Monografia Sobre Morghentau
Monografia Sobre Morghentau
Monografia Sobre Morghentau
Scholar Commons
Graduate Theses and Dissertations
Graduate School
2006
This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate
Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact scholarcommons@usf.edu.
by
Brian A. Keaney
Date of Approval:
May 1 2006
Dedication
For Patricia
and in memory of
Moyra, Charlie and Jim
Acknowledgments
I would like to thank Professor Susan Northcutt for all her assistance over the years. I am
very grateful to Professor Mark Amen for his support, guidance and interest to and
Professor Earl Conteh-Morgan, for being a member of my thesis committee, and for his
interest and his most insightful comments. I would also like to thank Ms. Doris Kearney,
Graduate Secretary of the Department of Government and International Studies for her
support. As always, I owe a deep debt of gratitude for so much to Kathleen Paul. I also
want to thank Alexandra Keaney and Abigail Keaney who gave me the incentive to
complete this project.
Table of Contents
Abstract
ii
Introduction
Defining Realism
Chapter One
Chapter Two
32
Chapter Three
50
Chapter Four
58
Chapter Five
Conclusion
67
76
References
81
This thesis analyzes the life and career of Hans J. Morgenthau, commonly
accepted as the father of the realist paradigm within the field of international relations. It
does so by offering a dynamic revisionist account of the nature of Morgenthaus classical
realism and suggests how the approach discussed might have wider application in the
field of international relations. Traditional perspectives of Morgenthau suggest that in the
course of his career, he changed from holding what would generally be labeled a
conservative political viewpoint to a liberal political viewpoint. This thesis takes a
different starting point. It does so by suggesting that constancy, not change, was the
hallmark of Morgenthaus intellectual development. Thus, what appeared to be a shift
from right to left, was in fact merely the different applications of a consistent reading of
international relations.
Central to this interpretation of Morgenthaus work is the second innovative
argument of this thesis: that Morgenthaus realism contained within it the potential for
both conservative (as traditionally defined) and progressive (as traditionally defined)
applications. Acknowledging that realism as conservatism is already an accepted
understanding within the field of international relations, this thesis focuses on drawing
out the progressive potential of Morgenthaus realism, by proving that what appeared in
Morgenthaus later career to be an intellectual shift in fact stemmed from the
progressivism inherent in the actual existing realism of Morgenthaus early career applied
to new situations met in his later career
Based on this analysis of what has been accomplished within the framework of
classical realism by Morgenthau, it is the challenge of this thesis to invite contemporary
ii
realist thinkers to do the same. In short, the thesis invites contemporary theorists to
explore, recover and reclaim the liberatory and progressive potential of classical realism.
In so doing, the thesis suggests the potential for two new research programs. First,
reclaiming the liberatory potential of Morgenthaus approach and use of realism provides
for the creation of a new understanding of contemporary realism which can transcend
both the essentially sterile internal debates between classical and neo-realism and those
between classical realism, neo-realism and neo-classical realism. Second, foregrounding
the liberatory possibilities of classical realism offers a fruitful approach for the recreation
of common ground between realism and other more politically progressive paradigms
in contemporary international relations theory such as peace research or constructivism. It
is the final hope for this thesis that it might, by building bridges within and between
different fields, lay the foundations of a possible path for the reintegration of the whole
discipline of international relations.
iii
Introduction:
Defining Realism
Over the course of the past half-century, realism, or the attempt to understand the
behavior of states based on the recognition that international politics, like all politics, is
a struggle for power, has been one of the central paradigms in United States
International Relations theory.1 The concept of realism or realpolitik can be dated back
to Thucydides and Ancient Greece or perhaps Cardinal Richelieu of the French Ancien
Regime.2 It is, however, more commonly associated with Otto Von Bismarck, the first
Chancellor of Germany and his efforts to create a nuanced counter-balancing between the
great European powers so as to avoid a general war in the later half of the nineteenth
century.3 In the United States it is yet more commonly associated with the work of Hans
J. Morgenthau, who both as a professor at the University of Chicago, and as the author of
Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, the seminal textbook of
realist theory, articulated what came to be accepted as the foundations of a realist
understanding of the post-war Cold War world.
If Morgenthau articulated and defended realism for over thirty years from within
the academy, it was policy makers in Washington who attempted to apply its theories to
the reality of international relations. Represented in such key policies as containment the conviction on the part of U.S. policy makers that they should try and contain the
power and influence of the Soviet Union - realism came to be as central to the post-1945
Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, (New York: Alfred A.
Knopf, 1948),
2
Thucydides, The Melian Dialogue, The History of the Peloponnesian War, trans. Rex Warner
(Harmonsworth: Penguin Classics, 1954) cited in John A. Vasquez, Classics of International Relations, 3rd
Edition, (New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 1996). Cardinal Armand Jean du Plessis Richelieu, The Political
Testament of Cardinal Richelieu, trans. Henry Bertram Hill, (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press,
1964).
3
A.J.P. Taylor, Bismarck: The Man and Statesman, (New York: Knopf, 1955); David Blackbourn, A
History of Germany 1780-1918: The Long Nineteenth Century, 2nd edition, (Oxford: Blackwell, 2003).
foreign policy of the United States as it was to the field of international relations.4
Although the practical application of containment was first laid out in George F.
Kennan's famous Long Telegram, made public in 1947 in his anonymous Foreign Affairs
article "The Sources of Soviet Conduct," better known as Article X, it was Hans
Morgenthau who provided the intellectual basis for the policy.5 The readiness of United
States policymakers to embrace both the theory and practice of realism may be traced in
part to the tremendous influence exerted by Morgenthau over the future U.S.
policymaking elite. Indeed, it would not be too much to suggest that for many U.S.
diplomats, politicians and civil servants, Morgenthaus realism was the framework
through which they understood their world.
As significant as the theory of realism has proven to be to the practice of politics,
however, its importance within International Relations theory has declined. As Francis A.
Beer and Robert Hariman have pointed out, realists believe that realism is the only story
of world politics. Post-realists assert that realism is only one story among many: although
it is an important story, it provides neither the only plausible explanation nor the only
possible world.6 In a similar vein, theorists such as Alexander Wendt have argued that
contrary to realisms focus upon power and material power structures, it is ideas and
culture that govern relations between states.7
This thesis takes a different starting point. As it does so, it offers three major
conclusions. First, through an analysis of the published writings of Hans Morgenthau
over the course of his forty-year career, the thesis suggests that Morgenthau, despite
appearances to the contrary remained consistent in his thought and analyses. Simply put,
Morgenthau, in the course of his career, appeared to shift from what would generally be
labeled a conservative political viewpoint to a liberal political viewpoint. In 1948, he laid
out the basis for what would become the containment of communism in Eastern Europe
by advocating an aggressive stance toward the Soviet Union; in 1968, he argued for the
acceptance of communism in South East Asia by advocating the withdrawal of U.S.
4
Kenneth Waltz Theory of International Politics Reading. MA: Addison Wesley, 1979.
George F. Kennan "The Sources of Soviet conduct," Foreign Affairs, XXV (July, 1947), 566-82
6
Francis A. Beer and Robert Hariman, Realism and Rhetoric in International Relations, in Francis A.
Beer and Robert Hariman ed., Post Realism: The Rhetorical Turn in International Relations, (East Lansing:
Michigan State University Press, 1996), 7.
7
Alexander Wendt, Social Theory of International Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1999).
5
troops. Despite the apparent shift in thought suggested by these different policies,
however, it is the thesis of this paper that they in fact represent two sides of the same
intellectual understanding of international relations, two sides of realism.
The second conclusion offered by the thesis is contained within the first: that
realism contains within it the potential for both conservative and progressive analyses,
and that the likelihood of one or the other being suggested at any given time or in any
given situation depends on the particulars of the time and situation. Thus, contrary to
traditional understandings of realism as a purely conservative doctrine, this thesis
demonstrates that realism contains within in it a progressive, liberatory and even moral
component. It is this component which will provide the mechanism by which
Morgenthau will appear to shift from conservative to liberal. The conservative
component of realism has long been recognized. It is the aim of this thesis to break new
ground by highlighting the progressive component not as a sign of Morgenthaus
change of heart but as a sign of the progressivism inherent within realism.
Third, the thesis suggests that accepting the legitimacy of these understandings of
Morgenthau changes the manner in which Morgenthaus work should be read, and
thereby changes both our understanding of what realism really is or was meant to be, and
our understanding of the consequences of the implementation of realist theory by so
many practical disciples in the years since 1945.
In order to understand both the subtleties of Morgenthaus original concepts of
realism along with the significance of his evolving applications, it is best to begin with an
analysis of what might best be termed basic realist theory. As proposed by Morgenthau
in the first edition of Politics Among Nations, published in 1948, realism may be said to
be based on a number of key assumptions. Firstly, that the state is the central actor on the
world stage. Thus for Morgenthau, the implication is that international organizations and
other non-governmental formations, whether commercial enterprises or co-coordinated
networks of individuals of like mind, are either essentially reflective of the interests of
established sovereign states, and thus would be covered under the general rubric of his
classical realism, or are simply not relevant in terms of his paradigm. Secondly, that the
natural state of international politics is that of anarchy - anarchy not in the sense of a war
of all against all but anarchy in the sense that there is no legal authority to bind a state
when it perceives that breaking any agreement with other states is in its interests.
Morgenthau did not suggest that the international legal order of conventions, treaties,
agreements, understandings and common shared practices of states have no effect but
rather that their effect is contingent upon the value placed upon them by the states which
observe them. Thirdly, that all states will seek to have the greatest amount of power that
they possibly can. Fourth, that it is the intrinsic nature of the human actors who control
the states that causes states to behave as they do. Fifth, that in their pursuit of security or
power, states will conduct politics and adopt policies according to a rational framework.
Sixth, that force, or the ability and willingness to use force when perceived to be
necessary, is an integral part of statehood.
Building on Morgenthaus work, Kenneth Walz later adapted realist theory to
incorporate the notion that it was the international structure, not the deliberate willed
actions of men and women, which influenced states behavior. According to Walz it is
the structure of the international system itself that determines the behavior of states.8 In
the years since, Walz neo-realism, or structural realism, has of course been further
refined by other scholars. Indeed, contemporary realist theory or neo-classical realism
now contains within it a number of critical debates. There is, for example, the debate
between offensive and defensive realists. Offensive realists hold the view that the
constant ebb and flow of security and power between states guarantees that the
international system will be dominated by opportunistic states forever fearfully looking
over their shoulders at potential and actual competitors. According to this offensive
interpretation, states must continuously seek to strengthen themselves and their position
vis--vis other states, even in the absence of a directly perceived threat. As a result, the
behavior and desire of states are mainly shaped by a perception of the relative capability
of other states. Thus the unknowable future and risk of threat are characteristics of the
offensive realist.9
By contrast, defensive realists hold the view that real security is available, and
that the best way for a state to achieve it is to forgo overtly offensive postures. In other
words, because of the anarchical nature of the international environment, the security of
8
For an explication of offensive realism see, John J. Mearsheimer The Tragedy of Great
Power Politics, (New York: W.W. Norton & Company, 2001).
4
the nation is not always best achieved through a maximization of the nations power vis-vis other nations.10 According to this defensive interpretation, the international system
creates positive incentives for behavior that does not threaten the wellbeing of other
states and which thereby preserves the stability of the international system. Unlike
offensive realism which posits a direct relationship between the international system and
the policy choices that states make, defensive realism sees the matter as being more
complex, in that the relationship between the nature of the international and the
behavior of states is frequently of an indirect nature. While it is possible to present this
conflict within realism in other terms as a debate between hawkish and dovish realists,
or between optimistic and pessimistic realists the offensive/defensive characterization
seems best able to capture the two sets of counter positions.
The vitality of the debates outlined above suggests that realism is a sufficiently
thriving force in International Relations practice for theorists to want to figure it out. This
thesis represents a contribution to that debate. Specifically, it seeks to reclaim the
liberatory potential of classical realism and in so doing suggests as one of the
implications of that reclamation, a new research program which may bring about the
possibility of real and systematic integration and melding between realism and other
paradigms in the field such as constructivism and democratic peace theory. Not alone
then does this thesis seek to reclaim Morgenthaus own interpretation and application of
realism in a liberatory direction, but it also offers a path toward a new general theory of
international relations for the twenty-first century; a theory which may finally resolve the
decades old tensions between realist and idealistic or normative approaches to the field.
The thesis will begin by examining in Chapter Two Morgenthaus life, bringing
out the influences of his youth which appear to have affected his later years, but focusing
on his adult life and his formation and articulation of realism. The thesis will pay
particular attention to Morgenthaus protestations against United States policy in
Vietnam, illustrating how what has traditionally been perceived as a liberal expression of
protest more clearly fits within an enhanced understanding of realism. Indeed, the
10
Key defensive realist works include Stephen M. Walt, The Origins of Alliances (Ithaca: Cornell
University Press, 1987) and Revolution and War (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1996); Snyder, Myths of
Empire; William C. Wohlforth, The Elusive Balance: Power and Perceptions during the Cold War (Ithaca:
Cornell University Press, 1990).
argument that the issues involved in Morgenthaus appraisal of Vietnam illustrates more
clearly than anything else the combination of flexibility and constancy that was inherent
within Morgenthaus understanding of realism is a thread which will run throughout the
thesis.
Chapter Three looks at the various editions of Politics Among Nations, drawing
out the core paradigm of realism while also illustrating how Morgenthau adapted each
edition to suit changing times. Chapter Four and Five consider selections of
Morgenthaus other published works, again using them to show the consistency with
which Morgenthau approached the issue of international relations. Chapter Six focuses on
Morgenthaus published reviews of the work of other scholars. More than some
academics, Morgenthau used the opportunity created by these reviews to articulate his
own views, judging a book largely by whether it fitted within his framework or not,
whether it offered a helpful lens through which to view the field and practice of
international relations. Finally, Chapter Seven, the conclusion, places Morgenthaus
achievements in a larger context, offering suggestions for future research. Before we can
appreciate the significance of Morgenthau the scholar, however, we need to learn
something of Morgenthau the man. It is to that task that we now turn.
Chapter One:
Morgenthau: From Realist to Realist
Hans J. Morgenthau, An Intellectual Autobiography: 1904-1932, Society, Vol. 15, No. 2, (Jan/Feb,
1978), 63-69.
12
This charming picture was published in Morgenthau, An Intellectual Autobiography, 63.
13
Christopher Frei., Hans J. Morgenthau. An Intellectual Biography, (Baton Rouge: Louisiana State
University Press, 2001), 13.
14
Frei.. Hans J. Morgenthau, 13. Morgenthau, Johnson interview, quoted in Frie, p.15.
15
Frei.. Hans J. Morgenthau, 15. Morgenthau recorded this view in a school composition written in
March, 1918.
16
Morgenthau, An Intellectual Autobiography, 63.
turmoil in America caused by the Vietnam War was hardly akin to that caused by the rise
of the Nazis, and while a number of intensive tax audits hardly compared with
persecution by the Gestapo, still in his own work, Morgenthau held by his convictions,
refusing to concede when it might have made him more popular with the authorities to
have done so.
