Ethics P.25 47
Ethics P.25 47
Ethics P.25 47
Of
Ethics
Outputs
Submitted to:
This is not for sale and only for our class.
#1
Copy from:
Glenn, Paul J.:
Ethics
A Class Manual in Moral Philosophy
National book Store. Philippine. Copyright 1968
INTRODUCTION
1. DEFINITION
Ethics is the practical science of the morality of human conduct.
a) Ethics is a science. A science is a relatively complete and systematically arranged body of
connected data together with the causes or reasons by which these data are known to be true.
Ethics squares with this definition, for it is a complete and systematically arranged body of
data which relate to morality of human conduct; and it presents the reasons which show these
data to be true. Ethics is therefore a science.
b) Ethics is a practical science. If the data of a science directly imply rules or directions for
thought or action, the science is called practical. If the data of a science enrich the mind
without directly implying rules or directions, the science is called speculative. A speculative
science presents truths that are to be known; a practical science presents truths that are to be
acted upon. A speculative science enlarges our knowledge and enhances our cultural
equipment; a practical science gives us knowledge with definite guidance. Now the science of
Ethics presents data which directly imply and indicate directions for human conduct. Ethics is
therefore a practical science.
c) Ethics is a science of human conduct. By human conduct we mean only such human activity
as is deliberate and free. A deliberate and free act, an act performed with advertence and
motive, an act determined (i.e., chosen and given existence) by the free will, is called a
human act. Acts performed by human beings without advertence, or without the exercise of
free choice, are called acts of man, but they are not human acts in the technical sense of that
expression which is here employed. Ethics treats of human acts; human acts make human
conduct: Ethics is therefore a science of human conduct.
d) Ethics is the science of morality of human conduct. Human conduct is free, knowing,
deliberate human activity. Such activity is either in agreement or disagreement with the
dictates of reason. Now the relation (agreement or disagreement) of human activity with the
dictates of reason is called morality. Ethics studies human activity to determine what it must
be to stand in harmony with the dictates of reason. Hence, Ethics deals with the morality of
human conduct.
e) The name Ethics is derived from the Greek word ethos, which means “a characteristic way of
acting.” Now the characteristic mark of human conduct is found in the free and deliberate use
of the will: in a word, this characteristic is found in human acts. Thus, we perceive that the
name Ethics is suitably employed to designate the science of human acts, of human conduct. -
The Latin word mos (stem: mor-) is the equivalent of the Greek ethos. Hence, we understand
why Ethics is sometimes called Moral Science or Moral Philosophy.
2. OBJECT
Every science has a Material Object and a Formal Object.
The Material Object is the subject-matter of the science: the thing, or things, with which the
science deals. The Material Object of Ethics is human acts, that is to say, human conduct.
The Formal Object of a science is the special way, aim, or point of view that the science employs
in studying or dealing with its Material Object. Now Ethics studies human acts (its Material
Object) to discover what these must be in order to agree with the dictates of reason. Hence the
special aim and point of view in Ethics is the right morality, or rectitude, of human acts. We
assert, then that the Formal Object of Ethics is the rectitude if human acts.
3. IMPORTANCE
Ethics employs the marvelous faculty of human reason upon the supremely important question of
what an upright life is and must be. It is therefore a noble and important science.
Ethics furnishes the norm by which relations among men (juridical, political, professional, social)
are regulated. It shows what such relations must be, and indicates the reasons that require them to
be so. Thus, Ethics is fundamental to the sciences of Law, Medicine, Political Economy,
Sociology, etc. It is, in consequence of this fact, a very important science.
The principles of Ethics are in perfect harmony with the morality of Christianity, and this fact
appeals to many minds when employed as a means of approach to the demonstration of the truth
of the Catholic Religion. Hence, Ethics has a large significance for the Catholic apologist-that is
to say, for every educated Catholic.
Faulty ethical theories, as well as the lack of definite ethical principles, have been and are still the
cause of great disorders in the political and social world. This fact is apparent in such things as
Bolshevism, Nihilism, Socialism, Birth control, Eugenics, Companionate Marriage. Sound Ethics
supplies the scientific knowledge which evidences the unworthiness and unreason of such things.
Ethics is therefore a science deserving of careful study.
4. DIVISION
Ethics has two major parts, viz., General ethics and Special Ethics.
General ethics presents truths about human acts, and from these truths deduces the general
principles of morality.
Special ethics is applied Ethics. It applies the principles of General ethics in different departments
if human activity, individual and social.
The following scheme presents the plan upon which the present study of Ethics is developed:
I. GENERAL ETHICS
II. SPECIAL ETHICS
as regards God
Individual
as regards self
Ethics
as regards
fellowmen
II. SPECIAL
ETHICS
in the family
in the world
(International
Ethics)
Following the scheme, we divide the present treatise into two Parts (viz., General ethics, and
Special Ethics). Part First is divided into Chapters. Part Second is divided into two Books (which
deal respectively with Individual Ethics and Social Ethics), and the Books are divided into
Chapters. The Chapters are divided into convenient Articles.
Chapter I.
HUMAN ACTS
This chapter studies the human act itself, defines it, classifies its varieties, discerns its essential
elements, and discusses the things that may modify the human act and make it less human.
The Chapter is conveniently divided into the following Articles:
Article 1. The Human Act in Itself
Article 2. The Voluntariness of Human Acts
Article 3. The Modifiers of Human Acts
The Adequate Cause of Human Acts-While all human acts have their source in man’s
free rational nature, there are some acts that begin and are perfected in the will itself,
and the rest begin in the will and are perfected by other faculties under control of the
will. Thus, some human acts find their adequate cause in the will alone (always
remembering that we speak of the will of advertent, knowing man, i.e. of the deliberate
will): and these are called elicited acts. Other human acts do not find their adequate
cases in the simple will-act, but are perfected by the actions of mental or bodily powers
under the control of the will, or, so to speak, under orders from the will; and these acts
are called commanded acts. To illustrate: I intend to go to my room and study. My
intention Is a simple will-act, begun and completed in the will. It is therefore an
elicited act. But to carry out the intention, commanded acts, of body and mind, must be
exercised. Thus, I walk to my room, turn on the light, sit at my desk, take down a book,
turn to the lesson, bend my eyes upon the page. All these bodily acts are (if done
advertently) humans acts, commanded, so to speak, by the will of carrying out its
intention. Now I start to study: I control the imagination, keeping out distracting
fancies; I focus my mind upon the matter to be understood. These internal mental acts
are also acts commanded by the will.
Under the head of “Adequate Cause” we therefore consider:
(A) Elicited Acts
(B) Commanded Acts
(b) Intention: the purposive tendency of the will towards a thing regarded as realizable, whether
the thing is actually done or not. We find intention expressed in the following sentences: “I
am going to Europe next summer;” “The cause is in my will; I will not come: that is enough
to satisfy the Senate.” — Intention is distinguished as actual, virtual, habitual, and
interpretative intention. We shall study these degrees of intention in the Article on the
Voluntariness of Human Acts.
(c) Consent: the acceptance by the will of the means necessary to carry out intention. Consent is
a further intention of doing what is necessary to realize the first or main intention. Thus, if I
intend to go to Europe, I consent to the necessary preparation for the journey, I cannot really
intend a thing honestly unless I consent to the means of carrying it out or realizing it. If I
make an Act of Contrition, I make an intention (usually called a resolution of amendment).
Now I am not honest in my act, if I do not consent to avoid the near occasions of sin; for
these are necessarily to be avoided if the intention is to be realized. Here we see justified the
ancient saying: “He that wills (intends) a thing, wills (consents to) the means required to
accomplish it.”
(d) Election: the selection by the will of the predicted means to be employed (consented to) in
carrying on an intention. Thus, while I may go to Europe either by ship or by airplane, I
cannot go by both simultaneously, but must elect or select one of the means. By election I
choose to sail on a certain day, form a certain port, etc.
(e) Use: the employment by the will of powers (of body, mind, or both) to carry out its intention
by the means elected. Thus, if I intend to go to a neighboring town, and elect to walk thither, I
exercise the will-act of use by the putting my body in motion. True, the movement itself is a
commanded act, but the commanding, the putting to employment of bodily action is the
elicited will-act of use.
(f) Fruition: the enjoyment of a thing willed and done; the will’s act of satisfaction in intention
fulfilled.
Of the elicited acts listed, three appertain to the objective thing willed, and three to the
means of accomplishing it. Suppose the thing willed is a trip to Europe. Then:
The will cannot act in the dark, for the will is a “blind” faculty in itself. It cannot
choose unless it “see” to choose, and the light, the power to see, is afforded by
intellectual knowledge. I cannot will to go to the island of Mauritius unless I know that
there is such an island. I cannot choose to eat oranges or not to eat oranges, if I have
never seen nor heard of oranges. I cannot will to play the sacbut if I know of no such
musical instrument. I cannot will to love and serve God if I do not know God.
Knowledge, then, is an essential element of the human act.
ii. Freedom--- A human act is an act determined (elicited or commanded) by the will and by
nothing else. It is an act therefore, that is under control of the will, an act that the will can do
or leave undone. Such an act is called a free act. Thus, every human act must be free. In other
words, freedom is an essential element of human act.
iii. Voluntariness. — The Latin word for will is voluntas, and from this word we derive the
English terms, voluntary and voluntariness. To say, therefore, that a human act must be
voluntary, or must have voluntariness, is simply to say that it must be a will act. This we
already know but the very definition of the human act. Voluntariness is the formal essential
quality of the human act, and for it to be present, there must ordinarily be both knowledge
and freedom in the agent. Hence the term voluntary act is synonymous with human act. In the
next Article, we treat the voluntariness of human acts in some detail.
ii. Simple and Conditional – Simple voluntariness is present in a human act performed, whether
the agent likes or dislikes doing it. Conditional voluntariness is present in the agent’s wish to
do something other that which he is actually doing, but doing with repugnance or dislike.
Example: The commander of a distressed vessel lightens cargo by throwing valuable
merchandise overboard. He wills to do it, and does it, and the act is simply voluntary. Still, he
dislikes doing it and would not do it if there were any other way of escaping shipwreck. He
wishes to keep the goods, but the wish is inefficacious will-act, for, as a matter of fact, he does
not keep the goods, but throws them away. In this inefficacious will-act, there is conditional
voluntariness. Inasmuch as the inefficacious will-act influences the efficacious act, the latter is
said to be involuntary. Hence the act of throwing away valuable goods is simply voluntary and
conditionally voluntary
iii. Direct and indirect- Direct voluntariness is present in a human act willed in itself. Indirect
voluntariness is present in that human act which is the foreseen result (or a result that could
and should have been foreseen) of another act directly willed. Example: a man kills a rabbit
for dinner. He directly wills the act of killing as a means to an end to be achieved, viz, the
dinner. He also directly will that the dinner as the end to be achieved by this means. We have
direct voluntariness in each aspect of the act. Now suppose that rabbit was a tame animal that
had played about the man’s grounds and had given its children pleasure. The man knows that
by killing the rabbit he will deprive his children of pleasure and cause them sorrow. This,
indeed, he does not directly will, but inasmuch as this is the foreseen consequences of his
directly willed act, he wills it indirectly or in its cause. In other words, he directly wills the
cause of his children’s sorrow, and thus wills the sorrow itself. A human act that is directly
willed is called voluntary in se (i.e., in itself), while a human is called a voluntary in causa
(i.e., in its cause).
Indirect voluntaries is a subject of the first importance, and we shall study it in detail in
the second section of this present Article.
iv. Positive and Negative – Positive voluntariness is present in a human act of doing, performing.
Negative voluntariness is present in a human act of omitting, refraining from doing. Examples:
a Catholic goes to Mass on Sunday (positive voluntariness). A Catholic deliberately misses
Mass on Sunday (negative voluntariness). — Of course, when a person omits an act, he must
really be doing something positive. But the special positive thing that he does is not the
essence of the omission as such. Thus, the man who remains away from Mass, he must really
be doing something—lying abed, reading the morning paper, walking about, playing a game,
eating his breakfast, or doing any one of an indefinite number of possible things. But the point
is that special and particular positive act, or series of acts enters into the essence of the
omission, for this consists simply in willing not to do an act.
v. Actual, Virtual, Habitual, and Interpretative. —
Actual voluntariness (or actual intention) is present in human act willed here and now.
Virtual voluntariness (or virtual intention) is present in a human act done as a result of (or
in virtue of) a formerly elicited actual intention, even if that intention be here and now
forgotten. Habitual voluntariness (or habitual intention) is present in a human act done in
harmony with, but not as a result of, a formerly elicited and unprovoked actual intention.
Interpretative voluntariness (or interpretative intuition) is that voluntariness which, in the
judgment of prudence and common-sense, would be actually present if opportunity or
ability for it were given. Examples:
(a) A man makes the morning offering. He actually, here and now, intends to live for God,
and to serve Him in all the thoughts, words, and deeds of the day. The act of offering is
an actual intention; it is a will-act in which there is actual voluntariness.
(b) A man makes the morning offering, but during the day he completely forgets it.
Nevertheless, his day is without sin which would contradict his pious intention, and we
say that the power or virtue of the intention endures, and that, as a result of the intention,
all the thoughts, words, and deeds of the day are really done for God. The man takes
breakfast, goes to work, attends to business duties, spends time in recreation, etc. In all
these acts he has no actual (“here and now”) intention of doing them for God, but he has
the virtual intention of doing them. Hence all the acts that the man performs throughout
the day—even those that are in themselves acts of man—are human acts of service by
reason of their virtual voluntariness
(c) A man makes the actual intention of becoming a Catholic. Years pass, and he does not
carry out the intention; neither does he revoke it. He is taken suddenly ill, and lies
unconscious at death’s door. A priest administers Baptism. Here the act of receiving the
sacrament is in agreement with the actual intention once made and unprovoked, and the
man is said to have a habitual intention for the act. The act, however, is not the result of
the original actual intention, for the virtue or power of that intention cannot reasonably
be presumed to endure throughout a long period of neglect and unfulfillment. For, if one
makes an invention of doing a thing, and fails to do it throughout years of continuous
opportunity for its accomplishment, it is obvious that the virtue or power of the original
intention is null. Still, as long as the original intention is not revoked, it remains with its
author, and is worn, so to speak, like a forgotten portion of his dress or habit, powerless
actively to produce a result, but remaining as the mark or symbol of an attitude of mind.
It is a mark of habitual voluntariness
B. Indirect Voluntariness
Indirect voluntariness, or voluntariness in cause, is present in that human act
which is an effect, foreseen or foreseeable, of another act directly willed.
We have not yet made a detailed study of the moral character of human acts nor of
their consequent imputability. But we have seen that human acts are acts under the free
control of the will. It is clear that, since the will controls such acts, the will is
responsible for them. In other words, human acts are imputable (as worthy of praise or
blame, reward or punishment) to their author.
Now the moment we bring together the matters of indirect voluntariness and
imputability, two supremely important ethical questions present themselves. The
questions are:
I. When is the agent (doer, actor, performer) responsible for the evil effect of a cause
directly willed?
II. When my one performs an act, not evil in itself, which has two effects, one good, one evil?
i. The First Question: When is an agent responsible for the evil effect of a cause directly
willed? -The agent is responsible for such an effect where three conditions are fulfilled, viz.: (1)
The agent must be able to foresee the evil effect, at least in a general way. (2) The agent must be
free to refrain from doing that which is the cause of the evil effect. (3) The agent must be morally
bound not to do that which is the cause of the evil effect.
This is an ethical principle of great moment. Let the student apply it in the
following cases:
(a) Michael knows that if he drinks liquor, he will drink to excess, and will use blasphemous
language, which will scandalize those that hear it. He declares, and truly enough, that he hates
intemperance, and that he dreads the evils of blasphemy and scandal. Nevertheless, he drinks
liquor, and the foreseen evil occurs. How far is Michael responsible for these evil effects? When
does he incur their guilt?
(b) If John says, “If I go to the meeting and hear Jones sharp things about our party, I know
I’ll lose my head and reveal some very damaging facts about Jones’ career that I alone know.”
John goes to the meeting; the evil of detraction follows. Determine John’s responsibility, and the
moment at which his guilt is imputed to him.
(c) Mary knows that by persistent company-keeping with a non-Catholic she will encourage
the weak-willed Jane to a similar course and to the consequent danger of an invalid marriage; for
Jane idolizes Mary and imitates her in every way. Mary believes, foolishly but sincerely, that she
herself is in no danger, but she is keenly aware of the danger in which Jane is placed through her
example. Nevertheless, she persists. Jane imitates, and eventually commits the sin of an
attempted marriage outside the Church. How far is Mary to blame? Why?
(d) Thomas has been repeatedly warned by prudent persons against attendance at a secular
university, and he has been shown that he will there encounter grave dangers to his faith. He
declares, in foolish pride, that nothing can shake his faith. He attends university, gradually loses
his fervor, and becomes but a nominal Catholic. At what time does his lapse become imputable
to him? Why?
(e) Timothy goes to bed on Saturday night, forgetting to set the alarm. Before falling asleep
he recalls the omission, bit he does not rise to adjust the clock. He knows that he is a heavy
sleeper, and that he will not probably awake in time for Mass on Sunday. This is precisely what
happens. When does Timothy incur the guilt of missing Mass? Why?
(f) The same Timothy deliberately neglects the clock on another Saturday night. But
contrary to al his experiences, he awakes in time for Mass on Sunday morning, and he attends
very devoutly. Does Timothy have any fault in the matter? Why?
