Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

The Shape of Things

2013, Reviews in Cultural Theory

T h e Sh ape of Thi ngs SAM HAN Peter Sloterdijk. Bubbles: Spheres Volume I: Microspherology. Trans. Wieland Hoban. Semiotext(e), 2011. 664pp. F or anyone even remotely interested in philosophy, when a igure sets out to “correct” Heidegger, you want to pay attention. his is not necessarily out of admiration for the author of Being and Time, or his ideas, but rather out of a genuine curiosity made up of equal parts amazement and horror. he interest would be compulsory, akin to intellectual rubbernecking, for it is more than likely that he or she, the subject of such an utterance, will, like Heidegger, be vulnerable to intense scrutiny and interpretation. herefore, when MIT Press describes the much-anticipated Spheres trilogy by Peter Sloterdijk as “the late-twentieth-century bookend to Heidegger’s Being and Time,” there is reasonable expectation for it to be disastrous. Ever since the English translation of his he Critique of Cynical Reason in 1988, Sloterdijk has been known in English-speaking intellectual circles as somewhat of a mercurial igure. Not much, still, is known about him. From where, that is, what intellectual milieu or tradition, did he emerge? Is he a Frankfurt guy? Is he a Luhmannite? Is he Heideggerian? he rather out-of-nowhere character of Sloterdijk’s work, as well as the inconsistent reception of his work outside a handful of watchers of developments in continental philosophy and social theory, placed Sloterdijk in the category of “heard of him” (otherwise known as “oh right, he wrote that one thing”) in North American cultural theory. But Sloterdijk’s trajectory difered tremendously in his native Germany. When copies of Cynical Reason started leaving the shelves at a rapid pace upon its release, the then-journalist was boosted into the highbrow German intellectual scene traditionally illed with academics. Today, we can count Sloterdijk among the country’s public intellectuals, a group that also includes luminaries like Jürgen Habermas and Axel Honneth (more on these two later). Sloterdijk is also host to a show called “Das Philosophische Quartett” (he Philosophical Quartet), which airs on ZDF, the German equivalent to PBS in the United States or NHK in Japan. It features Sloterdijk alongside guests of various intellectual pedigrees, from academics to journalists. More recently, Sloterdijk has made himself known among the wider American reading Reviews in Cultural heory Vol. 4, Issue 1. Copyright © 2013 Sam Han. 56 SAM HAN public for a controversy involving welfare state politics, class, ressentiment and Axel Honneth. As a blog post on the Global Post summarizes: According to an article published this past summer in one of Germany’s most widely read newspapers, the country’s welfare state is a “iscal kleptocracy” that has transformed the country into a “swamp of resentment” and degraded its citizens into “mystiied subjects of tax law.” he text, by philosopher Peter Sloterdijk, goes on in that vein for some 3,000 words[…] Among the country’s intellectual class, the article has served as kindling for a iercely fought and wide-ranging conversation about the national economy that, six months on, still shows little sign of abating. (Abadi) he article, entitled “Die Revolution der gebenden Hand” (“he Revolution of the Grasping Hand”), must be read as a polemic. While it includes some semblance of genealogical (in the Foucauldian sense) analysis of the modern democratic welfare state, its primary purpose is to ofend. He begins with a meditation on the birth of the democratic state as the compromise between classical liberalism and anarchism, each of which was amenable to the declining signiicance of the state. For liberalism, the state needed to be minimal and imperceptible to its subjects, the citizens. For anarchism, the state needed to be destroyed. Hence, the “modern democratic state gradually transformed into the debtor state, within the space of a century metastasizing into a colossal monster—one that breathes and spits out money” (Sloterdijk, “he Grasping Hand”). For a Europe that is currently under much economic turmoil, and with a Germany that is currently embroiled in a national debate, hinging in large part on a parochial stance toward Southern Europe as iscally irresponsible debtees, about whether to “bail out” Greece and Spain, this article, for many of its critics, amounted basically to “piling on.” Further, according to its critics, it preyed on extant, albeit latent, nationalist sentiment, which culminated in the infamous book by hilo Sarrazin, which all but placed the entirety of Germany’s economic woes on its immigrants. his was the context for the retort by Honneth, one of the last remaining lag bearers of the Frankfurt School. here he accused Sloterdijk of, among many things, being an ideological mouthpiece for advanced capitalism, “a mystical or speculative [interpreter] of history and the world,” and, rather strangely, a reader of Michel Foucault.1 1 While most of this exchange never made it to English-language publications, much of it has been chronicled on blogs. See Gregersen, homas. “Axel Honneth Versus Peter Sloterdijk.” Political heory - Habermas and Rawls. 