Geology Scientific Method
Geology Scientific Method
Geology Scientific Method
Subscribe
Permission request
Copyright not claimed on content prepared wholly by U.S. government employees within scope of their
employment. Individual scientists are hereby granted permission, without fees or further requests to GSA,
to use a single figure, a single table, and/or a brief paragraph of text in subsequent works and to make
unlimited copies of items in GSA's journals for noncommercial use in classrooms to further education and
science. This file may not be posted to any Web site, but authors may post the abstracts only of their
articles on their own or their organization's Web site providing the posting includes a reference to the
article's full citation. GSA provides this and other forums for the presentation of diverse opinions and
positions by scientists worldwide, regardless of their race, citizenship, gender, religion, or political
viewpoint. Opinions presented in this publication do not reflect official positions of the Society.
Notes
1
For footnotes 126, refer to the Endnotes between the text and References Cited near the end
of this paper.
960
values he or she might hold. Personal or cultural values must not enter into the scientific
reasoning process. A closely related point
was the insistence that one must distinguish
between the logic of discovery and the
logic of explanation. Identifying the particular social or psychological processes responsible for the scientists insights was the
job of the social scientist. The philosopher
of science was only interested in the logical
procedures that justified a scientific claim.
Second, the scientific method is empirical. Science is built upon a rigorous distinction between observations (which again
were understood, at least ideally, as being
factual and unequivocal) and theory. Facts
themselves were not theory-dependent; observation was thought to be a matter of taking a good look. The distinction between
statements that describe and statements that
evaluate was viewed as unproblematic.
Third, the scientific method constitutes an
epistemological monism. Science was thought
to consist of an single, identifiable set of logical procedures applicable to all fields of
study. This reduction of all knowledge to
one kind of knowledge proceeded in two
steps, summarized by the terms scientism
and reductionism. Scientism is the belief
that the scientific method provides us with
the only reliable way to know. Reductionism
is the further claim that it is possible to reduce all sciences to one science, physics.
It is important to note that the original
research program of Analytic Philosophy,
known as Logical Positivism, was challenged
from within Analytic Philosophy by the early
1950s. Authors such as Quine (1953), Goodman (1951), and Popper (1953) raised fundamental questions concerning many of the
points mentioned above. But for our purposes the crucial point is this: these debates
stayed in-house in the sense that the basic
orientation of Analytic Philosophy remained
intact until at least the mid-1970s. Thus,
while the exact status of scientific knowledge
became more problematic, the general assumption that science (i.e., physics) was the
model for knowing was not seriously questioned. Similarly, the degree of objectivity of
scientific knowledge may have been unclear,
but science was still thought of as essentially
value-free in comparison with ethical or political issues. Finally, while the positivist belief in the strict reducibility of all knowledge
to physics was abandoned, the belief in the
existence of one uniform method for all the
sciences was still generally held to.10
Thusand this bears emphasiswhile at
the cutting-edge of Analytic Philosophy,
961
these assumptions were to some degree being questioned, and the received wisdom
within the philosophic community and for
others such as those within the scientific
communityretained a fundamentally positivistic orientation. Our basic story concerning the nature of science came to be questioned only with the Kuhnian revolution.11
The claims of Continental Philosophy
the other main school of contemporary philosophy concerning science can also be
summarized in two points: (1) whereas science offers us a powerful tool for the discovery of truth, science is not the only, or
even necessarily the best way that humans
come to know reality, and (2) the existence
of the scientific method (understood as
above) is a myth. Science has neither the
priority in the discovery of truth, nor the
unity and cohesiveness of one identifiable
method, nor the distance from ethical, epistemological, and metaphysical commitments that Analytic Philosophy claims it has.
Thus, Continental Philosophys basic orientation (since Hegel, ca. 1806) comes from its
attempt to define the scope and limits of
scientific knowledge as well as to identify
what other ways we have for discovering
truth. The 200 year history of Continental
Philosophy can be seen as a series of attempts to invent or define other ways of
knowing (e.g., dialectics, phenomenology,
hermeneutics, existentialism).
