery of the science of man.”56 messiaen, similarly, sees
the composer as a demi-god, standing above the phenomenal time of
the musical work. the totality of the musical work in the composer’s
mind is akin to the eternity of God:
is not the composer-rhythmician a little demiurge, with total
control over his work that is his creation, his microcosm, his
child, his object? He knows in advance all the pasts and futures,
which are all simultaneously present to his consciousness, is
able to transform the present so that it grasps the past or future,
and rearrange before and after.…he can push his research in all
ways offered by inversions or permutations of durations, forward
motion, retrograde motion, movement from centre to extremes,
from extremes to centre, and innumerable other movements that
make a mockery of old Father time.57
the analyst is similarly able to conceive the whole as a synchronic
totality, understand the symbolic reversals and permutations, though
will not be able to realise new potential futures in the manner that the
composer during the creation of the work could. But by implication,
the listener without recourse to the score is often caught in time in the
same manner as humans.
messiaen’s theoretical exegesis of time and temporality in
his music is undeniably confusing. This mystiication is relected in
accounts of his music, which often draw upon the composer’s lessthan-transparent commentary. much of the problem is merely due
to the sheer diversity of sources he draws on, which are inevitably
contradictory. Aristotelian / Thomist time as “the number of
movement” does not it with Bergsonian durée réel, and the continuity
of these (and ininite divisibility of the former), along with relativity,
jars with the positing of a quantum time particle (chronon), even
though the latter suits messiaen’s rhythmic thought and suggests for
him an example, however ininitesimal in size, of duration outside
time, without change or before and after, the timeless being he sees
as a property of God.58 it is clear that messiaen is happy to cherrypick theories that appear to suit one aspect of his music’s temporality,
without building what could ever form a philosophically coherent
system. From a sympathetic perspective one could say that perhaps
any one rational system is incapable of fully explaining the temporality
274
On time and eternity in messiaen
of music; like God’s creation, philosophers, theologians, scientists can
create theories of time that are true for some aspects for his music
but false for others. a more sceptical view, however, can easily be
imagined.
The other problem is the inherent dificulty one encounters in
attempting to understand time and eternity. Writing about music and
time holds potential dangers, most obviously that this relationship may
well not be capable of suficient formulation in words; therein lies one
of the attractions of music. messiaen’s contention that music can reveal
aspects of temporality that philosophy (and by extension, discursive
thought) cannot dream of is not an unreasonable proposition,59 and to
this extent one has to wonder whether messiaen would not have been
better served leaving his unwieldy intellectual justiications to one side.
yet any separation of musical meaning into a purely musical essence
and an accidental surrounding discourse is nonetheless problematic,
and the lengths to which messiaen goes in order to explain his music
in words (especially in his marshalling of philosophy, theology and
science into his service) suggest his own ambivalence on this issue.60
as a consequence, speaking of time in music, and examining the
way the question of temporality in messiaen’s work has been treated
in verbal discourse, is a legitimate activity, though it should not be
forgotten that this may well not exhaust the meaning of his music–
only provide a cautionary note as to how we may speak of it.
Notes
1. Claude Samuel, Olivier Messiaen: Music and Colour. Conversations with
Claude Samuel, trans. e. thomas Glasow (amadeus press, portland Or,
1994), 34.
2. Paul Grifiths has gone so far as to claim that the denial of the “forwardmoving time” found in Western music since the Renaissance “is the generative
and fundamental substance of Messiaen’s music”. Paul Grifiths, Olivier
Messiaen and the Music of Time (ithaca, n.y.: Cornell University press,
1985), 17.
3. augustine, Confessions, Xi.xiv (17) [trans. henry Chadwick (Oxford:
Oxford University press, 1998), 230]. the absence of augustine from
messiaen’s considerations of time and eternity is surprising, not only given
Chapter FiFteen
275
the common religious perspective but also due to the importance of augustine
as a thinker on these issues (greater than aquinas, who unsurprisingly draws
on him).
