Statutory Interpretation in A New Nutshell
Statutory Interpretation in A New Nutshell
Statutory Interpretation in A New Nutshell
A NEW NUTSHELL
51
Ruth Sullivanl
Ottawa
This article attempts to update a Canadian classic - the realist account
ofstatutory interpretation published by John Willis in the Canadian Bar
Review in 1938. Willis' insights are compelling and they remain relevant
today. However, by focusing on the rhetoric of statutory interpretation, by
far its weakest point, Willis disregards the considerable work that goes on
when statutory interpretation is well done. This article draws attention to
that work.
Part 2 looks at the kinds of analyses relied on by good interpreters to
establish that elusive goal, the intention of the legislature . These include
textual, purposive, scheme, policy and consequential analysis . Part 2
examines the difference between easy and hard cases, then focuses on the
techniques used by interpreters to carry out the different kinds ofanalyses
and how these relate to the formal rules.
Part 3 looks at the range of arguments interpreters may construct based
on their preliminary analysis. Not every argument in statutory
interpretation is about the meaning ofwords. Interpreters also confront
drafter's mistakes, gaps in the legislative scheme, overlap and conflict,
and language that is over- or tinder-inclusive. The structure of these
different kinds ofarguments is set out and illustrated in Part 3.
Cet article essaie de mettre jour une thorie classique canadienne. En
1938, John Willis a publi dans cette revue un article prenant une
mthode raliste l'interprtation lgislative qui continue d'tre
pertinente aujourd'hui. Mais il se concentrait sur la rhtorique et laissait
de ct le travail considrable qui fait toujours une partie de
l'interprtation srieuse. Cet article essaie de mettre en relief ce travail
important.
La deuxime partie examine les types d'analyse utilises en cherchant un
objectif vasif., l'intention du lgislateur Ces types d'analyses
comprennent l'analyse textuelle, l'analyse fonde sur l'objet vis, le
rgime lgislatif, la position du lgislateur, et l'analyse des
I Ruth Sullivan, of the Faculty of Law, University of Ottawa, Ottawa, Ontario . In
preparing this article, I received many useful suggestions from Carol Diamond, Kate
Murray. Paul Salembier and Katie Wang . I also acknowledge the generous support of the
Social Science and Humanities Research Council of Canada.
52
(Vol .82
20031
53
Part 1: Introduction
In 1938 John Willis published an article called "Statutory Interpretation
in a Nutshell"? Willis' article is a significant contribution to the legal
realist literature of the twentieth century. In addition to being clever and
amusing, it offers a concise exposition ofthe main rules of interpretation,
with special focus on the so-called mischief rule, plain meaning rule, and
golden rule. Willis' thesis is that because these rules are open-ended and
inconsistent with one another, they are incapable of determining the
outcome in statutory interpretation disputes . Although judges purport to
apply them, in fact outcomes are determined by the politics and arbitrary
preferences of the presiding judge. "What use do courts make of the
`plain meaning rule'?" Willis asks. "The answer is that they use it, as they
use all other `rules of construction', as a device whereby to achieve some
desired reSUIL" 3
A current reader of Willis must be struck by how little has changed
since 1938. Judges continue to invoke the same rules, make the same
arguments and rely on the same rhetoric 4 as they did when Willis wrote.
And academics continue to deplore the contradictions and false premises
that disturbed Willis and other legal realists of the days
Yet some things have changed. Since 1938 there has been a
significant evolution in the way we think about rules and their role in
interpretation . For Willis and other legal realists, the inconsistency and
indeterminacy of the rules were unacceptable because these features
undermined their status as law. If the outcome of a dispute is not
determined by applying relevant rules to the facts of the case, then it is
not determined by law. If it is not determined by law, then it must be
determined by the personal preference of the individual judge. Those
appeared to be the only choices .
Most contemporary jurists have a broader conception of law and the
means by which legal disputes are resolved . They think of law as
including not only rules (which are binding) but also principles (which
2 (1939) 16 Can. Bar Rev . l .
3 Ibid. at 11 ; see also at 13 : "What use do the courts make of the `golden rule'today?
Again the answer is the same-they use it as a device to achieve a desired result . . ." and
at 15 : "What use do the courts make of the 'mischief rule'today? Once more, the answer
is that they use it to achieve a desired result . .."
4 In this article I use the term "rhetoric" in a technical rather than a pejorative sense.
Technically, rhetoric refers to the features of arguments that make them persuasive, the
means by which one person persuades another that a conclusion is appropriate and should
be accepted .
