Benton 1995 Self Conscious Spectator
Benton 1995 Self Conscious Spectator
Benton 1995 Self Conscious Spectator
Subsequent debates of this dualism in the visual arts have reflected both
descriptions. Indeed, Wollheim9 has acknowledged that he has adopted both
positions at different times. For clarity's sake, the three main contributions to
the debate—those of Gombrich (i960), Wollheim (1987), and Podro (1991) —
can be presented in tabular form (Figure 1), together with those of two
others—Clark (i960) and Koestler (1964) —whose comments help to illumin-
ate the point in the context of their writings on other issues. All the termino-
logy is direct quotation 10
CONCEPT MEDIUM VIRTUAL
SUBJECT
The five concepts vary in their degree of technicality but all are attempts to
explain the experience of viewing representational painting within the general
364 THE SELF-CONSCIOUS SPECTATOR
I would start from as far away as I could, when the illusion was complete, and
come gradually nearer, until suddenly what had been a hand, and a ribbon, and
a piece of velvet, dissolved into a salad of brushstrokes I thought I might learn
something if I could catch the moment at which this transformation took place,
but it proved to be as elusive as the moment between waking and sleeping.12
Clark's final remark suggests that in looking for a single moment we may be
seeking the wrong solution; what in fact he describes is a transformational
process —a series of moments during which the emphases of our perception
change. Nonetheless, this has not deterred others from trying to pin-point
this phenomenon.
Koestler's13 theory of bisociation is one that seeks to account for all creative
activity. It distinguishes between the single-minded routine skills of everyday
thinking, and creative thinking which is described as 'a double-minded, trans-
itory state of unstable equilibrium where the balance of both emotion and
thought is disturbed.' When he comes to discuss painting14, Koestler's dualism
is conveyed through the terms 'medium' and 'motif. He reminds us of the
familiar point that 'the impact (of a painting) does not take place on the canvas,
but in the artist's mind, and in the beholder's mind.' Because of the 'limitations
of the medium' and 'the prejudices of vision' the painter is forced to cheat
and the viewer is forced into complicity
The way he (the painter) cheats, the tricks he uses, are partly determined by the
requirements of the medium itself—he must think 'in terms of stone, wood,
pigment, or gouache—but mainly by the ldiosyncracies of his vision: the codes
which govern the matrices of his perception. Whether Manet's impression of The
Races of Longchamp looks more 'life-like' than Fnth's academically meticulous
Derby Day depends entirely on the beholder's spectacles. An artist can copy in
plaster, up to a point, a Roman copy of a Greek bronze head; he cannot 'copy'
on canvas a running horse He can only create an appearance which, seen in a
certain light, at a certain distance, in a certain mood, will suddenly acquire a life
of its own It is not a copy, but a metaphor. The horse was not a model, but a motif
for his creation —in the sense in which a landscape painter looks for a romantic or
pastoral motif.15
M G BENTON 365
Koestler is not as explicit about the operation of the split-mindedness of
medium and motif in painting as he had been earlier when discussing verbal
the beholder must mobilize his memory of the visible world and project it
into the mosaic of strokes and dabs on the canvas before him It is here, therefore,
- that the principle of guided projection reaches its climax The image, it might be
said, has no firm anchorage left on the canvas . . it is only 'conjured up' in our
minds. The willing beholder responds to the artist's suggestion because he enjoys
the transformation that occurs in front of his eyes The artist gives the
beholder increasingly 'more to do', he draws him into the magic circle of creation
and allows him to experience something of the thrill of 'making' . . .
Gombrich 2 ' has not helped his argument against simultaneity and for alter-
nating attention by basing his case on the well-known figure-ground reversals.
. . . two aspects of a single experience, they are not two experiences They are
neither two separate simultaneous experiences, which I somehow hold in the mind
at once, nor two separate alternating experiences, between which I oscillate. . . '24
These two aspects of viewing are thus distinguishable yet inseparable and
captured in the concept of 'twofoldness'. He calls the two complementary
aspects of seeing-in the recognitional aspect, where the spectator discerns some-
thing in the marked surface, and the configurational aspect, which indicates
the spectator's awareness of the marked surface per se. Both aspects of this
twofoldness operate in the spectator together, and it is this simultaneous
awareness of 'a depicted subject' and 'the marked surface' which ensures that
the framed scene registers both in depth and as flat.