(g) Again, timothy deliberately neglects the clock on Saturday night. Again, b an almost
miraculous repetition of the unexpected, he awakes in time or Mass on Sunday. But he reasons,
since he as already missed Mass in cause, there is now no obligation to incumbent upon him of
attending. He stays at home and does not hear Mass.— Here timothy was altogether wrong. He
willed an evil in cause and his will-act stopped there. Through no merit of his own, the cause
failed to function as a cause, and he awoke in time for mass. Now by a new and direct will-act he
wills to miss Mass. Here is a new evil, directly willed.
In the foregoing cases we see that the agent is bound to avoid the cause of the evil effect,
and his obligation arises from the very fact that the effect is evil. Why then, did we list
three condition for the imputability of evil willed in cause? Why not simply say that the
two conditions are requisite for such imputability, viz., that the agent he able to foresee
the evil effect, and that he be free to avoid the cause? is not the fact that the evil effect is
evil always a prohibition obliging the agent to refrain from the cause of evil? Not
always. Sometimes there is a good effect as well as an evil effect proceeding from a
single cause. this brings us to the Second Question.
ii. The Second Question: When may one perform an act, not evil in itself, from which flow two
effects, one good, one evil? — One may perform such an act when three conditions are fulfilled, viz., (1)
The evil effect must not precede the good effect. (2) There must be a reason sufficiently grave calling the
for the act in its good effect. (3) The intention of the agent must be honest, that is the agent must directly
intend the good effect and merely permit the evil effect as a regrettable incident or “side issue.” To
explain these conditions in detail:
The evil effect must not precede the good effect. If the evil effect comes ahead of the
good effect, then it is a means of achieving the good effect, and is directly willed as
such a means. Not it is a fundamental principle of Ethics— a clear dictate of sound
reason— that evil may never be willed directly, whether it be a means or an end to be
achieved. The end does not justify the means. There is no good, however great, that can
justify the direct willing of evil, however slight. If a lie- even a “harmless” lie – will
save a life- even in innocent life- that lie may not be told. Notice will that the principle
here discussed requires that the evil effect do not precede the good effect; we do not
say that the good effect must precede the evil, but that the good effect must either
precede the evil or occur simultaneously with it.
There must be a reason sufficiently grave calling for the act in its good effect. If this
condition be not fulfilled, there is no adequate reason for the act at all, and that act is
prohibited in view of its evil effect. The sufficiency of the season must be determined
by the nature, circumstances, and importance of the act in question. and by the
proportion this reason bears to the gravity of the evil effect.
The intention of the agent must be honest. If the agent really will the evil effect, there is no
possibility of the act being permissible. Direct willing of evil, as we have seen, is always
against reason, and hence against the principles of Ethics. Bit unless the agent directly wills
the good effect, he is really willing the evil effect—else he has no adequate motive for
performing the act at all. Let the student consider the following cases in the light of the
principle just explained:
(a) The general of an army storms an enemy city. He foresees that many non-combatants will be
killed. Yet to take the city will be a big step towards winning a just war. Is the general’s act
allowable? Notice the two effects here: that taking of the city as a step towards ending the war
with victory for the just cause -a good effect; and the killing of non-combatants an evil effect.
(b) The general of an army knows that by laying waste the farms of the enemy's
country, he will seriously inconvenience the enemy by cutting off the source of
supplies. At the present time the enemy is well supplied, but destruction of the crops
will destroy future supplies. Such destruction will mean present starvation to many
a farmer and his family, but ul- timely it with help win a just war. May the general
lay waste the farm-lands?
(c) In view of your answer to the foregoing question, would you justify or condemn
the havoc wrought by Sherman in his march to the sea
(d) A doctor can save a mother's life by destroying that of her child. May he do SO?
Why not?
(e) A child's life can be saved by destroying the ice of the mother. May this be
done? Why not
(f) A patient is dying in awful agony. Medical life there is none. Life cannot last
beyond a few hours at most. May a drug be administered to bring death quietly and
quickly? Why not?
(g) A student of very frail health sed a lucrative position upon graduation. He needs
the situation to support his aged and impoverished parents. He knows he must study
hard, else he will fail in his examinations, lose his degree, and, in consequence, will
not secure the promised position. Still, he is aware that earnest study may seriously
impair his health. May he study hard and run the risk of permanent infirmity?
a) IGNORANCE
Ignorance is the absence of knowledge and for our purpose here, it may be defined as
the absence of intellectual knowledge in man. Ignorance is thus a negation of
knowledge; it is a negative thing. But when it is absence of knowledge that ought to
be present, the ignorance I snot merely negative, but privative. Thus, ignorance of the
higher mathematics in a structural-steel worker is merely negative; but such ignorance
is privative in the architect or engineer who designs steel structures such as bridges
and the frame work of buildings. Again, ignorance of Catholic belief and practice is
negative in a Hottentot, but privative in a Catholic collegian. Ignorance has, indeed, a
positive aspect when it consists not merely in the absence of knowledge, but in the
presence of what is falsely supposed to be knowledge. Thus, if I see a stranger in the
street, and realize that I do not know him, my ignorance of his identity is merely
negative. But if I misled by my poor eyesight or by a resemblance in the stranger,
and judge him to be a well-known acquaintance, my state of mind is positive
knowledge him: I have what I judge to be positive knowledge of his identity.
Such positive ignorance is called mistake or error. We are to consider ignorance in its
effect upon human acts. Before stating the ethical principles which our study will
justify, we shall make a preliminary study of ignorance itself, considering it in three
ways, vir., i. in its object, i.e., in the thing of which a person may be ignorant; ii. in its
subject, i. e., in the person in whom ignorance exists; iii. in its result, i. e., with
reference to the acts that are performed in ignorance.
i. Ignorance in its Object. —The thing of which a person may be ignorant is a matter of
law, fact, or penalty.
(a) Ignorance of Law is the ignorance of the existence of a duty, rule, or regulation.
Examples: A motorist drives at the rate of forty miles an hour, not knowing that the local
speed-limit is twenty miles an hour. A hunter shoots game in early October, unaware that the
game-laws forbid such an act. A young Freshman leaves the campus during noon-recess, not
knowing that his action is a violation of the college rules.
(b) Ignorance of Fact is ignorance of the nature or circumstances of an act as forbidden.
Examples: A motorist knows the speed-limit, but unknowingly violates it because of an
inaccurate speedometer. A hunter knows the game-laws, but reads his calendar amiss, and kills
game one day before the season opens. A freshman knows the he must not leave the campus,
but goes out of bound through misinformation about the extent of the college property. Thus,
ignorance of fact is lack of knowledge that what one is actually doing comes under the
prohibition of a known law.
(c) Ignorance of Penalty is lack of knowledge of the precise sanction (i. e., an
inducement sufficient to make reasonable men obey the law) affixed to the law. Examples: A
motorist knowingly violates the speed-law, not knowing that, in that particular locality, the set
punishment for such an offense is a short prison term, in lieu of which no amount of money
will be accepted. A hunter violates that game- laws, believing that if apprehended, he will be
merely fined, whereas the established penalty for his offense is the revocation of the license to
hunt. A freshman willfully leaves the campus, thinking that he will escape with an admonition
not to do so again, whereas the fixed penalty for his offense is the suspension of all student-
privileges for a period two weeks.
ii. Ignorance in its Subject. —In the person in whom it exists, ignorance (of law, fact, or
penalty) is either
vincible or invincible
(a) Vincible Ignorance (i. e., conquerable ignorance; ignorance that can and should be
supplanted by knowledge) is ignorance that can be dispelled by the use of ordinary
diligence. Such ignorance is therefore, due to lack of proper diligence on the part of the
ignorant person, and is his fault. Vincible ignorance is, in consequence, culpable ignorance.
There are degrees of vincible ignorance: If it be the result of total, or nearly total, lack of
effort to dispel it, it is called crass (or supine) ignorance. If some effort worthies the name,
but not persevering and whole hearted effort, be unsuccessfully employed to dispel it, the
ignorance is simple vincible. If positive effort is made to retain it, the ignorance is called
affected. To illustrate: A freshman who has been in college a month and does not know the
college rules to order, is in the state of vincible ignorance in the matter. If he has made no
effort, or scarcely any, to know the rules, his ignorance is crass or supine. If he has
positively avoided learning the rules so that he may have a ready excuse for faults, and may
be able to say when taken in violation of order, “I did not know the rule,” his ignorance is
affected. If he has made some inquiries about the rules, or has tried once or twice, without
success, to procure a copy of the rule-book, his ignorance is simple vincible.
(b) Invincible ignorance is ignorance that ordinary and proper diligence cannot dispel.
This sort of ignorance is attributable to one of two causes, viz.: either the person in whom the
ignorance exists has no realization whatever of his lack of knowledge, of the person who
realizes his ignorance finds ineffective his effort to dispel it. Hence, invincible ignorance is
never the fault of the person in whom it exists, and it is rightly called inculpable ignorance.
Invincible ignorance has two degrees, viz.: If no human effort can dispel it, it is physically
invincible. If such effort as good and prudent men would expend to dispel it— taking into
account the character and importance of the matter about which ignorance exists— is found to
be ineffective, the ignorance is called morally invincible. To illustrate: A Catholic gets meat,
wholly unaware that the day is Friday. Here is his ignorance is invincible—even though in
itself it could be easily dispelled by asking the nearest person for the day of the week—and
even physically invincible, because no effort can be used with effect where there is no
realization whatever that effort is needed. A further illustration: A man is seeking for a
seventeenth century pamphlet to which he finds himself constantly referred in learned books
on the subject of economics. After months and months of searching through libraries and
following elusive clues, the man discovers that there is only one copy of the pamphlet in
existence ; that this copy is in the library of a recluse who resides in a foreign country, far
across the sea ; and that, although one may be permitted to read it, the pamphlet may neither be
borrowed nor copied. The man is in the state of invincible ignorance with regard to the
contents of the pamphlet. His ignorance is not physical invincible, for he could make a voyage
to the land of the recluse, and study the pamphlet in the later’s library. Still, this course would
involve difficulties and inconveniences out of all proportion of the
1
1 The word morally has no direct relation in the present use of morality, but to characteristic action of
men. Thus, ignorance is morally invincible when such effort as would be truly characteristic of good
and prudent men in the circumstances, is found powerless to dispel it. In common language, ignorance
is morally invincible when it would be extremely difficult to dispel it.
importance of the matter about which ignorance exists. We say, therefore, that the
man's ignorance of the contents of the pamphlet is morally invincible.
iii. Ignorance in its Result. Here we consider ignorance (of fact, law, or penalty)
with reference to acts performed while ignorance exists.
(a) Antecedent Ignorance is that which precedes all consent of the will. A man,
wholly unaware that to-day is a holyday of obligation, misses Mass. He would
certainly not miss Mass if he were conscious of his obligation. His ignorance is
antecedent to his act of missing Mass, and we say that the act is done through or in
consequence of ignorance. Antecedent ignorance does not differ from invincible
ignorance.
(b) Concomitant Ignorance is that ignorance which, so to speak, accompanies an act
that would have been performed even if the ignorance did not exist. A nominal
Catholic misses Mass, not aware that the day is a holyday. Yet, even had he known, he
would have missed Mass. His act of missing Mass does not come from ignorance, but
happens in company with his ignorance, and we call the ignorance concomitant. An act
done in concomitant ignorance is non-voluntary.
(c) Consequent ignorance is that which follows upon an act of the will. The will
may directly affect it, or supinely neglect to dispel it. Thus, consequent ignorance does
not differ from vincible ignorance. A careless Catholic suspects that the day is a
holyday but deliberately refrains from making sure, and does not attend Mass. If he
positively avoids knowledge in the matter, his (affected) ignorance is directly willed; if
he fails to acquire knowledge through sheer carelessness, his (crass or supine)
ignorance is indirectly willed. We may sum up the classification of ignorance in the
1
following scheme:
of law
of penalty
simply vincible
vincible crass or supine
affected
morally
invincible
physically
antecedent
in its results concomitant
directly willed
consequent
indirectly willed
The ethical principles which emerge from our study of ignorance as a modifier of
human acts are the following:
SECOND PRINCIPLE: Vincible ignorance does not destroy the voluntariness of an act.
Vincible ignorance is not an inevitable lack of knowledge. On the contrary, it supposed
knowledge in the agent of his own lack of knowledge and of his duty of dispelling ignorance.
Hence, the agent has knowledge which bears indirectly upon the act which he performs in
ignorance, and the act has, in consequence, at least indirect voluntariness, and is a human act
imputable to the agent.—To illustrate: A careless Catholic suspects that the day is Friday, but
fails, through sheer negligence, to make certain : and he eats meat. Now, while the agent does
lack knowledge that the day is Friday, he has knowledge of his own ignorant state of mind and
of his obligation to acquire knowledge. Failing to make proper effort
to dispel his ignorance, he will to keep his ignorance. But his ignorance is, in some sense, the
cause of his violation of the law of abstinence. Hence, he will this violation in cause. His act
has indirect voluntariness, and is a human act for which he is responsible
FOURTH PRINCIPLE: Affected ignorance in one way lessens and, in another way,
increases voluntariness.
Affected ignorance is that vincible ignorance which is directly willed and positively
fostered. Yet, in spite of the bad will which it implies, it is still a lack of knowledge,
direct and perfect, and, in so far, it lessens the voluntariness of the act that proceeds
from it. On the other hand, affected ignorance, being deliberately fostered to serve as
an excuse for sin against a law, shows the strength of the will’s determination to persist
in such sins. It is thus said to increase the voluntariness of an act, or, more accurately,
to indicate an increased voluntariness in the act that comes from it.
b.) CONCUPISCENCE
The term concupiscence is often used to signify the frailty, or proneness to evil, which
is consequent in human nature upon original sin. Ethics does not employ the term in
this sense. Here concupiscence means those bodily appetites or tendencies which are
called the passions, and which are enumerated as follows: love, hatred; joy, grief;
desire, aversion or horror; hope, despair; courage or daring, fear; and anger. We treat
here of the passions in general. In the next section of the present Article we shall study
in particular the passion of fear.
The passions are called antecedent when they spring into action unstimulated
by any act of the will; that is, when they arise antecedently to the will- act. They are
called consequent when they will, directly or indirectly, stirs them up or fosters them.
To illustrate; the feeling of joy that arises upon the suddenly revealed view of a
splendid landscape; the anger that surges in resentment of unjust and offensive
treatment; the first feeling of the attractiveness of a suddenly presented fancy or
thought, good or evil; the leaping desire for revenge for an unexpected act of cruelty;
the first feeling of hatred that comes with the thought or sight of a bitter enemy; the
shrinking in aversion from an unpleasant task; the urge to “give up” in despair in the
face of crowding difficulties- all these are examples of antecedent concupiscence or
passion. These movements or bodily appetites become consequent when they receive
the approval of the rational will. Thus, the passion or anger that arises antecedently
when one is liberately retained. Thus, the first movement of pleasure (love, joy) in an
unwholesome thought or fancy, becomes consequent when the will consents to retain
that thought or fancy.
Antecedent concupiscence is an act of man, and not a human act. It is therefore
a non- voluntarily act, and the agent is not responsible for it. Consequent
concupiscence, however, is the fault of the agent, for it is willed, either directly or
indirectly, that is either in itself or in cause. The agent is, in consequence, responsible
for it.
But what of the acts that come from concupiscence?
We state the ethical principles in the matter:
d.) VIOLENCE
Violence or coaction is external force applied by a free cause (i. e., by a cause with
free will; by man) for the purpose of compelling a person to perform an act which is
against his will. Thus, the martyrs suffered violence when they were dragged to the
altars of idols in the effort to make them offer sacrifice to false gods.
Violence cannot reach the will directly. It may force bodily action, but the will is not
controlled by the body. Still, the will has the command of bodily action, and since this
command is limited or destroyed for the moment by violence, the will is said to be
indirectly affected by violence. Hence, if the will does not exert its command to make
the bodily members offer due resistance to violence, it concurs, in so far as such
resistance is lacking, in the act done under violence.
PRINCIPLE: Acts elicited by the will are not subject to violence; external acts caused
by violence, to which due resistance is offered, are in no wise imputable to the agent.
e.) HABIT
By habit Ethics understands operative habit, which is a lasting readiness and facility,
born of frequently repeated acts, for acting in a certain manner. Thus, a man who has
always endeavored to speak the truth, has a habit of truthfulness, and it goes against his
habit- “against the grain” -to lie. Such a man finds it necessary to make a distinct effort
in order to utter a deliberate falsehood. Again, a man who has the habit of lying, finds
it very easy to falsify or evade the truth, and it is difficult for him to tell the truth when
a lie would prove convenient. Again, a man who has the habit of cursing finds profane
words slipping from him with great ease and readiness, while it requires a special
watchfulness on his part to avoid uttering them.
PRINCIPLE: Habit does not destroy voluntariness; and acts from habit are always
voluntary, at least in cause, as long as the habit is allowed to endure.
