T h e Sh ape of Thi ngs
SAM HAN
Peter Sloterdijk. Bubbles: Spheres Volume I: Microspherology. Trans. Wieland Hoban.
Semiotext(e), 2011. 664pp.
F
or anyone even remotely interested in philosophy, when a igure sets out to “correct” Heidegger, you want to pay attention. his is not necessarily out of admiration for the author of Being and Time, or his ideas, but rather out of a genuine curiosity made up of equal parts amazement and horror. he interest would be compulsory,
akin to intellectual rubbernecking, for it is more than likely that he or she, the subject
of such an utterance, will, like Heidegger, be vulnerable to intense scrutiny and interpretation. herefore, when MIT Press describes the much-anticipated Spheres trilogy
by Peter Sloterdijk as “the late-twentieth-century bookend to Heidegger’s Being and
Time,” there is reasonable expectation for it to be disastrous.
Ever since the English translation of his he Critique of Cynical Reason in 1988,
Sloterdijk has been known in English-speaking intellectual circles as somewhat of
a mercurial igure. Not much, still, is known about him. From where, that is, what
intellectual milieu or tradition, did he emerge? Is he a Frankfurt guy? Is he a Luhmannite? Is he Heideggerian? he rather out-of-nowhere character of Sloterdijk’s work,
as well as the inconsistent reception of his work outside a handful of watchers of
developments in continental philosophy and social theory, placed Sloterdijk in the
category of “heard of him” (otherwise known as “oh right, he wrote that one thing”)
in North American cultural theory.
But Sloterdijk’s trajectory difered tremendously in his native Germany. When copies of Cynical Reason started leaving the shelves at a rapid pace upon its release, the
then-journalist was boosted into the highbrow German intellectual scene traditionally illed with academics. Today, we can count Sloterdijk among the country’s public
intellectuals, a group that also includes luminaries like Jürgen Habermas and Axel
Honneth (more on these two later). Sloterdijk is also host to a show called “Das
Philosophische Quartett” (he Philosophical Quartet), which airs on ZDF, the German equivalent to PBS in the United States or NHK in Japan. It features Sloterdijk
alongside guests of various intellectual pedigrees, from academics to journalists.
More recently, Sloterdijk has made himself known among the wider American reading
Reviews in Cultural heory Vol. 4, Issue 1. Copyright © 2013 Sam Han.
56
SAM HAN
public for a controversy involving welfare state politics, class, ressentiment and Axel
Honneth. As a blog post on the Global Post summarizes:
According to an article published this past summer in one of Germany’s most
widely read newspapers, the country’s welfare state is a “iscal kleptocracy” that
has transformed the country into a “swamp of resentment” and degraded its
citizens into “mystiied subjects of tax law.” he text, by philosopher Peter Sloterdijk, goes on in that vein for some 3,000 words[…]
Among the country’s intellectual class, the article has served as kindling for a
iercely fought and wide-ranging conversation about the national economy that,
six months on, still shows little sign of abating. (Abadi)
he article, entitled “Die Revolution der gebenden Hand” (“he Revolution of the
Grasping Hand”), must be read as a polemic. While it includes some semblance of
genealogical (in the Foucauldian sense) analysis of the modern democratic welfare
state, its primary purpose is to ofend. He begins with a meditation on the birth of
the democratic state as the compromise between classical liberalism and anarchism,
each of which was amenable to the declining signiicance of the state. For liberalism,
the state needed to be minimal and imperceptible to its subjects, the citizens. For anarchism, the state needed to be destroyed. Hence, the “modern democratic state gradually transformed into the debtor state, within the space of a century metastasizing
into a colossal monster—one that breathes and spits out money” (Sloterdijk, “he
Grasping Hand”). For a Europe that is currently under much economic turmoil, and
with a Germany that is currently embroiled in a national debate, hinging in large part
on a parochial stance toward Southern Europe as iscally irresponsible debtees, about
whether to “bail out” Greece and Spain, this article, for many of its critics, amounted
basically to “piling on.” Further, according to its critics, it preyed on extant, albeit
latent, nationalist sentiment, which culminated in the infamous book by hilo Sarrazin, which all but placed the entirety of Germany’s economic woes on its immigrants.