5 See, for example, R. Sullivan, "The Plain Meaning Rule and Other Ways to Cheat
at Statutory Interpretation" in Ejan Mackaay, ed ., Les certitudes du droit / Certainty and
the Law (Montreal: Les ditions Thmis, 2000) at 151 .
54
[Vol.82
are not) as well as the values, assumptions and practices that contribute to
an evolving legal tradition. This post-realist conception permits
contemporary jurists to integrate statutory interpretation into law by
thinking of it as a principle-governed rather than a rule-governed activity.
As Dworkin might say, statutory interpretation is law because it is an
activity carried out within a practice-based legal principle . 6
This evolution in thinking about statutory interpretation is reflected in
the Supreme Court of Canada's adoption of Elmer Driedger's so-called
"modern principle" . In the first and second editions of The Construction
of Statutes,? Driedger explored the main rules discussed by Willis - the
plain meaning rule, the mischief rule and golden rule - in the first three
chapters of his book. He showed that each was dominant at one time in
history; and each reflects (albeit imperfectly) an important aspect of
interpretation, namely the reader's understanding of the text, the
intentions of the legislature, and harmony with established legal norms.
His thesis was that no single approach is adequale, that interpreters must
take into account and attempt to harmonize all aspects of interpretation.
In the fourth chapter he concluded:
Today there is only one principle or approach ; namely, the words of an Act are to be
read in their entire context and in their grammatical and ordinary sense harmoniously
with the scheme of the Act, the object of the Act, and the intention of Parliament 8
Since its initial appearance in 1974, this passage has been continually
cited and relied on by Canadian courts . In 1998, in Rizzo v. Rizzo Shoes
Ltd., it was adopted by the Supreme Court of Canada as stating its
preferred approach . 9
While the modern principle is not immune from criticism, 10 it must
be admired for the way it accommodates the post-realist conception of
law as a practice within a tradition. Instead of reducing statutory
interpretation to a silly game of pick-up-rules - or worse, to a shell game
- it describes a purposeful, multifaceted activity . To resolve statutory
interpretation disputes, judges must analyze and integrate a variety of
6 R.M . Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge : Belknap Press, 1986), especially
chapters 2, 7 and 9. Of course, Dworkin is also responsible for the rule-principle
distinction referred to in the text that has become a commonplace of legal discussion . See
R.M . Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge : Duckworth, 1978), especially at 22
-27.
7 Elmer Driedger, The Construction ofStatutes, tst ed . (Toronto : Butterworths : 1974)
and 2nd ed . (Toronto : Butterworths, 1984).
8 Ibid. at 67 . As Driedger explains at 82 of the 1 st ed . and at 106 of the 2nd ed .,
"intention of Parliament" includes presumed as well as express and implied intent.
9 See Rizzo v. Rizzo Shoes Ltd, [1998] 1 S.C .R . 27.
10 SeeR. Sullivan, "Statutory Interpretation in the Supreme Court of Canada" (199899) 30 Ottawa L. Rev. 178 .
2003]
55
I t The notion of law as a medium within which judges work to construct decisions
the way builders make structures out of bricks is suggested and developed by D. Kennedy
in "The Phenomenology of Judging" in A. Hutchinson & P. Monahan, eds., The Rule of
Law: Ideal or Ideology (Toronto : Carswell, 1987).
56
LA REVIEW DU BARREAUCANADIEN
[Vol .$Z
In Part III ofthis paper I set out the varying models of argument that
can be used in statutory interpretation and suggest how argument is
structured under each model . My purpose in Part III is to illustrate how
disputes about the meaning of legislation are argued and to emphasize
that there is more to statutory interpretation than such disputes .
Sometimes the meaning is clear, but there is a gap in the legislative
scheme, and the question is whether the court can do anything about it.
Sometimes there is overlap between a clear provision and the common
law, and the issue is whether both apply. Many disputes are about the
circumstances in which a court should update a statute or decline to apply
a legislative rule even though its meaning appears to be clear. In short,
determining the meaning of words in a legislative text is an important task
ofinterpreters, and a necessary first task, but it is only part of the work of
interpretation.
Part II: Preliminary analysis
When an interpreter sits down to deal with an issue in statutory
interpretation, he or she begins with a set of facts. The job is to determine
whether any legislative provision applies to those facts, and if so, to what
effect . To make this determination the interpreter has to answer the
following questions:
" What is the meaning of the legislative text?