4. aristotle, Physics, iV, 11 (200a34 & 25-26), translation taken from The
Complete Works of Aristotle, ed. Jonathan Barnes, 2 vols. (Princeton:
princeton University press, 1984), i:374 & 373. aquinas’ account of time,
derived principally from Aristotle (though signiicantly differing on the notion
of eternity), can be found in the Summa Theologica, i 10.4. messiaen uses
Aquinas’ deinition in his Traité de Rythme, de Couleur et d’Ornithologie,
tome i (paris: a. leduc, 1994), 7-9. a quotation from the geologist pierre
termier on p. 18 of the Traité further serves to support the reductionist idea
of the interdependence of time, space and movement, and messiaen’s appeal
to einstein’s relativity (pp. 14-17) is clearly incompatible with the opposing
newtonian conception of absolute time.
5. Cf. isaac newton, Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica, trans.
Andrew Motte, rev. Florian Cajori, 2 vols. (Berkeley: University of California
Press, 1934), 1:7: “Absolute, true or mathematical time, of itself, and from
its own nature, lows equably without relation to anything external, and by
another name is called duration: relative, apparent, and common time, is some
sensible and external (whether accurate or unequable) measure of duration by
the means of motion, which is commonly used instead of true time; such as an
hour, a day, a month, a year.”
6. messiaen, Traité, i:7; aquinas, Summa Theologica, i 10.4. aquinas’ thesis
is in turn derived from Boethius (The Consolation of Philosophy, V/6), itself
indebted to plotinus (Enneads, 3.7.3).
7. Samuel, Olivier Messiaen: Music and Colour, 34.
8. Goléa, Recontres avec Olivier Messiaen (Paris: Juilliard, 1960), 64, 70.
9. Grifiths, Olivier Messiaen and the Music of Time, 16.
10. Timothy Koozin, ‘Spiritual-temporal imagery in music of Olivier Messiaen
and toru takemitsu’, Contemporary Music Review, 7/2 (1993), 193; also cf.
194.
11. Robert Sherlaw-Johnson, ‘Rhythmic Technique and Symbolism in the
music of Olivier messiaen’, in Messiaen’s Language of Mystical Love,
ed. Siglind Bruhn (New York: Garland, 1998), 127 (cf. 139 note 17): “The
background rhythm of Liturgie de crystal, taken to its logical conclusion, can
be taken to be symbolic of eternity (especially if one considers that it could
then be subject to endless repetition); in using only an incomplete portion of
the whole process, messiaen is giving us a glimpse into eternity. the eternal
is brought into the world, into time”. Endless repetition of temporal cycles is
sempiternity, not atemporal eternity; a inite fragment of the sempiternal is
just time.
12. Samuel, Olivier Messiaen: Music and Colour, 28.
13. messiaen indicates this latter point in the Traité (i:33), using h.G. Wells’
thought-experiment of an instantaneous three-dimensional cube (i.e. one
existing in space but not in time).
276
On time and eternity in messiaen
14. messiaen, preface to miniature score of Quatuor pour la in du Temps
(paris, durand, 1942).
15. aristotle, On the Heavens, ii.1 (283b27-29); Physics, Viii.1 (251b11-28).
16. Cf. On the Heavens, i.9 (279a18-279b3), ii.1 (284a11-12); Physics, iV.12
(221b3-4).
17. See Mareli Stolp, ‘Messiaen’s Approach to Time in Music’ (MMus
Dissertation, University of Pretoria, 2006), 15; Eleanor F. Trawick, ‘Order,
progression, and time in the music of messiaen’, ex tempore, 9/2 (1999),
<http://www.ex-tempore.org/Volix2/trawick/index.html>.
18. messiaen, The Technique of My Musical Language, 2 vols. trans.
John Satterield (Paris: Leduc, 1956), 1:21. The unspeciied assumptions
concerning the perceptual experience necessary for this statement to be true
will be explored in the following section of this paper.
19. See on this point especially Camille Crunelle Hill, ‘Saint Thomas aquinas
and the theme of truth in messiaen’s Saint François d’Assise’, in Messiaen’s
Language of Mystical Love, ed. Siglind Bruhn (New York: Garland, 1998),
143-67, and Jean Marie Wu, ‘Mystical Symbols of Faith: Olivier Messiaen’s
Charm of impossibilities’, in ibid., 85-120. recent development of metaphor
theory would suggest that metaphorical description is indeed an intrinsic part
of all language use.