Morgenthau graduated from Munich in February 1927 and immediately began
training as a lawyer. The professional part of his training consisted of a series of
placements with various government departments. His main work focused on drafting
briefs on points of criminal and labor law. Whilst Morgenthau found this work to be
sometimes fascinating as an intellectual exercise, he perceived the questions with which
it dealt to be marginal to the crucial issues with which society had to come to terms.
According to Morgenthau what really mattered in contemporary Germany was not the
merits of different legal interpretations but the distribution of political power.21 In the
context of Weimar Germany, a democratic government facing threats from all sides,
Morgenthaus analysis certainly makes sense and helps explain perhaps his later
perception that power and the nature of its distribution were the core issues within
society.
As he trained, Morgenthau commenced work on his doctorate at the University of
Frankfurt which he completed in 1929 with a thesis entitled The International Judicial
Function and the Concept of Politics. Morgenthau had first become interested in the
topic of international law under the tutelage of Professor Karl Neumeyer at the University
of Munich. Building on his work with Neumeyer, which had led him to the conclusion
that international law was a particularly weak kind of law, Morgenthau in his thesis
suggested that its weakness stemmed from the intrusion of international politics.
Taking this discovery one step further prompted Morgenthau to issue what would come
to be the essence of his later work: what really mattered in relations between nations
was not international law but international politics.22 Thus we see that the constancy that
would later come to be a hallmark of Morgenthaus realist thought after Politics Among
Nations, was in fact already a part of his intellectual framework twenty years before. His
21
22
experience in the German law courts, his experience in the archives, and his experience
living in Weimar Germany, convinced him of the twin propositions that what mattered in
any society was power, and the nature of its distribution, and that what mattered in
international relations was politics not law, or as he would later phrase it, the politics of
power as it was actually was, not the aspirations of how things should be.
Morgenthaus last legal position, toward the end of 1931, was that of Acting
President of the Labor Law Court in Frankfurt. He found the experience dissatisfying,
however, and returned to his earlier focus upon an academic career. To achieve this he
needed to complete his habilitation, an advanced doctorate. With no openings available in
his own university Morgenthau took leave from his judicial function in February 1932
and went to Geneva to enroll in the Graduate Institute for International Studies, taking a
position as an instructor in German public law at the University of Geneva. His time in
Switzerland was not overly happy, however, as he grappled with anti-Semitic students,
fought with his colleagues, was unable to teach as much as he would have liked, and
found himself in sufficient financial peril that he had to supplement his university stipend
with some journalism. Perhaps in part as a result of these difficulties, Morgenthau
initially failed his habilitation, although he did, after much effort, eventually get this
decision reversed. Unfortunately, however, even if he had wanted to return to his post as
a judge, from which he had been on leave-of-absence since 1931, it would have been
impossible for at this point the national history of Germany caught up with Morgenthau
and as a result of the Nazi Law for the Restoration of the Career Civil Service,
Morgenthau was purged on 17 November 1933 from his position with the Frankfurt
Labor Court.23
The next four years were cumulatively quite difficult for Morgenthau, being
marked by his attempts to secure employment, of a kind he found amenable, wherever he
could quite a difficult task for a Jewish refugee in the 1930s. Morgenthau was initially
fortunate, however, that two years later, when his time in Switzerland came to an end,
and he was unable to return to Germany, he received assistance from the Emergency
Committee for German Scholars Abroad which arranged for him, in 1935, to go to Spain.
There he joined the faculty of the newly-created Institute of International and Economic
23
10
11
Morgenthau maintained his conservatism even to the extent of having difficulty with
students over his anti-communist position.28 In light of these difficulties, it is perhaps
not surprising that Morgenthau was happy to leave Brooklyn in 1939 for a full time job at
the University of Kansas City, even though the position carried a heavy teaching load of
18 hours split between the Liberal Arts College and the School of Law.29 Even at Kansas,
however, Morgenthau continued to be dogged by controversy. Feuding with the
administration, for example, resulted in his being fired, and although, rather like his
experience with habilitation in Germany, he later forced the decision to be reversed, he
made few friends in Kansas. Despite the feuds, however, he did take the opportunity to
become both a U.S. citizen and a member of the Missouri Bar.30 In September 1943
Morgenthaus life took a dramatic turn - perhaps even more significant for Morgenthau
than his original entry into the United States: he was offered the opportunity to leave
Kansas by replacing Quincy Wright for 6 months at the University of Chicago.31 The
position was to be the making of Morgenthau.
At Chicago, first as a visiting and subsequently as a permanent Associate
Professor, Morgenthau began work in the then new interdisciplinary subject of
International Relations. In 1946 he published his first monograph, Scientific Man versus
Power Politics. Following this success, Morgenthau turned his attention to what was to
be his greatest work, Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, the
first edition of which was published in September 1948. The book was immensely
popular, filling a gap in the market for an up to date text to supply the growing population
of US universities. Proving far more popular than its main competitor, Fredrick
Schumans International Politics, Morgenthaus book was the first coherent text that
sought to make sense of the postwar world. On the strength of this success Morgenthau
became a Full Professor in 1949 at the age of 45, and in 1950 was awarded funding to set
up the Center for the Study of American Foreign and Military Policy in 1950 of which he
remained the Director until 1968.32
It was during these years that Morgenthaus work became an essential fixture on
28
12
the syllabi of so many courses in International Relations taught across the country, and
during this same time that realism became an integral part of IR theory. Indeed within a
month of the books publication, it was adopted as a textbook for foreign policy and
international relations by Harvard, Yale, Princeton, Columbia and Notre Dame, and
within six months by ninety additional colleges.33 Arguing that "international politics,
like all politics, is a struggle for power," Morgenthau proposed that the only correct
approach to the conduct of United States foreign policy was an approach based on the
tenets of realism.34 Thus, only a robust application of balance of power politics would be
sure to generate the most positive possible outcome for the United States. After the
publication of Politics Among Nations, Morgenthau found himself with the opportunity to
express his concerns on an increasingly broad canvas.
He did so within the context of the Cold War. While the origins of this ideological
conflict between the United States and the Soviet Union can be traced back to 1917 and
Lenins subsequent announcement of the Third International, the years immediately after
1945 saw the conflict between the two remaining super powers escalate into a full-scale
Cold War.35 As might be expected given both his background and his current residency,
Morgenthau backed the United States. More than this, he specifically advocated an
aggressive realist approach to U.S. foreign policy, an approach predicated less on
securing an ideal peace between nations and more on recognizing that peace in the longterm could only be achieved through a realistic assessment of national interest. In short,
Morgenthau believed that the United States should practice what he preached.36
33
36
For an analysis of realism in action in U.S. foreign policy, see Joel H. Rosenthal, Righteous Realists :
Political Realism, Responsible Power, and American Culture in the Nuclear Age (Baton Rouge: Louisiana
State University Press, 1991).
13
This presumed relationship between what Morgenthau taught and what U.S.
diplomats practiced worked well throughout the 1950s. The result was Morgenthaus
increasing academic stature as he was offered Visiting Professorships across the country,
including positions at Berkeley, Harvard, Northwestern, Columbia and Yale. His
perceived direct relevance to future policy makers, militarists and analysts may be
gauged from his frequent invitations to lecture at the Armed Forces Staff College, the
NATO Defense College, and the Air, Army, Navy and National War Colleges, as well as
his association with the Washington Center for Foreign Policy Research.37 In all, and
standing testament to his significance to the field, Morgenthau delivered over 1300
formal guest lectures between 1950 and 1980.38
In addition to his academic credits, Morgenthau throughout the 1950s grew in
political fame as others perceived him to be a theorist willing and able to intervene and
advise on matters of current policy. Thus, at the invitation of George Kennan, the author
of the famous Long Telegram in 1947 which had first outlined the case for the policy of
containment subsequently implemented by President Harry S. Truman, Morgenthau had
right of audience at the State Department Planning Committee between 1948 and 1951 the key years of the development of the realism-based policy of containment.39 In 1951
the State Department drew upon Morgenthaus presumed area of natural interest and
expertise by asking him to make an official visit to occupied Austria and to offer advice
on the removal of Allied control and the restoration of sovereignty. Building on this visit,
and perhaps in recognition of the larger relevance assigned to Morgenthaus work, the
Department subsequently invited Morgenthau to visit South East Asia in 1954. The visit
proved to be the start of a turning point in Morgenthaus career causing him ultimately to
come into conflict with the practitioners of policy within the U.S. Government.40
Warnings About Vietnam
37
Hans Joachim Morgenthau, Current Biography 1963, ed. Charles Moritz, (New York: The M.W.
Wilson Company, 1963), 276.
38
Frie, Hans J. Morgenthau, 75.
39
Frie, Hans J. Morgenthau, 77, note 64.
40
Frie, Hans J. Morgenthau, 77, note 64. Frie records that Morgenthau also served as a Defense
Department advisor between 1963 and 1965, although little actual use was made of his expertise at this
time.
14
During his visit Morgenthau had the opportunity to make the acquaintance of
South Vietnamese policymakers of the highest level, including a meeting with Ngo Dinh
Diem himself. Morgenthau published the findings of his trip to South East Asia in a
series of articles in The New Republic. In these essays Morgenthau sounded a note of
warning. At first glance the warning might have appeared odd, in light of the fact that
U.S. policy in South East Asia appeared to be based on the very theories of realism
propounded by Morgenthau in the classrooms of Chicago. Visiting Vietnam, however,
and seeing the consequences of U.S. involvement in the region, prompted Morgenthau to
analyze the likely causes and consequences behind the U.S. presence. Outlining the
situation, Morgenthau described the war as consisting of one superpower engaged in
warfare and diplomacy in a region outside its direct and natural area of concern, and
another much smaller power engaged in (depending on ones point of view) a civil war or
at the very least local war.41
Thus right from the beginning of his association with Vietnam, Morgenthau
expressed reservations about U.S policy. In particular, Morgenthau had a fundamentally
hesitant view about John Foster Dulles, Secretary of State under President Dwight D.
Eisenhower from 1953 to 1959. In his piece on Dulles published in 1961 as a chapter in
An Uncertain Tradition: American Secretaries of State in the Twentieth Century,
Morgenthau fiercely criticized the development of U.S. foreign policy under Dulles.42
Suggesting that Dulles was simply not up to the task, and furthermore was one who gave
the impression to those with whom he dealt of being deceptive, Morgenthau evidenced
his growing disillusionment with those in government who were in charge of the conduct
of U.S. foreign affairs. After his first experience of Vietnam, Morgenthaus growing
disillusionment with the actual conduct of foreign policy became more obvious through
his writings and public pronouncements over the course of the next few years. Thus
although Morgenthau acted as a consultant for the Department of Defense as late as 1962,
his growing disenchantment with the actual conduct of the foreign policy of the United
41
Hans J. Morgenthau, The Immaturity of our Asian Policy , reprinted as The Immaturity of our Asian
Policy, in Hans J. Morgenthau, The Impasse of American Foreign Policy, (Chicago: University of
Chicago, 1962), 251-277.
42
Reprinted as John Foster Dulles, in Hans J. Morgenthau, Truth and Power, (New York: Praeger, 1970),
87-108.
15
Hans J. Morgenthau, We Are Deluding Ourselves in Vietnam, New York Times, April 18, 1965.
Op. cit., p. 85.
45
Op. cit., p. 85.
44
16
Politics Among Nations and its realist approach might be said to have provided a critical
part of the intellectual framework for the development of the policy of containment. The
paradox is easily resolved, however. Realism expects nation states to act according to
their perceived self-interest. In his call for withdrawal and an effective acceptance of a
communist Vietnam, Morgenthau was not suggesting that the United States abandon its
natural self-interest. Rather, he was suggesting that the Cold War and the general fight
against communism, though first targeted effectively against a Soviet Union perceived to
be ideologically and territorially expansionist, had now blinded United States
policymakers to the real interests of their state. For this blinding Morgenthau placed a
great deal of responsibility on John Foster Dulles: it is ironic that this simple
juxtaposition of Communism and Free World was erected by John Foster Dulles
crusading moralism into the guiding principle of American foreign policy when the
national communism of Yugoslavia, the neutralism of the Third World and the incipient
split between the Soviet Union and China were rendering that juxtaposition invalid.46
Accusing policymakers of being blind to the United States real interests and
focusing his critique upon one individual allowed Morgenthau to present his argument
still within a realist framework. For what is significant about Morgenthaus reasoning is
that it was based not on a moral assessment of U.S. policy but rather on a realist analysis
of what actions or policies in the given circumstances would best serve the interests of
the United States. Thus Morgenthau explained, for better or for worse we live again in
an age of revolution. It is the task of statesmanship not to oppose what cannot be opposed
with a chance of success but to bend it to ones own interests.47 Bismarck himself could
hardly have phrased it better. In effect, it was no longer a realist policy for the United
States to continue a military engagement in South East Asia. Quite the contrary. The
realist policy would be to accept what could not be changed the presence of
communism in the region and figure out how best to turn that presence to the advantage
of the United States.
If Morgenthau blamed Dulles for the mis-application of containment, he also
blamed Diem for changing the rules of the game within Vietnam. According to
46
47
17
48
At a peace conference in 1954 the French and North Vietnamese had agreed to a temporary division of
the country at the 17th parallel. The French ih in the South and the Army of North Vietnam in the North.
49
Morgenthau, Deluding Ourselves, New York Times, 85.
50
Op. cit, p. 87.
51
James Reston, Ann Arbor: The Strange Bedfellows in Vietnam, New York Times, 2 May, 1965, E10.
Joseph Alsop was an influential political journalist and commentator with easy access to the thinking
behind government policy at very high levels. See generally, Robert W. Merry, Taking on the World:
Joseph and Stewart Alsop: Guardians of the American Century (New York: Viking, 1996).
18
19
articulate his opposition to the war in a variety of formats. Just a few days after the
Teach-In, for example, Moregenthau debated Frank Sieverts, a former State Department
official of hawkish mien, at the New School for Social Research in New York.55
Similarly, on 21 June 1965 he participated in a CBS News Special debate between
McGeorge Bundy, National Security Advisor for Presidents Kennedy and Johnson from
1961-1966, Zbigniew Brezinski, G. J. Pauker, Rand Institute Asia specialist, O. Edmund
Club, a former Asian expert who had been forced out of the State Department during the
Eisenhower purges, and John D. Donahue, a former advisor to the South Vietnamese
government.
In addition to speaking against the war, Morgenthau, perhaps inspired by his own
position as a public academic (or telly-don), also articulated his views upon the correct
role of intellectuals in society. According to Morgenthau, in an essay published in The
New Republic in 1966, the intellectual was faced with a number of choices. First, he
could excuse himself from the political world altogether; second, he could offer policy
advice whilst remaining detached from the political process; and finally, he could
actively involve himself in the world of politics as an expert. In light of the active
political life adopted by Morgenthau, both during the height of the early Cold War and
later with regard to Vietnam, and based on the lives and careers of academics he had
admired as a student, it was clear that it was his belief that the intellectual had an
obligation to help guide and improve government policy, to involve himself in the world
of politics as an expert. Significantly, however, this role was to be played not as a
politician, but as an academic expert, for it was the very fact of being an outsider, or
depending on ones point of view an insider protected from the outside that protected the
academic from the pressures of politics. As Morgenthau phrased it, it was his
immunity from outside pressure, manifested through job security through tenure that
gave the academic the freedom to criticize and advise. Referring specifically to his own
situation, Morgenthau continued:
This immunity provides the academic with opportunity as well as with
temptation. He has the freedom to speak truth to power without needing to be
afraid of more than irritating reprisals of the powers that be. The White House
could threaten me with the FBI, and make the Internal Revenue Service waste
55
New School Slates Debate on Vietnam, New York Times, 21 May 1965, 13.