Habit does not destroy voluntariness. The agent is fully responsible for human acts
done from what is called force of habit. Even if such acts be in themselves acts of man,
the habit itself, so long as it is not disowned, and a positive and enduring effort made to
overcome it, is willed as a human act, and its effects are voluntary in cause, and hence
are human acts. To illustrate: John has the bad habit of using profane language. He is
conscious of this fault. Being conscious of it, he has knowledge of it; and he is free to
determine upon overcoming it, or to allow it to endure. Hence, both knowledge and
freedom are present, and there is nothing to balk Voluntariness. John is therefore
responsible for the bad habit as such, and, since it is the cause of the profane words---
many of which are uttered without advertence---he is responsible in cause or indirectly
for each profane utterance. Now, if John determines to overcome his evil habit, he
disowns it; he wills not to utter profane speech: But “He that wills the end wills the
means to that end.” Hence, John, to be honest in his will to reform, must consent to
ceaseless watchfulness over his tongue. While his good intention endures, and while
his watchfulness continues, the profane utterances that “slip out” are acts of man and
not human acts, since their cause is no longer willed; and hence they are not imputable
to John. But the moment John ceases to be watchful, that moment he consents
indirectly to let the habit continue, and his evil words become again imputable even if
they slip from him unnoticed.
A human act is always performed for an end. This Chapter discusses ends in
general, and the ultimate and of human acts in particular. The Chapter is accordingly
divided in the following Articles:
A. Definition B. Classification
b) DEFINITION OF END
An end is both a termination and a goal. In other words, an end is that which
complete or finishes a thing, and it is that for which the thing is finished. A sculptor has
reached the end of his work on a statue when the last bit of marble has been chipped
away; and he has reached the end in another sense, inasmuch as the finished statue is
the goal he set out to attain when he started the work. By an end we mean the end of an
activity. We do not speak of end in the sense of boundary, or edge, or rim, or side of a
bodily object, but as the termination and goal of activity. In the example given, the work of
the sculptor, the activity of making the statue (both in itself, and as coming from interior
plan and purpose) is the activity considered.
Every activity tends toward an end. A tree tends to grow to full stature, maturity, and
fruitfulness: and this is the end of its activity of growth. A hungry dog seizing a bit of beef
evinces an activity of instinct for the meat as a good thing to have, as an end to be
achieved. Even lifeless things have activities proper to their nature, and these tend
toward ends by reason of what we call lows. Thus, fire tends to burn, bodies tend to fall
toward the center of the earth, bodies at rest tend to remain at rest, bodies in motion
tend to remain in motion of the same direction and velocity.
Every activity tends toward and end; and thus every activity is a tendency. Now, every
tendency may be called an appetite, or more properly, appetency. When appetency exists
without any sort of knowledge—as in plants and lifeless things—it is called natural
appetency, in a special limited, and technical sense of the term “natural”. When
appetency comes of knowledge, it is two kinds, just as knowledge itself is of two kinds.
Appetency which is stirred into action by sensation (i.e., by knowledge acquired by the
senses) is called sense-appetency or sensual appetite. We have an example of such
appetency in the hungry dog seizing meat. Appetency which is stirred into action by
intellectual knowledge is called the will or rational appetency. We have an example of such
appetency in the at of the sculptor described above. The sculptor knows the statue to
be desirable (for one or many reasons: it may bring fame, or money; it may express
devotion to art; it may express love of the personage represented, and so on), and he
wills to make it. We have already learned in our study of Human Acts that the will
springs into action when only intellectual knowledge presents something desirable,
satisfactory, or simply good, to be achieved by, action. Every will-act, that is, every
human act, is the expression of rational appetency or will: it is an act directed to an end
known as desirable, that is to say, as good to attain.
In Ethics we speak of the ends of human acts. Here, then, the end is that which is
apprehended as good, as desirable, and which attracts the human agent to the
performance of the act. It is the agent’s motive and reason for acting. It causes the agent
to act, and in so far, the end is the final cause of a human act-a cause called final, from
the Latin word finis, which means end. The agent is the efficient cause of his acts, for it is
he that effects or performs them; but he would not affect them were he not attracted by
the end or final cause. No human act can exist, therefore, without a final cause, that is
to say, without an end apprehended by the agent as desirable or good enough to attract
the agent to action and to serve as his motive in the act.
The end or final cause of human acts must be apprehended as good. Evil cannot be
willed as much or for its own sake. Evil is done only when it assumes the aspect of
good, as something that will bring satisfaction or will lead to it. his does not mean that a
sinner thinks he is acting virtuously when he commits a sin. On the contrary, he knows
that the sin is morally evil and that he is responsible for it. But the point is that the sin to
which he consents is apprehended as something that will bring present satisfaction, or
will lead to it, and this is judged by the agent as a greater good than that which is
required by the moral law which forbids the sin. Notice that it is as a greater good that
the sin is chosen. Of course, the agent’s judgement in the matter is not sound: his sin
will not lead to ultimate happiness or satisfaction, but inasmuch as it is a judgement of
the sin as good, it explains what is meant by the statement that evil is not chosen as
such, nor for its own sake, but only when it assumes the aspect of good. In our sense,
good is that which answers tendency or desire
To define end: An end is termination and goal of activity. In a human act the end is
final cause, viz., that on account of which, or to attain which, the act is performed, and
which is, in consequence, apprehended as a good sufficiently desirable to motivate the
agent in performing the act.
b) CLASSIFICATION OF ENDS
Here we distinguished:
i. The end of the act, and the end of
i. The end of the act is the end toward which the act of its own nature tends. Thus,
the act of giving food and shelter to destitute persons tends of its nature toward the
relief of distress, and we say that the relief of distress is the end of the act. The end of
the agent is the end which the agent intends to achieve by his act. Thus, the act of
giving food and shelter to destitute persons may be performed by the agent to increase
his merit before God, or as an act of impetration to obtain a grace or favor, or as an act
of penance for sins committed. Again the agent may perform the act in order to have it
noticed by others, so that he may gain the reputation of a beneficent person. Again the
act may be performed by an agent who merely wishes to relieve distress. In the last
case, the end of the agent coincides with the end of the act. In the other cases, the end
of the agent is different from the end of the act. When we speak of the end in Ethics, we
usually mean the end of the agent.
ii. The proximate end is the end intended as the immediate outcome of an act. The
remote end is that which the agent wishes to achieve later on, and toward the attainment
of which he employs the present act as a means. Thus a politician who gives money to
the poor, wishes his good deed to be recorded in the newspapers: his proximate end is
favorable publicity. However, he does not desire publicity for its own sake, but for the
votes it will gain him in the coming elections; and he wishes for votes as a means to
office. Thus, while publicity is his proximate end, votes and election to office are remote
ends.
iii. An end, whether proximate or remote, is willed either for its own sake or as a
means to an end more remote. If it is willed for its own sake, it is a last or ultimate end,
and if it is willed as a means to a further end, it is an intermediate end. To illustrate: a
man gives money to the poor. He gives the money to gain favorable notice in the
newspapers (proximate and intermediate end) ; he wills publicity as a means to votes
(remote and intermediate end) ; he wills election for the prominence, power, and wealth
which the office will give him (remote and ultimate end). This example shows us a chain
or series of ends; and, since the ultimate end of the series is not the general or
unconditioned end of the man’s whole life and all its human acts, but ultimate only in
relation to the present series of ends, the ultimate end of the series is called an end
relatively ultimate. Now, there must also be an end which is unconditionally and
unlimitedly the ultimate end of all human acts; and this we call the absolutely ultimate end.
We shall discuss this end in the next Article. We notice here that it is the ultimate end
which gives meaning to the intermediate ends that lead to it. The intermediate end are
subordinated to the ultimate end, just as the steps of a stairway are subordinated to the
top step. And as a man who wishes to reach the top of a stairway must take many
intermediate steps before reaching the top, but would not take any of them except to
reach the top, so in a series of ends, the agent must attain intermediate ends before
achieving the ultimate end, but he would not try to attain any of them except on account
of the ultimate end. Thus, we repeat, the ultimate end of a series of ends gives meaning
and motive to the whole series.
An ultimate end is both objective and subjective. The objective ultimate end is that thing,
that object which, in last analysis, motivates a human act. The subjective last end is the
possession of the objective end and the satisfaction or happiness that is apprehended as
belonging to that possession. Thus, the politician's last end (in the series of ends which
we studied above) is a political office with its power, prominence, and good wages. This
is the objective ultimate end. The subjective ultimate end which the agent seeks to
achieve is the possession of the office and what it will bring. In other words, the object
sought is office; and the subjective desire of the agent (the acting subject) is satisfaction
in the possession of the office.
The Ultimate end of human acts is that which in the last analysis, serves as a
sufficient reason and motive for the acts. This end, considered as an objective thing
toward the attainment of which the acts are directed, is the objective ultimate end of
human acts. The possession of this objective end and the happiness which the agent
seeks in that possession, is the subjective ultimate end of human acts.
We have seen that a human act is always done on account of an end, and an
ultimate end. We now assert that all human acts are performed for a single absolutely
ultimate end.
a) THE OBJECTIVE ULTIMATE END OF HUMAN ACTS
A human act is deliberate and knowing act; it is an act performed by the knowing
agent who wills to perform it. And why does he will to perform it? Because he has a
motive, a reason, a final cause sufficiently attractive to induce him to perform it. And this
reason, motive, or final cause amounts to this: it appears good to the agent to perform
the act and attain its end. Even when the human act is difficult or undesirable in itself, it
becomes desirable in view of a further end to which it is directed as a means. Thus, a
man freely consenting to a serious operation, wills the operation, and his will-act is a
human act. But the operation is not willed for itself, but in view of relief form affliction or
in the hope of prolonging life, and in this aspect it is desirable and good, no matter how
dangerous and fearsome it may be in itself. Now, it may be that the man who submits to
the dangerous operation is a poor man; it may be that the prospect of prolonged life
which the operation affords is also the prospect of a hard and even destitute life; it may
be that the life to which the patient looks forward is a life inevitably filled with woes and
miseries. And yet he wants it, he wills it as an end. Why? Because he apprehends life
with all its hardships as a greater good than the loss of life. Again, the suicide (supposing
him same when he performs his horrible act) destroys life by a human act. He does so
because he apprehends the cessation of life as greater good than the continuance of
life with its miseries. Thus it clearly appears that human acts are always done for an end
apprehended as good, and as the greater good when there is question of sacrificing one
thing in view of another.
More: the driving power back of human acts viewed all together-or, more
accurately, the power of attraction that calls human acts into being- in not only the good,
or the greater good, but the greatest good, the absolutely illimitable, all inclusive, and all
perfect good. , This is the summum bonum, which, considered in itself, we call the
absolutely ultimate objective end of human acts. It will not be difficult to prove this
assertion.
Man seeks happiness. Whether he seeks it in riches, in pleasure, in power, in
prominence, in honors attained, or even in license and sin, the fact remains that what he
is seeking is that which will pleasure him, that which will satisfy his wants and desires,
that, in one word, which will make him happy. This quest of happiness is a tendency of
man’s very nature of which he finds it utterly impossible to free himself. Man is free in
his choice of objects in which he hopes to find happiness, and we call this the freedom
of the will, or the freedom of choice; but man is not free to seek unhappiness for its own
sake. Even the “cantankerous” individual who does mean things in a mean way, and
hurts himself in doing them, and, so to speak, cuts off his nose to spite his face, is
nevertheless doing what he wants to do, and in the achievement of that want he
apprehends some satisfaction; otherwise, there could be no conceivable motive for the
acts, and motive there must be, for the acts exist.
Now, there is an object towards which the whole tendency of human action is
ever directed; an object that will satisfy all tendency, fill up all capacity for desire, leave
nothing further that can be the end of human acts. And this we call the absolutely
ultimate objective end of human acts. We may define this end as that object, the
possession of which will give perfect happiness to man by completely filling up his capacity for
desire, and leaving nothing unpossessed toward which man could, by any possibility, continue to
tend as towards an end.
This absolutely ultimate objective end must be on, must be a single object. For
consider: this end is so perfect a good that nothing beyond it can be desired. Therefore,
it must be the infinite good. Nothing finite could meet the requirements of such an end.
The greatest happiness thinkable, shot of the possession of the infinite good, is
imperfect and fleeting. The largest fortune might still be larger; the serenest peace of life
must quickly give place to care or be lost in death; the highest honors man may achieve
leave other honors still unwon. And over all human achievements, over the bliss of
abounding health and the rapture of the presence of loved ones, over fame attained and
glory worthily won, over ambition fulfilled and high hope realized-over all that is finite
hangs a cloud, a menace, a threat that is certainly to be fulfilled: all must pass-and soon!
Hence all finite good is imperfect, if only that it will not last always. But it is imperfect, if
only that it will not last always. But it is imperfect also in scope, in extent. A finite thing
is, by its very definition, a thing with limits. Can any limited thing satisfy in fullest
measure of perfection the unlimited desires of man? No, for these pass all bounds;
there is no lime that can be drawn to mark the limit of the possibility of desire. Only the
infinite good can be the absolutely ultimate objective end of human acts. And there can
be but one infinite object. For an infinite object contains all possible perfection, and there
is, so to speak, no perfection left over for another object to possess. Hence we rightly
maintain that the absolutely ultimate objective end of human acts is one.
Now the infinite good is God. Ethics must leave to the philosophical science of
Theodicy (i.e., Natural Theology) the proof of the existence of the one God, infinitely
perfect, creator, conserver, and ruler of the universe, the efficient and final cause of all.
Ethics assumes the existence and attributes of God as proved. We assert that the
infinite good is God; that God is the only object, the possession of which will give perfect
happiness to many by completely filling up his capacity for desire, and leaving nothing
unpossessed toward which man could, by any possibility, continue to send as towards
and end. Hence we see that St. Augustine enunciated a solid philosophical truth, and
not a mere pious sentiment, when he wrote: “O God, Thou hast made us for Thyself,
and our heart is not at rest until it rests in Thee.”
But, you object, there is such a thing as sin, and such a thing as sinful desire.
Does the sinner tend in his human act of sin toward God? Is sinful desire to find the
perfect fulfillment in the possession of the All-Perfect? Of course, the sinner does not
tend towards God, nor if sinful desire as such satisfied with possession of the All-Perfect
—to say so would be foulest blasphemy. Yet the sinner, in his human act of sin, does
not exhibit a tendency away from what is apprehended as good; on the contrary, the very
sin is a tendency toward that which is, through perversion of reason, adjudged as good,
as satisfying. The sinner knows that his act is evil; but passion invites, immediate
satisfaction is promised, the fleeting pleasure of his act is ready at hand; the true good
is not perceived as ready, prompt, present; it is farther off; it presents certain difficulties,
not only in the matter of waiting longer for its satisfaction, but also in the effort required
to put down the present allurement which draws to sin. And so the matter is put to the
judgement of the agent; and, judging freely that the present satisfaction outweighs the
remote real satisfaction, he sins. Of course the judgement is perverse; but the point
here is that the sinner does not tend away from the good—and the ultimate good—as
such, but wrongly judges that the present object is good. And he is responsible for this
judgement, and so sin is no mere mistake. Remember that the tendency of the human
agent is towards the good, and the infinite good, in general; but the agent may make
perverse judgements about what is good in particular. Psychology clears up this matter
in its thesis that “Man is capable of objectively indifferent judgements,” i.e., man can
view what is really evil under the aspect of good, and can view what is truly good under
the aspect of evil. Thus sin which is foul promises a present pleasure, and in so far may
be Judged as good; while virtue inasmuch as it is difficult to acquire, may be adjudged
as evil.
An example will help to clarify the whole matter: Esau, returning hungry from the
hunt, and finding himself a long way from home, was able to judge present dinner as
most desirable and good, even though the eating involved the loss of a great and
valuable patrimony. He knew the value of his inheritance ; he knew that the present dish
of paltry food was not to be compared in real value to the smallest part of that
inheritance; and still he gave up the patrimony for the food. Why? Because the food was
ready, present, alluring, promising satisfaction. By perverse judgment he was able to
focus his consideration upon the desirability of that which was present to satisfy bodily
appetite, and to turn his mind away from the consideration of the surpassing value of
the inheritance that would be his if he denied that appetite. His judgment was wrong,
was perverse; yet it was his own fault. And so it was no mere mistake for which he was
not responsible. He was fully responsible, as all will admit. While following the inevitable
human tendency towards what is good in general, he perversely allowed his attention to
dwell upon the attractiveness of what was offered to please and flatter a bodily appetite,
and kept his mind from the consideration of the true attractiveness of what was really
good, and thus a perverse and culpable judgment fixed upon that as good which was
relatively evil, and upon that as evil which was really worth while.
Men may set various ends as ultimate by perverse judgment. Some look for the
ultimate good in wealth, some in honor, some in pleasure, some in the mere adapting of
oneself to one's environment; and thus there are many objects set up by personal
preference (and by wrong judgment ) as the really ultimate end towards which all
human action tends or should tend. But in all these objects we perceive that it is their
good which is attractive, viz., that which is adjudged as good, as satisfying, as ultimately
desirable. And hence, while there may be many philosophies of life, many theories
about what is the best thing towards which man should bend his efforts, there is,
nonetheless, no disagreement in point of fact: man inevitably tends towards the
illimitable good. And in itself, as we have seen, this object is God. When men do not live
in accordance with reason, they are perverse; and perversely they set up false gods.
Scripture is philosophical and scientific when it declares that those who live for the
pleasure of freshly appetites have made a god of their belly.
To sum up: The objective ultimate end of human acts is that which really in itself is
the crowning and perfect fulfillment of rational desire; it is the limitless good; it is God.