Initially, Analytic Philosophy and Continental Philosophy engaged in a common debate on the nature of knowledge, but by the
mid-20th century an informal division of labor had taken place. Analytic Philosophy focused on the intricacies of the philosophy of
science. It understood philosophy as being
ancillary to science, codifying and making
explicit the logic of science that scientists
already practiced, as well as deflating the
claims of other pseudo-scientific and nonscientific modes of knowing. For its part,
Continental Philosophy mostly ceded the
analysis of science to Analytic Philosophy.
Its main interest in science was not in scientific methodology per se, but in identifying what science left out in its one
dimensional (Marcuse, 1964) approach to
knowledge and experience. Continental Philosophy focused its attention on those types
of experience not amenable to the scientific
method: art, culture, subjectivity, and the
force of the irrational in our lives. Continental Philosophy insisted that these areas
were not truly understandable through the
scientific method.
962
sible to imagine a plurality of scientific approaches to a given problem, each with its
own particular strength or virtue.
The irony is that while Kuhn undercut the
main body of assumptions of Analytic Philosophy, raising issues from a perspective
more typical of Continental Philosophy, he
has been placed traditionally (if not always
comfortably) within the framework of Analytic Philosophy. Conversely, Continental
Philosophy itself (with a few exceptions) still
has not examined scientific knowledge with
the tools at its disposal.14 My project here is
to use the approach and concepts of the
Continental tradition to describe what is distinctive about the theory and practice of
geology.
GEOLOGY AS A HERMENEUTIC
SCIENCE
The two distinctive characteristics of reasoning in the earth sciences that I will discuss in the following sections are geologys
nature as a hermeneutic (interpretive) and
as a historical science.
The term hermeneutics means theory of
interpretation; hermeneutics is the art or
science of interpreting texts. A text (by
which is meant, typically, a literary work) is
a system of signs, the meaning of which is
not apparent but must be deciphered. This
deciphering takes place through assigning
differing types or degrees of significance to
the various elements making up the text.
The status of this deciphered meaning has
been the source of some dispute; in the 19th
century it was claimed that, when properly
applied to a text, hermeneutic technique resulted in knowledge as objective as that of
the natural sciences. In the 20th century,
however, hermeneutics has claimed that the
deciphering of meaning always involves the
subtle interplay of what is objectively
there in the text with what the reader brings
to the text in terms of presuppositions and
expectations. In effect, hermeneutics rejects
the claim that facts can ever be completely
independent of theory.15
Hermeneutics originated in the early 19th
century as a means of reconciling contradictory statements in the Bible through a systematic interpretation of its various claims.
In the early 20th century hermeneutics was
applied to historical (including legal) documents to help discover the original meaning
of the author. Hermeneutics was (and still
is) used when a theologian argues which
parts of the Bible to read literally and which
metaphorically, and what weight to give to
each part. Similarly, the literary scholar proceeds hermeneutically when she claims that
a narrators comments are to be taken seriously rather than ironically, as does the psychologist when he interprets a slip of the
tongue to be significant or not.
In the 20th century, however, hermeneutics has moved from being a rather straightforward methodology of the Geistwissenshaften (i.e., the humanities; literally, the
spiritual sciences) to a more general account of knowing. Hermeneutic philosophers such as Heidegger (1927, 1962) have
argued that all human understanding (including the natural sciences, although this
was not his main concern) is fundamentally
interpretive. Not only books, but the entire
world was a text to be read; in no field
does one find completely objective data or
information purely given. How we perceive the object is always shaped (though not
completely determined; objects assert their
own independence) by how we conceive and
act on the object with the sets of tools, concepts, expectations, and values that we bring
to the object.
When we apply this point to geology, this
becomes the claim: geologic understanding
is best understood as a hermeneutic process.