20
many man powers on repeated audits of my income tax return; it could order the
Secretary of Defense to fire me as consultant to the Department of Defense,
banish me from the councils of government, and ostracize me socially. But it
could not deprive me of my livelihood or of my freedom to speak and write in so
far as the media were willing to resist its pressure to deny me a hearing.56
With these words, Morgenthau both challenged his harassment by the government
and questioned President Johnsons commitment to the democratic process. Johnson,
according to Morgenthau, equated dissent with disloyalty.57 Comparing Johnson
with some of his predecessors, Morgenthau suggested I have taken a look at Woodrow
Wilsons and Franklin D. Roosevelts attitudes towards domestic dissent and I have been
struck not by the similarity but by the differences between their democratic ethos and the
climate of opinion prevailing today.58 Extending his argument in order to defend Senator
Fulbright, also under criticism from Johnson, Morgenthau claimed that. the President
has never deigned to argue with the Senator but has ridiculed and mimicked him and
treated him with contempt in public and to his face. White House-broken journalists have
taken their cue and have treated a brilliant, knowledgeable and high-minded public
servant as though he were an ignorant, irresponsible fool. Morgenthau continued his
attack by suggesting that the treatment to which Fulbright had been subjected was not
unique. It is but a particularly spectacular and distressing example of a general policy.
The White House project Morgenthau which in 1965 had the task to disseminate
information about me reflects the same general attitude.
It is clear from Morgenthaus writings of this era that he firmly believed himself
to be the victim of a harassment campaign by the White House. Indeed as David Sanford
later pointed out in his piece in The New Republic in 1969, Morgenthaus son Matthew
was drafted even though he was in a category of men (for medical reasons) not usually
drafted. Furthermore, claimed Sanford, Matthew was persecuted and court-martialed
during his basic training in Alabama, essentially because of his fathers political
statements against the war.59 What matters here, is not so much whether either Hans or
56
Hans J. Morgenthau, Truth and Power: The Intellectuals and the Johnson Administration, reprinted in
Truth and Power: Essays of A Decade (New York: Praeger, 1970), 13-28.
57
Op. cit., 20.
58
Op. cit., 20.
59
David Sanford, Matthew Morgenthaus Complaint, The New Republic, March 1, 1969, 14.
21
Matthew Morgenthau were actually the targets of harassment but that they believed
themselves to be so and acted and wrote accordingly.
In light of Morgenthaus past experiences both as a refugee from Nazi Germany
and as an observer of the McCarthy Era, his apparent surprise and anger at his treatment
by the White House might appear as somewhat nave: he surely must have experienced
and seen far worse than a few intensive tax audits, or even the unwarranted drafting of his
son. In fact, his response is, I believe, comprehensible within the context of
Morgenthaus status as an immigrant whereby he, like many immigrants, thought better
of the country he had chosen to call home and the country which had given him better
hospitality than his own. Thus, in his expectations of government behavior, Morgenthau
the refugee, thinking well of his adopted homeland, overwhelmed Morgenthau the
intellectual who could expect nothing but realpolitik from the governments of nation
states.
Perhaps understandably in light of what he perceived to be the nature of his own
situation, and aggravated by his belief in the responsibility of the intellectual to engage
with the needs of society and government, Morgenthau had little sympathy with
academics who either chose to stay on the political sidelines, or worse, chose to enter the
fray in absolute and fixed support of the government. Morgenthau offered a searing
critique of the academy when he suggested that the military-industrial complex against
which President Eisenhower had warned had been duplicated by an academic-political
complex in which the interests of the government are inextricably intertwined with the
interests of large groups of academics. Furthermore, the intimate connection that
research contracts have established between the government and the universities have
recently been brought to public attention. It stands to reason that an academic who is
working on such a contract or who expects to work on one is not likely to question the
basic policies of the government either within his contractual research or outside it. As a
result, according to Morgenthau, the interests and expectations of the government not
only determine the subject matter of contractual research but also influence ever so subtly
its scope and in a certain measure its results. 60 Morgenthaus understanding of both the
ideal and the actual relationship between academics and governments was undoubtedly
60
22
shaped by his own experiences most recently through his work with the State
Department but also by his earlier work in Spain, and perhaps even by his observations of
the role played by Carl Schmitt in Hitlers Germany.61
Carl Schmitt, a professor of Public Law at the University of Berlin, had published a short book entitled
The Concept of Politics in 1921. Morgenthau considered his doctors thesis at least partly a response to
Schmitt. While recognizing Schmitts superior intellectual endowments, Morgenthau made clear both in
writing and in conversations that he doubted that any German thinker surpassed Schmitt in subservience to
the Nazis and lack of principle. For Morgenthau, the most compelling evidence was Schmitts defense of
Hitlers blood purge of 1934 on the grounds that the will of the Fuhrer was the supreme law of the land.
Never denying Schmitts brilliance, Morgenthau found him the most evil man alive. Morgenthau, An
Intellectual Biography, 68.
62
Hans J. Morgenthau, How Totalitarianism starts: The Domestic Involvement of the CIA, The Christian
Science Monitor, March 10, 1967, reprinted in Truth and Power: Essays of A Decade (New York: Praeger,
1970), 51-55.
63
Op. cit., 54.
64
Op. cit., p.51.
65
Op. cit., p.51.
23
suggested that had the Government had more confidence in the strength of a free
democracy than in the efficiency of pseudo-totalitarian methods, it could have served the
national interest without paying so heavy a price. Internationally, all individuals and
organizations speaking on behalf of the United States will from now on be suspect as
secret agents of the government.66 Morgenthau virulently criticized the policymakers for
having created a situation where domestically the moral confidence of the people in
their government has been shaken. This is not a moral crisis affecting this particular
Administration but a moral crisis affecting American democracy. Contrasting the
sixteenth century perception of diplomats as honest men sent abroad to lie for their
country, Morgenthau suggested that in the twentieth century public officials were
increasingly perceived to be honest men staying at home to lie for the government.67
Arguing that the government practiced systematic deception paralleling that practiced by
the CIA. Morgenthau asserted that this philosophy was not of democracy but of
totalitarianism. Furthermore argued Morgenthau, as the integrity and independence of
the government have been subverted by the military industrial complex, so the integrity
and independence of the educational community have been impaired by the academicpolitical complex. The educational community has in large measure become the
handmaid of government, while maintaining its pretence to independence. Offering a
solution to the problems raised by the disclosures of government deception, Morgenthau
called for a radical moral reorientation of both the government and the academic
community.68
Morgenthau took his political engagement to its logical conclusion by involving
himself in the 1968 Presidential campaign as an advisor to Eugene McCarthy. Following
Johnsons dramatic withdrawal, Morgenthau put his experience of international affairs at
McCarthys disposal, and became a charter member of a special advisory panel on
foreign policy put together by McCarthy.69 Under the chairmanship of Stanley Hoffman
of Harvard University, Morgenthau served alongside Quincy Wright, formerly of the
University of Virginia, John Kenneth Galbraith then teaching economics at Harvard, and
66
Hans J. Morgenthau, Truth and Power: Essays of A Decade (New York, Praeger, 1970), 52.
Hans J. Morgenthau, Truth and Power: Essays of A Decade (New York, Praeger, 1970), 52.
68
Hans J. Morgenthau, Truth and Power: Essays of A Decade (New York, Praeger, 1970), 53.
69
New York Times, 5 August, 1968.
67
24
Gabriel Almond then of Stanford University, but formerly of the University of Chicago,
and the serving president of the American Political Science Association. Morgenthau
made his support of McCarthy public through an article in the New York Review of
Books, then a relatively newly established liberal counterweight to Commentary.
Given that Morgenthau had described U.S. foreign policy toward Vietnam as
being in part a function of the psychopathology of certain individuals, he offered a
contrasting image of McCarthy, writing that what struck me again the other dayis
the complete absence of any visible contrast between the public role he plays and the man
he is.70 Morgenthau supported McCarthy for three reasons. Firstly, he would restore
a philosophy of government and of the American purpose that is in tune with the
genius of the American people.71 Secondly, he can move large masses of the
American people and, more particularly, of the younger generation back into active
participation in the democratic process. Thirdly, he presents clear cut alternatives to the
policies of the present administration as well as of his competitors. With regard to
foreign policy, Morgenthau argued that McCarthys policies would be in essence
common sense restored to its rightful place.72 Emphasizing his support, Morgenthau
quoted approvingly from McCarthys own work, The Limits of Power: our foreign
policy should be more restrained and in so far as prudent judgment can determine more
closely in keeping with the movement of history.73 Taking a sideswipe at Johnsons
Vice President Hubert Humphrey by attacking Zbigniew Brzezinski who had been
Humphreys primary foreign policy advisor, Morgenthau claimed that, McCarthy does
not believe in the philosophy of American paramountcy as propounded by Professor
Brzezinski.74 Furthermore proposed Morgenthau, the United States should, if it sought
to influence other states, focus on its own domestic policies first. Thus we serve our
goal of promoting racial justice throughout the world better by setting an example in the
ordering of our race relations at home than by exerting pressure on South Africa.75
Morgenthau concluded by suggesting that the American mission was not to dominate but
70
New York Review of Books, 22 August, 1968, quoted in Truth and Power, 191.
Op. cit., p. 192.
72
Op. cit., 192.
73
Op. cit., 193.
74
Op. cit., 193.
75
Op. cit., 193.
71
25
to lead.
In his support for McCarthy, Morgenthau succeeded in defending his own past
theories of realism even as he criticized their subsequent mis-application by particular
policymakers. According to Morgenthau, McCarthy was convinced that the great
innovations that radically transformed American policy in the Spring of 1947 the policy
of containment, the Truman Doctrine, the Marshall Plan are irreversible but he also
believes that these policies suffer from two major deficiencies:they have not been
adapted to drastically changed circumstances, and they have been corrupted by a
disproportionate emphasis on military measures.76 With this analysis Morgenthau
defended both realism and Politics Among Nations, considered by some to be as much a
part of the process of arming for the Cold War as any military preparations. In particular,
and perhaps fittingly in light of the wars significance to his own intellectual
development, Morgenthau drew on his own service to government as a means of
attacking Humphrey. Specifically he made clear that from personal observation, the war
could have had no more genuinely committed supporter than the Vice President. It is only
now, in an election year, that the Vice President feels compelled to make this appear to be
Mr. Johnsons war but not necessarily Mr. Humphreys.77
By November 1968, the Democratic Party had made its choice. The Chicago
Nominating Convention had come and gone and the American people were about to go to
the polls. In his piece Nixon versus Humphrey: The Choice, Morgenthau explained the
absolute importance of the coming election by suggesting rather dramatically that the
very survival of American democracy depended upon the elections outcome.78
Morgenthau believed that the threat to democracy came from two directions: on the one
hand, the lack of any clear difference in terms of substantive policy between Humphrey
and Nixon; on the other from the Wallace ticket.79 By election time with the possibility of
a successful Wallace-LeMay ticket, no matter how unlikely this really was, Morgenthau
argued for the lesser of two evils. In the absence of a vote which would put Wallace into
76
26
the White House and LeMay into the U.S. Naval Observatory, Morgenthau suggested if
the choice were simply between Humphrey and Nixon within the traditional context of a
two-party system, I would have said that the choice is a matter of political taste but not
political judgment since there is really nothing to choose between their qualifications.
There is no lesser evil to be preferred since both candidates portend evils different in kind
but not in degree. In the concrete circumstances of the perceived possibility of a Wallace
Presidency, however, Morgenthau argued that it was the candidate who was best capable
of stopping such an event who should be supported. Making the case that not alone
would it be necessary to stop Wallace in 1968 but also in 1972, Morgenthau argued that
American democracy seems to be best served not only by Nixons victory in 1968 but
also by a defeat of the Democratic Party so drastic as to amount to the disavowal of its
present leadership, philosophy, and policies and to render inevitable the radical
transformation of its philosophy and structure. Morgenthau continued for without such
a defeatthe Democratic Party may consistently and on a large scaleact out what
Wallace preaches. Only if the Democratic Party of Johnson and those of a similar world
view are defeated, only then will the men who could have saved it in 1968 the
Kennendys, the McCarthys, the McGoverns and their heirs have a chance to save it in
1972.80
Drastic words indeed. In the event, Nixon did win the election but contrary to
Morgenthaus hopes, the Democratic Party did not take this as a sign of a need to reinvent itself and subsequently lost the next election too. By that time, however,
Morgenthau had already removed himself from the center of political affairs by
transferring from Chicago to New York where he taught at the New School with the rank
of full City University of New York Professor until his retirement from full time teaching
in 1974. Even then, however, he found it difficult to give everything up and so continued
to teach a light load at the New School. He also continued to involve himself, albeit
gently, with progressive affairs, serving, for example, as the Chair of The Academic
Committee for Soviet Jewry, helping to facilitate the emigration of Soviet Jewish
80
27
81
M. Benjamin Mollov, Jewrys Prophetic Challenge to Soviet and Other Totalitarian Regimes According
to Hans J. Morgenthau, Journal of Church and State, v. 39 (Summer 1997), 561-75.
82
Op.cit.,563
83
Hans J. Morgenthau, The Pathology of American Power, International Security, Vol. 1, No. 3 (Winter,
1977), 3-20.
28
interest.84
According to Morgenthau neither the continuation of poverty nor the
militarization of American life could in any sense be considered as reflective of U.S.
national interests. Thus, according to any realist interpretation of the political system, it
behoved America to solve these problems first, before it engaged in issues beyond its
immediate concern. From this perspective Morgenthau may be seen to be far more
consistent than has previously been thought to be the case. He articulated a realist
framework (with all the potential for military engagement that framework implied) in
order to meet what he perceived to be the very real threat of Soviet expansionism; he
advocated withdrawal from Vietnam when he perceived it to be against Americas
national interests to remain militarily committed; and he called for resolution of
Americas most pressing and most divisive domestic problems because he perceived such
resolution and resultant domestic unity to be in the countrys long-term interests.
In much the same way, one might argue, did Bismarck institute old age pensions
and a limited form of sickness insurance: not because he believed in the worth of the
programs as a means of helping German citizens, but because he perceived their
institution to be a means of undercutting support for the Social Democratic Party, a much
more important objective for the German Empire than the financial costs of any programs
of relief. Thus the larger national security interests of Germany were preserved even if
the actual policies implemented appeared contrary to the innate conservatism of the
government. Likewise, the larger national security interests of the United States, the
preservation of the state, dictated the resolution of domestic divisions even though the
implementation of policies such as welfare relief, or anti-racist initiatives might appear
contrary to the general conservatism of the government.