Towards good in general all human action, even sinful human action, tends. But action
is sinful by reason of man's abuse of free will ; and sinful action is possible because
man may freely focus his attention upon the desirability of that which satisfies minor or
inordinate appetites, to the exclusion of that which is supremely desirable and infinitely
good in itself.
b) THE SUBJECTIVE ULTIMATE END OF HUMAN ACTS
We have learned that the subjective end of an act consists in the possession of the
objective end. The name subjective is given to this end to indicate its possession by a
subject, that is, by the person who has it or strives to have it.
The absolutely ultimate end of human acts, considered in itself or objectively, is the
limitless good. The absolutely ultimate end of human acts, considered with reference to
the person who strives to possess it (that is, considered with reference to its subject), is
the perfect happiness which consists in the possession of the limitless good. In a word,
the absolutely ultimate subjective end of human acts is happiness.
In considering the objective end of human acts we found it necessary to speak much
of happiness. We saw that man acts for happiness in acting for the limitless good which
is the objective ultimate end of human action. Here we are to consider happiness more
directly, and to discuss the kinds of happiness, the nature of desire for happiness, and
the manner in which happiness is to be possessed. But first we must face an obvious
difficulty.
The difficulty is this : man, acting in a human manner, is seldom conscious of the
fact that he is acting for happiness. The upright man acts virtuously, the sinner acts
viciously, the ordinary man lives his ordinary life, without thinking directly of happiness
as an end to be attained. How is it possible then to say that man always acts for
happiness? We must recall our distinction , made in an earlier chapter, between an
actual and a virtual intention elicited here and now with direction consciousness of that
which is intended. Happiness is seldom, if ever, says to himself: “In this action I intend
to achieve happiness.” But a man always acts for happiness, at least by a virtual
intention. A virtual intention is an intention which exists in an act performed in virtue of a
formerly elicited actual intention. We have seen that man always tends towards the
good in general; and his connatural bent of will for the good involves a virtual intention
for that good. And as the possession of good means happiness, we conclude that man
acts for happiness by a virtual intention. But, it may be said, this sort of virtual intention
does not exist by reason of an actual intention formerly elicited. It does, if we consider
that an actual intention may be implicit as well as explicit. A man who shoots at a rabbit,
does not, in order to have an actual intention, require a moment’s pause in which to
elicit the will-act of actual intention; he may not be aware of his intention as an intention;
he simply does what he wants to do; he simply raises his gun and fires; but we say, and
rightly, that his actual intention is implied in his action. And similarly we declare that a
man, in his more serious and deliberate actions in life, makes up his mind to do what he
adverts to as best, and here, at least implicitly, we have an actual intention to act for
good (objective end) and for the possession of the good (subjective end, i.e., happiness).
Then, in the less thoughtful acts of life, the virtue of this implicit actual intention endures,
and a man’s acts are, in consequence, performed for happiness.
Now we must consider: i. Kinds of happiness; ii. The nature of man’s desire for
happiness; iii. The manner in which happiness is to be possessed.
i. Kinds of Happiness. – Happiness is natural when it comes of man’s possession of
that which he finds achievable by his unaided natural powers, or which is not
beyond the reach of his nature. Thus, a man’s happiness in the possession of
sound health is natural happiness. Happiness is supernatural when it consists in
the possession of that which is of a value surpassing all that natural powers
can achieve unaided. Thus, man’s happiness in possessing the grace of God
is supernatural. Now, man tends toward the limitless good, and since this is
infinite, – and hence beyond man’s finite powers, – man tends toward
something which is beyond the reach of unaided nature. Man tends towards
supernatural, eternal happiness. The appetite of man’s very nature is for the
supernatural. Still, this tendency and appetite for the supernatural is only
indicated in Ethics. As a purely rational science, independent of divine
revelation, Ethics cannot investigate the matter of supernatural happiness,
nor describe the manner in which it is to be attained. But this science can and
does show that man’s tendency is to the limitless good, the infinite good, and
we know that natural powers can achieve only limited things. Yet, to confine
our study within its proper limits, we must consider the limitless good, and
happiness in its possession only in so far as this is achievable by natural
powers, that is, by the perfect natural life, by a life which fully agrees with the
dictates of the right reason
ii, The Nature of Man’s Desire for Happiness, --- Man’s desire for limitless good, and
consequently
for perfect happiness, is not illusory; it is not a deceitful and vain desire. It is a desire
capable of fulfillment; it is a realizable. We may, with St. Thomas, reason to this
conclusion in the following manner: Nature does nothing in vain. Now, nature has
implanted in man the desire for perfect happiness. Therefore, this desire is not vain; in
other words, this desire is realizable. ---Again, Ethics may prove the same truth by
assuming as demonstrated the facts which are scientifically evidenced in the science of
Theodicy. Now Theodicy proves that there is one God, the Creator, who is all-wise, and
all-good. But an all-wise Creator could not implant in His rational creature a fine and
worthy desire that cannot be realized; else the all-wise God would be the author of a
futility. Nor could the all-good God mock man by causing him inevitably to desire the
unattainable. Hence, we conclude that man’s desire for perfect happiness is not illusory,
but is realizable in very fact. We cannot assert that each man will actually attain to
perfect happiness; we only declare the scientific truth that each man may attain that
happiness. Certainly, this perfect happiness is not attainable in this world here and now;
then---since its attainment has been shown possible---it must be attainable in another
world hereafter.
iii. The Manner in which Happiness is to be Possessed---Man’s absolutely ultimate subjective
end is
the act of perfect happiness. Powers or faculties are that y which action is
accompanied; the act is the crowning fact, the perfection of the faculty. Now, how is the
act of happiness to be exercised? Man has the following faculties: the senses, intellect,
will. The senses are not man’s highest faculties, but serve the intellect during bodily life.
All knowledge begins somehow in sensation (i. e, in the act of the senses) for man in
bodily life; but sensation is not, in itself, essential to intellectual knowledge as such.
Obviously, perfect happiness, as an act, is the act of man’s highest and best faculties.
Hence, the essential act of happiness (which, of course, will eventually and in proper
measure include the satisfaction of the senses) is not an act of sensation. Nor is it an
act of will ; for the will either tends towards an end (and then the end is not yet attained)
or, by fruition, delights in the end (and then the end is already attained). The act of
attainment, the act of happiness, is, in consequence, neither a sense-act nor a will act.
It remains that it must be an act of intellect. But here again we must consider a twofold
act of intellect : the intellect either knows a thing to do (practical intellect) and this must
be knowledge that leads to an end to be achieved ; or the intellect knows a thing to hold
contemplation. (speculative intellect)). This latter act is the crowning perfection of man’s
highest faculty of knowledge. We assert, then, that the ultimate act of perfect happiness
is an act of speculative intellect, it is an act of contemplation of the limitless good ; and
this act of the intellect will be accompanied by the delight of the will, and by the perfect
satisfaction of the senses according to their proper place, order and capacity.
SUMMARY OF THE ARTICLE
We have seen in this article that man acts for the attainment of an absolutely
ultimate end, and that this end is, objectively, the infinite good or God, and, subjectively
the possession of the limitless good, the Possession of God, and that the act of
possession is an act of perfect happiness. We have established the truth that man, in
every human act, acts for perfect happiness, by at least a virtual intention.
We have defined two kinds of happiness, have seen that man’s desire for perfect
happiness is not a futile, vain, illusory desire, but is realizable in fact by an act of the
speculative intellect accompanied by the act of full fruition on the part of the will, and by
fullness of sense-satisfaction in so far as the senses can have a part in the attainment
of a man’s end.
CHAPTER III
THE NORMS OF HUMAN ACT
Let us view man as a traveler standing at a point where many roads converge. The
traveler wishes to reach the City of Limitless Good. This city is the goal toward which
the traveler tends by a connatural and inevitable bent of his will. Now, the tendency of
the traveler will remain the same, even if he should choose a wrong road. In other
words, man, the traveler, will choose a road for the purpose of reaching the City of
Limitless Good, even if, as a fact, the chosen road leads away from his goal. It is
obvious, then, that the traveler needs guidance; he needs direction, lest perverse and
mistaken judgment thwart his purpose and render impossible the attainment of his goal.
In a word, the traveler needs a map. More: he requires ability to read the map, and to
interpret it rightly where the road seems to fork or byways open invitingly. Now, the
map, the guiding direction, is supplied to man, the traveler, by low; and the application
of law in individual acts—the reading and interpreting of the map at particular curves
and concerns—is achieved by conscience. Human acts are directed to their true end by
law, and law is applied by conscience. Hence law and conscience are the directives or
norms of human acts. The present Chapter treats of these matters in two Article, as
follows:
Article 1. Law
Article 2. Conscience
Article 1. Law
a.) Definition b.) Classification C.) Important Classes
a.) DEFINITION OF LAW
St. Thomas Defines law as an ordinance of reason, promulgated for the common
good by one who has charge of a society. To explain this definition in detail:
i. A law is an ordinance, i.e., an active and authoritative ordering or directing
of human acts in
reference to an end to be attained by them.
ii. A law is an ordinance of reason, and not an arbitrary or whimsical
decree of the legislator’s
will. A law does, of course, come from the will of the lawgiver, but from his reasonable
will, that is, from his will illumined by understanding of an end necessary or useful to be
attained, toward which the law serves as a proper direction. Hence, law must be
reasonable, and this means that it must be just, honest (not contravening a higher law),
possible of fulfillment (not exacting undue or extraordinary effort on the part of those
bound by it), useful, and in some degree permanent (not a fleeting or whimsical decree).
To be reasonable, to be a true law, a law must have all the qualities here enumerated.
Besides it must be promulgated, that is, made known to those who are bound by it.
Hence, the essential qualities of a true law are these: it must be just, honest, possible,
useful, relatively permanent, and promulgated.
iii. A law is promulgated, i.e., made known to those bound by it, and
these are called its subjects. This is a requirement of law as reasonable, as already
explained. By promulgation a law is put in application as an authoritative
ordinance.
iv. A law is promulgated for the common good. This is the purpose of
law. In this point, a law is
distinguished from a precept, which is an ordinance issued by public or private authority
for the particular or private good of one or several persons. A law also differs from a
precept in the fact that a law is territorial and applies to subjects only while they are in a
certain place; while a precept is personal and binds it subjects wherever they may be.
Again, a law is always enacted by public authority, while a precept may be issued by
either public or private authority. Finally, a law endures in force until it is repealed by the
authority that enacted it, even though the actual persons who framed it be dead or
removed from office; but a precept ceases to bind with the preceptor’s death or removal
from office. To illustrate all this: A mother forbids her little child to accept money from
adults. Here we have a precept, not a law. It is personal not territorial, and binds the
child wherever he may be. It is private, since it is for the individual good of the child and
a part of his individual training. It is blinding, unless revoked by the mother, as long as
the child remains under the mother’s direction in such matters, or until the mother’s
death, in case she dies before the child comes of age. Now, on the other hand, the civil
ordinance forbidding the hunting of game at certain seasons is a law, and not a precept
in the strict technical sense of the word. It is territorial, not personal, and binds its
subjects only while they are in the place in which the law applies, and not when they go
into another territory where a different law in the matter prevails. Further, the law in
question is for the common good; it is public, not private, and is meant to ensure the
opportunity of finding game to all citizens, and to maintain a supply of game as common
property. Finally, the law binds its subjects until it is repealed by the public authority that
enacted it, even though the actual legislators who passed the law be dead or have
passed from office.
A law, then, is for the common or public good. This is the purpose of law. Law is
not meant to impose hardship or needless restriction Upon its subjects, but to promote
their good, and hence to protect and promote true Liberty among them. When a law is
truly a law, that is to say, when he has all the requisite qualities of law, and is just,
honest, Possible, useful, relatively permanent, and duly promulgated dash then it
inevitably acts as a liberating agency and not as an in slaving one true Lord tends to
make men good, and thence to liberate them from the pre verse mistaken judgments
that would lead them astray in the quest for their ultimate end. To them at the man who
accepts the direction of true law is the man who is free to attain his goal, just as the man
who accepts direction when seeking the road to a city which wishes to reach is the man
who is really free to go to that city. He who refuses direction - Although he refuses, as
he thinks, in the name of freedom - Is enslaved by his own ability to error. Such a man
is like a traveler who says, “I wish to go to a certain city, but you must not tell me how to
get there; I refuse to be enslaved by map; I maintain my freedom to try all the roads in
the world. “We should not consider such a traveler reasonable. We should not regard as
very favorable his prospect of reaching the desired city. We should not esteem his idea
of Liberty as anything short of an absurdity, the purpose of law, therefore, is to protect
and promote true freedom among members of our society in common, by ensuring the
unhampered and unthwarted exercises of free acts which will carry man forward to his
proper end.
v. A law is promulgated in society period this is evident from the fact
that law is for the common
good comma and hence opposes a commonality or community of subjects; and a
community is a society, Law in the fullest sense can exist only in a perfect society, for
such a society alone has the full and perfect right to legislate (i,e., full jurisdiction) for all
subjects. Now, the supreme and perfect society in the natural order is called the State
(that is, a body of people politically united under one government), and the supreme
and perfect society in the supernatural order is the true Church. In the fullest sense,
therefore, human laws can come only from Church or State.
vi. A law is promulgated by one who has charge of a society. By “one” is
meant a person,
whether this be a single human being (physical person) or a body of men united to form
the governing power (more person). Here we have indicated the author of law, that is,
the lawgiver or legislative. A legislator has jurisdiction, which means, literally, “the saying
of what is right.” One who has the just authority of
“saying what is right” in the community is empowered to enact and promulgate true
laws. Almighty God is the Supreme Lawgiver, and properly constituted human
legislation has its power and authority, directly on indirectly, from God.- The author of
law enacts laws as ordinances of reason, and hence he must have a direct care and
concern about their observance. To insure observance the author of the law establishes
sanctions for law, i. e., inducements (rewards and punishments) sufficiently strong to
lead reasonable men to follow the prescriptions of the law.
b) CLASSIFICATION OF LAWS
i. According to their immediate author, laws are distinguished as divine laws,
which come directly from God (such as the Ten Commandments), and human laws,
which are the enactments of Church or State. Human laws enacted by the Church
are called ecclesiastical laws, while human laws enacted by the State are called
civil laws.
ii. According to their duration, laws are temporal or eternal. The Eternal
Law is God's plan and
providence for the universe. We shall speak of this law in detail in the next section of
this Article. All human laws are in themselves temporal, although some of them give
expression to requirements of the Eternal Law.
ii. According to the manner of their promulgation, laws are distinguished as the natural
law and positive laws. The natural law, in widest sense, is that which directs creatures to
their end in accordance with their nature, and, so understood, it coincides with the
Eternal Law. Usually, however, the laws that govern irrational creatures in their being
and activities are called physical laws, while the moral law which is apprehended by
sound and matured human reason is called the natural law. In this restricted sense we
shall understand the term, the natural law; and we shall define it as the Eternal Law as
apprehended by human reason. Positive laws are laws enacted by positive act of a
legislator, and these fall under the classification already made as divine and human.
Thus, the Ten Commandments are divine positive laws, and the laws of Church and
State are human positive laws.
iv. According as they prescribe an act or forbid it, laws are affirmative
or negative. Negative laws are also called prohibitory law. Affirmative laws bind
always, but not at every moment. Thus, the Commandment of hearing Mass on
certain days binds only on those days, and the requirement of this law may be
satisfied at any hour at which Mass is offered. The law binds always (that is, it
remains constantly in effect) but not at every moment (that is, its subjects are not
required to perform continuously and without intermission the act which it
prescribes). On the other hand, negative laws of the natural order bind always and
at every moment. Thus, the law “Thou shalt not kill,” remains continuously in force,
and must be obeyed at every moment without exception and in all circumstances.
v. According to the effect of their violation, laws are distinguished as
moral (violation of which is
fault or sin), penal (violation of which renders the violator liable to an established
penalty, but does not infect him with sin) , and mixed (violation of which involves both
fault and penalty).
C.) IMPORTANT CLASSES OF LAWS
Here we are to consider: 1. The Eternal Law; The Natural Law; iii. Human Positive
Law. The discussion of Divine Positive Law belongs to Theology and not to Ethics.
i. The Eternal Law is God’s eternal plan and providence for the universe. God,
decreeing from
eternity to create the world for an end (which is Himself) , eternally plans and directs all
things toward that end. Thus there is from eternity a “plan of Divine Wisdom as director
of all acts and movements”— and this is The Eternal Law. St. Augustine defines the
Eternal Law as the Divine Reason and Will commanding that the natural order of things be
preserved and forbidding that it be disturbed. The Eternal Law extends to all acts and
movements in the universe. Thus, bodies obey the tendencies of their nature and follow
the laws of cohesion, gravity, inertia, etc. ; plants grow ; animals follow the guidance of
instinct ; the earth turns upon its axis ; the heavenly spheres swing through their mighty
orbits ; all in accordance with the Eternal Law, powerless to reject its influence or to
disobey. Of all bodily creation, man alone may refuse the direction of the Eternal Law in
matters of free choice. For the Eternal Law applies to all creatures and directs them in a
manner consonant with their nature ; and man’s nature, in its rational part, is free. As a
bodily being man acts in accordance with physical laws; so he does also in those
animal and vegetal functions which are proper to his nature but not under the control of
his will.
But in matter that lie under man’s free control—in a word, in human acts—man may
be perverse and disobedient, refusing the direction of the Eternal Law as known to
him by his reason. Thus, the Eternal Law governs all things except human acts by
necessity, that is, allowing the things governed no choice in the matter; the same
Eternal Law directs human acts by suasion.