The geologist assigns different values to various aspects of the outcrop, judging which
characteristics or patterns in the rock are
significant and which are not. Examining an
outcrop is not simply a matter of taking a
good look. Rather, the geologist picks up
on the clues of past events and processes in
a way analogous to how the physician interprets the signs of illness or the detective
builds a circumstantial case against a
defendant.
Most of us are familiar with the hermeneutical aspect of understanding, the shift in
our awareness of an object when we approach it with a fresh set of concepts or expectations. This happens regularly to students when they are first introduced to a
subject. While in college I enrolled in an
introductory course in art history. Lacking
previous instruction in art, but armed with
my prejudices, I approached the course with
a sceptical attitude. Each class began with
lights dimmed, as the professor showed a
slide of a famous work of art. She then gave
us a few minutes to consider it on our own.
Typically especially at the beginning of the
semesterI saw nothing of any significance
in the slide, and I could not understand why
it was considered a great work of art. Yet it
became a truism that after a few minutes of
lecture, during which the professor intro-
963
of prejudgments: an idea of what the problem is, what type of information we are looking for, and what will count as an answer.
What keeps these prejudgments from slipping into dogmatism and prejudicethat is,
what makes science as distinguished from
ideology still possibleis the fact that they
are not blind. We remain open to correction, allowing the text or object to instruct us
and suggest new meanings and approaches.
This brings us to a second point revelant
to geological reasoning. Heidegger identified three types of prejudgments or forestructures that we bring to every situation.
First are our preconceptions, the ideas and
theories that we rely on when thinking about
an object. Concepts are not neutral tools;
rather, they allow us to get hold of an object
in a particular way, opening up certain possibilities and encouraging certain ways of
understanding while closing off others.
Thus, for instance, to approach the Western
Cordillera with concepts like ophiolite complexes and accretionary terranes will affect
what one sees in the field. These preconceptions include our initial definition of the object to be investigated as well as the criteria
used to identify which facts are significant
and which are not.
Second is our foresight, our idea of the
presumed goal of our inquiry and our sense
of what will count as an answer. Heidegger
argues that without some vague (and, one
hopes, open-minded) sense of what type of
answer we are looking for, we would not recognize it when we find it. Again, this implies
that the values of the scientistwhat he or
she hopes to find or achieveare intrinsic
rather than extrinsic to the scientific
enterprize.
Third, we always approach the object of
study with a set of practices we have in advance, what Heidegger called our fore-having. These are the culturally acquired set of
implements, skills, and institutions that one
brings to the object of study. In field geology, implements include the geologists
hammer, 0.10% HCl, a measuring tape, a
hand lens, a Jacobs staff, pencil and paper,
and a Brunton compass. At the lab there is
another set of tools: display trays, rock saws,
computers, acids, a light microscope, and a
scanning electron microscope.
As with our preconceptions, the nature of
these tools shape the type of information
collected; without a light microscope one
could not study the structure of nannoplankton; without a mass spectrometer isotopic
geochemistry would be impossible. With a
different set of tools other data would be
964
gathered that would give us a different (possibly a quite different) sense of the object.
This concept of fore-having also includes
the various skills that the geologist learns in
the field or the laboratory: map-making,
measuring strike and dip, preparing samples, cleaning and preserving specimens,
and even how to properly wield a hammer to
split a rock without destroying fossils. Included here as well are the mathematical
and statistical techniques used in research.