Thus, as I suggested in my introduction, realism, whether propounded by
Bismarck or Morgenthau was a conservative doctrine, being based on the assumption that
states, under perceived conditions of relative scarcity of essential resources, would pursue
power, as defined by national interest and survival. This realism contained within it,
however, a progressive liberatory potential since in order to preserve the state, it allowed
84
Hans. J. Morgenthau. Foreword Arnold S. Kaufman, The Radical Liberal: New Man in American Politics
(New York: Simon and Schuster, 1970), ii.
29
for the implementation of a wide range of policies both in the domestic and foreign
policy sphere - the value of which was to be judged according to their utility to the
interests of the state, not according to a narrowly defined expression of political bias.
Thus Morgenthau in advocating the containment of communism in Western Europe had
begun his academic career as a realist, and despite appearances to the contrary, he had, by
advocating the acceptance of communism in South East Asia, ended it as a realist. This
combination of progressivism and constancy was perhaps most obvious when
Morgenthau involved himself in popular and public politics. It was also obvious,
however, if one read Morgenthaus realist masterpiece, Politics Among Nations, with the
same attention to detail with which he wrote it. It is time now to do just that.
30
Chapter Two
Politics Among Nations: The Duality of Realism
Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace was Morgenthaus
masterpiece. First published in 1948, successive editions appeared in 1953, 1960, 1967,
1973, 1978 and 1985.85 While each edition carried the same title, however, the sum total
over the course of Morgenthaus career really amounts to more than one book republished six times.86 Indeed a close reading of the text of each edition suggests that
Morgenthau should more properly be credited with producing a corpus of work
representing a lifetimes thought and analysis. Specifically, over the course of his six
editions, Morgenthau examined the most fitting and profitable role to be adopted by
states in international relations, the means by which states acquired and maintained
power, and the most likely means by which states might attain and preserve peace. More
succinctly, with each edition of Politics Among Nations, Morgenthau shaped the very
field of international relations according to his conception not of how the world should or
could work in the future but how it actually worked right now.
While the substance of each edition remained largely the same, what changed, and
what highlights the consistency of Morgenthaus analysis was the manner in which
Morgenthau made clear how his theories, the theories first presented in 1948, could and
should be understood and implemented in the light of the changed political environment
85
I have elected to confine my analysis of Politics Among Nations to the editions on which Morgenthau
personally worked. The final edition, the Sixth, published in 1985, while still reflecting Morgenthaus core
theories also included elements of the work of its editor, Kenneth Thompson. For that reason, its analysis
fits better into a study of evolving theories of International Relations rather than a study of Hans
Morgenthau.
86
Proof of this assertion might be found in Thomas C. Walkers recollection that when as students he and
John Vasquez discussed Politics Among Nations, they found the editions to be so different as to make them
question whether we had indeed read the same book. Thomas C. Walker, Introduction: Morgenthaus
Dual Approach to International Politics, International Studies Notes, Vol. 24, No. 1, 1999.
31
of the moment.87 Thus while it is appropriate to claim originality in each edition, and
while students reading different editions might well be struck by the differences between
them, it is also true that at heart, each edition contained the same essential premise. What
was constant for Morgenthau throughout his career was his belief that the core of his
arguments remained the same, even as the situations to which they must be applied
changed over time. Thus this chapter follows the mold created by its predecessor and
seeks to prove that appearances to the contrary notwithstanding - six editions in thirty
years - Politics Among Nations represents two critical elements of Morgenthaus political
thought: it was simultaneously constant yet flexible and contained within it the potential
for both conservative and liberatory applications.
Perhaps unusually, the bulk of the material from which Morgenthau prepared the
first edition of Politics Among Nations consisted not of archival notes, nor even of his
own notes of other books or case studies, but rather tape recordings made of his lectures
at the University of Chicago. As Kenneth W. Thompson, one of Morgenthaus research
assistants reported, it was a tradition of students to tape the better professors, whose
words were thought likely to be destined for posterity.88 Morgenthau was one of these
professors, and it was the tapes and subsequent transcript by one particular graduate
student, Mary Jane Benowitz, along with research and transcribing carried out by
Thompson, which provided Morgenthau, who lectured without notes, with a written copy
of both his lectures and what would prove to be the outline for his book. Morgenthau
recognized his debt to Benowitz in the preface of the first edition. Over the course of
succeeding years, many other students helped Morgenthau organize both his thoughts and
his writing. In this sense at least, one might even suggest that Politics Among Nations
was something of a collaborative work. If it was, however, it was so only in the laborintensive parts of its production. For as useful as Morgenthau found his research team, he
87
John A. Vasquez, The Power of Power Politics: From Classical Realism to Neo-traditionalism,
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 36.
88
Kenneth W. Thompson, The Writing of Politics Among Nations: Its Sources and its Origins,
International Studies Notes, Vol. 24, No. 1, 1999.
32
rarely discussed the origins of his work nor shared his analysis of its implications but
rather used his students as a resource, asking them to provide copies of particular events
or case studies for his review. Thus while students provided the material, Morgenthau
provided the conceptual framework into which it was placed.
Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, (New York: Alfred A.
Knopf, 1948), Forward.
90
Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations, 1948.
91
Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations, 1948, 9.
33
Six years later Politics Among Nations was reissued as a Second Edition. In the
Preface Morgenthau took great pains to emphasize the distinctions between the two
92
34
editions, and in so doing revealed as much about the context of the first edition as about
the second. Morgenthau explained the considerable changes which he had made to this
edition by referencing the new developments during the last six years in the intellectual
climate of the United States, the conditions of world politics, and the mind of the
author.97 Specifically, Morgenthau drew the readers attention to the circumstances
surrounding the production of his first edition, the result of an intellectual experience of
twenty years. Its origins lay in a period when a false conception of foreign policy, put
into practice by the western democracies, [had] led inevitably to the threat and the
actuality of totalitarianism and war. 98 Clearly Morgenthau had been deeply affected by
what he perceived to be the betrayal of appeasement and blamed guilty men such as
Neville Chamberlain for their failure to act in a manner which would have preserved the
security and interests not only of the United Kingdom but of Western democracy.99
Fighting against such a lackluster interpretations of states rights and
responsibilities, and such a weak interpretation of what it was possible for states to
achieve, Morgenthau in the first edition of Politics Among Nations, had put forward the
case for an aggressive diplomacy, or what he termed a frontal attack, a radical
statement which made clear just how much independence of action each state
possessed.100 In essence Morgenthau had put forward the case for realism, urging his
fellow intellectuals and contemporaries in the world of diplomacy to concentrate on the
realities of the world situation the reality of a weak United Nations in the midst of
strong nation states rather than on what they hoped might become the situation a
strong United Nations capable of imposing its peaceful will upon subservient nation
states.
In his call Morgenthau was undoubtedly influenced by what he perceived to have
been the failure of international politics in the inter-war years, a period when academics
97
Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, (New York: Alfred A.
Knopf, 2nd edition, 1954, Preface.
98
Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations, 2nd edition, 1954, Preface.
13
The term guilty men was coined by Michael Foot et al in their analysis of the appeasement generation.
Michael Foot, Peter Howard, and Frank Owen, The Guilty Men, (London: Victor Gollancz,, Left Book
Club, 1940)
100
35
and politicians alike appeared to have focused so much on what they had hoped could be
achieved that they had placed excessive confidence in institutions and organizations
which in reality had had little effect upon what was actually achieved. They had, in
effect, hoped that a strong League of Nations or a forceful International Court of Justice
would be able to impose their peaceful will upon subservient and compliant nation states.
Thus whether one looked at Woodrow Wilson at the start of the age, or Neville
Chamberlain at the end, each, and many others in between, were guilty of hoping that
international law or agreed upon norms of behavior would be sufficient to ensure peace
between nations. As Morgenthau was only too well aware, the policymakers hopes had
not been met. In Morgenthaus direct experience the struggle for power by Hitlers
Germany (amongst others) had overwhelmed the democracies struggle for peace.
Based on this personal experience, as well as an academic understanding of international
relations, Morgenthau, in the first edition of Politics Among Nations, had emphasized the
reality that nations would, in the final analysis, always be struggling for power, but he
also offered the hope that a state of international peace would be the most desirable. Until
such a state was achieved, however, (most likely by the real conceding of national power
to a supranational body), he argued that the theory by which one attempted to understand
the world should be shaped by how the world actually was, not by what one hoped it
might become. In short he argued that international relations should be understood within
a realist, not an idealist framework.101
Six years on Morgenthau considered himself to have been successful. From his
viewpoint, the United States had stood up to the Soviet Union, contained the spread of
communism in Europe and achieved the friendship of like-minded states. Six years on
with that battle largely won, Morgenthau perceived himself, and the United States, free
to shift in focus a little and to consider the changed nature of the international arena. Not
only had the United Nations achieved far more than he had considered likely six years
previously but particular groups of nation states had co-operated to form regional
supranational bodies. Thus, according to Morgenthau, it was now possible to consolidate
the victory of having his earlier robust theories accepted by now not only consolidating
and defending his arguments, but where necessary, adapting them to new situations and
101
36
experiences.102
Of the many new situations perceived by Morgenthau he was perhaps most struck
by the possible consequences of decolonization, the rise of supranational regional
institutions, and the activities of the United Nations. According to Morgenthau the
colonial revolution has spread over much of Asia and Africa and has increased in
intensity, thus emerging as a new force in world politics, creating new problems, and
calling for new policies.103 Critically, and foreshadowing his later position on U.S.
involvement in Vietnam, Morgenthau adapted his theory of realism to include an entirely
new component. In future, he argued, the struggle for the minds of men needed to be
added to the traditional dimensions of diplomacy and war.104 Thus, even as early as
1953, a year before Dien Bien Phu, and almost a decade ahead of President Lyndon B.
Johnsons call to win the hearts and minds of the Vietnamese people, Morgenthau
acknowledged the need to win the support of the people amongst whom, and with whom,
the U.S. would later fight.105 He was clearly ahead of his time, recognizing that even as
he had earlier asserted the rights of states to act independently and free of all fetters, they
were in reality limited by their ability to win the minds of men.
With this assessment Morgenthau had not abandoned his realist position. He still
believed fiercely in the likelihood that states would act according to their perceived selfinterest. He was merely now acknowledging that it was not always as easy as it had once
been. Where once might had made right, (whether one liked it or not) and where once
Lord Palmerstons Gunboat Diplomacy could assure the British Empire of the success of
its endeavors, now the United States, and indeed the United Kingdom, corralled and
limited by the colonial revolution with its unleashing of national aspirations and political
ambition, could act only if they recognized that the struggle for the minds of men was a
new and integral dimension of international politics.106
In light of Morgenthaus early recognition of the validity and, perhaps more
102
37
importantly, potential strength of the struggle to win mens minds, as expressed in 1953,
his later arguments against U.S. involvement in Vietnam make more sense. His
experience visiting the country, along with his academic assessment of the diplomatic
and military possibilities, led him to believe that this was one dimension of international
politics which the United States could not win. As we have seen, Morgenthau considered
the conflict in Vietnam to be a civil war and blamed U.S. policymakers for transforming
it, in outward appearance at least, into a war of Northern aggression. As it was not such a
war, it followed that it could not be won according to such terms. Thus it is apparent
again, even as early as 1953 that what would later appear to be a liberal and progressive
politics on the part of Morgenthau, was in reality, a willingness to adapt - by expanding
and including new facets his political theory to a changed situation.
If Morgenthau was hesitant about the consequences of the colonial revolution,
unsure of the likely effects upon the older imperial powers, he was impressed by the
efforts of various nations to try and achieve a level of common interest through the
creation of supranational organizations such as the European Coal and Steel Community
or the North Atlantic Treaty Organization. This pooling of states sovereignty appealed to
Morgenthau who saw within it a means of achieving both the broad objectives of the
community and the specific aspirations of the member states. Here again we see
Morgenthau the realist adapting his viewpoint in order to accommodate changed
circumstances. And as would be the case for Vietnam, he proved to be right. The ECSC,
as is well-known, proceeded to form the foundation for the success of what would
become first the European Economic Community, and later the European Union.
Published in 1953, the Second Edition was drafted in the shadow of the Korean
War. Accordingly, the war and its consequences had been worked into the theoretical
framework of the book.107 Indeed it was the Korean War which prompted Morgenthau
to re-consider the potential utility of the United Nations. Disillusioned by the meager
achievements of the inter-war League of Nations, Morgenthau, in the first edition of
Politics Among Nations, had not initially expressed high hopes for the nascent United
Nations. Six years later he was prepared to acknowledge that the organization had
achieved a great deal, albeit in areas fundamentally different from those originally
107
38
conceived. It had been under the flag of the United Nations, for example, that the United
States had been able to enter and fight the Korean War.108
Morgenthau had two other innovations to bring to the Second Edition, both of
which would, as was the case with Vietnam and the UN, foreshadow his later public
positions. Morgenthau asserted that this second edition would take much more account of
domestic politics, even to the point of asserting a new rule of diplomacy dealing with
the relationship between foreign and domestic policy. 109 Again, as he foreshadowed
events in Vietnam, Morgenthau, albeit with a slightly different focus, articulated the
primacy of domestic politics six years before the publication of William Appleman
Williams seminal work in the field, The Tragedy of American Diplomacy.110 In this light,
Morgenthaus later call for the resolution of domestic racial divisions, the abolition of
poverty and the cessation of environmental pollution appear less as radical statements of
a newly found liberal conscience and more as the mature reflections of an academic
convinced that the first step to securing a successful foreign policy is to implement a
domestic policy which in meeting the needs of the people meets the needs of the state.
Thus whether one places Morgenthaus analysis within the context of Bismarck the
conservative policymaker or Williams the liberal academic, one can see that realism,
though outwardly concerned with the behavior of states to each other, contained within it
a strong element of potential progressivism.
As we have seen, it was not just what Morgenthau said in the 1960s that led both
some of his contemporaries and later scholars to perceive him as a conservative turned
liberal, but the changed nature of his relationship with the United States government. He
appeared to have transformed himself (or been transformed) from an ally of the state,
expounding the amorality of realpolitik, to an extremely vocal critic, sure that the U.S.
state was doing something very much immoral. In fact, the paradox is only illusory, and
as with so much else, was foreshadowed in the Second Edition of Politics Among
Nations. In his Preface, Morgenthau introduced as a new element of national
powerthe quality of government. It is against this articulation about the importance of
108
39
the quality of government, written in 1954, that Morgenthaus later assaults upon the
Johnson administration must be placed. 111
According to Morgenthau the quality of the government of a country was so
important that it could, in certain circumstances, determine whether a country won or lost
a war. Using as examples the cases of Austria-Hungary in the Great War, and France in
the Second World War, Morgenthau argued that in both cases the failure of the
relationship between the governed and the governors so degraded national morale that
military success was no longer an option. Specifically, in Austria-Hungary the House of
Hapsburg had failed to retain the loyalty of its Slavic subjects, and in France a significant
proportion of the citizenry had preferred Hitler to the socialist Bloom. Aggravating the
defeat in both instances was that the initial lack of solidarity caused by the government,
further prompted the citizenry to reject the government and thus led to eventual national
destruction.112 As an alternative, Morgenthau proposed what he believed to be the
hallmarks of good or effective government: one which would cherish all of the children
of the nation equally and enlist the strength of sectional groups into a common struggle
for the good of all.