his was the context for the retort by Honneth, one of the last remaining lag bearers
of the Frankfurt School. here he accused Sloterdijk of, among many things, being
an ideological mouthpiece for advanced capitalism, “a mystical or speculative [interpreter] of history and the world,” and, rather strangely, a reader of Michel Foucault.1
1
While most of this exchange never made it to English-language publications, much
of it has been chronicled on blogs. See Gregersen, homas. “Axel Honneth Versus
Peter Sloterdijk.” Political heory - Habermas and Rawls. 26 Sept. 2009. Web. 25
Sept. 2012; Shingleton, Cameron. “he Great Stage: Axel Honneth: Against Sloterdijk (Die Zeit, 24 September, 2009).” he Great Stage. 11 Feb. 2010. 25 Sept. 2012.
he Shape of hings 57
he gist of Honneth’s critique, which I cannot fully assess in this space, is that Sloterdijk has taken ressentiment as “irst psychology” of the lower classes and has attempted
to pull the rug from up under the very foundations of European liberal democracy—
the welfare state—by criticizing it. I bring up Honneth’s public spat with Sloterdijk
in order to portray a picture of the latter that presents not only his prominence in the
German intellectual scene but also his embattled public image. While Sloterdijk may
only recently be gaining mass recognition in North America, he has, in Europe, at
least, been a visible presence for the past two decades or so.
For Sloterdijk, the problematic of inhabitation is that which courses through the
veins of Western metaphysics and philosophy. he “old cosmology of ancient Europe,” as he calls it, “that rested on equating the house and home with the world,”
can be seen in even the disparate philosophies of Hegel and Heidegger. Humans in
this view were “inhabitants in a crowded building called cosmos”(Sloterdijk, “Spheres
heory”). As it was for his most obvious predecessor, Gaston Bachelard, the motif of
the house—signifying order, unity and certainty—is one that unduly holds too much
purchase in the West. For Sloterdijk, the Enlightenment should have dispelled the
need for a “universal house in order to ind the world a place worthy of inhabiting”
(Ibid.). Yet, it remains, thanks in part to philosophers such as Heidegger, whose selfproclaimed task to “end metaphysics” as such did not do away with the, if we can call
it something, the “metaphysics of the universal house.” Sloterdijk’s project, therefore,
in his three-volume study called Spheres, is to forge a path beyond Heidegger, by
providing a general theory of “associations.”
For Heidegger, the overarching question of metaphysics was temporal—with the keywords “being” and “becoming.” For Sloterdijk, it is spatial; the keyword is “world.”
While it is the case that Sloterdijk views Heidegger to have been wrong all along,
there is something about the current technological, socio-political moment that has
occasioned a particular response. Sloterdijk writes:
It’s the inal stage of a process that began in the epoch of Greek philosophical
cosmology, and whose present vectors are rapid transportation as well as ultrahigh-speed telecommunication. At the same time, it’s the product of a radical
disappointment, whereby human beings had to abandon the privilege of inhabiting a real cosmos—which is to say, a closed and comforting world. he cosmos,
such as the Greeks conceived it, was the totality of being imagined under the
form of a great, perfectly symmetrical bubble. Aristotle and his followers were
responsible for this idea of a cosmos composed of concentric, celestial spheres of
increasing diameters, the majority of which consisted of a hypothetical material
they called ether. For us, this model of the world is obviously no longer operational. (Sloterdijk, “Foreword to the heory of Spheres” 223)
58
SAM HAN
In response to this “inoperability,”2 Sloterdijk ofers a “spherology,” beginning from
the micro, which is the subject of volume I of Spheres entitled Bubbles, all the way
to the macro, the subject of volume III, entitled Foams. Sphere, for Sloterdijk, does
not assume a totality or inality as the phenomenologically inlected “lifeworld” or
“world” entails. As he puts it rather paradoxically, “the primordial existential sphere is
created every time a moment of inter-psychic space happens” (Sloterdijk, “Foreword
to the heory of Spheres” 223–224). Against the weight of “existence,” Sloterdijk
puts forth a succession of events, of happenings, wherein meaningful and signiicant connections are made but do not sufocate. Hence, the microspherology he
presents in Bubbles, the volume under review, is, at root, a theory of “atmosphere”
or as he likes to say, of “air.” He chooses these ethereal metaphors as he believes
that spheres, the closest Heideggerian cognate being Stimmung (more on this later),
“never speak but…brings everything together and makes everything possible…a treasure that that allowed human beings to realize the fact that they’re always already
immersed in something almost imperceptible and yet very real, and that this space
of immersion dominates the changing states of the soul down to its most intimate
modiications”(Sloterdijk, “Foreword to the heory of Spheres” 225).