Just as crucial, however, and often discounted, are the social and political structures of science: professors, various graduate students, research groups, professional
associations, and other types of groups. Science is a social as well as a mental activity,
dependent on the existence of a community
of scholars. The work of science proceeds
through having colleagues to bounce ideas
off of, professional societies and journals to
define hot topics and favored lines of research, and graduate students for help with
running labs and collecting samples.18
The third basic concept of hermeneutics,
applicable to geology and indeed to all the
sciences, is the historical nature of human
understanding. Here the claim (distinct
from the argument of the next section) is
that the particular prejudgments we start
with have a lasting effect. It is often claimed
that, no matter what assumptions or goals
we begin with, the scientific method will
eventually bring us to the same final understanding of objective reality. Hermeneutics
argues otherwise: our original goals and assumptions result in certain facts being discovered rather than others, which in turn
lead to new avenues of research and sets of
facts. Any scientist can name areas of potential importance that do not get pursued
because of the lack of time and resources or
the lack of sufficient commitment on the
part of the scientific community. As these
decisions get multiplied over the decades
the body of scientific knowledge comes to
have a strongly historical component.
Heideggers claims as they relate to science and especially to geology can be summarized in two theses. First, he rejects the
view that data are purely given and that theories are totally objective constructions.
Rather, science is seen as involving various
types of values that are not only unavoidable
but also necessary and productive to the discovery of truth. Second, science is not only
something that one thinks; it is also something one does. Science is a social and historical activity structured to a significant degree by the scientists skills and equipment,
GEOLOGY AS A HISTORICAL
SCIENCE
Hull (1976) identified four historical sciences: cosmology, geology, paleontology,
and human history. A historical science is
defined by the role that historical explanation plays in its work. While explanation
within the historical sciences uses many of
the tools common to all sciences (i.e., the
deductive-nomological model of explanation, defined below), there remains a fundamental and distinctive difference in historical explanation. This difference as it
relates to geology can be characterized in
terms of three points: the limited role or
relevance of laboratory experiments, resulting in geologys dependence on other types
of reasoning; the problem of natural kinds
(i.e., the question of defining the object of
study within historical geology); and geologys nature as a narrative science.
Insofar as their work is based on laboratory experimentation, the experimental sciences (e.g., physics and chemistry) are essentially non-historical: the particularities of
place and time play no significant role in the
reasoning process. Work takes place in the
lab, an ideal space where conditions can be
controlled. Truth claims in these disciplines
presuppose that other researchers can recreate the identical conditions of the initial
experiment within their own laboratory.
Thus, for a truth claim to count as scientific,
a scientist in Oslo must be able to reproduce
results identical to those of the original experimenter in Seattle. In this sense, time and
history have no place in the experimental
sciences.19
Of course, in another sense time and history are an inescapable part of every science;
a chemical reaction takes time to complete,
and every chemical reaction is historical in
that it has some feature, no matter how insignificant, that distinguishes it from every
other reaction. But our interest in chemical
reactions typically is not in chronicling the
specific historical conditions that affect a
given reaction, but rather in abstracting a
general or ideal truth about a given class of
chemical reactions. Even the chemicals used
are idealized, in that the supplies used by the
chemist have been assayed for purity. A particular chemical reaction thus becomes
merely an instance of a general law or
principle.
tional explanation. Just as claims within human history must assume that we can analogize from what we know of human
motivations today to make sense of past actions, reasoning in historical geology is built
upon the assumption that the present is the
key to the pastthat present-day geologic
processes operate in a manner similar to
those of the past.
Within geology the assumption of analogy
between past and present has been given explicit recognition in the principle of uniformitarianism. Recent discussions of uniformity (Rudwick, 1976a; Berggren and Van
Couvering, 1984; Gould, 1987) have described the confused way this principle has
sometimes been used. Following Rudwick,
Gould argues that geologists have at times
conflated four different types of uniformity.
The first two, the methodological claims of
uniformity of law and process, are nothing
more than geologys version of sciences
twin assumptions that nature is governed by
lawlike behavior, and that we should not invent new or unknown causes until we have
exhausted the ones we have. The second
two, uniformity of rate (gradualism) and of
state (i.e., that the Earth is in steady state,
with no periods of significantly warmer climate, higher sea level, or more volcanic activity) make substantive claims about the
Earths history that have been largely rejected by the geological community.