Taking account of all these changes in international politics, Morgenthau in 1953
informed his readers that his ideas on a great many issues had also changed. He had
refined his analysis of such integral concepts as power, cultural imperialism, world public
opinion, disarmament, collective security and peaceful change. Furthermore, his analysis
of politics among nations had been expanded to include the new flash-words of the age
such as containment, cold war, uncommitted nations and Point Four. Thus Morgenthau
prepared his readers for an adjusted interpretation of the rights and responsibilities of
nation states, as well as an acknowledgement that the world had changed in the course of
the past six years. Putting the two together, however, did not produce an abnegation of
realism but rather a readjustment to suit different times.
111
112
40
constituted the six principles of political realism.113 Given the centrality of these
principles to Morgenthaus intellectual framework, it is worth analyzing them in some
detail, particularly so that we might see the extent to which they foreshadowed
Morgenthaus later public pronouncements, providing the basis for his later (apparent)
political shift. For Morgenthau, the first principle of realism was the recognition that
politics was governed by objective laws which had their roots in human nature and that in
order to improve society it was first necessary to understand these laws. One of these
laws, constituting the second principle of realism, was that statesmen think and act in
terms of interest defined as power. According to this perspective, Morgenthau believed
it futile to be concerned with either the motive or political sympathies of the individual
statesman. As proof of the former he drew upon the example of Neville Chamberlain
who, despite having as his objective the morally virtuous goal of preserving peace, in fact
instituted policies which made the Second World War inevitable. By contrast,
suggested Morgenthau, the motives of Winston Churchill had been much less universal
in scope and much more narrowly directed toward personal and national power, yet his
resultant policies were far superior. Likewise denying the importance of political
preference, Morgenthau argued that statesmen must choose between what they might
consider desirable, and what was possible under the concrete circumstances of time and
place.
The third principle of realism acknowledged that while the dominant force for any
individual or nation state was the pursuit of its own interests, the nature of the power
employed or sought would vary according to the political and cultural environment.
Applying this analysis to the division of power or interests between states, Morgenthau
made it clear, perhaps particularly so to those he perceived as having mis-understood his
theories, that nothing in the realist position militates against the assumption that the
present division of the political world into nation states will be replaced by larger units of
a quite different character, more in keeping with the technical potentialities and the moral
requirements of the contemporary world. Where realism differed from other schools of
thought, however, was the recognition that this transformation would come about only
as a result of manipulating the perennial forces that have shaped the past rather than by
113
41
confronting a political reality that has its own laws with an abstract ideal that refuses to
take those laws into account. With these words Morgenthau made his position with
regards to the United Nations quite clear. He had acknowledged in the Preface that the
first edition of Politics had offered a somewhat pessimistic view of the UNs potential but
here he took the opportunity to clarify that though pessimistic about the likelihood of
change stemming from an idealist understanding of international relations, realism did
contain within it the possibility for transformation from a world of nation states to one of
supranational institutions so long as the shift was accomplished on the basis of states real
interests. Thus again, Morgenthaus reasoning illustrates the progressive and liberatory
potential within realism.
Morgenthaus fourth principle focused on the question of morality, arguing that
universal moral principles could not be applied as abstract formulations but only when
filtered through the concrete circumstances of time and place. Thus, a nation state must
act according to what would likely preserve its national interests not according to an
abstract idea of morality. The fifth principle of realism articulated by Morgenthau
proclaimed that while states will inevitably pursue what they perceive to be their national
interests, they should not think that in so doing, they always have God on their side.
Morgenthau issued particular warning against the crusading frenzy which blinding a
nation to its true interests, could lead to the nations destruction. The distinction drawn by
Morgenthau here between the reality that states will always pursue their own interests
and the idea that states are always right is a fine one but one that is critical to an
understanding of realist thought. Equally important is the recognition that the very basis
given by Morgenthau for avoiding a crusading frenzy is less the moral consequences of
believing itself to be right and far more the political consequences that it would likely be
to the detriment of the state. Thus realism, even as it acknowledges the limits of what
states should do does so on the basis of what is best for the state. Again, it is from within
this rationale hinted at in1948 but articulated here more clearly in this Second Edition
in1953 - that Morgenthau will later criticize U.S. involvement in Vietnam.
The final principle of realism asserted that whilst acknowledging the existence of
other spheres, a political realist must always judge a course of action not by its effects
upon those spheres but by its effects upon the power of the state. By way of illustration,
42
Morgenthau detailed three historical examples, and in so doing highlighted the very heart
of realist thought. Weighing up whether Britain and France should have intervened when
Russia invaded Finland, Morgenthau had no doubt that the answer to the legal question
was in the affirmative: Russia had violated a treaty and ought, according to the legalist
framework, be brought to book. According to a realist interpretation, however, France
and Britain were better not to have intervened since to have done so would have put them
at war with both Russia and Germany a situation inimical to the interests of either state.
Analyzing the question of the recognition of China and the decision by Britain to
intervene following Germanys invasion of Belgium in 1914 in much the same light,
Morgenthau used the events of history to emphasize what he perceived to be the core of
realist thought: that whatever other influences might be stake, realism dictated a focus
upon the power and interests of the state first and foremost.
Seven years later, in 1960, Morgenthau again revisited the theory and practice of
realism as he published the third edition of Politics Among Nations.114 While he claimed
in his preface that assumptions, tenets, and theoretical structure had been left intact, in
fact, the book, as had its predecessor five years before, included a number of innovative
applications. Morgenthau placed much greater emphasis upon the existence of an
objective and universally valid truth about matters political which was accessible to
human reason. Even as he argued for universal truth, however, Morgenthau emphasized
that its nature and form would change according to the ever changing configurations of
successive periods of history.115 In short, it would appear in different forms at different
times. Thus to English people of the nineteenth century, a time when Great Britain was
the workshop of the world, the notion of the balance of power as consisting of several
states weighing themselves and their desires and actions against each other, each kept in
check by the weight of the others, was both commonly and easily understood. By
contrast, the United States currently operated within a bi-polar international system.
Critical to Morgenthaus insight was his argument that while the two systems of
international relations appeared superficially quite different, the earlier multi-polar, the
later bi-polar, in fact the underlying principles behind each were identical. Each system
114
Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, (New York: Alfred A.
Knopf, 3rd edition, 1960).
115
Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations, 3rd edition, 1960, Preface.
43
44
A decade after the appearance of this Third Edition, the U.S. Government,
frustrated by the continued survival of the Viet Cong, and indeed North Vietnam, had
turned to a policy of massive military engagement, throwing thousands of tons of bombs
at its opponents, confident (rather like the generals of the Western Front in the First
World War) that the breakthrough would surely come if only they threw enough
firepower at the enemy. According to Morgenthaus proscription, no such break-through
would come. Indeed it could not do so since from the realist perspective of Morgenthau,
U.S. policymakers had become so fixated on the acquisition of material and military
strength as a means to power that they were neglecting other, equally integral aspects of
the system of international relations. That Morgenthaus critique was not merely a moral
critique but one framed within a realist perspective is manifest in his warning that in
neglecting the vital interests of other states, in this case North Vietnam, U.S.
policymakers were risking the interests of the United States. As Morgenthau himself put
it if we look at all nations, our own included, as political entities pursuing their
respective interests defined in terms of power, we are able to do justice to all of them.
We are able to judge other nations as we judge our own and, having judged them in this
fashion, we are then capable of pursuing policies that respect the interests of other
nations, while protecting and promoting those of our own. Moderation in policy cannot
fail to reflect the moderation of moral judgment119
Morgenthau waited nine years before publishing the Fourth Edition of Politics
Among Nations.120 As before, he refined his concepts and theoretical propositions and
added new material to address new situations. In 1967, the primary new situation was the
changed configuration of the United Nations, particularly the new election and voting
procedures for both the Security and Economic and Social Councils. As he had done in
previous editions, Morgenthau also took the opportunity to engage his academic
colleagues or perhaps more accurately to explain his refusal to engage. Referring to
criticism leveled against him for failing to defend his theories against currently
fashionable ideas within International Relations theory such as systems analysis or
simulation, Morgenthau argued that academic disputes about methodology were likely to
119
120
45
achieve little and indeed were most likely to obscure political truths. Despite this
seemingly disinterested stance, however, Morgenthau in fact did engage with the theories
of his colleagues. Referring to the plethora of theories available, for example, he made
clear that a theory must be judged not by its epistemological pretenses and
methodological innovations but by the contribution that it makes to our knowledge and
understanding of phenomena which are worth knowing.121 Thus Morgenthau made clear
that in his opinion the theories with which he was supposed to engage were unworthy of
his time since, no matter how sophisticated they appeared, they would likely make little
contribution to knowledge.
It was another nine years before Morgenthau published the Fifth Edition of his
book, during which period, according to Morgenthau, international politics had witnessed
the most significant changes since the end of World War II.122 Morgenthau focused
particularly in this edition upon the consequences of the Vietnam War, and the explicit
recognition by the West of the territorial status quo in Europe, a recognition which, for
Morgenthau, symbolized the effective end of the Cold War. The arena of International
Politics had also changed substantially with the entry of China as a would-be third
superpower and the coming of age of the defeated Axis powers, Japan and Germany, as
independent, democratic nation states. Further complicating global politics, however, was
the fact that the United Nations, the apparent success of which only twenty years before
had caused Morgenthau to revise his initial proscriptions, had now declined as a force in
international politics.
In light of Morgenthaus public protestations over the Vietnam War by 1973, it is
hardly surprising that he took the opportunity provided by a fifth edition to analyze the
consequences of the war for both U.S. power, and international politics more generally.
Inserting an analysis of the war into his core principles of realism, Morgenthau suggested
that U.S. conduct in Indo-China provided the tools with which to construct a countertheory of irrational politics, a kind of pathology of international politics. Morgenthau
articulated an in-depth critique of the policy makers whom he believed responsible for
U.S. policy. They had replaced experience with superstition; refused to correct their
121
122
46
picture of the world in the light of subsequent experience; used intelligence not as a
tool with which to adapt policy to reality but as a means of reinterpreting reality to accord
with policy; allowed their egoism to widen the gap between perception and reality; and
used action, any kind of action, as a means of closing the gap between perception and
reality. Whilst the specifics of Morgenthaus denunciation were new to the Fifth Edition,
the argument on which they were based was not; it rested on the same core six principles
of realism as had his earlier analyses of the Winter War, World War I, and the
recognition of China. As he had done all along, however, Morgenthau applied his core
thinking to new situations, and where necessary, expanded the range of analytical tools
available to his readers. Thus, as a means of helping students of International Relations
make sense of the Vietnam War, Morgenthau not only inserted an analysis of the war into
his core principles but also expanded his analysis of political prediction and included a
systemic emphasis upon the factor of irrationality in the conduct of foreign policy.
As he had made clear in previous editions, so here did Morgenthau emphasize that
while all of the changes to which he referred were significant, and while they all played
some part in shaping a new tapestry of international relations, still his theories, the same
theories as first expounded twenty-five years before, were relevant tools of analysis.123
While on the one hand this assertion might be seen as a statement of self-confidence,
almost arrogance, it also reflected Morgenthaus conviction that the substance of his
arguments had not changed, even as the political circumstances to which they could be
applied had. Thus again it becomes obvious that, from Morgenthaus perspective his
criticism of the Vietnam War was a logical development within the original parameters of
realism as first put forward two and a half decades before.
Five years later in 1978 a Revised Fifth Edition of Politics Among Nations
appeared, the last to be personally supervised by the then 74 year old Morgenthau.124 As
before, perhaps the most prominent statement by Morgenthau concerned the continuing
relevancy of his work. Indeed, more than this, he celebrated the foresight shown in
previous editions by suggesting that many recent developments in foreign policy had
123
47
Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, Fifth Edition,
Revised, (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1978), Preface.
126
Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations, 5th edition, Revised, 1973), 29.
127
Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations, 5th edition, Revised, 1973), 4-15.
128
Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations, 5th edition, Revised, 1973), 492.
48
same time making clear the continuing relevancy, through its adaptability, of his core
argument. Furthermore, his confidence in the constancy of his work enabled him to offer
critiques of contemporary U.S. foreign policy without losing faith in his own theories. In
essence, Morgenthau, through his critiques and analysis, made clear that realism, as
articulated by him over the course of the post-war period, contained within it both
conservative and progressive elements and thus consisted of a theoretical consistency
combined with a practical flexibility. Morgenthaus intellectual consistency was reflected
throughout the successive editions of Politics Among Nations. It was also evident in his
other monographs, monographs to which we now turn.
49
Chapter Three
Five Monographs: Morgenthaus Approach Applied
Hans J. Morgenthau, Scientific Man vs. Power Politics, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1946).
50
130
Hans J. Morgenthau, In Defense of the National Interest: A Critical Examination of American Foreign
Policy, (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1951).
51
stray from its proper course. The result, in the post-war age, was that what should have
been a realist age had been perverted. Morgenthau now called upon policymakers to
abandon these errors and revert to the realism of Washington. Specifically, he urged that
contemporary U.S. foreign policy should be guided by the objective of securing a balance
of power in Europe and Asia, and by maintaining a dominant position for the United
States within its own hemisphere. Even more succinctly, he argued that national interests
should be yardstick against which all foreign policy decisions should be measured.
Just over a decade later, with three editions of Politics Among Nations under his
belt, Morgenthau again applied the more general theories contained within his
masterpiece to the particular needs of his adopted country. In Politics, Morgenthau had
urged both theorists and policymakers to theorize and act according to the situation as it
actually was, not according to how they thought it should be, or hoped it might one day
become, and above all else, to focus on the national interest. Examining U.S. policy in
1962 in The Purpose of American Politics, Morgenthau argued that while not all states
had a national interest, the absence of which explained their relative lack of influence in
the world, for the United States the national interest was an amalgam of equality and
liberty. It was this creative tension that existed between equality and liberty - the national
purpose - that gave a normative nature to the outcome sought by U.S. foreign policy.
Having asserted the centrality of national interest, Morgenthau in American Politics was
ready to follow the same rule even at the cost of apparently contradicting his earlier
arguments.131 As elsewhere, however, a close reading of Morgenthaus argument reveals
not an inconsistency with earlier thought but rather a flexibility, an ability to adapt an
existing theory to a new situation sufficiently well that the original theory, might at first
glance appear to have been overruled. In fact, it is still very much present.
The new situation that actually was in 1962, according to Morgenthau, was the
combined existence of nuclear weapons and the advanced rockets and guidance systems
designed to carry the weapons from continent to continent. The result was that America
could no longer secure its borders exclusively through its own efforts. No matter how
much material strength the U.S. amassed, it could not prevent an attack of such
131
Hans J. Morgenthau, The Purpose of American Politics, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962).