20. aquinas, Summa Theologica, i 10.1. also see i 10.3, where the loosely
metaphorical use of the word eternal to describe long inite durations of time is
indicated: “some things are called eternal in Scripture because of the length of
their duration, although they are in nature corruptible; thus (ps. 75:5) the hills
are called ‘eternal’”. His argument, however, seems more designed to defend
the validity of the loosely worded Biblical text, rather than a recommendation
for subsequent practice.
21. Cf. aquinas, Summa Theologica, III sup. 77.4, ‘Whether the resurrection
will happen suddenly or by degrees’, who points out that “all sound is
measured by time” (Ob. 3) and that therefore the resurrection cannot occur
before the last note of the trumpet of the apocalypse.
22. messiaen, Traité de Rythme, de Couleur et d’Ornithologie, tome iii
(paris: alphonse leduc, 1996), 353-54.
23. this notion of immutable duration does admittedly have a long pedigree,
being present in plato’s theory of forms (Timaeus 37d; cf. Deinitions 415a),
and attested to again in a different manner later in the passage from aristotle
cited previously: “this word ‘duration’ [αἰών] possessed a divine signiicance
for the ancients.…the fulilment of the whole heaven…which includes all
time and ininity, is duration–a name based upon the fact that it is always [αἰεὶ
ὤν]–being immortal and divine.” On the Heavens, i.9 (279a22-27), Complete
Works, 463. One could note that this notion its the semantic correlate of
duration as indicating ‘to endure’, in this case enduring perfectly without
change, though (as with aristotle) it is hard to conceive this as not being
within time (i.e., the lack of change of the enduring object is relational to an
external environment that is subject to temporal change).
Chapter FiFteen
277
24. miguel de Unamuno, Del sentimiento trágico de la vida en los hombres y
en los pueblos (Madrid: Alianza Editorial, 1986), ch. 10.
25. aquinas, Summa Theologica, ii.i 31.2. the point has also been raised as to
why silence does not play a greater part in messiaen’s music, since this would
seem to bear a closer relationship to aural stasis than music (even though taking
this idea to its ultimate conclusion would obviously result in the negation
of music as conventionally understood). in this context one could note that
Aquinas holds that “although immobility is simply nobler than movement,
yet movement in a subject which thereby can acquire a perfect participation
of the divine goodness is nobler than rest in a subject which is altogether
unable to acquire that perfection by movement.” (Summa Theologica, iii.sup.
91.2 reply to ob. 10.) By implication, music (motion) is better than silence
(immobility), especially when it attempts to glorify God or reach this end.
26. Olivier messiaen, Technique de mon langage musical (paris, alphonse
leduc, 1944), 5.
27. Roberto Fabbi, ‘Theological Implications of Restrictions in Messiaen’s
Compositional processes’, in Messiaen’s Language of Mystical Love, ed.
Siglind Bruhn (New York: Garland, 1998), 81. Messiaen himself confessed
“One thing alone is important to me; to rejoin the eternal durations and the
resonances of the above and beyond, to apprehend that inaudible which is
above actual music…Naturally, I shall never achieve this.” ‘Who Are You,
Olivier Messiaen?’, interview with Bernard Gavoty, Tempo, 58 (1961), 36.
28. messiaen, Traité, i:9.
29. Andrew Shenton, ‘Observations on time in Olivier Messiaen’s Traité’,
in Olivier Messiaen: Music, Art and Literature, ed. Christopher dingle and
Nigel Simeone (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2007), 173.
30. messiaen, Traité, i:9
31. henri Bergson, Time and Free Will: An Essay on the Immediate Data of
Consciousness, trans. F.l. pogson (london, 1910), 86.
32. messiaen himself elaborates upon this following his discussion of rhythmic
subdivision (Traité, i:33).