" What was the legislature's intent? That is, when the text was enacted, what rule did
the legislature intend to adopt? What purposes did it hope to achieve? What specific
intentions (if any) did it have regarding these facts?
" What would the consequences be if a proposed interpretation were adopted? Would
these consequences violate important, legally recognized norms?
If all goes well, the meaning of the text (as understood by the
interpreter) coincides with the legislature's intention (as reconstructed by
the interpreter) and produces results that (in his or her view) accord with
2003]
57
sa
wol.a2
the text differs from the meaning that was probably intended by the
legislature . Or applying the text as written leads to anomalous
consequences that were probably unforeseen by the legislature . In such
cases the interpreter is forced to choose an outcome, ideally on a
principled basis, which he or she can both articulate and support .
Suppose, for example, that John drove an ambulance into the park, in
response to an emergency call, to save the life of a seriously injured child .
An ambulance is clearly a vehicle . Moreover, it has the potential to do
damage to grass and flower beds ; it produces exhaust and more than its
share of disruptive noise; and it is a threat to the safety of pets and
pedestrians who may be using the park. Nonetheless, most people would
agree that the ambulance should have legal access to the park. It would
be absurd to exclude it, The legislature must have taken it for granted that
rational interpreters would read down the prohibition to exclude obvious
exceptions such as these.
The point of these examples, like the point of Driedger's modern
principle, is that in every case, interpreters must explore all aspects of
interpretation . Before deciding which factors to rely on and how they will
construct their arguments, interpreters must know whether the case is
easy or hard, and if hard, why and how it is hard. They must identify
sources of doubt or conflict and the relevant indicators of legislative
meaning and intent; and they must assess the weight of the competing
factors. Preliminary analysis of this sort is necessary to ensure sound
judgement and persuasive argument .
There is no standard way of classifying the different types ofanalyses
that must be carried out at the preliminary stage . In the list below I
describe them under the headings textual analysis, purposive analysis,
scheme analysis, poliv analysis, and consequential analysis . I also
include a short comment on the use of extrinsic aids. Others might prefer
fewer, or more, or different categories.13 The important thing is not how
this preliminary work is categorized, but how it is carried out. The goal is
to be as comprehensive and as explicit as possible .
Being explicit is particularly important . Interpretation normally
operates at a sub-conscious level. Upon reading the words of a text, a
reader may intuitively reach certain conclusions - the text is clear (or
unclear), it expresses a particular meaning or purpose, it leads to absurd
13 My categories are not mutually exclusive . For example, scheme analysis overlaps
with purposive analysis on the one hand and textual analysis on the other; policy analysis
overlaps with purposive and consequential analysis. The descriptions of the different
categories of analysis and of the rules relied on by interpreters in carrying out these
analyses is found in R. Sullivan, Statutory Interpretation (Concord, OnU irwin Law,
1996) and R. Sullivan, Sullivan and Driedger on the Construction of Statutes, 4th ed.,
2002.
2003]
Statutory Interpretations in
a New Nutshell
59
14 In fact, of course, the average person or the general public is a convenient fiction .
The audience to which legislation is addressed, particularly legislation like the Criminal
Code, is diverse in terms of culture, gender, race, and the like. These differences
undermine traditional assumptions about "common" meaning and "common" sense.
60
[Vol.82
" Plausible meaning rule : if the ordinary meaning is rejected to give effect to the actual
or presumed intentions of the legislature, the meaning adopted must be one thewords
are capable of bearing.
20031
61
" Limited class (ejusdem generis) : when general language follows a series of more
specific terms, the class of things referred to by the general language may be read
down to refer to a narrower class of things to which the specific terms all belong .
(B) Purposive analysis
62
(Vol .82
The rules governing the admissibility and use of this material are
complex and in a state of flux . Generally speaking, legislative sources and
legislative evolution are always admissible, as is precedent. Legislative
history and other forms of expert opinion are subject to specialized rules.
20031
63
The list is not closed. In recent years, Canadian courts have added the
following policy-based presumptions :
" the legislature intends to combat the feminization of poverty
" the legislature intends to protect the environment from pollution
(F) Consequential analysis
64
[Vol.8Z
The clearer and more precise a text seems to be, the greater the
absurdity required to depart from its ordinary meaning. The greater the
absurdity that flows from a particular interpretation, the more justified an
interpreter is in rejecting it.