ARTICLE 2. CONSCIENCE
a) Definition b) States of Conscience
b) Forming One’s Conscience
a.) Definition of Conscience
Conscience is the practical judgment of reason upon an individual act as good and to be
performed, or as evil and to be avoided.
i. It is a judgment of reason, that is, it is a reasoned conclusion. Although the term
conscience is also used to designate the act of reasoning out of the right and wrong of a
situation before choosing what to do, it is more properly employed, as in our definition, to
signify the judgment which is the conclusion of that act of reasoning. Now, an act of
reasoning requires a principle, or set of principles, from which the process of reasoning
proceeds. By principles we mean things known with certainly with which we may compare
new facts or proposed actions and so discover new truths – new applications of the
principles. Thus, before we can reason out the truth that the angles of a triangle are
equal to 180 degrees, we must have a grasp of certain mathematical principle; we must
know, for instance, that when parallels are cut by a transversal, the alternate interior
angles are equal, and that opposite angle are equal. Knowing these facts, we can
proceed to the proof of the theorem is question. These facts are principles, that is,
starting points whence one may reason to further truths or to individual application of
the original known data. Similarly, in matters of right and wrong, we must have morals
principles to start with. We acquire these principles – many of them, – in early life and
when we have a workable grasp of them, we become responsible for our conduct, we
cease to be infants and
THE NORMS OF HUMAN ACTS
We are said to have "come to the use of reason." Now, this acquired equipment
of moral principles is called synteresis. Synteresis is the starting point of the reasoning
process which ends in the judgment of conscience. This reasoning process may proceed
so smoothly and swiftly that we are not aware of it as a reasoning process at all; indeed,
this is ordinarily the case. Still, the process is always a fact, if only an implicit fact. Thus,
when we are confronted with a possible course of action, we compare it mentally with
our moral principles, and conclude that it is good and hence to be done (or at least
permitted), or evil and hence to be avoided. For example, suppose I am face to face
with a difficulty form which I might extricate myself by a clever and fictitious explanation
of my conduct. My moral reasoning goes on as follows:
Lies are never allowed (principle from synteresis);
The explanation which suggests itself to me is a lie;
Therefore, this explanation is not allowed (judgement of conscience).
ii. Conscience is a practical judgment. This means that it has reference to something to
be done, i.
e., either the performance or the omission of an act. The reasoning process always in a
practical judgment. When, for instance, one concludes the proof of the theorem which
states that the angles of a triangle equal 180 degrees, one expresses that conclusion in
a judgment; this judgment, however, does not indicate a source of action (practical
judgment), but enriches knowledge by the addition of a newly recognized truth
(speculative judgment). It is obvious that conscience is a practical judgment. It is a
judgment that commands, forbids, allows, or advises, according as it declares an
individual act obligatory, prohibited, permissible, or prudent. It is a judgment which says:
“Do this!” “Avoid that!” “You may do this!” “It would be well to do that!” In a word,
conscience is a dictate.
iii. Conscience is a judgment upon an individual act, here and now, in these present
circumstances, tobe performed or omitted. It is also a judgment upon an individual act
after it has been performed or omitted. But it is always an individual judgment upon
an individual act; it is not a general moral judgment or principle (for such judgments
belong to synteresis), but it is the reasoned judgment, drawn from a general principle
and an individual act; it applies the general moral principle in individual action. Before
action, conscience judges an act as good and to be performed (i.e., as something
obligatory, advisable, or permissible), or as evil and to be omitted. After action,
conscience is a judgment of approval or disapproval.
b) STATES OF CONSCIENCE
Probabilism is of great use in dispelling doubt and forming one’s conscience, but
its use is best limited to matters of business and to the field of human positive law. In
the more abstract questions of morals there is a grave danger of applying Probabilism
too quickly and without proper justification. It must always be remembered that
Probabilism is deduced from a reflex moral principle which has no place in the
legitimate formation of conscience unless the direct method (of positive study and
investigation of the actual situation) proves impossible or fruitless in the matter of
dispelling doubt.
There is one case in which Probabilism cannot be made to serve at all, viz., in
the case of a certain end absolutely to be achieved. Thus, even when there is a solidly
probable reason that a convert to the Catholic faith has been validly baptized, the
sacrament will be administered conditionally upon his reception into the Church. For
Baptism is absolutely necessary to salvation and probability has no service to render in
the matter, since certainty is directly achievable.
Let the student consider the following cases and judge where Probabilism may
serve:
i. A physician has a sure remedy for a certain disease. He has also a
second remedy which, he has very strong reasons for believing, will effect
a cure more rapidly, and with less discomfort to the patient, than the first.
May he use the second remedy?
ii. Pasteur found his ant-toxin for hydrophobia most effective when used on
animals. No other remedy for the dread disease was known. A child that
had been bitten by a mad dog was brought to Pasteur. Could he
administer the anti-toxin, although it had never before been used in the
treatment of a human being ?
iii. A nurse knows that a certain physician ー a skillful and capable man ー has once,
through hurry and the mistake of a lay attendant, caused the death of a patient
by administering a lethal drug. She doubts whether she is obliged to declare the
matter and have the physician dismissed from the hospital staff. She realizes that
the death of the patient was a most unfortunate accident, and that the physician
will most probably be very careful to avoid such accidents in future. Still, the
man destroyed a human life, and perhaps the persons who employ him should
be made aware of the fact. How is the doubt to be resolved ?
iv. A tenant doubts whether he has paid his rent for a certain month. His
landlord, a careless man in his accounts, is also in doubt. Must the tenant
pay the rent ? If he decides to do so, may the landlord accept it ?
v. A hunter sights an animal far off among the trees. He feels sure that it is a
deer ; still he realizes that it is possible that the animal may be a horse or
cow belonging to a farmer of the neighborhood. May he fire? May he fire
even if he is willing to pay handsomely in case of error?
Sources:
This chapter deals with the good and evil (i.e., the morality) of human acts, explains
the nature of morality, and studies the criterion or norm by which the morality of acts
is known. It then establishes the determinants of morality, i.e., the points of contact
which human acts have with their measure or norm and according to which the acts are
known as good or evil.
a) DESCRIPTION OF MORALITY
Morality is that quality of human acts which leads us to call some of them good
and some evil.
Now why do we call anything good or evil? We have already seen the answer
to this question, but we must here recall and enlarge our knowledge of the matter.
A thing is good inasmuch as it can answer a tendency, appetite, desire. In other
words, it is good…
Inasmuch as it serves as an end of such tendency. Thus, I call my coat a good “good
coat” if it furnishes me what I want in a coat, viz, warmth, style, fit, good cloth, good
tailoring, etc. I call my automobile good if it does what can be reasonably expected of
it in the way of speed, comfortable riding, rich appearance, etc. What I expect of my
coat and automobile are the ends I wish to achieve by means of garment or motor car.
Inasmuch as the cot or the car serves any or all of these ends, I say it is not good.
Now in the matter of human acts---where moral good or evil is the point in question---
there is always a last end towards which the action tends. Objectively, this is the
Summum Bonum, the Limitless Good, God. Subjectively, the last end of human acts is
perfect happiness in the possession of Summum Bonum. Such being the end of human
action, it follows that human acts are good inasmuch as they serve to carry the agent
on towards the attainment of this end, and not good, or evil, inasmuch as they fail to
lead towards the last end, or even lead away from it.
B., THE NORM OF MORALITY
In the Article of Law we learned that there is an eternal plan for the ordering or
government of all acts and movements in the universe, and that this plan directs things
towards their fast end. But, as we also learned, man is free and rational, he is not
concerned
(in the field of free choice) by the plan, but is meant to recognize it by his reason and
freely follow it in all his free or human acts. Human acts which are in harmony with
the eternal plan are good; those not in harmony with it are evil. Now, the eternal plan is
the Eternal Law, which is the Divine reason (and Will) expressing itself in the ordering
of the universe. Thus human acts are good or evil inasmuch as they agree or conflict
with the Divine Reason. Now how is the Divine Reason recognized by man?
Obviously by human reason, which pronounces on individual human acts-in a word, by
Conscience. Hence, the Eternal Law (Divine Reason) on the other hand, and
conscience (human reason) on the other, constitute the Norm of Morality. From this it
will be seen that we were right when we said that human acts are good or evil
inasmuch as they agree or conflict with the dictates of reason (divine and human).
The Divine Reason, or the Eternal Law, is the ultimate Norm of Morality. But that
which serves man immediately in action, that which is available to his proximate use,
is human reason pronouncing upon the good or evil of individual human acts: in other
words, conscience is the proximate Norm of Morality.
Summing the matter up, we say that the Norm of Morality is, remotely and ultimately
(but primarily), the Eternal Law; while approximately (but secondarily) it is
conscience. In reality, then, there are not two norms but only one; for conscience is the
judgement
of human reason recognizing and applying the Eternal Law in individual acts.
c) DEFINITION OF MORALITY
Morality is the relation of human acts to the ir norm
Morality is the quality (or property) or a human act whereby it measures up to what it
should be as a step towards the objective last end of human action, or fails so to
measure up. It consists therefore in the relation existing between human acts and the
norm of morality.
The morality of an act, its character as good or evil, is not a mere external
denomination or classification, it is not a mere label pasted on arbitrarily. It is
something that belongs inevitably to the human act as such, either to the act considered
objectively as a deed performed, or to the act considered as characterized by its
circumstances, particularly the circumstance called the end of the agent.
Some ethicians have placed the essence of the morality of human acts in freedom. This
doctrine is false. It is true that a human acct is a free act; and, in a true sense,, it is a
moral act (i.e., has morality, is right or wrong, good or evil) because it is free. But
freedom does not constitute morality. Morality is the property of a free act, that is, it is
an inevitably present characteristic of a free act. But it consists formally, as we have
said, not in the freedom itself, but in the relation which the act bears towards the norm
or measure of what it should be-towards the Norm of Morality.
D) DIVISION OF MORALITY
I. Material and Formal - A human act considered in itself as a deed performed stands in
relation to the Norm of Morality as materially good or evil. A human act considered as
conditioned by the agent’s understanding and will, stands in relation to the Norm of
Morality as formally good or evil. Sometimes the terms objective and subjective are
used respectively for material and formal in this connection. Thus, a lie is objectively
or materially evil: it is a thing that is evil in itself, as a deed done, for it conflicts with
the Norm of Morality. But a lie which a person mistakenly deems to be permitted and
justified in certain circumstances, is, while materially evil, not subjectively or formally
so.
II. Intrinsic and Extrinsic. - Material or objective morality is intrinsic when the
human act, as a deed performed, stands by reason of its very nature in relation to the
Norm of Morality as good or evil. Material or objective morality is extrinsic when the
stand or relation of an act to the Norm of Morality is determined, not by the nature of
the act itself, but by the prescription of positive law. Thus, murder is intrinsically evil.
Eating meat on Friday is extrinsically evil
Stances, one circumstance stands out as most important, and we give it special
consideration apart from all other circumstances of the act: this is the circumstance
called the end of the agent. Thus we list three determinants of morality, viz., (a) the act
itself (i. E, object) ; (b) the end of the agent; (c) the circumstances other than the end of
the agent.
A human act, to be a morally good act, must be found in agreement with the Norm of
Morality on all three points, i. E, it must be good in itself or objectively, in its end, and
in its circumstances. A human act is evil if it fails to conform with the Norm of
Morality in any one of the points or determinants. This is expressed in the ancient
axiom: “Bonum ex integra causa, malum ex quocumque defectu,” i.e,. “A thing to be
good must be entirely good; it is vitiated by any defect.” We may see the justice of the
axiom by a rough analogy: A man to be a healthy man must have all organs
functioning properly; while he is unwell even if only one organ (the heart, for example,
or the stomach, or the liver) is diseased or deranged. Similarly, in human acts we find
goodness dependent upon the agreement of the avts with the Norm of Morality on the
score of all determinants; it is not good enough that an act be good in itself; it must
also be good in its end and in the circumstances that affect it as a moral act. But it is
evil if it conflict with the moral law on any of the three points.
Note-no p104
A.)THE OBJECT. By the object is mean the human act performed, the deed done. If
an act as object is good or evil, we say-as we have learned-that it has objective
morality. If an act, considered abstractly, is indifferent (good or bad), its morality is
determined by the end for which it is performed and by circumstances which affect it.
Now certain actions are in the
themselves, or objectively, good, and certain others are objectively evil: and this
morality is intrinsic, i. e, resides in the act independently of positive law prescribing or
forbidding the act. This assertion recommends itself at once to the normal mind as a
true statement; yet some moralists have denied it. It is therefore necessary to prove
briefly that some acts are intrinsically good, and some intrinsically evil.
Now those that deny the intrinsic morality of any human act must admit, as all other
men do, that there are certain acts which have always and everywhere been regarded as
good, and others which have been universally considered as evil. The acceptance of
these acts as respectively good and evil is a fact to be explained. We explain it by
stating the doctrine of intrinsic morality: men have always regarded certain acts as
good in themselves because, as a matter of fact, they are good; and they have regarded
others as intrinsically evil, because they are evil. Our opponents declare that what we
call intrinsic morality is merely the result of long established custom among men, or of
special human legislation, or of the arbitrary decision of God’s will that some acts are
good and some evil. In the inadequacy of these explanations we find the negative proof
of our own position. Let us consider the matter in detail.
i. Custom cannot account for the universal acceptance of some acts as good in
themselves and of other acts as intrinsically evil. How did the custom come into being?
If as a dictate of right reason, because all people saw that certain things were in line
with their rational desires and certain other things opposed to these, then the argument
falls to nothing, and is merely an indefinite restatement of the true doctrine that certain
acts are perceived by right reason as good and other acts as evil— in a word, that
certain acts are perceived as intrinsically good or evil. If the custom did not arise as a
dictate of right reason among men, then it arose out of circumstances. Since
circumstances can be artificially arranged, it would be possible to get current a
movement to change the present moral views of men. It would be possible, for
example, to form a society, and to spread its influence generally throughout the human
race, for the furtherance of murder and theft as virtuous acts! It would be possible to
train men to the state of mind in which they could behold themselves robbed of their
possessions not only without resentment, but with positive approval of the theft, and
with veneration for the thieves as saintly men! It would be possible to have parents
generally (always excepting a very few reactionaries) delighted with the ingratitude of
their children. It would be possible to have those in authority reward disobedience and
punish obedience; to throw the honest man in jail, and to elevate the malefactor as the
model citizen. Then we should see men and women standing trial for murders they
impiously failed to commit, for degradations to which they failed to sink, for slanders
they fail to utter. But, you say, these things are utterly impossible. Then it is utterly
impossible that the universal conviction of men concerning the intrinsic good and evil
of human acts is a mere outgrowth of custom.
ii. Human legislation cannot account for the universal acceptance of some acts as
good in themselves and of other acts as intrinsically evil. If human legislation means
law in the true sense, then we are back in our own position, for true human law is an
ordinance of reason in line with the Eternal Law, and it exists because there really are
acts good in themselves to be prescribed, and acts evil in themselves to be forbidden.
Acts are not good because true law prescribes them; they are prescribed by law
because they are good. Nor are acts evil because true law forbids them; the law forbids
them because they are evil. Certainly there are some acts (such as hunting out of
season, driving at a certain rate of speed, etc.) which are not good or evil in
themselves, and which fall under penal law; but our question does not concern these.
We are merely proving that some acts are intrinsically good, and others intrinsically
evil; while our opponents deny all intrinsic morality of any and every act. Now, if
legislation be taken to mean, not a reasonable ordinance, but the whimsical and
arbitrary decree of a ruler or ruling body, then legislation may change the whole
scheme of morality. A “law” may be passed tomorrow making it imperative for sons to
kill their fathers, for servants to rob their masters, for men to curse God, for spouses to
be unfaithful; and such a “law” would not only make these crimes imperative, but
virtuous. Then men, in time, would come to regard these acts of virtue in their true
light, and we should find that murder would be everywhere regarded as noble. Fathers
would embrace the slayers of their little children; mothers would rejoice in the shame
of their daughters; employers would thank Heaven for the favor of dishonest
employees! Such an impossible topsy-turvydom could not be created by legislation.
Then neither could the existent moral scheme have been so created. If legislation be
not guided by reason - which does not make, but only recognizes good and evil in
human acts - then it might just as well and as easily produce the topsy-turvy morality
described as the morality we actually acknowledge.
iii. The arbitrary decision of God’s will cannot account for the universal acceptance of
some acts as good in themselves and of other acts as intrinsically evil. God is infinitely
perfect ; His acts are therefore infinitely right and reasonable. Hence an arbitrary
decisions of the Divine Will without reference to the Divine Reason is so impossible as
to be absolutely unthinkable. We have learned that God directs all acts and movements
in the universe to their last end by the Eternal Law. Now, the Eternal Law is an
ordinance of Divine Reason, and is put in effect by the Divine Will, not arbitrarily or
gratuitously, but precisely because the Divine Reason recognizes it as right and
reasonable. We speak of God in weak and inadequate human language, of course, and
thus seem to separate the Divine reason and Will; but as a matter of fact these are not
separated, but are identical with Divine Essence. Thus it follows that all the acts of
God are infinitely reasonable ; no divine act can be severed from Divine Reason. Thus
to assert that God has unreasonably decided that certain things shall be good and other
things evil, is to enunciate an absurdity.