he development of this “spatial vocabulary” is necessary, therefore, because the concept of “world” is simply too bulky to do anything analytically. “Sphere” works better
for several reasons. For one, it is more in tune with the development of modernity,
which is characterized by “the increasing removal of safety structures from the traditional theological and cosmological narratives” (Sloterdijk, Bubbles 25) that used to
provide human subjectivity with a degree of ontological security by providing human
beings a place in the world, which was ixed, identiiable and orientating. Yet, these
“safety structures” in the form of “worlds,” according to Sloterdijk, remained. While
the emergence of the Figure of Man, allowed for humans to become the subject and
object of knowledge, the “empirico-transcendental” as Foucault so rightly put it, it
did not mean the complete “end of metaphysics.” It just diverted the sublimated energy. “People,” Sloterdijk precisely notes, “no longer wanted to receive their inspired
ideas from embarrassing heavens”(Sloterdijk, Bubbles 28). Instead of God, these ideas
came from within, so to speak, albeit mediated via technology, which relected the
“distance between what God was capable of in illo tempore and what humans will, in
time, themselves be capable of ” (37). Hence, supposedly secular models of subjectivity that emerged in the wake of the scientiic revolutions of Galileo, Copernicus and
later Newton, nonetheless remained closely tied to the imago Dei. he image of man
as God simply shifted the low of power from one end to another. It did not reconsti2
One cannot but help to think of the continual resonance between Sloterdijk’s project and the recent work of Jean-Luc Nancy. his is the case not only with the recent
work by Nancy on religious themes and globalization but also his earlier work on
“communality” and “singular plurality.”
he Shape of hings 59
tute the very elements of the prior cosmological system. he shape of the world, even
after the emergence of the Figure of Man, did not much change.
But it was not just the shape of the system that did not budge, but rather the way
things in it related to one another. While Sloterdijk takes much care to provide various illustrations having to do with the contours of what he is describing, he is in fact
attempting to describe relationality. One could even go so far as to say that for him
the way in which certain elements in a system relate—let us call this the “relational
quantum”—gives the system itself shape. hus to call something “foam,” “bubble,” or
“sphere” is really an attempt by Sloterdijk to theorize a “connecting force.” Spheres,
then, are “the original product of human coexistence.” In other words, spheres form
out of the relations of certain existing ontological objects, or as Sloterdijk tends to call
them, “nobjects.” Spheres therefore are unlike environments. “Environment,” while
certainly a milieu for the facilitation of elements in action therein, is nevertheless a
top-down way of thinking about social forms. Environments are determinants and
causes, though perhaps not linear or direct ones. hey are, still, somehow initiators.
Spheres are more “atmospheric-symbolic places.” hey are like “air” or even “airconditioning systems in whose construction and calibration, for those living in real
coexistence . . . is out of the question not to participate” (46). “Living in spheres”
is indeed a condition, a structure but one which is dynamic and ethereal. It “means
inhabiting a shared subtlety” (46, emphasis added).
Bubbles, the irst volume of the project, is a “theory of the shared inside” (542). he
bubble is the irst step, the most elemental, the smallest unit of sphere. he question, of course, is what kind of bubble are we talking about here? In describing it,
Sloterdijk references a variety of illustrations, including vaginas, wombs and soap.
Stranger still is Sloterdijk’s embrace of the term “soul,” not the Cartesian variety but
the Platonic one. Spheres are a form of “soul expansion” that would have previously
been associated with “spirit,” although Sloterdijk claims that what was “meant was
always inspired spatial communities” (19). But today, there is no thinking about
spatial communities without thinking of networks, which has triggered “a general
space crisis,” or what Paul Virilio calls “the annihilation of space.” his complicates,
in particular, age-old ideas about subjectivity.