Having carried out these different types of analysis, the interpreter
must then consider how the results can be used to support a preferred
position (in the case of litigants) or to explain andjustify the correct legal
result (in the case of judges). This involves choosing an appropriate
model of argument and developing persuasive supporting arguments.
Part III: Constructing Argument
This part surveys the various models of argument that can be used to
structure disputes about the proper interpretation of a legislative text . It is
based on the following framework :
corrigible mistake
disputed meaning
over-inclusive text
non-application
under-inclusive text
overlapping provisions
2003]
65
66
wol.a2
2003]
67
"capable of firing bullets in the relevant way. On this point the appellant
and the Crown could each make plausible, but conflicting claims . These,
then, were the words of doubtful application.
(2) Formulating an effective interpretation
The second step is to develop an interpretation of the doubtful
language that effectively clarifies whether the legislation applies and
leads to the preferred result .ls Such an interpretation usually takes the
form of a paraphrase or definition, or in some cases a set of criteria that
operates as a legal test. The formulation should be as precise and concise
as possible and should be set out as the initial claim in the argument : "In
this provision, properly understood, the words in dispute mean . . ."
Coming up with an effective definition, paraphrase or set of criteria
is perhaps the most challenging and important task in interpretation. It is
here that the skill and imagination of counsel can make a real difference.
In the Hasselwander case, the defendant claimed that the phrase "is
capable of means "has a current or existing capacity to do a thing" . Since
at the moment of seizure the Mini-Uzi had no existing capacity to fire
bullets in rapid succession during one pressure of the trigger, it was not a
prohibited weapon within the meaning of the Code. The defendant wisely
included the word "is" in identifying the language in dispute to
emphasize existing as opposed to future capability.
68
(Vol.82
2003]
69
70
lvol.8z
Under this scheme, counsel argued, weapons that were designed, altered
or intended to fire automatically were merely restricted before 1978 but
after that date the same weapons became prohibited unless they were
registered as restricted on January 1, 1978. In order for this scheme to
work, the class of weapons described as "capable of firing automatically
must be coextensive with the class described as "designed, altered, or
intended" to fire automatically. Otherwise, those who owned convertible
semi-automatic weapons at the start of 1978 would have had to give up
their weapons whereas those with filly automatic weapons could have
kept them - an obvious absurdity. To avoid this absurdity, the class of
firearm that is capable of firing automatically must be limited to firearms
actually altered and not just capable of being altered to fire automatically.
Finally, the defendant's counsel relied on both purposive and policy
analysis . He pointed out that the goal of protecting the public was
adequately served by including semi-automatic weapons in the category
of restricted weapons. He also pointed out that penal legislation
traditionally receives a restrictive interpretation. If there is a choice
between a narrow and a broad interpretation of disputed language, the
narrow interpretation should prevail.
Counsel for the Crown relied primarily on purposive and
consequential analysis, and its arguments were adopted by a majority of
the Court. Cory J. wrote:
What then should "capable" mean as it is used in the s. 84(1) definition of prohibited
weapon? It should not be restricted to the narrow meaning of immediately capable.
Such a definition would mean that the simple removal of a part, which could be
replaced in seconds, would take the weapon outside the definition . This surely could
not have been the intention of Parliament. If it were, the danger from automatic
weapons would continue to exist just as strongly as it did before the prohibition was
enacted .zl
Parliament's purpose was to protect the public from weapons whose only
purpose, Cory J. suggested, is to wound or main people . Given the
pressing importance of this purpose, and the minimal social utility of
permitting ordinary citizens to possess such weapons, achieving the
purpose was assigned considerable weight - enough to defeat the textand-scheme-based arguments of the defendant.
(5) Conclusion
if the interpreter has done her job of identifying the disputed
language, interpreting it, and supporting her interpretation on both
linguistic and legal grounds, the result will be obvious. Once the court in
21 Supra note 15 at 415 .
20031
71
Since Ms. Vabalis had not adopted her husband's name when she married,
applying this provision to her would have required her husband, whose
surname was different, to change his name to Vabals . Here is how the
court responded :
In our opinion the double application requirement contained in s. 4(1) should be
construed as being applicable only where the married person applying for the change
of surname uses th same surname as the spouse. We are all agreed that the literal
interpretation of s. 4(1) as requiring a change of name of the applicant's spouse in the
present situation would lead to an obvious absurdity. A statute enacted by the
Legislature of this province should not be so interpreted.23
72
(Vol.82
of occumence .z5
Two other grounds for non-application are (1) conflict between two
overlapping provisions, such that it is impossible for both to apply, and
(2) a provision constitutes or is part of an exhaustive code, such that all
24
25 Ibid.
2003]
73
74
[Uo1.82
These paramountcy rules have the force of genuine rules: they are binding
on the courts .