In view of the truth established---viz, that there is such a thing as intrinsic morality---
we are forced to reject many moral theories as false. Among those so rejected we find:
ii. The Theory of Usefulness (called Utilitarianism), which asserts that what is
discerned as useful (to individual men or to human society) is good, and what is found
harmful is evil. It is true that good is ultimately useful, and evil harmful; but the
usefulness comes from goodness, not goodness from usefulness; and harmfulness
comes from evil, not evil from harmfulness. Certain human acts are, as we have
proved, intrinsically good or evil; and hence their usefulness or uselessness can have
nothing to do with their nature. Further, the theory of utilitarianism would make the
code of morals as changeable as the stockmarket rates; for what is useful (in a merely
temporal and material sense) is variable and differs from times and persons: but the
Norm of Morality, to be a norm or law, must be a stable thing. Again, how would the
test of usefulness be established? Act would have to be “tried out” first without any
rule at all to discover which acts might be listed as useful, and hence good, and which
are harmful, and hence forbidden as evil.
To sum up: The object of a human act, the act itself as a deed done or to be done, that
is, the act considered as fact, has often its own intrinsic morality. Even if the act be in
itself indifferent, it may have extrinsic morality, which is still objective, that is, as an
object, the act may stand in harmony or in disagreement with the prescriptions of
positive moral law. Hence in determining whether any human act is good or evil, we
look first to the object. The object is the primary determinant of morality. If the object
be evil, our quest ends there; the act is definitely evil and forbidden; nothing can make
it good. But if the act is good as an object, it may still be vitiated by its circumstances ,
particularly by that circumstance called “the end of the agent.” Hence, if we find an act
good in itself as an object, we have still to look to the end of the agent and to the other
circumstances before pronouncing it good and permissible as an individual act.
i. An objectively good act performed for a good purpose (i.e, a good end of the
agent) takes on a new goodness from the good end; and if it have several good ends, it
takes on a new goodness from each. Thus, a man who gives alms to relieve distress, to
honor God, and to do penance, performs an act which has threefold goodness:
objectively it is an act of mercy; and in its end it is an act of religion, and an act of the
virtue of penance.
ii. An objectively evil act performed for an evil purpose(i. e. An evil end of
agent) takes on a new malice or evil from the evil end; and if it have several evil ends,
it takes on a new malice from each. Thus, a man who steals money in order to buy
liquor with which to get another intoxicated and have him sign an unjust contract,
performs an act in which there is a threefold malice or evil objectively, it is an act of
injustice; and by reason of the evil ends it is an act of intemperance in cause and an act
of injustice to the signer of the contract.
iii. An act which is objectively good, but done for an evil end, is entirely evil
if the evil end is the whole motive of the act; likewise the act is entirely evil if the evil
end is gravely evil (i. e. Mortally sinful) even though it is not the whole motive of the
act; but the act is only partially evil if the evil end is neither gravely evil (i. e. Is not
morally sinful) nor the whole motive of the act. Thus, to give money to a poor man in
order to wean him away from the true faith, is an act entirely evil. Likewise, to assist in
extinguishing a destructive fire with the purpose of stealing valuable property from the
burning building, is an entirely evil act. But to give alms to the poor for the purpose of
relieving distress and with the added intention of gaining a little prominence as a
beneficent person, is an act partially good and partially (but not gravely) evil.
iv. An objectively evil act can never become good by reason of a good end. The
primary determinant of morality is the object, the act itself. If an act itself is evil, it is
and remains evil in spite of every circumstance. The end does not justify the means.
The end does specify the means : that is, supposing a choice of different means all of
which are good, the nature of the end in view will determine which of the available
good means is to be chosen as most suitable or practicable. But there is no end,
however good, that can justify an evil means, however slightly evil. Thus we see that
there is nothing but folly in expressions like the following that too often fall from the
lips of thinking men (perhaps even from the lops of graduates of Catholic colleges) :
“It’s all in one’s intention ;” “I do not look at the matter as you do ; I do not consider it
wrong ; therefore it is not wrong for me ;” “There is nothing either good or bad, but
thinking makes it so”
v. An act which is indifferent objectively becomes good if done for a good end, and
evil if done for an evil end. Thus, to sing in order to praise God, or to please one’s
guests, or even to charm one’s own ears, who desires quiet is an evil act, being an
offense against charity.
c) THE CIRCUMSTANCES
Circumstances are conditions that affect an act- and may affect it morally- although
they do not belong to the essence of the act as such. In other words, circumstances are
conditions without which the act could exist, but which happen to affect or qualify it an
its concrete performance. Examples of circumstances are place, time, company, etc.. in
which an act is performed.
We enumerate seven circumstances. These are usually set forth in mnemonic Latin
line: Quis, quid, ubi, quibus auxiliis, cur, quomodo. quando. Which may be freely
translated as follows:
Who, what, where, with what ally,
In what condition, when, and why?
Some circumstances merely increase or diminish the good or evil object (i.e., act as
such). Other circumstances add to the act a new good or evil, differing in nature, or
species from that of the act. Thus, the circumstance of time in the case of an evil
intention long entertained merely increases the evil, merely makes the act worse, but
leaves it unaltered, or rather, with no new kind of evil added. Robbing a church,
however, adds to the evil of theft the new of sacrilege, thus changing the nature of the
evil act from a simple to a complex one. The circumstances which merely increase or
diminish the moral quality of an act, leaving it in the same species or nature, are called
circumstances which make the act better or worse. The circumstances that add a
specifically new moral character to the act are called circumstances that change the
nature of the act.
The ethical principles involved in the matter of circumstances as determinants of
morality are the following :
i. An indifferent act becomes good or evil by reason of its circumstances. That
is to say, an act which is indifferent in itself as object, takes its moral quality from its
circumstances. Thus, to eat meat is an act in itself indifferent. But to eat meat on a day
of abstinence is evil; and the evil comes from the circumstance of time.
ii. A good act may become evil by reason of circumstances. Thus, to pray to
God is a good act objectively. But to pray to God for misfortune to befall an enemy is
an evil act by reason of the end of the agent―a circumstance already fully considered.
Further it involves evil from the circumstance of person, for such a prayer is an insult
to the All-Perfect God.
iii. A good or evil act (objectively) may become better or worse by reason of
circumstances, and may even take on specifically new goodness or malice from its
circumstances. This matter has been treated in the paragraph on circumstances which
make the act better or worse, and circumstances that change the nature of the act.
iv. An evil act can never be made good by circumstances.
v. A circumstance which is gravely evil (mortally sinful) destroys the entire goodness
of an objectively good act. Thus, to do charity with stolen money is evil by reason of
the circumstances of means or instrument.
vi. A circumstance which is evil, but not gravely so(not mortally sinful), does
not entirely destroy the goodness of an objectively good act. Thus, to pray carelessly
and lazily does not entirely destroy the goodness of the act of prayer, although the full
goodness of the act is injured by the circumstance of manners.
..and logically, his answer must be made to Him who imposes the Norm of Morality.
Imputability, therefore, means the accountability that man must bear for his human acts
before the Almighty God.
God has established an Eternal Law for his creatures, an eternal ordinance of the
Divine Reason to direct and guide all things to their proper last end, which is Himself,
His own external glory. All bodily creatures except man are necessitated by this law;
but within the field of application of the Eternal Law there is a special place for God’s
free creatures; and here man, while obligated by the Law, is not forced or necessitated.
Now man has reason, and very early in life, he acquires an equipment of reasoned
moral principles which are really recognitions of the Eternal Law, and these his
conscience applies in individual acts, so that he knows his obligation in evident moral
matters even when he disregards it. By these acts, then, man must stand; he cannot
disclaim them; they are his. And so we say that for every human act man stands liable
to answer at the bar of Reason--of human reason (conscience) here, and of Divine
Reason (God) hereafter. This, in fine, is the doctrine of the imputability of human acts.
The extent of human imputability has, of necessity, been treated as a matter
pertinent to the very nature of human acts. The student is referred in particular to
Chapter I, Article 2, b.
Nor is merit (or demerit) only a “quality, state or fact” of human acts. It is a property of
such acts, since it belongs to them by natural necessity. For human acts being what
they are- free, knowing, imputable-it follows that good human acts “deserve well,”
while evil human acts “deserve ill” at the hands of the Ruler of the human acts. The
Ruler of the human acts is God. In the field of free choice God rules men by suasion,
not by force; and His rule is the Norm of Morality, that is Divine Reason (the Eternal
Law) and human reason (conscience). Thus, as the obedient subject of a true law
deserves well of the lawgiver, and as the disobedient subject deserves punishment, so
the agent of good human acts deserves well of God, the Divine Lawgiver, while the
agent of evil human acts deserves punishment. Thus we see that merit and demerit are
really extensions of the property of imputability in human acts: for such acts are
imputed to their agent as worthy of praise or blame, of reward or punishment. Still,
while a man “deserves well” for his good acts, he has in that fact no strict title to
reward: nor does the subject of human law look for a premium from the State for being
a good citizen. Something more is required to establish a claim to reward. The human
act which is good, and which confers a benefit upon him from whom reward is looked
for, a benefit not already due and a benefit for the conferring of which it is some such
is the human act which establishes a claim to reward.
Now, God has established his External Law. He has made sanctions for it, i.e.,
inducements to lead reasonable men to obey its prescriptions, and punishments to deter
men from violating them. By this very fact He has given promise of reward and threat
if punishment. Man cannot, indeed, confer a benefit, strictly so-called, upon God, for
man cannot give to God anything that is not already His ; the most loving and devoted
service man can render throughout his life is already owed to God. Still, by our good
acts we can honor God, although it were possible, by abuse of free will, to dishonor
Him ; and thus, in some sense, we can do what it is due Him, we render ourselves
liable in strict justice to punishment at His hands. But the real foundation of human
merit before God is the perfection of God Himself. God is necessarily true to His
promises ; and He who has implanted in the heart of man a quenchless thirst for
happiness, will not allow that thirst to exist in vain; that thirst will be satisfied unless
man, by evil human acts, rejects God who alone can satisfy it.
A man does more easily that which he has done before, and the more frequent
the repetition of an act, the easier becomes its performance. In a word, human acts tend
to form habits. Since human acts have morality, the habit of performing any human act
will be a moral habit. If it is a good moral habit, it is a virtue. If it is an evil moral
habit, it is a vice. Vice and virtue are not matters of a single human act, nor of an act
once or twice repeated, but of an act frequently repeated. Frequent repetition of an act,
and in this strong inclination lies the active or operative habit of so acting.
Now the word “habit” is the only past participle of the Latin verb habere, “to
have.” Literally, it is “thing had,” a thing possessed. It also involves the notion of some
permanence in the possession. A habit is something that is not close to one, that is, so
to speak, carried about with one ordinarily, like a uniform dress - and, indeed, a
uniform dress is called “a habit.” Habits may affect a thing in its substance (entitative
habit) or in its active powers (operative habit). Thus, beauty or fatness is an entitative
habit; painting or typewriting is an operative habit. Virtues and vices are operative
moral habits.
a.) VIRTUES
The word virtue comes from the Latin word virtus. This Latin word was military and
meant the courage, the bravery of the soldier. The word is itself derived from the noun
vir, a man. Hence, virtue is, quite literally, manliness; it is the mark and characteristic
of the true and upright man. In Ethics, virtue signifies that habitual manliness and
power for good acts which arises from the frequent performance of such acts. It has a
special signification, too, and while we speak of virtue in general, as when we mention
“a virtuous person”, we also speak of virtues, using the plural advisedly, and referring
to different habits of acting well the special name of different virtues. Thus we speak
of the virtues of prudence, justice, etc. Thus, too, we speak of this or that virtue, or of a
virtue.
A virtue may be natural or supernatural; it may be infused into the soul by God, or
acquired by repeated acts; it may be physical virtue, and intellectual virtue, a
theological virtue, or a moral virtue. Thus, the native disposition one may have for
study is a natural virtue; divine Faith is a supernatural virtue; fortitude is an acquired
virtue; bodily strength or perfection is physical virtue; wisdom is an intellectual virtue;
faith is a theological virtue; fortitude is a moral virtue. In Ethics we deal only with
acquired moral virtues.
An acquired moral virtue is a morally good operative habit. It is a moral habit of acting
in accordance with the dictates of reason.
The chief moral virtues are: prudence, justice, fortitude and temperance. These are
called cardinal virtues, and the name derives from the Latin cardo, a hinge; for as a
door depends for its proper action in opening and closing upon its hinges, so do all
moral virtues depend upon the “hinges” of the cardinal virtues. We shall say a word of
each of these four virtues.
i. Prudence is that virtue of the understanding which enables one quickly
and clearly to know, in concrete circumstances, the best means to an end,
and it further inclines one to take these means promptly and accurately.
Strictly, then, prudence is an intellectual virtue, not a moral (or “will”
virtue), but we list it with the moral virtues because it has an immediate
connection with the actual willing of the means to an end which this virtue
enables the understanding to grasp. The marks of prudence, as we may
learn from its definition, are a certain watchfulness and clear sightedness,
on the one hand, and cautious promptitude and precision on the other. A
prudent man is never precipitate or headlong; he does not embroil or
entangle a situation; he is nor cock-sure, headstrong, or self-confident.
Nor, on the other hand, is he weak, hesitant, or over cautious. For the
Christian, prudence, raised to the supernatural plane by grace, is a
thoroughly fundamental virtue. The ancients counselled prudence in their
axiom, “Virtue stands in the middle,” that is, virtue does not run to
extremes; prudence preserves the “meson” or sane balance of Aristotle,
and makes human action avoid the human action avoid the evil of falling
too short or of overreacting its object; it makes human action fall just right
according to the norm of right reason.
ii. Justice is the virtue which inclines one with constancy always to render to everyone his
own. Man has, by his rational nature, a clear knowledge of something owed to God, to
his country, and to his fellowmen, Justice is the virtue which steadily inclines man to
recognize and pay this debt. A just man, therefore, is a religious man, an obedient,
peace-loving, kind, grateful and truthful man.
iii. Fortitude is the virtue which inclines one to face dangers with intrepidity, especially
with such dangers as threaten life. Fortitude, like all virtues, observes the “meson”or
balance. It is not rashness, over-boldness, or presumptuous love of danger for its own
sake or for ostentation; nor, on the other hand, is it supineness or dead submission. It
involves a largeness of mind and soul, and combines with these the power of fadeless
endurance.
iv. Temperance is the virtue which controls one in the pursuit and use of pleasure of life,
especially of those pleasure that attract most strongly, and in while there is a
consequent danger of excess and disorder. Temperance keeps the desire and use of
sense-pleasures particularly, within the bounds of right and
reasonable action. Temperance, therefore, is not insensibility nor the extinction of
natural tendencies. It is the regulation of tendencies, the sane self-mastery which
reason (conscience) dictates.
B. VICES
A vice is a morally evil operative habit. A single evil human act is a sin. Vice is a habit
of sin. We distinguish different vices inasmuch as different habits if sin stand opposed
to virtues. For vice is a habitual lack of virtue; and it stands opposed to virtue either by
defect or by excess. Virtue stands in the middle, being neither defective nor excessive
when measured by the requirements of right reason; while vice lies upon either hand.
To give but a few examples of vice as opposed to the cardinal moral virtues:
Opposed to prudence by defect we find, among other vices, imprudence,
precipitateness, lack of docility, carelessness, improvidence, etc. Opposed to prudence
by excess, we find the vices of over-solicitude, smartness, trickery, fraud, etc.
Opposed to justice we find the vices of injustice, irreligion, impiety, irreverence,
mendacity, ingratitude, cruelty, etc.
Opposed to fortitude we find weak spiritedness, inconsistency, impatience, etc., as
vices by defect; while we find the following as vices by excess: presumptuous
boldness, stubbornness, insensibility, etc.
Opposed to temperance by defect we find pride, lust, anger, gluttony, etc.; while we
find opposed by excess the vices of fanatical rigorousness, too great self-effacement of
self-abjection, affectation, morose and gloomy conduct, etc.
In the above scenario, cheating is the human act. Cheating is a free act
wherein the will is under the control of the doer. Wherein James action which is
cheating emerges from his will act and accompanied with the knowledge that
by doing such act his girlfriend as well as Ica will get hurt in the process.
Nevertheless, he still execute it regardless of knowing the ahead
consequences that it will hurt and destroy the life of the two girls. Voluntarism
in order to be present must have both the free will and knowledge of the doer
which is very evident in the act done by James . Therefore, cheating is the
human act which emerges from the free will, knowledge and voluntarism of the
doer which is James. In correlation of end of human act, James is the agent
who was willed to act upon his desires. He was also aware how wrongful his
actions are yet he was willing to do it anyway. His actions were motivated by
his desire to cheat, in which in return, gave him satisfaction. But all of this has
to end since James desires were met, therefore an end of an activity. In any
angle, this activity tends to end because of the fact that in any other way
around what he was doing was morally wrong. So, in the scenario, when the
affair was uncovered, it immediately ended. Thus, the goal was accomplished
and termination of the activity was established. In terms of the property of
imputability, the doer is liable for such acts or effects when the three conditions
are fulfilled: (1) the agent must be able to foresee the evil effect, (2) the agent
must be free to refrain from doing that which is the cause of the evil effect, and
(3) the agent must be morally bound not to do that which is the cause of the
evil effect. In this case, James knew that the act of cheating would definitely
torment Cams, but he still eagerly performed this act. However, James was
able to foresee the evil effect of his action. The act that he performed torment
the people he cares about including his own family and their supporters. The
moment he foresees the effects of his action, he admitted everything to Cams
and to their family. The doer conceded everything not to inflict more
disappointment and pain on those people who were involved and to those
people who got affected by their issue, but because of his guilt. In this manner,
the doer of this such act is imputed to the action that he incited towards those
individuals who were victims of his deed and voluntarily endure the blames and
the hurtful words that his supporters say about him.