According to Sloterdijk, the annihilation of space inally reveals the myth of individual autonomy, which he describes as the “basic neurosis of Western culture,” that
is, “to dream of a subject that watches, names and owns everything, without letting
anything contain, appoint or own it, not even if the discreetest God ofered himself
as an observer, container and client” (86). he Enlightenment emphasized and augmented loneliness as the default setting of the human being. his is the case not only
with the ancients but also with Hegel and Heidgger in particular. To the contrary, for
60
SAM HAN
Sloterdijk, there is, what we can call, a primary “intimacy” between beings. Even phenomenological conceptions of “intersubjectivity” took as its quantum the individual,
perceiving subject—a point made loud and clear most acutely by post-structuralist
critics. But more to the point, the Modern Age too easily discarded the primacy of,
what Sloterdijk describes as a magolological and erotological tendency. He writes:
Among humans, fascination is the rule and disenchantment the exception. As
desiring and imitating begins, humans constantly experience that they not only
hold a lonely potential for desiring the other within themselves, but also that
they manage, in an opaque and non-trivial manner, to infect the objects of their
desire with their own longing for them; at the same time, individuals imitate the
other’s longing for a third element as if under some infectious compulsion…
Where philosophy of the early Modern Age mentions such efects of resonance
and infection, it spontaneously draws on the vocabulary of magological traditions. As easy as antiquity, it was relection on afective causalities of the magical
type that initiated the clariication of the interpersonal or inter demonic concert,
which, from Plato’s time on, was interpreted as a work of eros. (208)
Tracing this genealogy magolological of relation from the Middle Ages and the Early
Modern Age allows for Sloterdijk to contrast the spheres’ model of relationality to
that of subjectivity, which he, after Lacan, refers to as the psychoanalytic model.
In large part, he does this to tie it to Judeo-Christian understandings of he Law,
which “does not encourage merging, but constantly makes the case for constructive
separations; its focus is not intimate fusion, but rather the discretion of the subject
in relation to the other” (217). he Law model of subjectivity, we can argue, is the
basis for so many of the recent theories of the subject that are no doubt derivative
of Lacan and Althusser. In the Althusserian version, which I think Sloterdijk has in
mind although he more explicitly takes aim at Lacan, the subject is the subject of
ideology, constituted in and through the ISAs (Ideological State Apparatuses) that
have surrounded the subject’s entire identity through various layers of institutional
identity formation and recognition. hus, when the police oicer hails you, the subject was always already interpellated, as evidenced by the subject’s assumption that it
is he that oice is addressing. Put in juxtaposition to Sloterdijk, this model seems to
be top-down in that there is no theory of “bindability” beyond the superstructural
notion of “ideology.” his amounts to sacriicing the “relationships between things”
for “being-in-itself ” (220). Put diferently, Sloterdijk identiies in this model of subjectivity an overemphasis on the ontic.
he question of the ontic most certainly leads to questions around notions of thinghood and objects. Especially nowadays, there has been a lurry of philosophical interest in ideas of object-oriented ontology. “hings” or objects are a subject of serious
he Shape of hings 61
theoretical inquiry. Sloterdijk, hardly a source for many of the thinkers associated
with OOO and speculative realism, nevertheless shares these analytic concerns.3 Subjectivity is but one rather convenient level for him to begin. It is a point of entry, not
his primary intellectual concern. Nevertheless, the importance of relationality brings
Sloterdijk to theorize objects, those very entities whose relations he expresses such
profound interest in. In large part, he use the term “nobject” from homas Macho, a
German cultural theorist whose work has not quite reached the English-speaking theory world quite yet.4 In Sloterdijk’s rendering, nobjects are “things, media or persons
that fulill the function of the living genius or intimate augmenter for subjects” (467).
hey are “objects that…are not objects because they have no subject-like counterpart” (294). His examples of “nobjects” include air as well as placental blood. Air, he
writes, “possesses unmistakable nobject properties as it afords the incipient subject
a irst chance at self-activity in respiratory autonomy, but without ever appearing as
a thing with which to have a relationship” (295). Placental blood is one of the many
images of the gynecological register that Sloterdijk draws from throughout the work.
he womb is of particular importance to Sloterdijk as it functions to counter the
assumed importance of “primary narcissism” (320). Instead, he says that there is a
primary duality, which is born out not only in art (a privileged area of evidence for
Sloterdjik) but also in mythology.