26 Sept. 2009. Web. 25 Sept. 2012; Shingleton, Cameron. “he Great Stage: Axel Honneth: Against Sloterdijk (Die Zeit, 24 September, 2009).” he Great Stage. 11 Feb. 2010. 25 Sept. 2012. he Shape of hings 57 he gist of Honneth’s critique, which I cannot fully assess in this space, is that Sloterdijk has taken ressentiment as “irst psychology” of the lower classes and has attempted to pull the rug from up under the very foundations of European liberal democracy— the welfare state—by criticizing it. I bring up Honneth’s public spat with Sloterdijk in order to portray a picture of the latter that presents not only his prominence in the German intellectual scene but also his embattled public image. While Sloterdijk may only recently be gaining mass recognition in North America, he has, in Europe, at least, been a visible presence for the past two decades or so. For Sloterdijk, the problematic of inhabitation is that which courses through the veins of Western metaphysics and philosophy. he “old cosmology of ancient Europe,” as he calls it, “that rested on equating the house and home with the world,” can be seen in even the disparate philosophies of Hegel and Heidegger. Humans in this view were “inhabitants in a crowded building called cosmos”(Sloterdijk, “Spheres heory”). As it was for his most obvious predecessor, Gaston Bachelard, the motif of the house—signifying order, unity and certainty—is one that unduly holds too much purchase in the West. For Sloterdijk, the Enlightenment should have dispelled the need for a “universal house in order to ind the world a place worthy of inhabiting” (Ibid.). Yet, it remains, thanks in part to philosophers such as Heidegger, whose selfproclaimed task to “end metaphysics” as such did not do away with the, if we can call it something, the “metaphysics of the universal house.” Sloterdijk’s project, therefore, in his three-volume study called Spheres, is to forge a path beyond Heidegger, by providing a general theory of “associations.” For Heidegger, the overarching question of metaphysics was temporal—with the keywords “being” and “becoming.” For Sloterdijk, it is spatial; the keyword is “world.” While it is the case that Sloterdijk views Heidegger to have been wrong all along, there is something about the current technological, socio-political moment that has occasioned a particular response. Sloterdijk writes: It’s the inal stage of a process that began in the epoch of Greek philosophical cosmology, and whose present vectors are rapid transportation as well as ultrahigh-speed telecommunication. At the same time, it’s the product of a radical disappointment, whereby human beings had to abandon the privilege of inhabiting a real cosmos—which is to say, a closed and comforting world. he cosmos, such as the Greeks conceived it, was the totality of being imagined under the form of a great, perfectly symmetrical bubble. Aristotle and his followers were responsible for this idea of a cosmos composed of concentric, celestial spheres of increasing diameters, the majority of which consisted of a hypothetical material they called ether. For us, this model of the world is obviously no longer operational. (Sloterdijk, “Foreword to the heory of Spheres” 223) 58 SAM HAN In response to this “inoperability,”2 Sloterdijk ofers a “spherology,” beginning from the micro, which is the subject of volume I of Spheres entitled Bubbles, all the way to the macro, the subject of volume III, entitled Foams. Sphere, for Sloterdijk, does not assume a totality or inality as the phenomenologically inlected “lifeworld” or “world” entails. As he puts it rather paradoxically, “the primordial existential sphere is created every time a moment of inter-psychic space happens” (Sloterdijk, “Foreword to the heory of Spheres” 223–224). Against the weight of “existence,” Sloterdijk puts forth a succession of events, of happenings, wherein meaningful and signiicant connections are made but do not sufocate. Hence, the microspherology he presents in Bubbles, the volume under review, is, at root, a theory of “atmosphere” or as he likes to say, of “air.” He chooses these ethereal metaphors as he believes that spheres, the closest Heideggerian cognate being Stimmung (more on this later), “never speak but…brings