Other rules establish paramountcy among legislative provisions :
"
"
"
"
Unlike the rules based on hierarchy, these paramountcy rules are based on
presumed legislative intent. They are therefore liable to be displaced by
evidence of actual intent revealed through textual, purposive, scheme,
policy and consequential analysis .
A good example of the paramountcy model of argument is found in
R. v Greenwood.27 In that case an accused was charged with sexual
assault and sexual interference involving a thirteen-year-old child. At the
preliminary inquiry, the only evidence adduced was the unsworn
testimony of the child. The issue was whether this evidence was
admissible . Section 16(3) ofthe Canada Evidence Act provided :
A person referred to in subsection (1) [i .e . a person under 14 years of age] who does
not understand the nature of an oath or a solemn affirmation but is able to communicate
the evidence may testify on promising to tell the truth.
After questioning the child, the provincial courtjudge concluded that the
child did not understand the nature of an oath or a solemn affirmation, but
did understand the importance of telling the truth in the circumstances.
He therefore ruled that the child's evidence was admissible, given the
ordinary meaning of s. 16(3).
Counsel for the accused did not challenge this interpretation of s.
16(3), but argued that the section did not apply because it was superceded
by s. 540(l)(a) ofthe Criminal Code. That provision required evidence at
a preliminary inquiry to be given under oath :
Where an accused is before ajustice holding a preliminary inquiry, the justice shall
(a) take the evidence under oath....
2003]
75
enactments of the federal Parliament, they occupied the same place in the
legal hierarchy.
Counsel for both parties tried to rely on the specialibus rule: when
two provisions conflict, the more specific one impliedly creates an
exception to the more general one. Counsel for the accused focussed
narrowly on the conflicting provisions themselves. He argued that s.
16(3) of the Canada Evidence Act should be considered general because
that provision applies to proceedings of all kinds whereas s. 540 of the
Criminal Code should be considered specific because it is limited to
preliminary hearings. Conversely, counsel for the Crown focussed
broadly on the two statutes as a whole. He argued that the Canada
Evidence Act should be considered the specific legislation because it
deals with the specialized subject of evidence in contrast to the Code,
which deals with crime in general . He could also have argued, focussing
on the two conflicting provisions, that s. 16(3) of the Canada Evidence
Act is specific because it deals with the special case of minors whereas
the Criminal Code provision is general because it applies to witnesses in
general .
In the end, the court concluded that the Canada Evidence Act
provision should prevail . However, the basis for this conclusion was not
the specialibus rule but rather the court's purposive and consequential
analysis . Griffiths J.A . wrote:
If s. 540(1)(a) of the Code were literally interpreted28 to exclude the application of s.
16(3) of the Canada Evidence Act, then this would lead to a highly undesirable and
anomalous result, which surely could not reflect the intention of Parliament . To deny
the applicability of s. 16(3) to the preliminary inquiry is to defeat its manifest purpose,
most especially in cases of sexual assault and cognate crimes against children 29
After pointing out other unacceptable consequences that would flow from
assigning paramountcy to the Code, Griffiths J.A. concluded that s. 16(3)
of the Canada Evidence Act was meant to operate as an exception to the
general rule set out s. 540(1)(a) of the Code.
(2) Exhaustive code
An interpreter may wish to rely on an exhaustive code model of
argument in either of the following circumstances :
" provisions from different statutes apply without conflict to particular facts, or
" legislative provisions and the common law apply without conflict to particular facts.
28 Griffiths J. says "literally interpreted" but he means "applied". The problem here
is not meaning, but conflict among applicable rules.
29 Supra note 27 at 8.
76
[Vol.82
2003]
77
However, the Court of Appeal ruled otherwise. Anderson J.A . for the
majority offered the following explanation:
The above quoted provisions [from the Financial Administration Act], although framed
in wide and general language, do not, in my opinion give the power to issue directives
in respect of matters specifically dealt with by the School Act.