Sources:
Monde, J. (2021, April 17). Jamill Issue: Jayzam Speaks About "Cheating"
Issue, Here's Statement. Philippine News.
https://philnews.ph/2021/04/17/jamill-issue-jayzam-speaksabout-cheating-
issue-heres-statement/.
INTRODUCTION
In August 2007, newspapers reported what seemed to be yet another
sad incident of fraternity violence. Cris Anthony Mendez, a twenty-year-old
student of the University of the Philippines (UP), was rushed to the hospital in
the early morning hours, unconscious, with large bruises on his chest, back,
and legs. He passed away that morning, and the subsequent autopsy report
strongly suggests that his physical injuries were most probably the result of
“hazing” (“the term colloquially used to refer to initiation rites in which
neophytes may be subjected to various forms of physical abuse). What exactly
happened remains an open question, as none of those who were with him that
night came forward to shed light on what had transpired. Needless to say, none
of them came forward to assume responsibility for the death of Cris.
No one knows just what exactly happened. No charges have been filed,
no definitive testimony has been forthcoming. But there is more to this for us
than just a criminal mystery. Pondering on the death of Cris, we may find
ourselves asking questions such as “What is the value of one’s life?” “What
exactly were the wrongs done to Cris by his so-called fraternity brothers?” or
perhaps even “Is there any good to fraternities?” These questions that concern
good and bad, right or wrong -- and these are questions concerning value --
are the kind of questions that we deal with in ethics.
VALUE
Ethics, generally speaking, is about matters such as the good thing that we
should pursue and the bad thing that we should avoid; the right ways in which
we could or should act and the wrong ways of acting. It is about what is
accepted and unacceptable in human behavior. It may involve obligations that
we are expected to fulfill, prohibitions that we are required to respect, or ideals
that we are encouraged to meet. Ethics as a subject for us to study is about
determining the grounds for the values with particular and special significance
to human life.
Recognizing the notions of good and bad, and right and wrong, are the
primary concern of ethics. In order to start, it would be useful for us to clarify
the following points.
Kinds of Valuation
We can also consider how a notion of right and wrong actions can easily
appear in a context that is not a matter of ethics. This could also be when
learning how to bake, for instance. lam told that the right thing to do would be
to mix the dry ingredients first, such as flour or sugar before bringing in any
liquids, like milk or cream this is the right thing to do in baking, but not one that
belongs to a discussion of ethics. This could also be when learning how to play
basketball. lam instructed that it is against the rules to walk more than two
steps without dribbling the ball; again, obeying this rule to not travel is
something that makes sense only in the context of the game and is not an
ethical prohibition. We derive from the Greek word techne the English words
“technique" and "technical" which are often used to refer to a proper way (or
right way) of doing things, but a technical valuation (or right and wrong
technique of doing things) may not necessarily be an ethical one as these
examples show.
One complication that can be noted is that the distinction between what
belongs to ethics and what does not is not always so clearly defined. At times,
the question of what is grave or trivial is debatable, and sometimes some of the
most heated discussions in ethics could be on the fundamental question of
whether a certain sphere of human activities belongs to this discussion. Are
clothes always just a matter of taste or would provocative clothing call for some
kind of moral judgment? Can we say that a man who verbally abuses his
girlfriend is simply showing bad manners or does this behavior deserve
stronger moral condemnation?
Our second point of clarification is on the use of the words 'ethics" and
"morals: This discussion of ethics and morals would include cognates such as
ethical, unethical, immoral, amoral, morality, and so on. As we proceed, we
should be careful particularly on the use of the word "not" when applied to the
words "moral" or “ethical" as this can be ambiguous. One might say that
cooking is not ethical, that is, the act of cooking does not belong to a
discussion of ethics; on the other hand, one might say that lying is not ethical,
but the meaning here is that the act of lying would be an unethical act.
Let us consider those two words further. The term “morals” may be used
to refer to specific beliefs or attitudes that people have or to describe acts that
people perform. Thus, it is sometimes said that an individual's personal
conduct is referred to as his morals, and if he falls short of behaving properly,
this can be described as immoral. However, we also have terms such as “moral
judgment” or “moral reasoning”, which suggests a more rational aspect. The
term “ethics” can be spoken of as the discipline of studying and understanding
ideal human and ideal ways of thinking. Thus, ethics is acknowledged as an
intellectual discipline belonging to philosophy. However, acceptable and
unacceptable behaviors are also generally described as ethical and unethical
respectively. In addition, with regard to the acceptable and unacceptable ways
of behaving in a given field, we have the term “professional ethics” (e.g. legal
ethics for the proper comportment of lawyers and other people in the legal
profession; medical ethics for doctors and nurses; and media ethics for writers
and reporters).
A moral issue is a situation that calls for moral valuation. the term issue
is often used to refer to situations that can cause a debate. To make a moral
decision, it is when we are placed in a situation and confronted by the choice of
what to do. but when one is observing to make an assessment on the chosen
behavior, the person is making a moral judgement. lastly, when we are on the
matter of choosing right over wrong, or good over bad, and considering the
complicated situation wherein we feel torn on deciding, this is called moral
dilemma.
From a number of possible actions, and there are compelling ethical reasons
for the various choices. A mother may be conflicted between wanting to feed
her hungry child, but then recognizing that it would be wrong for her to steal is
an example of moral dilemma.
REASONING
Why do we suppose that a certain way of acting is right and its opposite
wrong? The study of ethics is interested in questions like these: Why do we
decide to consider this way of acting as acceptable while that way of acting, its
opposite, is unacceptable? To put it in another way, what reasons do we give
to decide or to judge that a certain way of acting is either right or wrong?
A person’s fear of punishment or desire for reward can provide him a reason
for acting in a certain way. It is common to hear someone say: “I did not cheat
on the exam because I was afraid that I might get caught.” Or “I looked after
my father in the hospital because I wanted to get a higher allowance.” In a
certain sense, fear of punishment and desire for reward can be spoken of as
giving someone a “reason” for acting in a certain way. But the question then
would be: Is this reason good enough? That is to say, this way of thinking
seems to be a shallow way of understanding reason because it does not show
any true understanding of why cheating on an exam is wrong or why looking
after a member of my family is in itself a good thing. The promise of rewards
and the fear of punishments can certainly motivate us to act, but are not in
themselves a determinant of the rightness or wrongness of a certain way of
acting or of the good or the bad in a particular pursuit. Is it possible to find
better reasons for finding a certain way of acting either acceptable or
unacceptable?
But why do we maintain one particular principle rather than another? Why should
I maintain that I should care for fair play and that cheating is, therefore, wrong?
Returning to the case of fraternity hazing where we started this chapter, why is
it wrong to cause another person physical injury or to take another’s life? We
can maintain principles, but we can also ask what good reasons for doing so.
Such reasons may differ. So, for example what makes the death of Cris such a
tragedy? One person may say that life is sacred and God – given. Another
person may declare that human life has a priceless dignity. Still another may
put forward the idea that taking another’s life does not contribute to human
happiness but to turn to theory. A moral theory is a systematic attempt to
establish the validity of maintaining certain moral principles. Insofar as a theory
is a system of thought or of ideas, it can also be ideas, and at the same time, a
structure though which we can evaluate our reasons for valuing a certain
decision or judgement.
There are different frameworks that can make us reflect on the principles
that we maintain and thus, the decisions an judgements we make. By studying
these, we can reconsider, clarify, modify and ultimately strengthen our
principles, thereby informing better both our moral judgements and moral
decisions.
The next chapters of this book will explore different ethical frameworks
that have come down from the history of philosophy. This is not an exhaustive
list, and many worthwhile theories and thinkers have been set aside. But the
choice had been made to discuss more deeply and at greater length just a few
of the more significant and influential thinkers and ideas that have contributed
to ethical discernment.
Before turning to the ethical theories, we will spend the rest of this
chapter exploring certain notions of ethics that are commonly maintained, but
further thought on these notions will reveal that these are quite problematic.
This involve either an appeal, a particular form of authority or to a particular
way of understanding the self.
SOURCES OF AUTHORITY
Several common ways of thinking about ethics are based on the idea
that the standards of valuation are imposed by a higher authority that
commands our obedience in the following section, we will explore 3 of such
ideas: the authority of the law, the authority of one's religion and the authority
of one's culture
LAW
One point to be raised is the prohibited nature of law. The law does not
tell us what we should do; it works by constraining us from performing acts that
we should not do. To put it slightly differently, the law cannot tell us what to
pursue, only what to avoid. Would we be satisfied thinking about ethics solely
from the negative perspective of that which we may not do, disregarding the
important aspect of a good which we could and maybe even should do, even if
it were not required of us by the law?
---
Page 9
in line with this, we might find that there are certain ways of acting which are
not forbidden by the law, but are ethically questionable to us. For instance, a
company that pads its profits by refusing to give its employees benefits may do
so within the parameters of the law. The company can do so by refusing to hire
people on a permanent basis, but offering them six-month contracts.
Constrained to work under this contractual system the employees are thus
deprived not only of benefits, but also of job security. Here, no law is violated,
yet one can wonder whether there is something ethically questionable to this
business practice. The fact that one can make such a negative value judgment
of the practice where there is no violation of the law is already a hint that one
can look to something beyond the law when making our ethical valuations.
To make this point concrete, recall the story of a toddler who had been
run over by a couple of vehicles. While there were many passers-by who
witnessed what had happened, for quite a long while, no one did anything to
help. The child later died in the hospital The law does not oblige people to help
others in need, so none of these passers-by were guilty of breaking any law.
However, many people reacting to this sad news report share a sense that
those passers-by were somewhat ethically culpable in their negligence. In view
of all this, perhaps one should think of ethics in a way that does not simply
identify it with obedience to the law. Later, we shall see how the concept of law
is creatively utilized in the Deontology of Immanuel Kant in a more ethically
significant way.
RELIGION
"Love the Lord, Your God, therefore, and always heed his charge: his
statutes. decrees, and commandments." (New American Bible) This verse is
the first line of Chapter 11 of the book of Deuteronomy. It expresses a claim
that many people of a religious sensibility find appealing and immediately valid:
the idea that one is obliged to obey her God in all things. As a foundation for
ethical values, this is referred to as the divine command theory. The divinity
called God. Allah, or Supreme Being commands and one is obliged to obey her
Creator. There are persons and texts that one believes are linked to the Divine.
By listening to these figures and reading these writings, an individual discovers
how the Divine wants her to act. Further, someone maintaining a more radical
form of this theory might go beyond these instruments of divine revelation and
claim that God "spoke to her directly to instruct her what to do.
At first glance, this seems to make a lot of sense. Many of us had been
brought up with one form of religious upbringing or another so it is very
possible that there is a strong inclination in us to refer to our religious
background to back up our moral valuations. We are presented with a more-or-
less clear code of prohibitions and many of these prohibitions given by religion-
Thou shall not kill" "Thou shall not steal" and "Thou shall not commit adultery"
seem to intuitively coincide with our sense of what ethics should nightly
demand In addition, there is an advance here over the law because religion is
not simply prohibitive but it also provides Ideals to pursue. For instance, one
may be called to forgive those who
--
Page 10
sinned against him or be charitable to those who have less. Further, taking
religion as basis of ethics has the advantages of providing us with not only a
set of commands but also a Supreme Authority that can inspire and compel our
obedience in a way that nothing else can. The Divine can command absolute
obedience on one’s part as the implications of her actions involve her ultimate
destiny. Thus, we would not be surprised if we were to hear someone say,
“Ethics? It is simple. Just follow whatever your religion says.”
However, there are some problems with this. First, on the practical level,
we realize the presence of a multiplicity of religions. Each faith demands
differently from its adherents, which would apparently result in conflicting
ethical standards. For instance, certain religions have prohibitions concerning
what food may be consumed, while others do not share the same constraints.
Are we then compelled to judge others negatively given their different morality?
Are we called upon to convert them toward our own faith? How about the
problem of realizing that not everyone is devout or maintains a religious faith?
Would we be compelled to admit then that if religion is the basis of morality,
some people would simply have no moral code? Differences, however, are not
confined to being problematic of varying religious traditions. Experience
teaches us that sometimes even within one and the same faith, difference can
be a real problem. For instance, we easily imagine a number of Christians
agreeing that they should read and find their inspiration from the Bible; but we
could also easily imagine them disagreeing on which particular lines they need
to focus on. Which of the passages from the sacred Scriptures are they
supposed to follow? All of them or only some? If so, which ones? Which pastor
am I supposed to obey if I find them debating over how to interpret the
scriptures, not to mention ethical issues? The problem of difference thus
remains.
If, on the other hand, we were to accept that killing is in itself wrong,
then we acknowledge that perhaps there are standards of right and wrong that
we can refer to independently of God. But if this is the case, then we actually
do not obey a command because God commanded it, but we are looking for
those objective standards of right and wrong, to which God simply concurs.
One would not even have to think in terms of obeying God- or even believing in
Him- in order to abide by such ethical standards.
Later, we shall see one way that we can have a more subtle and yet
powerful presentation of how one’s faith may contribute to ethical thought when
we look at the Natural Law theory of Thomas Aquinas.
CULTURE
The discussion would not be complete if we were to ignore the topic of Filipino values. Early in
our upbringing, we were taught about certain valuable traits that we say are characteristics of
Filipinos, such as respect for the elderly, close family ties, a sense of hospitality, and also o
solidarity with others at times of distress. We proudly say that we value these qualities of
Filipinos. These are indeed laudable qualities, but could we simply identify ethics with the
positive valuations that we make of these qualities? We will be discussing these related
questions more thoroughly in the last chapter.
-
-
Manila: What is my culture? On one hand, let us say that my father is American
and my mother is Filipina, and I was brought up in San Diego, California, but I
am currently studying in a university in the Philippines. What am I supposed to
take as “my culture”? In an increasingly globalized world, the notion of a static
and well-defined culture gives way to greater flexibility and integration. One
result of this is to call into question an idea like cultural relativism, which only
makes sense if one could imagine a clear-cut notion of what can be defined as
my culture.
It is sometimes thought that one should not rely on any external authority to tell
oneself what the standards of moral valuation are, but should instead turn
inwards. In this section, we will look into three theories about ethics that center
on the self: subjectivism, psychological egoism, and ethical egoism.
SUBJECTIVISM
With the situation and is burdened with the need to make a decision or
judgment. From this point, subjectivism leaps to the more radical claim that the
individual is the sole determinant of what is morally good or bad, right or wrong.
A number of clichés familiar to us would echo this idea:
“No one can tell me what is right and wrong.”
“No one can tell me what is right and wrong.” In a sense, there is some
validity to this. No one can compel another to accept a certain value of
judgment if she herself does not concur with it. However, we know that this
statement cannot be taken as absolute. We realize, in many instances, that we
had maintained an idea or an opinion that further discussion reveals it as
actually erroneous. We realize that we can be mistaken and that we can be
corrected by other. Why is this not also possible applicable when we are
speaking of ethics?
“No one knows my situation better than myself.” Once again, in a sense,
there is some validity to this. This particular person who is put in a certain
situation, which calls for a decision, has knowledge of the factors that affect her
situation and decision. But to take this fact as a ground for not listening to
others is to have a mentality that imagines that one’s own situation or concern
is so personal and unique that there is no way another person can possibly
understand her and give her any meaningful advice. But does not it make
greater sense to recognize the reality that many human experiences are
common and that others may have something useful to suggest?
--
“It is good if I say that it is good.” With this line, we get to the heart of the
problem with subjectivism. The statement implies: “It is my personal
consideration of X as good that makes X good. X good on the basis of my
saying so.” The problem now becomes: “What is my basis for saying X is
good?” This renders subjectivism an untenable view for someone who is
interested in ethics. It takes the fact that I am the subject making the valuation
and uses this fact as the very basis for that valuation. But when “I,” as subject,
am asking what is right or wrong, good or bad, with subjectivism, there is no
other basis that I can look toward.
PSYCHOLOGICAL EGOISM
Let us consider another cliché. It would go like this: “Human beings are
naturally self-centered, so all our actions are always already motivated by self-
interest.”
This is the stance taken by, psychological egoism, which is a theory that
describes the underlying dynamic behind all human actions. As a descriptive
theory, it does not direct one to act in any particular way. Instead, it points out
that there is already an underlying basis for how one acts. The ego or self has
its desires and interests, an all our actions are geared toward satisfying these
interests.
But what about other types of behavior that we would commonly say are
directed toward the other? Consider, for example, an act of generosity, in
which someone helps a friend with her thesis rather than play videogames, or
someone makes use of her free Saturday helping build houses for Gawad
Kalinga? The psychological egoist would maintain that underlying such
apparently other-directed behavior is a self-serving desire, even if one does not
acknowledge it or is even conscious of it. Perhaps he only helped his friend
with her thesis because he is trying to impress her. Perhaps she helps out with
Gawad Kalinga because this is how she relieves her sense of guilt at being
well-off compared to others. The idea is that whether or not the person admits
it, one’s actions are ultimately always motivated by self-serving desire.
This theory has a couple of strong points. The first is that of simplicity.