everything together and makes everything possible…a treasure that that allowed human beings to realize the fact that they’re always already immersed in something almost imperceptible and yet very real, and that this space of immersion dominates the changing states of the soul down to its most intimate modiications”(Sloterdijk, “Foreword to the heory of Spheres” 225). he development of this “spatial vocabulary” is necessary, therefore, because the concept of “world” is simply too bulky to do anything analytically. “Sphere” works better for several reasons. For one, it is more in tune with the development of modernity, which is characterized by “the increasing removal of safety structures from the traditional theological and cosmological narratives” (Sloterdijk, Bubbles 25) that used to provide human subjectivity with a degree of ontological security by providing human beings a place in the world, which was ixed, identiiable and orientating. Yet, these “safety structures” in the form of “worlds,” according to Sloterdijk, remained. While the emergence of the Figure of Man, allowed for humans to become the subject and object of knowledge, the “empirico-transcendental” as Foucault so rightly put it, it did not mean the complete “end of metaphysics.” It just diverted the sublimated energy. “People,” Sloterdijk precisely notes, “no longer wanted to receive their inspired ideas from embarrassing heavens”(Sloterdijk, Bubbles 28). Instead of God, these ideas came from within, so to speak, albeit mediated via technology, which relected the “distance between what God was capable of in illo tempore and what humans will, in time, themselves be capable of ” (37). Hence, supposedly secular models of subjectivity that emerged in the wake of the scientiic revolutions of Galileo, Copernicus and later Newton, nonetheless remained closely tied to the imago Dei. he image of man as God simply shifted the low of power from one end to another. It did not reconsti2 One cannot but help to think of the continual resonance between Sloterdijk’s project and the recent work of Jean-Luc Nancy. his is the case not only with the recent work by Nancy on religious themes and globalization but also his earlier work on “communality” and “singular plurality.” he Shape of hings 59 tute the very elements of the prior cosmological system. he shape of the world, even after the emergence of the Figure of Man, did not much change. But it was not just the shape of the system that did not budge, but rather the way things in it related to one another. While Sloterdijk takes much care to provide various illustrations having to do with the contours of what he is describing, he is in fact attempting to describe relationality. One could even go so far as to say that for him the way in which certain elements in a system relate—let us call this the “relational quantum”—gives the system itself shape. hus to call something “foam,” “bubble,” or “sphere” is really an attempt by Sloterdijk to theorize a “connecting force.” Spheres, then, are “the original product of human coexistence.” In other words, spheres form out of the relations of certain existing ontological objects, or as Sloterdijk tends to call them, “nobjects.” Spheres therefore are unlike environments. “Environment,” while certainly a milieu for the facilitation of elements in action therein, is nevertheless a top-down way of thinking about social forms. Environments are determinants and causes, though perhaps not linear or direct ones. hey are, still, somehow initiators. Spheres are more “atmospheric-symbolic places.” hey are like “air” or even “airconditioning systems in whose construction and calibration, for those living in real coexistence . . . is out of the question not to participate” (46). “Living in spheres” is indeed a condition, a structure but one which is dynamic and ethereal. It “means inhabiting a shared subtlety” (46, emphasis added). Bubbles, the irst volume of the project, is a “theory of the shared inside” (542). he bubble is the irst step, the most elemental, the smallest unit of sphere. he question, of course, is what kind of bubble are we talking about here? In describing it, Sloterdijk references a variety of illustrations, including vaginas, wombs and soap. Stranger still is Sloterdijk’s embrace of the term “soul,” not the Cartesian variety but the Platonic one. Spheres are a form of “soul expansion” that would have previously been associated with “spirit,” although Sloterdijk claims that what was “meant was always inspired spatial communities” (19). But today, there is no thinking about spatial communities without thinking of networks, which has triggered “a general space crisis,” or what Paul Virilio calls “the annihilation of space.” his complicates, in particular, age-old