... the School Act provided a comprehensive code dealing with local self-government
in the public education field.... [T]he very matters dealt with by the directive were
specifically reserved to school boards subject to the collective bargaining and
arbitration process outlined in the School Act31
78
[Vol.82
Even though the legislative intent was fairly clear, and even though the
failure to achieve that intent was probably due in fact to a mistake by the
drafter, the court could not correct it because to do so would effectively
confer a new power on the coroner - a power to send journalists to jail .
Not surprisingly, the court held that it lacked jurisdiction to do this .
Notice how paramountcy apd exhaustive code arguments differ from
the disputed meaning model of argument. Whereas the disputed meaning
model addresses doubt about the meaning of a provision in relation to
particular facts, paramountcy and exhaustive code arguments are
concerned with the relationship among legal rules .
2003]
(E)
79
Supplementation
80
[Vol.82
sense of it using the standard techniques of interpretation . The court must redraft
the provision so as to give it some sensible application.
(2) The wording of the text states or suggests one thing, but it is clear that the
legislature intended something else. This discrepancy between meaning and
intention is due to a drafting mistake . The court has jurisdiction to correct this
mistake by notionally redrafting the text so as to bring it in line with the clear
intention of the legislature.
2003]
81
An example of a court bringing the text in line with what the legislature
obviously intended is found in the judgement of the Ontario Court of
Appeal in R. v. Creaghan 39 The defendant was charged with mischief
under the Criminal Code and relied on what was then s. 386(2) as a
defence:
No person shall be convicted of an offence under sections 387 to 402 where he proves
that he acted with legal justification or excuse and colour of right .
Although the defendant could not establish that he acted with legal
justification or excuse, he did establish to the satisfaction of the court that
he acted with "colour of right" . In the view of the court, despite the
wording of s. 386(2), it was not necessary for the defendant to establish
that he acted not only with colour of right but also with legal justification
or excuse :
We are all of the view that the word "and" which precedes the words "with colour of
right" in s. 386(2) should be read as "or" . Manifestly, it would not be sensible to
require the accused to prove not only that he acted with legal justification or excuse
and with colour of right . If the accused acted with legal justification or excuse he is not
criminally liable and that is the end of the matter and there is no need to resort to colour
of right 40
37 ibid. at 712 .
38 1bid at 713-14 .
82
[Vol .82
Notice that the claim being made by the interpreter who relies on this
model of argument is not that courts are entitled to amend legislation or
disregard the will of the legislature. The claim is that, due to incompetent
drafting, the provision as written fails to express the true intent of the
legislature, and if the court is to give effect to that intention, it must repair
the drafting mistake . In order to establish the true intention of the
legislature, the interpreter relies on the various forms of analyses
canvassed in Part 2 and on any relevant extrinsic aids .
Part IV: Conclusion
In this article I have tried to show that statutory interpretation disputes are
resolved, not by arbitrary preference, but by work. During the preliminary
analysis stage, the interpreter analyzes the legislation to locate sources of
doubt and conflict . He or she then identifies reasons to resolve the doubt
or conflict one way as opposed to another. During the argument
construction stage, the interpreter decides which model of argument is
best and formulates the claims associated with that model . He or she then
relies on the preliminary analyses of text, purpose, scheme, policy and
consequences in support of the claims.
t have also tried to show that there is more to statutory interpretation
than argument about the meaning of text and whether it is plain or
ambiguous . Determining whether legislation applies, and how it applies,
depends on all admissible evidence of legislative intent, both actual and
presumed. While some interpretation problems can be dealt with in one
way only, many lend themselves to more than one model of argument. In
such cases, the choice of model is strategic: the interpreter adopts the
model that best supports his or her preferred outcome . This aspect of
interpretation is nicely illustrated by the judgement ofthe Supreme Court
of Canada in R. v Mclntosh,41 which considered the self-defence
provisions of the Criminal Code . The majority used the disputed meaning
model of argument and purported to decide the case on the basis that the
ordinary meaning was plain. The dissent relied on the corrigible mistake
model of argument.
It is obvious that interpreters enjoy significant discretion when they
argue and resolve interpretation disputes . However, they are obliged to
justify what they do by showing how their preferred outcome relates to
the meaning of the text, the intentions of the legislation and evolving
legal norms. These considerations determine the outcome in easy cases,
where they all point in the same direction . In hard cases, they limit the
range of acceptable outcomes. These considerations also underlie the
rules of statutory interpretation, which, properly used, do not disguise
choice but expose it and justify it in a persuasive way.
41 l19951 1 S .C.R . 686 .