33. messiaen, Conférence de Bruxelles (paris: leduc, 1958). this claim seems
impossible. Since there are no events in this universe apart from the beats
messiaen conceives, there is no external calibration against which to measure
them; the duration spoken of must either be internal, subjective, or absolute
in a newtonian sense. although the claim for the prolongation of a beat
by silence implies a subjective conception of duration (and if a provisional
eternity follows the last beat, this cannot be measured by abstract time),
subjective duration cannot be numbered. Ian Darbyshire claims “there is a
confusion of ideas here”: “the deinition of rhythm is actually identical to the
deinition of time”, and that given the distinction between eternity and time
Messiaen makes, eternity “cannot be numbered an antecedent or consequent
of change in relation to that single beat” (‘Messiaen and the Representation
of the theological illusion of time’, in Messiaen’s Language of Mystical
Love, ed. Siglind Bruhn (New York: Garland, 1998), 42). Messiaen might
278
On time and eternity in messiaen
have some defence on the latter point in aquinas (Summa Theologica, i 46.1
reply to Objection 8), though this is certainly a contentious matter. robert
Sherlaw-Johnson similarly suggests that what the composer really means here
is the birth of duration; a third beat would need to be added for this situation
to constitute rhythm (‘Rhythmic Technique and Symbolism’, 121; also see
139).
34. messiaen, Traité, i:11-12 & 9.
35. ‘Who Are You, Olivier Messiaen?’, 35.
36. Cf. anthony pople, Messiaen: Quatuor pour la in du Temps (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1998), 4, who speaks of “the slower perceptible
[metric] beat, which is delightfully uneven”.
37. almut rössler, Contributions to the Spiritual World of Olivier Messiaen,
with Original Texts by the Composer, trans. Barbara Dagg, Nancy Poland and
timothy tikker (duisberg: Gilles and Francke, 1986), 41.
38. pierrette mari, Olivier Messiaen (Paris: Seghers, 1965), 59.
39. See Sherlaw-Johnson, ‘Rhythmic Technique and Symbolism’, 13638; Roberto Fabbi, ‘Theological Implications of Restrictions’, 60-61;
Paul Grifiths, Olivier Messiaen and the Music of Time; Andrew Shenton,
Olivier Messiaen’s System of Signs: Notes Towards Understanding His
Music (aldershot: ashgate, 2008). a good example is ian darbyshire in
‘Messiaen and the Representation of the Theological Illusion of Time’, who
wisely omits Bergson from his discussion. His emphasis on an alternative
hypothetical connection between music and out innate mental construction of
the world in temporal and spatial terms is a better argument for messiaen’s
music as constituting a truly theological activity (although the grounding
in etymological kinship is speculative). a sympathetic interpretation of this
discrepancy via the philosophy of Gilles Deleuze is also given by Amy Bauer,
‘The impossible charm of Messiaen’s Chronochromie’, in Messiaen Studies,
ed. Robert Sholl (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), 159-67.
40. messiaen, Traité, i:21
41. messiaen, Traité, iii:353-54.
42. Cf. Bergson, Time and Free Will, 200: “duration is something real for
the consciousness which preserves the trace of it, and we cannot here speak
of identical conditions, because the same moment does not occur twice.”
messiaen appears to be aware of this notion (cf. Traité, i:22), though does not
take it into account in conjunction with the rest of his temporal theories.
43. For illustration of this point, the pun with temporal order haydn achieves
in the opening of the String Quartet Op. 33 No. 5, where the irst phrase is
introduced by a closing gesture that returns at its end, thus questioning its
initial position further, is more-or-less impossible for messiaen.
44. Such as is found, for instance, in the early novels of William Faulkner or
ilms of Alain Resnais. This is also the case with the time travel thematicised
in h.G. Wells’ The Time Machine, which messiaen on more than one occasion
cites as comparable for his music.
45. Stefan Keym, Farbe und Zeit: Untersuchung zur musiktheatralen Struktur
Chapter FiFteen
279
und Semantik von Olivier Messiaens Saint Francois d’Assise (hildesheim:
Olms, 2002), 238. Ch. 4, ‘Musikalische Zeit’, especially pp. 232-330,
provides an excellent overview of messiaen’s beliefs on musical time within
his historical context. instead of Bergson, Keym proposes Armand Cuvillier
(also cited by Messiaen) and Gaston Bachelard (not cited) as more appropriate
thinkers for the composer.