ideas about subjectivity. According to Sloterdijk, the annihilation of space inally reveals the myth of individual autonomy, which he describes as the “basic neurosis of Western culture,” that is, “to dream of a subject that watches, names and owns everything, without letting anything contain, appoint or own it, not even if the discreetest God ofered himself as an observer, container and client” (86). he Enlightenment emphasized and augmented loneliness as the default setting of the human being. his is the case not only with the ancients but also with Hegel and Heidgger in particular. To the contrary, for 60 SAM HAN Sloterdijk, there is, what we can call, a primary “intimacy” between beings. Even phenomenological conceptions of “intersubjectivity” took as its quantum the individual, perceiving subject—a point made loud and clear most acutely by post-structuralist critics. But more to the point, the Modern Age too easily discarded the primacy of, what Sloterdijk describes as a magolological and erotological tendency. He writes: Among humans, fascination is the rule and disenchantment the exception. As desiring and imitating begins, humans constantly experience that they not only hold a lonely potential for desiring the other within themselves, but also that they manage, in an opaque and non-trivial manner, to infect the objects of their desire with their own longing for them; at the same time, individuals imitate the other’s longing for a third element as if under some infectious compulsion… Where philosophy of the early Modern Age mentions such efects of resonance and infection, it spontaneously draws on the vocabulary of magological traditions. As easy as antiquity, it was relection on afective causalities of the magical type that initiated the clariication of the interpersonal or inter demonic concert, which, from Plato’s time on, was interpreted as a work of eros. (208) Tracing this genealogy magolological of relation from the Middle Ages and the Early Modern Age allows for Sloterdijk to contrast the spheres’ model of relationality to that of subjectivity, which he, after Lacan, refers to as the psychoanalytic model. In large part, he does this to tie it to Judeo-Christian understandings of he Law, which “does not encourage merging, but constantly makes the case for constructive separations; its focus is not intimate fusion, but rather the discretion of the subject in relation to the other” (217). he Law model of subjectivity, we can argue, is the basis for so many of the recent theories of the subject that are no doubt derivative of Lacan and Althusser. In the Althusserian version, which I think Sloterdijk has in mind although he more explicitly takes aim at Lacan, the subject is the subject of ideology, constituted in and through the ISAs (Ideological State Apparatuses) that have surrounded the subject’s entire identity through various layers of institutional identity formation and recognition. hus, when the police oicer hails you, the subject was always already interpellated, as evidenced by the subject’s assumption that it is he that oice is addressing. Put in juxtaposition to Sloterdijk, this model seems to be top-down in that there is no theory of “bindability” beyond the superstructural notion of “ideology.” his amounts to sacriicing the “relationships between things” for “being-in-itself ” (220). Put diferently, Sloterdijk identiies in this model of subjectivity an overemphasis on the ontic. he question of the ontic most certainly leads to questions around notions of thinghood and objects. Especially nowadays, there has been a lurry of philosophical interest in ideas of object-oriented ontology. “hings” or objects are a subject of serious he Shape of hings 61 theoretical inquiry. Sloterdijk, hardly a source for many of the thinkers associated with OOO and speculative realism, nevertheless shares these analytic concerns.3 Subjectivity is but one rather convenient level for him to begin. It is a point of entry, not his primary intellectual concern. Nevertheless, the importance of relationality brings Sloterdijk to theorize objects, those very entities whose relations he expresses such profound interest in. In large part, he use the term “nobject” from homas Macho, a German cultural theorist whose work has not quite reached the English-speaking theory world quite yet.4 In Sloterdijk’s rendering, nobjects are “things, media or persons that fulill the function of the living genius or intimate augmenter for subjects” (467). hey are “objects that…are not objects because they have no subject-like counterpart” (294). His examples of “nobjects” include air as well as placental blood. Air, he writes, “possesses unmistakable nobject properties as it afords the incipient subject a irst chance at