his leads him to venture into some rather odd places. For instance, in a chapter
on what he calls “the primal companion,” he spends a lot of space on what he calls
the “sanitization of afterbirth.” here, he argues that the importance of afterbirth
which subsequently sufered from a “bourgeois-individualist” attempt to retroactively
isolate the subject. He even goes so far as to ofer a periodization. He notes that
“modern individualism could only enter its intense phase in the second half of the
eighteenth century, when the general clinical and cultural excommunication of the
placenta began” (384). hus the “lonely modern subject” is a “ission product from
the informal separation of birth and afterbirth. Its positively willful being is tainted
by a fault to which it will never admit: that it rests on the elimination of its most
3
here are many books and other writings, mostly on the World Wide Web, on
object-oriented ontology. he best deinition of OOO has come from videogame
theorist Ian Bogost. hat can be found at: Bogost, Ian. “What Is Object-Oriented
Ontology?” IAN BOGOST - VIDEOGAME THEORY, CRITICISM, DESIGN
8 Dec. 2009. Web. 26 Sept. 2012. Of the books, the following anthologies provide
suitable introductions. Bryant, Levi, Nick Srnicek, and Graham Harman. he Speculative Turn: Continental Materialism and Realism. re.press, 2011. Harman, Graham.
Towards Speculative Realism: Essays and Lectures. O Books, 2010.
4
here seems to be almost nothing of Macho’s translated into English. He does,
however, have a web site. http://www.culture.hu-berlin.de/tm/
62
SAM HAN
intimate pre-object” (386). Hence, the Modern Age can be thought of as deined by
“placental nihilism.”
Undoubtedly this is stylization taken to the nth degree. But there is something to
Sloterdijk’s overuse of the metaphor. He views the maternal relationship as the prototype for his theory of relationality in spheres—“proto-subjectivity.” “[I]ntimacy is a
transmission relationship . . . not taken from the symmetrical alliance between twins
or like-minded parties, where each mirrors the other, but from the irresolvable asymmetrical communion between the maternal voice and the fetal ear” (511). While one
could not blame any reader for being fed up with Sloterdijk’s “illustrative” method,
there is, in my mind at least, a method, that is, a clear intention on the part of
Sloterdijk. he imagistic aspect of his illustrative method is born out in not only the
dearth of examples that he uses, but in the countless photographs and illustrations
that Sloterdijk includes in Bubbles.
But returning to the issue of spheres and proto-subjectivity, Sloterdijk does not necessarily spend all of his eforts in a nostalgic explication for a time where ontological
thinking was not devoid of magolological or erotological elements. Instead, he suggests that “modern mass culture” already exhibits this sort of reality of spheres as it
“ofers new, direct ways of fulilling the desire for homeostatic communion.” He goes
on to argue that “pop music and its derivatives” allow for the “possibility of diving
into a body of rhythmic noise in which critical ego functions become temporarily
dispensable” (527). hese sorts of communions share in common with religious communions the opportunity for “absorption,” as he calls it. he most telling of examples
he provides is that of the Love Parade, held in Berlin for a long time but later moved
to other cities in Germany. Up until its recent cancellation, the Love Parade was characterized by its particularly EDM (electronic dance music)-heavy focus, exhibitionist
ethos, and the sheer number of attendees with igures (though disputed) reported to
be in the hundreds of thousands. Of this festival, Sloterdijk writes:
…[T]hey could easily be called “Truth Parades,” as their aim is to absorb large
numbers of people, all of whom value the attributes of their individuality, into
happy, symbiotic reversible and thus “true” sonospheres. hese communions
with the audio gods or the rhythmic juggernauts are based on the same truth
model as post-Freudian psychoanalysis—with the diference that the latter recommends that its clients develop a strict individual rhetoric of mourning for
the lost primal object, while integristic music therapy in the streets relies on
drug-assisted group euphorias that may advance lirtation with absorption into a
spheric primal body in the short term, but yield little proit for the participants’
media competence in the sobering periods that follow (527–528).
It is in this unlikely example of the Love Parade, where I believe the key to Sloterdijk’s
he Shape of hings 63
“theory of the shared inside” lies. By viewing this music festival as “communion,” and
thus employing a religious register, Sloterdijk arguably betrays, what I view to be,
his true intellectual concerns—theology. In showing that “life is always a life-in-themidst-of-lives, Being-in, then, should be conceived as the togetherness of something
with something in something” (542), Sloterdijk ends up using the theological concept of “perichoresis,” which the Protestant German theologian Jürgen Moltmann in
his God in Creation describes as “the principle of mutual interpenetration.”