The overall effect of Goulds account is
deflationary; uniformitarianism becomes a
rather common-sense principle embodying
no peculiarly geological claims. By separating methodological from substantive uniformitarianism Gould empties the principle of
any specifically geological meaning. He
therefore arrives at a position identical to
Nelson Goodman (1967), who concludes
. . . the Principle of Uniformity dissolves
into a principle of simplicity that is not peculiar to geology but pervades all science.
The nature of geological reasoning is again
not different in principle from any other
science.
But this reduction of uniformitarianism to
the principle of simplicity leaves too much
unexplained. The problem is that the
present is too small a window into the past
to provide the geologist with a full set of
analogs. This is true in two senses. First, by
rejecting the claims of uniformity of state,
the geologic community is acknowledging
that some of the depositional environments
of the past (e.g., epeiric seas, Bretz floods)
do not exist today; but, one can scarcely
draw a strict analogy from a nonexistent
965
966
967
Heelan, P., 1983, Natural science as a hermeneutic of instrumentation: Philosophy of Science, v. 50, p. 181204.
Heidegger, M., 1927, Sein und zeit: Tu
bingen, Germany, Neomarius Verlag, 488 p.
Heidegger, M., 1962, Being and time, Macquarrie, J., and Robinson, E., trans.: New York, Harper and Row, 589 p.
Herrick, C., and Jamieson, D., in press, The social construction of
acid rain: Some implications for science/policy assessment:
Global Environmental Change.
Hull, D. L., 1976, Central subjects and historical narratives: History and Theory 14, p. 25374.
Hull, D. L., 1981, Historical narratives and integrating explanations, in Sumner, L. W., et al., eds., Pragmatism and purpose: Toronto, Ontario, University of Toronto Press, 352 p.
Johnson, G. A., editor, 1993, The Merleau-Ponty aesthetics reader: Chicago, Northwestern University Press, 421 p.
Kitcher, P., 1993, The advancement of science: New York, Oxford
University Press, 421 p.
Kitts, D. B., 1977, The structure of geology: Dallas, Texas, SMU
Press, 180 p.
Knorr Cetina, K., 1981, The manufacture of knowledge: Oxford,
United Kingdom, and New York, Pergamon, 189 p.
Kocklemans, J., and Kisiel, T., 1970, Phenomenology and the natural sciences: Evanston, Illinois, Northwestern University
Press, 520 p.
Kornblith, H., editor, 1985, Naturalizing epistemology: Cambridge, Massachusetts, MIT Press, 478 p.
Koyre, A., 1957, From the closed world to the infinite universe:
Baltimore, Maryland, Johns Hopkins University Press,
313 p.
Kuhn, T. S., 1957, The copernican revolution: Planetary astronomy
in the development of western thought: Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press, 297 p.
Kuhn, T. S., 1970, The structure of scientific revolutions: Cambridge, Massachusetts, Harvard University Press, 210 p.
Kuhn, T. S., 1977, The essential tension: Selected studies in scientific thought and change: Chicago, Illinois, University of
Chicago Press, 366 p.
Latour, B., and Woolgar, S., 1979. Laboratory life: Beverly Hills,
California, Sage Publications, 272 p.
Laudan, R., 1987, From mineralogy to geology: Chicago, Illinois,
University of Chicago Press, 278 p.
Levi-Strauss, C., 1966, The savage mind: Chicago, Illinois, University of Chicago Press, 290 p.
Marcuse, H., 1964, One-dimensional man: Boston, Massachusetts,
Free Press, 260 p.
McPhee, J., 1981, Basin and range: New York, Farrar, Straus,
Giroux, 215 p.
Pickering, A., editor, 1992, Science as practice and culture: Chicago, Illinois, University of Chicago Press, 474 p.
Popper, K., 1953, The logic of scientific discovery: New York,
Harper and Row, 474 p.
Quine, W. V. O., 1953, From a logical point of view: Cambridge,
Massachusetts, Harvard University Press, 184 p.
Printed in U.S.A.
968