46. messiaen, Traité, I:32. As we have seen, the dificulties for the former
seem greater than the composer would admit. Still, at least he appears to admit
here, however obliquely, that he might be ascribing simply too much for the
capacities of the average concert-goer. messiaen’s ideal listener is the scorereader.
47. the division is not absolute; some aspects (such as isorhythms) may have
a symbolic-hermeneutic character and yet arguably affect the aural perception
of musical temporality, and the degree to which abstract features also have a
basis in sonic perception obviously depends on the capabilities of the listener.
Still, it is hardly too presumptuous to suggest that such features as symmetrical
permutations are rarely, if ever, directly perceived by listeners.
48. See Grifiths, Olivier Messiaen and the Music of Time, esp. 15-18; diane
Luchese, ‘Olivier Messiaen’s Slow Music: Glimpses of Eternity in Time’
(phd diss., northwestern University, 1998), esp. ch. 2; Keym, Farbe und
Zeit, 248-59; Sherlaw-Johnson, ‘Rhythmic Technique and Symbolism; Iain
G. Matheson, ‘The End of Time: A Biblical Theme in Messiaen’s Quatuor’,
in The Messiaen Companion, ed. peter hill (london: Faber and Faber, 1994),
esp. 236-42; Stolp, ‘Messiaen’s Approach to Time in Music’; Trawick, ‘Order,
Progression, and Time in the Music of Messiaen’; Anthony Pople, ‘Messiaen’s
musical language: an introduction’, in The Messiaen Companion, ed. peter
Hill (Portland, OR: Amadeus Press, 1995), 15-50; Jonathan D. Kramer, The
Time of Music: New Meanings, New Temporalities, New Listening Strategies
(new york: norton, 1988), esp. 213-17.
49. See on this point Grifiths, Olivier Messiaen and the Music of Time, 15-18,
Keym, Farbe und Zeit, 249-50.
50. the connection with the philosophy of Gilles deleuze is particularly
apparent on this point, whose account of music seems highly (and almost
solely) relevant for Messiaen. See Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, A
Thousand Plateaux (vol. 2 of Capitalism and Schizophrenia), trans. Brian
Massumi (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987), ‘1837: Of the
refrain’, 342-86.
51. Shenton, ‘Time in Olivier Messiaen’s Traité’, 174.
52. messiaen, Traité, 3:352.
53. Claude lévi-Strauss, The Raw and the Cooked (Le Cru et le cuit,
Mythologiques vol. I) trans. John and Doreen Weightman (Chicago: University
of Chicago press, 1983), 16.
54. John Ellis McTaggart, ‘The Unreality of Time’, Mind, 68 (1908), 458-67.
the comparison between the two–mctaggart’s theory and messiaen’s music–
is not precise, as mctaggart purports to demonstrate that time itself is unreal
280
On time and eternity in messiaen
as contradictory, whereas it is only the fact that certain of messiaen’s claims
for the temporality of his music are contradictory (not other aspects of his
music, or other music, or time itself), that is under discussion here.
55. McTaggart, ‘The Unreality of Time’, 457.
56. lévi-Strauss, The Raw and the Cooked, 18.
57. messiaen, Traité, i:28
58. messiaen, Traité, i:27.
59. the belief that music is able to convey meanings not articulable in words
and is as such instructive for philosophy has been viewed in a positive light
by philosophers since the early 19th century; Bergson himself uses music
to explain his philosophy of durée, rather than vice-versa. Andrew Bowie
considers music’s importance for philosophy in his recent Music, Philosophy
and Modernity (Cambridge: Cambridge University press, 2007); similarly,
from a theological perspective, see Jeremy Begbie, Theology, Music and Time
(Cambridge: Cambridge University press, 2000).
60. in this sense, it is pointless trying to argue what our appreciation of
messiaen’s music would be like without the extra-musical context the
composer provided: such notions as the Catholic religion, time, eternity and
colour are an integral part of its cultural meaning. i would guess, however,
given the culturally ingrained expectations drawn from most previous Western
music, that messiaen’s work would be more often perceived in a negative
light if this different relationship to time had not been verbally articulated and
understood as a framework for its understanding.