In Moltmann’s theology, all relationships “are analogous to God.” his is characterized by a “primal, reciprocal indwelling and mutual interpenetration,” which in theological terms is called perichoresis: “God in the world and the world in God; heaven
and earth in the kingdom of God, pervaded by his glory.” his mutual interpenetration disabuses the notion of a solitary life. Against a panpsychic Leibnizian monadology, which sees ontologically individual beings that coordinate with another through
a divine pre-established harmony, Moltmann describes the principle of mutual interpenetration as all living things “[living] in another and with one another, from
one another and for one another”(Moltmann 17). his is analogous to Sloterdijk’s
“onto-theology.”
Yet, no matter how novel Sloterdijk’s overall argument, and mode of argument, in
the end, it is rather familiar because it is, even according to him, a corrective. Bubbles,
and the Spheres trilogy generally, is an attempt to demystify, a tact nearly identical to
the theoretical methods of Rudolf Bultmann but also—surprisingly—the Frankfurt
school, especially Adorno and Horkheimer. To demythologize is to suggest that if
we simply understood the proper genealogy of a particular concept at the root of
contemporary metaphysics, it would make for a better world. For Sloterdijk, it is
“sphere,” whereas for the Frankfurt School, it was “mass culture.” For all of their
public back-and-forths regarding the German welfare state, it seems that Sloterdijk
and Honneth, the current director of the Frankfurt Institute for Social Research, have
more in common than previously imagined.
Works Cited
Abadi, Cameron. “Germany’s Welfare State Under Fire.” GlobalPost 9 Jan. 2010.
Web. 24 May 2012.
Bogost, Ian. “What Is Object-Oriented Ontology?” IAN BOGOST - VIDEOGAME
THEORY, CRITICISM, DESIGN 8 Dec. 2009. Web. 26 Sept. 2012.
Bryant, Levi, Nick Srnicek, and Graham Harman. he Speculative Turn: Continental
Materialism and Realism. re.press, 2011. Print.
64
SAM HAN
Gregersen, homas. “Axel Honneth Versus Peter Sloterdijk.” Political heory - Habermas and Rawls 26 Sept. 2009. Web. 25 Sept. 2012.
Harman, Graham. Towards Speculative Realism: Essays and Lectures. O Books, 2010.
Print.
Moltmann, Jurgen. God in Creation. 1st Fortress Press ed. Fortress Press, 1993. Print.
---. God in Creation. Fortress Press, 1993. Print.
Salam, Reihan. “he Peter Sloterdijk Controversy.” he Agenda 12 Jan. 2010. Web.
24 May 2012.
Shingleton, Cameron. “he Great Stage: Axel Honneth: Against Sloterdijk (Die Zeit,
24 September, 2009).” he Great Stage 11 Feb. 2010. Web. 25 Sept. 2012.
Sloterdijk, Peter. Bubbles: Spheres Volume I: Microspherology. Trans. Wieland Hoban.
Semiotext(e), 2011. Print.
---. Derrida, an Egyptian. 1st ed. Polity, 2009. Print.
---. “Foreword to the heory of Spheres.” Cosmograms (2005): 223–240. Print.
---. “Spheres heory: Talking to Myself About the Poetics of Space.” Harvard Design
Magazine 2009: n. pag. Print.
---. “he Grasping Hand.” City Journal Winter 2010. Web. 24 May 2012.
Virilio, Paul. Polar Inertia. Sage, 2000. Print.
---. he Information Bomb. Verso Books, 2000. Print.
---. he Vision Machine. Indiana University Press, 1994. Print.
Sam Han is a Seoul-born, New York City-raised interdisciplinary social scientist,
working in the areas of social and cultural theory, new media, religion, globalization,
and race/ethnicity. He is author of Web 2.0 (Routledge, 2011), Navigating Technomedia: Caught in the Web (Rowman & Littleield, 2007) and editor (with Daniel
Chafee) of he Race of Time: A Charles Lemert Reader (Paradigm Publishers, 2009).
He is at work on two projects on digital religions in the United States and in Asia.
He is currently Assistant Professor of Sociology at Nanyang Technological University
(NTU) in Singapore. He can be found at: sam-han.org.