Even though Wollheim avoids the difficulty of divided attention inherent
in Koestler's and Gombrich's accounts, his two-in-one combination produces
a synthetic concept without telling us anything about its modus operandi. As
Martin Kelly25 has pointed out, Wollheim does not elaborate on the 'in' that
he attaches to 'seeing' other than to say that figures are seen in a marked
surface. Prepositions, as suggested at the outset, locate the viewing experience,
and may, as here, indicate its salient features, but they say little about it as a
dynamic process. For some insights into this we must turn to the last of the
five formulations.
M G BENTON 367
26
In his paper 'Depiction and The Golden Calf, Podro borrows a term from
Vasari and develops what he calls 'the disegno thesis —the thesis that we follow
. . . the sense in which the painting selects from, connects and reconstructs the
subject in the medium and procedures of painting; and, because these things are
indissolubly connected, it is concerned with the way that the drawing or painting
directs itself to the mind of the perceiver, who sees the subject remade within it,
sees a new world which exists only in painting and can be seen only by the spectator
who attends to the procedures of painting 27 (My italics.)
The key words here are 'in', 'world', and 'procedures', for they take us on
from Wollheim's 'seeing-in' to theorize what the 'in' implies. This is formu-
lated in terms of a virtual world which, in turn, is sustained by the way the
viewer's attention is undivided in that subject and medium interpenetrate each
other in the viewer's awareness of the procedures of painting.
In his discussion of 'how we see the painting procedure in the subject as
well as the subject in the painting procedure', the notion of the 'marked
surface' is problematic. Podro comments:
To talk of our sense of the surface may appear to be returning to the notion that
attention to surface and attention to represented subject compete or are reciprocally
independent, while in our account we assume the opposite 28
periods of intense absorption during which they seem a part of the very world
they are creating; at other times their role, physically and mentally, may be
LOOKING AROUND
Another preposition has now appeared. Adopting the metaphor of the second-
ary world invites us to speak of the spectator looking around this creation.42
Looking around describes the spectator's imaginative participation and sug-
370 THE SELF-CONSCIOUS SPECTATOR
gests the pleasures of exploration and discovery that are commonly felt before
a painting in those moments that Collinson characterizes as 'sensuous immedi-
The function of the spectator in the picture is that he allows the spectator of the
picture a distinctive access to the content of the picture.
This access is achieved in the following way First, the external spectator looks
at the picture and sees what there is to be seen in it, then adopting the internal
spectator as his protagonist, he starts to imagine in that person's perspective the
person or event that the picture represents, that is to say, he imagines from the
inside the internal spectator seeing, thinking about, responding to, acting upon,
what is before him, then the condition in which this leaves him modifies how he
sees the picture The external spectator identifies with the internal spectator, and
it is through this identification that he gains fresh access to the picture's content.46
. once the spectator of the picture accepts the invitation to identify with the
spectator in the picture, he loses sight of the marked surface. In the represented
space, where he now vicariously stands, there is no marked surface. Accordingly,
the task of the artist must be to recall the spectator to a sense of what he has
temporarily lost The spectator must be returned from imagination to perception:
twofoldness must be reactivated. Otherwise the distinctive resources of the
medium will lie untapped 49
Manet's A Bar at the Folies-Bergere. Most paintings designate stance less expli-
citly than these examples but all pre-define the position from which they are
REFERENCES
1 4
E H Gombnch, 'The Beholder's Share', in K. Walton, Mimesis as Make-Beheve, On the
Art and Illusion (London Phaidon, i960) Foundations of the Representational Arts
2
R Wollheim, 'What the Spectator Sees', in (Cambridge, MA Harvard U.P , 1990)
5
Painting as an Art (London Thames and Ibid , p 301
6
Hudson, 1987) D Colhnson, 'Philosophy Looks at
3
D W Harding, 'Psychological Processes in Paintings', in E Deighton (ed ), Looking into
the Reading of Fiction', in British Journal of Paintings (Milton Keynes Open U . P ,
Aesthetics, Vol 2, No 2, 1962 1985), pp 271-4
M G. BENTON 373
7 31
E Kris, Psychoanalytic Explorations in Art D. W. Winmcott, Playing and Reality
(New York- International U P., 1952/64), (Harmondsworth Penguin, 1974) pp 102-
P 256 3-