self-activity in respiratory autonomy, but without ever appearing as a thing with which to have a relationship” (295). Placental blood is one of the many images of the gynecological register that Sloterdijk draws from throughout the work. he womb is of particular importance to Sloterdijk as it functions to counter the assumed importance of “primary narcissism” (320). Instead, he says that there is a primary duality, which is born out not only in art (a privileged area of evidence for Sloterdjik) but also in mythology. his leads him to venture into some rather odd places. For instance, in a chapter on what he calls “the primal companion,” he spends a lot of space on what he calls the “sanitization of afterbirth.” here, he argues that the importance of afterbirth which subsequently sufered from a “bourgeois-individualist” attempt to retroactively isolate the subject. He even goes so far as to ofer a periodization. He notes that “modern individualism could only enter its intense phase in the second half of the eighteenth century, when the general clinical and cultural excommunication of the placenta began” (384). hus the “lonely modern subject” is a “ission product from the informal separation of birth and afterbirth. Its positively willful being is tainted by a fault to which it will never admit: that it rests on the elimination of its most 3 here are many books and other writings, mostly on the World Wide Web, on object-oriented ontology. he best deinition of OOO has come from videogame theorist Ian Bogost. hat can be found at: Bogost, Ian. “What Is Object-Oriented Ontology?” IAN BOGOST - VIDEOGAME THEORY, CRITICISM, DESIGN 8 Dec. 2009. Web. 26 Sept. 2012. Of the books, the following anthologies provide suitable introductions. Bryant, Levi, Nick Srnicek, and Graham Harman. he Speculative Turn: Continental Materialism and Realism. re.press, 2011. Harman, Graham. Towards Speculative Realism: Essays and Lectures. O Books, 2010. 4 here seems to be almost nothing of Macho’s translated into English. He does, however, have a web site. http://www.culture.hu-berlin.de/tm/ 62 SAM HAN intimate pre-object” (386). Hence, the Modern Age can be thought of as deined by “placental nihilism.” Undoubtedly this is stylization taken to the nth degree. But there is something to Sloterdijk’s overuse of the metaphor. He views the maternal relationship as the prototype for his theory of relationality in spheres—“proto-subjectivity.” “[I]ntimacy is a transmission relationship . . . not taken from the symmetrical alliance between twins or like-minded parties, where each mirrors the other, but from the irresolvable asymmetrical communion between the maternal voice and the fetal ear” (511). While one could not blame any reader for being fed up with Sloterdijk’s “illustrative” method, there is, in my mind at least, a method, that is, a clear intention on the part of Sloterdijk. he imagistic aspect of his illustrative method is born out in not only the dearth of examples that he uses, but in the countless photographs and illustrations that Sloterdijk includes in Bubbles. But returning to the issue of spheres and proto-subjectivity, Sloterdijk does not necessarily spend all of his eforts in a nostalgic explication for a time where ontological thinking was not devoid of magolological or erotological elements. Instead, he suggests that “modern mass culture” already exhibits this sort of reality of spheres as it “ofers new, direct ways of fulilling the desire for homeostatic communion.” He goes on to argue that “pop music and its derivatives” allow for the “possibility of diving into a body of rhythmic noise in which critical ego functions become temporarily dispensable” (527). hese sorts of communions share in common with religious communions the opportunity for “absorption,” as he calls it. he most telling of examples he provides is that of the Love Parade, held in Berlin for a long time but later moved to other cities in Germany. Up until its recent cancellation, the Love Parade was characterized by its particularly EDM (electronic dance music)-heavy focus, exhibitionist ethos, and the sheer number of attendees with igures (though disputed) reported to be in the hundreds of thousands. Of this festival, Sloterdijk writes: …[T]hey could easily be called “Truth Parades,” as their aim is to absorb large numbers of people, all of whom value the attributes of their individuality, into happy, symbiotic reversible and thus “true” sonospheres. hese communions with the audio gods or the rhythmic juggernauts are based on the same truth model as post-Freudian psychoanalysis—with the diference that the latter recommends that its clients develop a strict individual rhetoric of mourning for the lost primal object, while integristic music therapy