52
magnitude as would likely destroy the nation. Thus where once Morgenthau had doubted
the utility of supranational bodies, now he saw them as the only possible mechanism by
which new weapons of mass destruction could be controlled. True to his earlier analysis,
Morgenthau in 1962 did not suggest that a strong United Nations or some other such
institution, was a guarantee that nuclear weapons would not be used, only that it was the
best method of potential control available. As he phrased it, The United States must
choose not between insecurity and security, but between utter insecurity and a measure of
insecurity which, in view of the alternative, is tolerable.132
While it would be possible to read American Politics as a shift to the left for
Morgenthau, and his call for a stronger supranational body as proof of his growing
disenchantment with the politics of power between nations, it would be more appropriate
to see in it a constancy of purpose, a call for nation states to act in a manner which would
best serve their self-interests. Thus, believed Morgenthau, if every nation state signed up,
it would make the supranational body all the stronger, and all the more likely to be able to
impose its will upon constituent members, and thereby assure both the collective and
individual security of those same members. From this perspective, the conceding of
national sovereignty, was not, as might superficially be assumed, against the interests of
nation states but rather very much integral to them.
If in American Politics Morgenthau applied his realist framework to an overview
of U.S. foreign policy, in Vietnam and The United States, he concentrated his analysis
upon what was in 1965, the year of the books publication, possibly the hottest single
issue in U.S. foreign policy.133 Although the book could be perceived as being what
would be termed today an instant book, written in response to a particular set of
circumstances of the moment, its analyses and arguments reflected years of scholarly
research and reflection. As we have seen, Morgenthaus analysis of U.S. involvement in
Vietnam represented not an aberration of the realist conception of international relations
produced in1948, but rather its practical application to a new set of circumstances.
Consisting of previously published essays drawn from Morgenthaus contribution to the
mass media between 1956 and 1965, along with an original introductory essay written for
132
133
53
the occasion, Vietnam and The United States, summarized and foregrounded
Morgenthaus thoughts about U.S. policy and Vietnam.
Essentially Morgenthau proposed that U.S. policy toward Vietnam was based on
three myths: a binding commitment to the Saigon government that engages our honor;
aggression from the North against a people anxious to have us defend their national
independence; and the identity of the interests and policies of the Viet Cong, North
Vietnam and China.134 According to Morgenthau, since none of the propositions behind
these ideas was true, the U.S. policy which had resulted from them was also false, i.e. a
policy not in the true interests of the United States. Instead, what had resulted was a
policy which could result only in the indiscriminate killing of everybody in sight by
genocide.135 Morgenthaus use in an academic monograph of language more likely to be
heard on the streets, or on the campuses of student-dominated universities might, as
before, suggest a shift to the left. Again, however, a contextualized reading of his
argument makes clear that this is not the case. Morgenthau argued against genocide not
on moral grounds but because the policy from which it would result was flawed, flawed
in the sense of not serving the interests of the United States. From this perspective, as
elsewhere, Morgenthaus realism may be seen to contain within it a liberatory potential
since it recognized that the indiscriminate killing of everybody in sight was hardly
good or useful politics.
In the second edition of Politics Among Nations, Morgenthau had introduced the
element of quality of government as an aspect of international politics. We have
already discussed his later use of this dimension in reference to the Johnson
administration and its harassment of him through the arms of government. In Vietnam
and The United States, Morgenthau employed the same analytical tool to serve a
blistering attack upon the individuals within government he perceived to be responsible
for U.S. involvement in Vietnam. He accused these policymakers of being unable to
distinguish between what was good for the country and what was good for their own
reputations. His analysis is worth quoting in some detail since it manifests the anger
Morgenthau clearly felt when he considered the Vietnam War. As he saw it,
134
135
54
136
55
his last work, A New Foreign Policy for the United States in 1969.138 The very title of the
book might well be seen to reflect a shift in Morgenthaus thinking. As one credited with
formulating the basis on which so much of post-45 U.S. foreign policy had been built, if
Morgenthau was now calling for a new foreign policy, then surely he must be rejecting
the old, or more specifically his old. In fact, he was, as ever, developing and applying his
existing policy to the new circumstances of the late 1960s. Doing so would mean a
change in the actual foreign policy as currently practiced by the United States, but it
would not change the fundamental grounds on which such policies would be based. That
basis was the same in 1969 as it had been in 1949 the pursuit and preservation of U.S.
national security and power.
Arguing that the United States must most urgently decide what was essential for
its national well-being and reject what was peripheral and contingent, Morgenthau argued
for a ruthless prioritization so as best to promote the national interests of the United
States. In essence, rejecting both isolationism and globalism, Morgenthau called for new
policies for a new world. Reiterating his conviction that there was no such thing as a
monolithic communist world, Morgenthau emphasized that in interfering in countries
where it had no business to be, the United States was acting against its own best interests.
Instead, Morgenthau laid out a new vision of foreign policy. Based as ever on the pursuit
of U.S. national interests, this policy should, according to Morgenthau, avoid an arms
race, conduct nuclear policy at the international level, recognize China and form a new
Atlantic alliance with Western Europe. In short, the United States should decide where its
national interests lay and implement policies exclusively in those regions, neglecting
areas of no particular concern to the U.S. As harsh as the proposal might have sounded,
or indeed as soft as it might have sounded given its general advice to withdraw from
Vietnam, the underlying message was the same as it had always been find, and secure,
the interests of the state.
Perhaps of most obvious dramatic significance, Morgenthau, in A New Foreign
Policy, called for an end to the policy of containment. Arguing that it had been valuable
during the famous fifteen weeks of the spring of 1947 when the Truman Doctrine and
the Marshall Plan had together represented the implementation of the then innovative
138
Hans J. Morgenthau, A New Foreign Policy for the United States, (New York: Preager, 1969).
56
57
Chapter Four
From Germany to Nuclear Weapons: Realism in Practice
139
Christopher Frei., Hans J. Morgenthau. An Intellectual Biography, (Baton Rouge: Louisiana State
University Press, 2001), 76. Frie records that Morgenthau published over 420 articles, essays and
commentaries between 1950 and 1980.
140
Hans J. Morgenthau, Germany: The Political Problem, Germany and the Future of Europe, ed. Hans
J. Morgenthau, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1951), 76-89.
58
cope with a newly united Germany, then the Europe of the 1950s was plagued by the
German question in the shape of how to deal with a divided Germany, and in particular
how to respond to a West Germany which though territorially much reduced in size was
still a major economic and political power to be reckoned with.
With the decision by the United States to actively engage in a process of
containment of the Soviet Union, West Germany was the frontline state with the Soviet
sphere of influence. By choosing to examine the issue of Germany, Morgenthau was in
many ways looking at the central problem of the early Cold War. For Morgenthau there
were three key problems to be dealt with when examining Germany. Firstly, to prevent a
rebirth of the worldview that led firstly Prussia, then a united Wilhemite Germany, and
then Hitlers Reich into war. Secondly, how, whilst making sure that Germany would not
again be a threat to its neighbors, it would yet be an economically powerful and
politically stable state. And finally, how this economically powerful and politically
stable German state would be able to protect itself against Finland-style domination by
the Soviet Union. At the same time as he sought to avoid German domination, however,
Morgenthau believed that Germany had to be sufficiently strong so as to serve as a buffer
against communism. Indeed, Morgenthau believed that a strong Germany was essential to
the success of anti-communism efforts. In essence, Morgenthau sought to engage with the
issue of how a rearmed Germany could be prevented from dominating its neighbors to the
detriment of the interests of the Western Allies while still being allowed to grow
sufficiently strong as to protect them.141
Even as Morgenthau was offering solutions to Europes, and in light of the global
nature of international relations in 1950, the worlds German question, he was also
identifying what he perceived to be the origins of recent errors in U.S. foreign policy.
According to The Mainspring of American Foreign Policy: The National Interest vs.
141
Europes German question has since been re-born yet again with the re-union of East and West
Germany in October 1990. Now Europeans must grapple with the issue not only of how to respond to a
united Germany (as had faced them in 1870) but how to do so in the context of the European Union. The
problem might be summarized thus: give Germany too much power and freedom and it might, in
enthusiasm, run away with (and thereby destroy) the Union; on the other hand, give Germany too little
power and freedom and it might, in frustration, run away from (and thereby destroy) the Union. For an up
to date analysis of the German question in the context of the European Union see, Desmond Dinan, Ever
Closer Union? An Introduction to the European Community. (Houndmills, Basingstock, Hampshire:
MacMillan Press, 1994).
59
Moral Abstraction, published in 1950 in The American Political Science Review, the
premier journal in the field, the error lay in the original claim of early colonists of the
would-be United States that their society was fundamentally different from Europe.
Specifically, according to Morgenthau, they claimed that their society was the antithesis
of Europe rather than, through its imperialistic nature, its culmination. It was only,
claimed Morgenthau, because the indigenous inhabitants of the North American
landmass were so inferior in terms of numbers, organization and military capability that
the apologists and politicians of the European settlers were able to make the argument
that the political expansion of the original thirteen colonies into the interior was an act
of civilization rather than conquest and as such essentially differed from, and was
morally superior to, the imperialist ventures, wars of conquest, and colonial acquisitions
with which the history of other nations was replete.142
As a result of this deception, claimed Morgenthau, the American public believed
itself to be morally superior to Europe. With this belief, cloaking the expansion of the
country in a civilizationist framework, they were denying the reality of the power politics
by which the expansion had actually been achieved. This denial of power politics and the
accompanying perception that politics was in fact guided by moral impulses such as the
civilizational impulse which had sponsored expansion into the interior, had, claimed
Morgenthau, led directly to the disaster of Wilsonian idealism. Morgenthau believed now
that the only way forward was for U.S. policymakers to acknowledge the reality of what
had actually made the United States such a strong country and to deny the myth of what
people believed had made them strong. To do so would be to correct the basis on which
future foreign policies could be established, an essential prerequisite for future success
since it stood to reason that a policy built upon false assumptions, as had been the case
with idealism, could reap only false rewards, or at least rewards antithical to the real
interests of the United States.
Likewise antithical, according to Morgenthau was the granting of aid to other
nations on grounds unrelated to U.S. national interests. Preface to a Political Theory of
Foreign Aid, published in The American Political Science Review in 1962, might in
142
Hans J. Morgenthau, The Mainspring of American Foreign Policy: The National Interest vs. Moral
Abstraction, The American Political Science Review, Volume 44, Issue 4 (Dec. 1950), 833-854.
60
143
Hans J. Morgenthau, Preface to a Political Theory of Foreign Aid, The American Political Science
Review, June 1962, pp 31-39.
61
would be unlikely to benefit the United States. Instead of this idealist path, the U.S.
would do better to determine its aid recipients according to its friendships - a harsh
proscription perhaps but one that would be more palatable, at least within the domestic
sphere of U.S. politics, if the idealism under which aid was currently cloaked was
abandoned and the public taught to see aid for what it really a was, as another dimension
of international relations.
In Politics Among Nations Morgenthau had articulated the hope that the
international political order could eventually create a mechanism for the enforcement of
international peace. In 1963, The Political Conditions for an International Police Force,
published in a special issue of International Organization, he looked specifically at the
likelihood that such a peace could be maintained by an international police force. 144
Arguing that the political conditions for international peace would be in place when
nation states were willing to surrender real aspects of their sovereignty to a supranational
body, Morgenthau declared that that time had clearly not yet come. Thus he had reached
the conclusion that in a world of sovereign nations, the idea of a reliable and effective
police force was a contradiction in terms.
According to Morgenthau, an international police force, by dint of being
international could not be more reliable or efficient than the political interests and
military capabilities of the nations supporting it allowed it to be. Furthermore, the loyalty
of the individuals within the international police force would always lie first with their
own nation state. Taking as his example the attitude of the police during the forced
integration of the University of Mississippi in 1962, Morgenthau argued that the
political preferences of the police are likely to color the performance of its functions.145
Thus in order to be effective, a supranational body would have to create its own force
rather than relying on the borrowed forces of nation states. In effect, Morgenthau was
144
Hans J. Morgenthau, The Political Conditions for an International Police Force, International
Organization, Volume 17, Issue 2 International Force : A Symposium (Spring ,1963), 393-403.
145
Morgenthau, The Political Conditions for an International Police Force, p.394. What Morgenthau
found to be true of Mississippi in1962 would also prove to be true of Northern Ireland in 1968, a year
infamous for the obvious preference of the police force for the Protestant cause against the nationalist at the
outbreak of what would come to be known as The Troubles. For a through evaluation of the role of the
police in Northern Ireland see, Aogan Mulcahy, Policing Northern Ireland: Legitimacy, Reform and Social
Conflict (Cullompton : Willan Publishing, 2004); and Chris Ryder, The RUC: A Force Under Fire,
(London: ~ Methuen Publishing, 1989).
62
following the advice offered many years earlier by Lenin that the dictatorship of the
proletariat could not merely take over the instruments of the Tsarist state and use them
for its own purposes since instruments designed for one purpose cannot readily be used
for another. Thus just as Lenin held that the proletariat had to create institutions of its
own, so too did Morgenthau hold that a supranational institution must create its own
police force.
Significantly, and suggestive of the progressivism inherent within his realist
framework, Morgenthau suggested that the creation of just such a force was a real
possibility - in a totally disarmed world. According to Morgenthau, an environment of
total disarmament would create, or be created by, a supranational authority rendering the
international sphere to be no longer anarchic. In other words, total disarmament and
world government go hand in hand146 With this article Morgenthau appeared to offer
something to all sides. On the one hand, a dismissal of the likely effectiveness of any
international police force - a clear string for the right; on the other, the expression of hope
that one day total disarmament and world government would govern international
relations - a clear string for the left. In reality, Morgenthau was pulling politically for
neither side. He was simply, as he had been doing since 1946, applying the essentials of
his realism - that nation states sought, maintained and used power according to perceived
national self-interest - to the perplexing question of whether or not, or at what point in
time or circumstances, an international police would or could become a viable reality.
One of the most chilling aspects of the Cold War for many ordinary citizens must
surely have been the knowledge that the destruction of their country, and perhaps the
world as they knew it, was always only a few minutes away. In this respect, Morgenthau
was no different from his fellows. Analyzing the influence of nuclear weapons upon
international relations in The Four Paradoxes of Nuclear Strategy, published in The
American Political Science Review in 1964, Morgenthau proposed that the transition
from pre-nuclear to nuclear age was as significant as that from antiquity to medieval and
medieval to modern.147 The existence of nuclear weapons was made yet more
complicated by the four paradoxes of Morgenthaus title. First, the impossibility of the
146
147
63
use of nuclear weapons because of the fear of their destructive capability, whilst still
holding a commitment to use these same weapons. Second, the desire for the creation of a
viable nuclear strategy which was sufficiently complex so as to avoid ever having to use
nuclear weapons. Third, the conflict between seeking to prevent a nuclear arms race
whilst continuing to develop ever more powerful nuclear weapons. And finally, the desire
by the United States to create an international alliance system to protect its interests, even
as there existed rockets to carry hydrogen bombs from continent to continent which, for
Morgenthau, made such an alliance structure obsolete. In essence, Morgenthau suggested
all these paradoxes result from the contrast between traditional attitudes and the
possibility of nuclear war, and from the fruitless attempts to reconcile the two.148 In
short, Morgenthau was calling for policymakers to see the world as it actually was, as it
had become, rather than either how they wished it to be, or even how it had been. The
innovation of nuclear weapons necessitated a re-evaluation of international relations.
Again, this re-evaluation represented not a shift away from realism but a recognition that
as times changed so too must the policy stemming from a realist appraisal of the world.
The presence of nuclear weapons had not only changed the particulars of
international relations, it had also changed the means by which states would or could do
business with each other. Based on his experience and judgment, Morgenthau was clear
that neither superpower wished to use nuclear weapons. Berlin, Korea, Hungary and
Cuba, for instance, were each examples of the superpowers willingness to compromise
their original positions so as to avoid the threat of nuclear attack on their respective
homelands. As significant as this withdrawal from the brink was, however, Morgenthau
drew the readers attention to the fact that on several occasions, each power had
threatened to deploy nuclear weapons, each side in effect hoping to bluff the other into
believing that it was willing to risk its homeland in pursuit of its objective. Such a
position, argued Morgenthau, led to a new dimension within international relations and a
new twist on the realist assumption that a nation state will, in pursuit of its interests,
employ military force, the effectiveness of which in defeating an enemy or defending
ones own nation, lies in its actual application. In the new era of the nuclear age,
suggested Morgenthau, this was no longer the case. Rather the primary function of
148
64
nuclear force lies in making its physical application superfluous by deterring the
prospective opponent from using it.149
Thus as he pre-figured Johnson in his call for the hearts and minds of men, here
Morgenthau may be said to have pre-figured Mikhail Gorbachev who, in his vision of
perestroika and glasnost, declared nuclear weapons to be irrational and ineffective tools
of diplomacy since to use them would be to bring about the destruction of ones own
state.150 Likewise, only five years after the first post-war protesters against nuclear
weapons marched to Aldermaston151 in the United Kingdom, and many years before the
women of Greenham Common152 would call for the removal of cruise missiles, Hans J.
Morgenthau, arch-realist, proponent of a realpolitik likely to find favor with Bismarck,
was calling for a new understanding of international relations in order to take account of,
and preferably control, nuclear weapons.
In light of this call, it is perhaps hardly surprising that some have mistaken
Morgenthaus views, that some have considered him to have become more liberal with
age. It is also possible for others to look only at the emphasis placed upon states interests
and see only a conservative, concerned only with the preservation of his own nation state.
In fact, as we have suggested throughout, Morgenthau is not so easily or neatly classified,
or at least not if one insists on employing the limiting terminology of left and right.
Morgenthau, as we have argued form the beginning, is in fact more easily understood as a
progressive realist. As a realist, he advocated tirelessly for the implementation of a
foreign policy which would best reflect the interests of the nation state. As a progressive,
he advocated for causes against the perceived current political interests of his
government. For Morgenthau there was no inconsistency in his position. His realism, as
149
65
the very title of his masterpiece suggested, contained within it the recognition that
relations between states were based on power but also the recognition that nations would
struggle for peace as well as power. In addition to tracing that struggle in his own work,
as we have seen here, Morgenthau also charted the struggle through the work of other
people. It is to those reviews that we now turn.
66
Chapter Five
Realism Through Other Peoples Words:
Morgenthaus Book Reviews
67
conflicting interests. Thus, just as the ideals of the League of Nations were unattainable,
so were Cohens aspirations for collective security based on an unrealizable international
solidarity. Morgenthau concluded in the realm of politics, it is by definite political,
and not by abstract humanitarian, considerations that states are moved.153 With this
comment Morgenthau pre-figured Politics Among Nations as surely as if he had written
his own article.
A year later, and a year into the European war, Morgenthau again returned to the
limits of what international law could possibly achieve. Making International Law Work
argued that law and force were incompatible at the international level. In keeping with his
later, more developed, arguments, Morgenthau claimed the contrary. Indeed he asserted,
there is no such thing as law without force, nor has there ever been organized force
without law. Morgenthau rejected the notion that a supranational state would come into
existence based solely on the aspirations of international law. Rather, he claimed,
supranational states would come into existence when it suited nation states to concede
sovereignty. In other words, supranational institutions, as all aspects of international
relations, would owe their existence to power politics not idealistic hopes. Again
prefiguring his later work, Morgenthau made clear what he believed to be the foundation
of international relations: power politics is not an artificial attribute of our social life; it
grows out of the very nature of man as a social being.154
Given the centrality of this perception to Morgenthaus intellectual worldview, it
is perhaps hardly surprising that he chose to review Georg Schwarzenbergers Power
Politics. In his review, he once again rejected the notion that power politics and the rule
of force were the antitheses of community spirit and the rule of law. From Morgenthaus
perspective, quite the opposite was true: it was only through the use of power politics that
one could hope to achieve community spirit, and only through the threat or use of the rule
of force that international law could work. With these words, Morgenthau foreshadowed
the dualism present within Politics Among Nations, and the progressivism and liberatory
potential within realism. Thus according to Morgenthaus realist understanding, it was
153
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of Neo-Neutrality, Georg Cohen, The American Political Science Review,
vol. 33, No. 5, (Oct, 1939), 893-894.
154
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of Making International Law Work, George W. Keeton and Georg
Schwarzenberger, The American Journal of International Law, Vol. 34, No. 3, (July, 1940), 537.
68
possible to have international community and to live according to, and within limits set
by, international law. In order to effect such a situation, however, one had to accept that
states would only act according to their perception of their best interests. Praising
Schwarzenbergers work because it would help educate non-specialists who were easily
dazzled by the pseudo scientific pretensions of the prophets of permanent peace,
Morgenthau also suggested that our professional peace planners would do well to
ponder its lessons.155
Morgenthau returned to his vitriolic disdain for liberal idealism in the last full
year of the war, a time when both policy makers and members of the public were
thinking about peace. In his review of Towards An Abiding Peace, Morgenthau made
clear his conviction that that liberalism was an ineffective means of trying to understand
the world: the liberal who, contemptuous of power politics, endeavors to exorcise
social evils by invoking reason, law, and ethics, will at best remain ineffective in the
political sphere and at worst fall victim to those evil forces which he may understand but
which he is unable to meet on their own ground.156 Again Morgenthau foreshadowed his
own later political development, making the point that for people who thought as he did,
the antithesis is not between power politics on the one hand, and reason, law, and
ethics, on the other, but between power politics for evil and power politics for desirable
objectives.157
For Morgenthau the significance of power politics was not just that it governed
relations between states, but that it also governed relations within states. This much was
clear from Morgenthaus review of Were the Minorities Treaties a Failure?, a study of
the treaties governing the rights and obligations of European minorities mandated by the
Treaty of Versailles.158 Morgenthau answered the question in the affirmative, suggesting
that the treaties failed because they regarded the issue of national minorities as a legal
rather than as a political question. Further complicating the chances of success by
international treaty was the reality that the minority issue was a question of political
155
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of Power Politics, The American Journal of International Law, Vol. 36 No.
2 (Apr., 1942), 351-352.
156
Op. cit. p. 351.
157
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of Towards An Abiding Peace, R. M. MacIver, The Journal of Political
Economy, Vol. 52, No. 1 (Mar., 1944), 91-92.
158
Hans J. Morgenthau , Review of Were the Minorities Treaties a Failure? Jacob Robinson et al, Journal
of Modern History, Vol. 16, No. 3 (Sept. 1944), 237.
69
import to the larger state within which the given minorities resided, and which was
therefore unlikely to allow arbitration by an international body.
A month before the Allies declared victory in Europe, Morgenthau wrote a review
of War and Its Causes. Morgenthau rejected the authors argument that all wars were to
be equally avoided and that war was always bad. According to Morgenthau, a war of
defense differed from a war of aggression, and there was a significant difference between
just and unjust wars.159 Significant to Morgenthaus later views is that what could here be
seen as militarism, rejecting those who opposed war, in fact provided the same
intellectual framework which would later allow Morgenthau to call for an end to the
Vietnam War. Thus, here again we see that what later appeared to be radical, new views,
had in fact already been articulated, albeit in a different context, the year World War II
ended.
As the United States (and other nations) prepared for the post-war world,
Morgenthau took it upon himself in book reviews, as he would later do in monographs
and articles, to articulate what he believed should serve as the parameters of international
relations in the post-war era. Reviewing Foxs The Super Powers, and using language
that would later form the sub-title of his masterpiece, he chided U.S. policymakers for
refusing to face the political facts of life, the very essence of which was the struggle for
power, that is, the desire of individuals or nations to keep the power they have or to add
to the power they have, or to show the power they have.160 Clearly Morgenthau praised
Fox because his views coincided with Morgenthaus own. The same was true a few
months later when he reviewed Manley Hudsons book International Tribunals.
Morgenthau applauded Hudsons recognition of the natural limitations of the judicial
function and his warning against regarding it as a universal method for the peaceful
solution of international disputes.161 Morgenthau would hardly put it more eloquently
himself over the course of his career.
Morgenthau used the occasion of his review of The Device of Government: An
159
Hans J. Morgenthau , Review of War and Its Causes, L. L. Bernard, American Political Science Review,
Vol. 39, No. 2 (Apr. 1945), 365-366.
160
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of The Super Powers, William T.B. Fox, Ethics, Volume 55, Issue 3
(Apr., 1945), 227-228.
161
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of International Tribunals, Manley O. Hudson, The American Political
Science Review, Vol.39, No.4 (Aug., 1945), 802-804.
70
Essay on Civil Polity, to establish his view that the proper role of the intellectual was an
activist, engaged with the problems of the age.162 More poetically, a scholarship devoid
of contemporary relevance, was for Morgenthau nothing less than medieval scholasticism
in modern garb. Again, it is against this context that one must place Morgenthaus later
anti-war activism. It was not that the Vietnam War sparked a new idea for Morgenthau, it
was not that he suddenly felt a compulsion to speak out. Rather, what was new about the
1960s was that so many others felt such a sudden compulsion. Morgenthau had been
articulating his realism since before the Second World War. For many of those who
would become activists in the 1960s, it was the Vietnam War which prompted them to
speak out. Significantly, not all who spoke out did so inspired by a realist assessment of
international relations but since what they said appeared to coincide with what
Morgenthau said, it appeared to the superficial observer, as though Morgenthau must be
inspired by the same ideals as they. In fact, if the point needs to be made again, he was
not. He was inspired by the same framework as twenty years before: a realist analysis of
U.S. national interests.
As the United Nations geared up for its work, Morgenthau used his review of
Pioneers in World Order: An American Appraisal of the League of Nations to elucidate
his analysis behind the failure of the League.163 Its officials, argued Morgenthau, had
erred in perceiving the problems of the day to be capable of solution through technical or
legal means when in fact they had been political problems that needed to be solved by
political means. For Morgenthau, the gap between the ideals upon which the League was
based and the concrete environment in which it was forced to work could not be
obliterated by the attempt to superimpose a set of abstract principles upon a
recalcitrant reality. In 1946, as he would shortly make clear in the first edition of
Politics Among Nations, Morgenthau was similarly distrustful of the nascent United
Nations.
He was equally pessimistic about the potential for change through voluntary
means within the press. Reviewing A Free and Responsible Press, composed by The
162
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of The Device of Government: An Essay on Civil Polity, John Laird, The
Journal of Political Economy, vol. 54, No. 6 (Dec., 1946), 566.
163
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of Pioneers in World Order: An American Appraisal of the League of
Nations, ed. Harriet Eager Davis, Journal of Political Economy, vol. 54, No. 6 (Dec. 1946), 568-569.
71
Commission on Freedom of the Press, Morgenthau asserted that the main threat to the
freedom of the press came from monopoly practices.164 Morgenthau perceived a
similarity with international relations, suggesting that just as it was useless to hope that
international law could work without teeth, so it would be useless to hope that
monopolistic wielders of power would give up that power of their own volition. Thus
the government should step in and create institutional devices which will make it
impossible[for]the abuse of power. In this as elsewhere, we see the liberatory
potential within realism, whereby the power of the state could be used to control
circumstances for the good of all - if one accepts that it would be for the good of all to
avoid the concentration of media power.
Proof of the potentially beneficent effects of realism was also evident in
Morgenthaus review of Herbert Feiss The Spanish Story.165 During World War II Spain
was dependent on Britain and the United States for oil, just as Germany was dependent
on Spain for key mineral resources. Morgenthau contrasted the different policies of
British Prime Minister Winston Churchill and U.S. Secretary of State Cordell Hull.
Churchill used Spains dependency upon British oil as a mechanism by which to achieve
Britains larger objective - ensuring that Spanish North Africa and Gibraltar remained out
of German hands. By contrast, Hull saw Spains giving of economic supplies to Hitler as
a bar to normal relations. Praising Churchill for his realism, and condemning Hull for his
idealism and moral indignation, Morgenthau argued that it was the realist approach of
Churchill rather than the idealist perspective of Hull, which had secured the Allies larger
interests.
As we have seen, Morgenthau credited realism with the ability to win wars, form
the basis of supranational bodies, and in his review of La Constitution Federale de la
Suisse, 1848-1948, a centenary commemorative volume of the Swiss confederation of
1848, with the potential to form the basis of nationhood.166 Morgenthau explored the
image by which popular understanding of Switzerland was constructed: the Swiss
164
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of A Free and Responsible Press, composed by The Commission on
Freedom of the Press, American Journal of Sociology, vol. 53, No. 3 (Nov., 1947), 225.
165
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of The Spanish Story, Herbert Feiss, The American Political Science
Review, Vol. 42, Issue 4 (Aug., 1948), 791-792.
166
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of La Constitution Federale de la Suisse, 1848-1948. The American
Political Science Review, Vol. 42, No. 6 (Dec., 1948), 1222-1224.
72
constitution of 1848 and the peaceful co-operation of four different nationalities under it
has become one of the popular arguments in favor of international federation on a
European, if not a world, scale. The public is treated to the mythological spectacle of a
Swiss democracy where for more than six centuries segments of the main European
nations have lived together in peace and freedom. Against this image, Morgenthau
posited the blunt assertion that Switzerland as a Federal state was the result, not of a
centuries old harmony among reasonable and peaceful people, but of a struggle for
power culminating in a civil war through which one faction of the nation was able to
impress its will upon the other.
Returning to one of the central themes of his lifes work, Morgenthau undertook a
review of Harold Laskis Liberty and the Modern State.167 Laski had argued that the Four
Freedoms of President Roosevelt were a prerequisite to the achievement of liberalism.
Morgenthau disagreed, contending that the Four Freedoms were insufficient planning
tools for the post-war world, since they lacked intellectual rigor, were imprecise and were
as a result, unachievable. This denunciation of what might still be termed New Deal
politics would appear to place Morgenthau firmly in the conservative camp and would
certainly appear to place him at odds with his later self and his calls to end poverty. In
fact, as elsewhere, the distinction is more apparent than real. Morgenthau disliked the
Four Freedoms because they were an imprecise basis for future policy. They did not take
account of the situation as it actually was, but rather hoped for how it might become
without providing the tools necessary to get there. Thus it was not the objective of
abolishing hunger that Morgenthau rejected but rather the likelihood that the Four
Freedoms would serve as a means of achieving it.