in the streets relies on drug-assisted group euphorias that may advance lirtation with absorption into a spheric primal body in the short term, but yield little proit for the participants’ media competence in the sobering periods that follow (527–528). It is in this unlikely example of the Love Parade, where I believe the key to Sloterdijk’s he Shape of hings 63 “theory of the shared inside” lies. By viewing this music festival as “communion,” and thus employing a religious register, Sloterdijk arguably betrays, what I view to be, his true intellectual concerns—theology. In showing that “life is always a life-in-themidst-of-lives, Being-in, then, should be conceived as the togetherness of something with something in something” (542), Sloterdijk ends up using the theological concept of “perichoresis,” which the Protestant German theologian Jürgen Moltmann in his God in Creation describes as “the principle of mutual interpenetration.” In Moltmann’s theology, all relationships “are analogous to God.” his is characterized by a “primal, reciprocal indwelling and mutual interpenetration,” which in theological terms is called perichoresis: “God in the world and the world in God; heaven and earth in the kingdom of God, pervaded by his glory.” his mutual interpenetration disabuses the notion of a solitary life. Against a panpsychic Leibnizian monadology, which sees ontologically individual beings that coordinate with another through a divine pre-established harmony, Moltmann describes the principle of mutual interpenetration as all living things “[living] in another and with one another, from one another and for one another”(Moltmann 17). his is analogous to Sloterdijk’s “onto-theology.” Yet, no matter how novel Sloterdijk’s overall argument, and mode of argument, in the end, it is rather familiar because it is, even according to him, a corrective. Bubbles, and the Spheres trilogy generally, is an attempt to demystify, a tact nearly identical to the theoretical methods of Rudolf Bultmann but also—surprisingly—the Frankfurt school, especially Adorno and Horkheimer. To demythologize is to suggest that if we simply understood the proper genealogy of a particular concept at the root of contemporary metaphysics, it would make for a better world. For Sloterdijk, it is “sphere,” whereas for the Frankfurt School, it was “mass culture.” For all of their public back-and-forths regarding the German welfare state, it seems that Sloterdijk and Honneth, the current director of the Frankfurt Institute for Social Research, have more in common than previously imagined. Works Cited Abadi, Cameron. “Germany’s Welfare State Under Fire.” GlobalPost 9 Jan. 2010. Web. 24 May 2012. Bogost, Ian. “What Is Object-Oriented Ontology?” IAN BOGOST - VIDEOGAME THEORY, CRITICISM, DESIGN 8 Dec. 2009. Web. 26 Sept. 2012. Bryant, Levi, Nick Srnicek, and Graham Harman. he Speculative Turn: Continental Materialism and Realism. re.press, 2011. Print. 64 SAM HAN Gregersen, homas. “Axel Honneth Versus Peter Sloterdijk.” Political heory - Habermas and Rawls 26 Sept. 2009. Web. 25 Sept. 2012. Harman, Graham. Towards Speculative Realism: Essays and Lectures. O Books, 2010. Print. Moltmann, Jurgen. God in Creation. 1st Fortress Press ed. Fortress Press, 1993. Print. ---. God in Creation. Fortress Press, 1993. Print. Salam, Reihan. “he Peter Sloterdijk Controversy.” he Agenda 12 Jan. 2010. Web. 24 May 2012. Shingleton, Cameron. “he Great Stage: Axel Honneth: Against Sloterdijk (Die Zeit, 24 September, 2009).” he Great Stage 11 Feb. 2010. Web. 25 Sept. 2012. Sloterdijk, Peter. Bubbles: Spheres Volume I: Microspherology. Trans. Wieland Hoban. Semiotext(e), 2011. Print. ---. Derrida, an Egyptian. 1st ed. Polity, 2009. Print. ---. “Foreword to the heory of Spheres.” Cosmograms (2005): 223–240. Print. ---. “Spheres heory: Talking to Myself About the Poetics of Space.” Harvard Design Magazine 2009: n. pag. Print. ---. “he Grasping Hand.” City Journal Winter 2010. Web. 24 May 2012. Virilio, Paul. Polar Inertia. Sage, 2000. Print. ---. he Information Bomb. Verso Books, 2000. Print. ---. he Vision Machine. Indiana University Press, 1994. Print. Sam Han is a Seoul-born, New York City-raised interdisciplinary social scientist, working in the areas of social and cultural theory, new media, religion, globalization, and race/ethnicity. He is author of Web 2.0 (Routledge, 2011), Navigating Technomedia: Caught in the Web (Rowman & Littleield, 2007) and editor (with Daniel Chafee) of he Race of Time: A Charles Lemert Reader (Paradigm Publishers, 2009). He is at work on two projects on digital religions in the United States and in Asia. He is currently Assistant Professor of Sociology at Nanyang Technological University (NTU) in Singapore. He can be found at: sam-han.org.