As early as the late 1950s, Morgenthau was already questioning the value of
nuclear weapons, suggesting that their presence necessitated a re-orientation of traditional
diplomacy based on military strength. Specifically, Morgenthau praised Henry
Kissingers Nuclear Weapons and Foreign Policy for its recognition that peace and war,
political and military policy were different phases of one organic whole: the defense and
promotion of the national interests vis--vis other nations. Yet he doubted Kissingers
167
Hans J. Morgenthau, The Corruption of Liberal thought, Review of Liberty and the Modern State,
(1949), reprinted in Dilemmas of Politics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958).
73
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of Vietnam: A Diplomatic Tragedy: The Origins of The United States
Involvement, Victor Bator, American Historical Review, vol. 71, No. 3, April 1966, 1101.
169
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of The Cultural Approach: Another Way in International Relations, Ruth
McMurry and Muna Lee, American Journal of Sociology, Vol. 53, No. 5, (Mar., 1948), p.397-398.
74
Reviewing China: The Peoples Middle Kingdom and the U.S.A, Morgenthau argued that
the current China policy of the United States was in error.170 Specifically, Morgenthau
called for the removal of the seventh fleet, the presence of which was surely a
provocation to China, as a means of avoiding a regional conflict, and for a re-orientation
of policy toward China in general.
Morgenthaus book reviews touched on a wide variety of subjects, but at the root
of all was his twin belief that as a framework for international relations, idealism should
be replaced by realism. This fundamental position, which remained constant throughout
his career, led him to reject international concern for minorities within foreign nations,
indiscriminate aid to foreign countries based on notions of charity, and collective security
arrangements based on presumed faith and goodwill. Each of these positions would
generally fall within what could be termed the politics of conservatism. The same realist
framework, however, led Morgenthau to call for withdrawal from Vietnam, recognition
of China, establishment of collective security based on the will of nation states, and the
abandonment of nuclear weapons if not absolutely at least to international control willed
by, and recognized by, nation states. Each of these positions would generally fall within
what might be termed the politics of liberalism. This duality of political perspectives
suggests a level of confusion within Morgenthaus thinking. In fact, there is no confusion,
only two sides of a single coin. Such was the beauty of Morgenthaus realism. It, being
constant and containing within it both conservative and progressive elements, could be
applied to a variety of different situations, which might, because of their different natures,
result in a variety of implications, a variety sufficient as to suggest conflicting positions
within Morgenthaus thinking. In fact, while the suggested policy choices might differ,
the fundamental analytical basis remained the same. Thus Morgenthau, recognizing his
own consistency, and believing firmly in the obligations of the intellectual to engage with
the problems of the day, believed himself to be compelled to honor the implications of his
beliefs, whatever the public and political consequences of so doing. Thus in both his calls
for withdrawal from Vietnam, and his rejection of foreign aid as a charitable endeavor,
170
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of China: The Peoples Middle Kingdom and the U.S.A., John K. Fairbank,
China Quarterly, No.32 (Oct.-Dec., 1967), 174-175.
75
Morgenthau was acting according to the same political impulse: advocacy of the policy
which would best serve the interests of the United States.
76
Conclusion
Toward A New Paradigm?
Hans Morgenthau came to the United States in 1937 as a refugee from European
fascism. He did so carrying the burden of his experience both as a man excluded from his
native country because of the significance attached by one particular political party to his
ascribed ethnicity, and as a European who had watched that same political party build up
sufficient military strength so as to pose a threat to the rest of the continent. This
experience of rejection engendered within Morgenthau an abhorrence both for
totalitarianism and the weak methods of understanding relations between states on which
he perceived the international system to have relied.
In addition to these burdens of rejection and disillusionment, however,
Morgenthau also arrived bearing the advantages of one who had attended university and
acquired a comprehensive understanding of political relations. Putting the burdens and
the advantages together, it should come as no surprise that upon his entry into the U.S.
intellectual academy, he should have advocated an understanding of international
relations which contained within it both the potential to be aggressively robust where
needs be - in order to prevent, for example, the take over of Europe by totalitarianism,
whether German fascism or Soviet communism - but also the potential to be liberatory
and inclusive where needs be - resolve issues pertaining to domestic ills, withdraw from
fights of fancy - in order to preserve the state and promote the greater good of the society
empowered by the state. It should also come as no surprise that as a member of that
intellectual academy, Morgenthau perceived himself to have a responsibility as a scholar,
teacher and public intellectual to convince others of the righteousness of his beliefs, and
thereby work toward the advancement of both the state and society in which he now
lived.
Specifically, Morgenthau published monographs, articles, book reviews; delivered
77
speeches, taught consistently, both at his home university and at various guest
institutions, and was a regular participant in popular analyses of current events. In so
doing, particularly at the start of his career, he helped produce much of the intellectual
underpinnings of the strategic posture of the United States during the early Cold War.
Politics Among Nations, and the teaching that helped produce it, and later resulted from
it, helped shape the worldview of a generation of scholars and policymakers. They
believed Morgenthau when Morgenthau told them that relations between states were
determined above all else by the pursuit of each state for power and security. They
believed Morgenthau when he asserted that supranational bodies in an age of nation
states were unlikely to be able to do very much. They believed Morgenthau when he
proposed that states, being states, will defend their interests up to and including the use of
military force. Morgenthau propounded, his students and others influenced by his words
implemented.
Over the course of Morgenthaus career, he continued to propound, and others
continued to implement. As the years passed, however, a discrepancy grew up between
what Morgenthau was propounding and what others were implementing. Superficially, or
so it appeared to many at the time, it appeared as though the discrepancy was the fault of
Morgenthau. As one who had apparently shifted from arguing the need to contain the
communism of the Soviet Union to advocating the need to accept the communism of
North Vietnam, he had apparently shifted his political position. Indeed, it would be
logical to assume that having made such a journey in his political outlook, from
conservative to radical, Morgenthau would have made a similar journey in terms of his
theoretical perspective. Morgenthau seemed to suggest as much when he chose to serve
as a political advisor to Eugene McCarthy, the most liberal of the candidates in the 1968
Democratic primary race, and again when he chose to serve as a board member for the
Institute for Policy Research, the left-wing think-tank and bete noir of the American
right.171 Morgenthaus perception of himself as the philosopher speaking truth to power that he must honor his convictions with actions and words - made him an uncomfortable
bedfellow for some of his original political associates. As a result, seeing his apparent
171
Peter Kovler, The Left-Leaning Think Tank, Change (The Magazine of Learning), Vol. 10, No. 5,
May 1978.
78
shift and listening to his real criticisms, some policymakers condemned him for his
treachery and his weakness.
As this thesis has demonstrated, however, Morgenthau, despite all appearances to
the contrary, made no such shift. Certainly what he said in 1968 involved implementing
policies different to those inspired by what he said in 1948, but the difference was in the
policy not the theory. Thus Morgenthau in 1948 called for a robust containment of the
Soviet Union ere it become too aggressive and seek to expand across the continent or
even world. Morgenthau perceived that such an expansion would be against the interests
of the United States. And, just as importantly, he perceived that the United States, could
by making its position clear from early on, succeed in its objective and contain the
communism of the Soviet Union within the Soviet Union.
In 1968 Morgenthau called for the withdrawal of U.S. troops from Vietnam
because he did not believe that it was in the interests of the United States to continue to
involve itself in the region. Furthermore, and just as importantly, he did not perceive that
the United States could succeed in its objective of preventing the spread of communism
from one part of what Morgenthau considered to be a single country (even if current U.S.
policymakers failed to recognize this) to the other. In both cases, however, Morgenthau
was proposing that U.S. policy makers should base their course of action upon the real
interests of the United States. In short, he was arguing for a realist interpretation of
international relations.
It is perhaps not surprising that so many of Morgenthaus contemporaries failed to
recognize the consistency contained within his arguments and so accused him of
changing his political tune. Perceived to be the doctrine which provided the basis for the
containment of communism, realism was perhaps inevitably perceived to be a
conservative doctrine. And so it was in its opposition to the unchecked spread of Soviet
communism. What was not so obvious in the early years of Morgenthaus career was the
variety of potential policies which could all be justified on the basis of realism. They
were not so obvious because the progressive element contained within the very theory of
realism, was not so obvious. As we have seen through an analysis of Morgenthaus
published works, it was there - right from the beginning - but again perhaps
understandably, in the 1940s and 1950s, at the height of the Cold War hysteria, others
79
80
81
References
Primary Monographs
Hans J. Morgenthau, Scientific Man vs. Power Politics, (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1946).
Hans J. Morgenthau, In Defense of the National Interest: A Critical Examination of
American Foreign Policy, (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1951).
Hans J. Morgenthau, The Purpose of American Politics, (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1962).
Hans J. Morgenthau, Vietnam and The United States, (Washington: Public Affairs Press,
1965).
Hans J. Morgenthau, A New Foreign Policy for the United States, (New York: Preager,
1969).
Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, (New
York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1948),
Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, (New
York: Alfred A. Knopf, 2nd edition, 1954
Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, (New
York: Alfred A. Knopf, 3rd edition, 1960).
Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, (New
York: Alfred A. Knopf, 4th edition 1967).
Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, (New
York: Alfred A. Knopf, 5th edition, 1973)
Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, (New
York Alfred A. Knopf, 5th edition , revised , 1978)
82
Collected Essays
Hans J. Morgenthau, Dilemmas of Politics, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958).
Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics in the Twentieth Century: The Decline of Democratic
Politics, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962).
Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics in the Twentieth Century: The Impasses of American
Foreign Policy, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962).
Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics in the Twentieth Century: The Restoration of American
Politics, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962).
Hans J. Morgenthau, The Crossroad Papers: A Look Into The American Future (New
York: W.W. Norton and Company, 1965).
Hans J. Morgenthau, Truth and Power: Essays of A Decade (New York: Praeger, 1970).
83
Book Reviews
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of Neo-Neutrality, Georg Cohen, The American Political
Science Review, vol. 33, No. 5, (Oct, 1939), pp 893-894.
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of Making International Law Work, George W. Keeton and
Georg Schwarzenberger, The American Journal of International Law, Vol. 34,
No. 3 (July, 1940), 537.
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of Power Politics, Georg Schwarzenberger, The American
Journal of International Law, vol. 36, No. 2 (Apr, 1942), 351-352.
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of Towards An Abiding Peace, R. M. MacIver, The Journal
of Political Economy, Vol. 52, No. 1 (Mar., 1944), 91-92.
Hans J. Morgenthau , Review of Were the Minorities Treaties a Failure? Jacob
Robinson et al, Journal of Modern History, Vol. 16, No. 3 (Sept. 1944), 237.
Hans J. Morgenthau , Review of War and Its Causes, L. L. Bernard, The American
Political Science Review, Vol. 39, No. 2 (Apr. 1945), 365-366.
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of The Super-Powers, William T.B. Fox, Ethics, (Apr.
1945), 227-228.
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of International Tribunals, Manley O. Hudson, The
American Political Science Review, Vol.39, No.4 (Aug., 1945), 802-804.
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of The Device of Government: An Essay on Civil Polity,
John Laird, The Journal of Political Economy, vol. 54, No. 6 (Dec., 1946), 566.
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of La Constitution Federale de la Suisse, 1848-1948. The
American Political Science Review, Vol. 42, No. 6 (Dec., 1948), 1222-1224.
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of Vietnam: A Diplomatic Tragedy: The Origins of The
United States Involvement, Victor Bator, American Historical Review, vol. 71,
No. 3, April 1966, 1101.
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of The Cultural Approach: Another Way in International
Relations, Ruth McMurry and Muna Lee, American Journal of Sociology, Vol.
53, No. 5, (Mar., 1948), p.397-398
84
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of China: The Peoples Middle Kingdom and the U.S.A.,
John K. Fairbank, China Quarterly, No.32 (Oct.-Dec., 1967), 174-175.
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of Pioneers in World Order: An American Appraisal of the
League of Nations, ed. Harriet Eager Davis, Journal of Political Economy, vol.
54, No. 6 (Dec. 1946), 568-569.
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of A Free and Responsible Press, composed by The
Commission on Freedom of the Press, American Journal of Sociology, vol. 53,
No. 3 (Nov., 1947), 225.
Hans J. Morgenthau, Review of The Spanish Story, Herbert Feiss, The American Political
Science Review, Vol. 42, Issue 4 (Aug., 1948), 791-792.
Secondary Monographs
David Blackbourn, A History of Germany 1780-1918: The Long Nineteenth Century, 2nd
edition, (Oxford: Blackwell, 2003).
Desmond Dinan, Ever Closer Union? An Introduction to the European Community,
(Houndmills, Basingstock, Hampshire: MacMillan Press, 1994).
Christopher Frei, Hans J. Morgenthau. An Intellectual Biography, (Baton Rouge:
Louisiana State University Press, 2001).
Michael Foot, Peter Howard, and Frank Owen, The Guilty Men, (London: Victor
Gollancz,, Left Book Club, 1940).
Mikhail Gorbachev, Perestroika, (Borgo Press, 1991).
John J. Mearsheimer, The Tragedy of Great Power Politics, (New York: W.W. Norton &
Company, 2001).
Robert W. Merry, Taking on the World: Joseph and Stewart Alsop: Guardians of the
American Century, (New York: Viking, 1996).
Aogan Mulcahy, Policing Northern Ireland: Legitimacy, Reform and Social Conflict
(Cullompton: Willan Publishing, 2004).
Cardinal Armand Jean du Plessis Richelieu, The Political Testament of Cardinal
Richelieu, trans. Henry Bertram Hill, (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press,
1964).
85
Articles
Francis A. Beer and Robert Hariman, Realism and Rhetoric in International Relations,
in Francis A. Beer and Robert Hariman ed., Post Realism: The Rhetorical Turn in
International Relations, (East Lansing: Michigan State University Press, 1996).
John Paul Hill, A.R. Happy Chandler, George C. Wallace and the Presidential Election
of 1968, The Historian, vol. 64, No. 3+4 (Spring/Summer 2002), 667-685.
George F. Kennan, "The Sources of Soviet conduct," Foreign Affairs, XXV (July, 1947),
566-82.
James Reston, Ann Arbor: The Strange Bedfellows in Vietnam, New York Times,2
May, 1965, E10.
86
David Sanford, Matthew Morgenthaus Complaint, The New Republic, March 1, 1969,
Harold Sprout, In Defense of Diplomacy World Politics, Volume 1, Issue 3 (Apr.,
1949), 404-413.
Kenneth W. Thompson, The Writing of Politics Among Nations: Its Sources and its
Origins, International Studies: Notes of the International Studies Association
Special Issue: The Legacy of Hans Morgenthau, Vol. 24, No. 1, (1999).
New York Times, New School Slates Debate on Vietnam,, 21 May 1965, 13.
L.H. Woolsey, Review of Politics Among Nations, Hans J. Morgenthau, American
Journal of International Law, Vol. 44, Issue ! (Jan., 1950), 219-221.
John Vasquez The Enduring Contributions of Hans J. Morgenthaus Politics Among
Nations, International Studies, Volume 24, Number 1, 1999.
Reference Works
Hans Joachim Morgenthau, Current Biography 1963, ed. Charles Moritz, (New York:
The M.W. Wilson Company, 1963).
87