When an idea is marked by simplicity, it has a unique appeal to it; a theory that
conveniently identifies a single basis that will somehow account for all actions
is a good example of this. The second is that of plausibility. It is plausible that
self-interest is behind a person’s actions. It is clearly the motivation behind
many of the actions one performs which are obviously self-serving: it could very
well also be the motivation behind an individual’s seemingly other-directed
actions. It is not only plausible, but also irrefutable.
--
The first question asks whether we have to accept the theory because it
happens to be irrefutable. Let us consider this analogy: A post that B has an
Oedipal complex and according to A, this translates into a desire in B to get rid
of the father figure. Then, A insists that everything about B and what he does—
his choice in music, course, favorite food—is all ultimately rooted in this
complex. Therefore, no matter what B says, A would be able to insist that even
without his acknowledging it deep down, it is this complex that drives him to act
the way he does. In this scenario, A's claim is irrefutable. But does B have to
accept it? Similarly, one could maintain, if he really wanted to, thathuman
nature is intrinsically self-interested and that human beings could not possibly
be benevolent. When they seem to be so, it is only a matter of pretense. One
could maintain that but does one have to?
ETHICAL EGOISM
Ethical egoism differs from psychological egoism in that it does not suppose all
our actions are already inevitably self-serving. Instead, ethical egoism
prescribes that we should make our own ends, our own interests, as the single
overriding concern. We may act in a way that is beneficial to others, but we
should do that only if it ultimately benefits us. This theory
--
Page 18
acknowledges that it is a dog-eat-dog world out there and given that, everyone
ought to put herself at the center. One should consider herself as the priority
and not allow any other concerns, such as the welfare of other people, to
detract from this pursuit. It is clear that we have our interests and desires and
would want them satisfied. Thus, this question can be asked: Why should I
have any concern about the interests of others? In a sense, this question
challenges in a fundamental way the idea of not just a study of ethics, but also
the effort of being ethical: Why not just look after one’s own self? To examine
ethical egoism, we will take a look into Plato’s Republic, which is Plato’s
response to the assertion that one should only care about one’s own interests.
The Myth of Gyges Plato's Republic (359c-360d) Now, that those who practice
justice do so involuntarily and because they not the power to be unjust will best
appear if we imagine something of this kind: having given both to the just and
the unjust power to do what they will, let us watch and see whither desire will
lead them; then we shall discover in the very act the just and unjust man to be
proceeding along the same road, following their interest, which all natures
deem to be their good, and are only diverted into the path of justice by the
force of law. The liberty which we are supposing may be most completely given
to them in the form of such a power as is said to have been possessed by
Gyges, the ancestor of Croesus the Lydian. According to the tradition, Gyees
was a shepherd in the service of the king of Lydia, there was a great storm,
and an earthquake made an opening in the earth at the place where he was
feeding his flock. Amazed at the sight, he descended into the opening, where,
among other marvels, he beheld a hollow brazen horse, having doors, at which
he stooping and looking in saw a dead body of stature, as appeared to him,
more than human and having nothing on but a gold ring this he took from the
finger of the dead and reascended. Now the shepherds met together,
according to custom, that they might send their monthly report about the flocks
to the king; into the assembly he came having the ring on his finger, and as he
was sitting among them he chanced to turn the collet of the ring inside his
hand, when instantly he became invisible to the rest of the company and they
began to speak of him as if he were no longer present. He was astonished at
this, and again touching the ring the turned the collet outwards and
reappeared, he made several trials of the ring, and always with the same result
— when he turned the collet inwards he became invisible, when outwards he
reappeared. Whereupon he contrived to be chosen one of the messengers
who were sent to the court; whereas as soon as he arrived, he seduced the
queen, and with her help conspired against the king and slowed him, and took
the kingdom. Suppose now that there were two such magic rings, and just put
on one of them and the unjust the other, no man can be imagined to be of such
--
an iron nature that he would stand fast injustice. No man would keep his hands
off what was not his own when he could safely take what he liked out of the
market or go into houses and lie with any one at his pleasure, or kill or release
from prison whom he would, and in all respects be like a God among men.
Then the actions of the just would be as the actions of the unjust; they would
both come at last to the same point. And this we may truly affirm to be a great
proof that a man is just not willingly or because he thinks that justice is any
good to him individually, but of necessity, for wherever anyone thinks that he
can safely be unjust, there he is unjust. For all men believe in their hearts that
injustice is far more profitable to the individual than justice, and he who argues
as I have been supposing will say! that they are right. If you could imagine any
one obtaining this power of becoming Invisible, and never doing any wrong or
touching what was another's, he would be thought by the lookers-on to be a
most wretched idiot, although they would praise him to one another's faces,
and keep up appearances with one another from a fear that they too might
suffer injustice."
It will take Socrates the rest of the ten books of the Republic to try to
answer this most important question on whether the pursuit of ethics is
worthwhile. Does it make sense to be ethical? The beginning of Socrates's
answer can be found in Book 4, in which Socrates presents how the good
human life stems from a proper harmony of the parts of the soul Harmony
requires a certain ordering, a hierarchical system in which reason as the
highest part is in charge dutifully followed by the lower parts of the soul of will
and appetite. The presence of such an internal ordering that one consciously
strives to accomplish is what it means for justice to be present in the individual.
On the other hand, the absence of order or the lack of harmony, with desires
and appetites running rampant, results in acts of injustice This point is
developed in Book 9 with the portrayal of the tyrant. The presence of internal
disorder in a person placed in power turns the seemingly pleasant prospect of
doing whatever one wants-of acting with impunity--into a terrifying portrait of a
character without self-control or self-possession. Being nothing more than a
disordered and nervous jumble of cravings, such a person would be so
obsessed with these longings than to bother
--
caring about how this might affect others. Situating this story into a larger social
and political context, the connection can be made between one’s pursuit of
one’s own interest with abuse of power that may easily result in the misery of
millions. The question then that we can ask is: Do we still want to say, in the
face of what history has shown us of tyrants and dictators, that to act with
impunity is desirable?
This is what ethical egoism ultimately translates into -- not just some
pleasant pursuit of one’s own desires, but the imposition of a will to power that
is potentially destructive of both the self and of others. One can take on this
view, if one wishes, but it is also possible to wonder whether there is a way of
recognizing our being in the world with others, of thinking of our own well-being
concomitantly with the well-being of others. Perhaps this is what the study of
ethics is all about.
In this chapter, we have established the scope and the rationale for a
discussion of ethics. We explored various of valuation in order to distinguish
what makes a particularly grave type of valuation a moral or ethical one. We
clarified some of the terms that will be used in the study of ethics; some give a
too simplistic answer to the question of our grounds or foundations for moral
valuation, while others seem to dismiss the possibility of ethics altogether.
In the final chapter, we will see how these diverse theories - which at
first glance may seem to simply be contradicting each other – can inform our
own attempts to think of our own grounds for determining moral value.
#2. Note: this topic is not given as a topic to be reported but for readings:
II. History
Situation ethics was developed by American Anglican theologian
Joseph F. Fletcher, whose book Situation Ethics: The New Morality
(1966) arose from his objections to both moral absolutism (the view
that there are fixed universal moral principles that
have binding authority in all circumstances) and moral relativism (the
view that there are no fixed moral principles at all). Fletcher based
situation ethics on the general Christian norm of brotherly love,
which is expressed in different ways in different situations. He
applied this to issues of doctrine. For example, if one holds to the
absolute wrongness of abortion, then one will never allow for
abortion, no matter what the circumstances within which the
pregnancy occurs. Fletcher held that such an absolute position pays
no attention to the complexity and uniqueness of each situation and
can result in a callous and inhumane way of dealing with the
problem. On the other hand, if there are no principles at all, then the
decision is reduced to nothing more than what one decides to do in
the moment, with no real moral implications involved. Rather,
Fletcher held, within the context of the complexities of the situation,
one should come to the most loving or right decision as to what to
do.
Various Christian sects are legalistic; for instance, some might refuse
medical help — such as blood transfusions — when someone in
their community is ill because they think it is against God’s
commands.
1. Pragmatism
Pragmatism is generally considered to be the first and only
philosophical school of thought or tradition to have emerged in North
America. The term was originated by
C.S. Peirce, who would later term his form of the new movement
"pragmaticism" in order to distinguish his ideas from those of the
most famous exponents: William James and John Dewey. G.H.
Mead and F.S.C. Schiller were lesser-known members of this
tradition in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries when it
flourished.
2. Relativism
Situation Ethics is a moral relativist theory. It mustn’t be confused
with Cultural Relativism, which says that there is no objective
morality, and moral values vary from one society to another. What is
right is relative to the situation. Some textbooks claim that there is
therefore an absolute principle in Situation Ethics
– to always love. However, Fletcher himself said that love “relativizes
the absolute, it does not absolutize the relative”. St Augustine said,
“Love, and do what you will.” Situationists believe that all things are
possible in love. One example Fletcher gives is of a married woman
in a prison camp who has an affair and gets pregnant in order to get
home to her family.
• Fletcher calls his theory ‘principled relativism’, because ‘it relativises the
absolute, it doesn’t absolutise the relative”.
• By this he means that the absolute principle of agape must be made relative
to every contingent situation in order to discover what is right.
• It is a form of relativism in application, not in the principle itself (agape) which
never changes is meaning.
3. Positivism
Positivism — using the principles of Christian love, a value
judgement has to be made. The whole of situation ethics relies upon
the fact that the person freely chooses to believe in agape love as
described by Christianity. His use of “positivism” is not the
philosophical idea with the same name but rather is where:
4. Personalism
Personalism under-covers the centrality of a person. It is any
philosophy that considers personality as the supreme value and the
key to measure reality.
“Love and justice are the same, for justice is love distributed, nothing
else.”
There can be no love without justice. Consider any injustice – a child
starving, a man arrested without charge etc. These are examples of a
lack of love. If love was properly shared out, there would be no injustice.
4. Love is not liking
□ Demands for love. Can everyone love sacrificially all the time
knowing that people have the tendency to be selfish at
times?
□ Depends on individual’s appraisal of the situation. A person,
even with the finest of intentions, cannot foresee every
consequence of an action, nor realize the number likely to
be affected by it.
□ Laws are necessary. the law and absolutes are there for
protection of society. This is the reason they exist.
VII. References
i. Rosenthal, S. B. (2017, May 26). Situation ethics. Encyclopedia
Britannica. https://www.britannica.com/topic/situation-
ethics ii. British Broadcasting Corporation. (2014). Ethics -
Introduction to ethics: Situation ethics. BBC.
http://www.bbc.co.uk/ethics/introduction/situation_1.shtml
iii. Dimmock, M., & Fisher, A. (2017). Chapter 5. Fletcher’s Situation
Ethics.
Open Book Publishers.
http://books.openedition.org/obp/4423 iv. Situational ethics.
(n.d.). In Wikipedia.
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/
Situational_eth ics
v. Advantages and Disadvantages of Situational Ethics. (2018).
Retrieved from testmyprep.com:
https://testmyprep.com/subject/philosophy/advantages -and-
disadvantages-of-s ituational-
ethics#:~:text=situations%20are%20extreme%20that%20the,is
%20 most%20beneficial%20lustrate%20it.
vi. Bailey, S. (2015, April). Strengths and weaknesses of
situational ethics. Retrieved from Cram.com:
https://www.cram.com/flashcards/strengths-and-
weaknesses-ofsituation-ethic s-5755792
vii. Julia. (2016, April 11). Situation Ethics Strengths and
Weaknesses.
Retrieved from getrevising.co.uk:
https://getrevising.co.uk/grids/situation-ethics-strengths-
andweaknesses
viii. Katie. (2013, May 3). Strengths and weaknesses of situation
ethics.
Retrieved from getrevising.co.uk:
https://getrevising.co.uk/grids/the_strengths_and_weaknesse
s_of_situ ation_et hics
ix. McHugh, P. J. (2006). Situation Ethics. Retrieved from
tere.org:
https://www.tere.org/assets/downloads/secondary/
pdf_downloads/ALev el/SitE thics.pdf
x. Goffs School AS and A2 Religious Studies. (n.d.). RS –
Philosophy &
Ethics. https://rsasa2.wordpress.com/situation-
ethics/ xi. Baghramian, M. (2020, September 15).
Moral Relativism - Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy. Retrieved from
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/relativism/#WhaRel
xii. Rachels, J. (2015, August 24). Ethical relativism.
Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/topic/ethicalrelativism
xiii. Velasquez, M., Andre, C., Shanks, T., S.J., & Meyer, M. J.
(1992,
August 1). Ethical Relativism - Markkula Center for Applied
Ethics. Retrieved from https://www.scu.edu/ethics/ethics-
resources/ethicaldecision-making/ethical-re lativism/
xiv. Dewey, J. & Tufts, J.H. Ethics. 1922
xv. Joseph Fletcher, Naturalism, situation ethics and value
theory, in Ethics at the Crossroads, 1995 xvi.
Pragmatist Ethic. (n.d.). Qcc.Cuny.Edu. Retrieved
May 10,
2021, from
http://www.saint-andre.com/ismbook/P.html xvii.
LaFollette, H. (n.d.). Pragmatist Ethic. Qcc.Cuny.Edu.
Retrieved May 10, 2021, from
http://www.etsu.edu/philos/faculty/hugh/pragmati.htm
xviii. Williams, T. D., & Bengtsson, J. O. (2009). Personalism.
xix. Rourke, T. R., & Rourke, R. A. (2006). A theory of
personalism. Lexington Books.
xx. Lavely, J. H. (1991, October). What is personalism?. In The
Personalist Forum (Vol. 7, No. 2, pp. 1-33). University of
Illinois Press.
xxi. Veino, K. "Situation ethics". The American Heritage
Dictionary of the
English Language Fourth Edition (2000) xxii. Hampton,
Charles Allen, "Studies in Situation Ethics" (1968). Honors Theses.
301. http://scholarlycommons.obu.edu/honors_theses/301
xxiii. Situation ethics. (n.d.). RS - Philosophy & Ethics. Retrieved May 10,
2021, from https://rsasa2.wordpress.com/situation-
ethics/ xxiv. Situation ethics. (n.d.). Psychology Wiki.
Retrieved May 10,
2021, from https://psychology.wikia.org/wiki/Situation_ethics
xxv. Revision World Networks Ltd. (n.d.). Situation Ethics |
Revision World. Retrieved May 7, 2021, from
https://revisionworld.com/a2-level-level-revision/religious-
studies-levelrevisi on/ethics/situation-ethics
xxvi. Situational Ethics. (2019, November 4). New World
Encyclopedia, . Retrieved 14:22, May 9, 2021 from
https://www.newworldencyclopedia.org/p/index.php?
title=Situational_E thics &oldid=1026838.
xxvii. Situation Ethics Aspects of Theory.
situation_ethics_aspects_of_theory.pdf. (n.d.).
http://www.rsrevision.com/Alevel/ethics/revision/situation_ethics
_aspect s_of_ theory.pdf.
xxviii. Peped Follow. (2015, November 7). Situation ethics ppt.
SlideShare.
https://www.slideshare.net/PhilosophicalInvestigations/situati
on-ethicsppt-54 853070.
PRAGMATISM
ETHICS
ASSIGNMENT #
7
GROUP 2
Submitted by:
II. Nature
According to pragmatism,
A. Biological Pragmatism
A human being's power or capacity is valuable and
important when he or she can adapt well to any environment
based on his or her needs and requirements. John Dewey's
experimentalism is established on biological pragmatism, which
holds that the ultimate goal of all knowledge is to bring man into
harmony with his environment. Education fosters social skills that
improve one's quality of life. The school is a reflection of the
society that prepares children for future life.
B. Nominalistic Pragmatism
When we experiment, we pay close attention to the
outcome or the result. Our goal is to examine the material. Every
experiment is preceded by a hypothesis about the results. The
results of an experiment, according to nominalistic pragmatism,
are always specific and concrete, never general and abstract.
C. Humanistic Pragmatism
This type of pragmatism is particularly found in social
sciences. According to it, the satisfaction of human nature is the
criterion of utility. In philosophy, in religion, and even in science
man is the aim of all thinking and everything else is a means to
achieve human satisfaction. Humanist pragmatism is centered on
the idea that we live in a world that we shape and create, a world
in the making.
D. Experimental Pragmatism
Modern science is based upon the experimental method.
The fact that can be ascertained by experiment is true. No truth is
final, truth is known only to the extent it is useful in practice. The
pragmatists use this criterion of truth in every field of life. Human
problems can be solved only through experiments.
IV. Definition
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-02441-3_2
Nikita Iyer (2016) Pragmatism: Meaning, Forms and Aims. Retrieved 10 May
2021, from https://www.yourarticlelibrary.com/philosophy/pragmatism -
meaning-forms-andaims/848 22
Pragmatism - By Branch / Doctrine - The Basics of Philosophy. (2021).
Retrieved 10 May 2021, from
https://www.philosophybasics.com/branch_pragmatism.html
Born: February
21, 1921
Baltimore,
Maryland
Died: November 24, 2002 (aged
81) Lexington, Massachusetts
Rawls was the second of five children of William Lee Rawls and Anna Abell
Stump. After attending an Episcopalian preparatory school, Kent School, in
Connecticut, he entered Princeton University, where he earned a bachelor’s
degree in 1943. He enlisted in the army later that year and served with the
infantry in the South Pacific until his discharge in 1945. He returned to
Princeton in 1946 and earned a Ph.D. in moral philosophy in 1950. He taught
at Princeton (1950–52), Cornell University (1953–59), the Massachusetts
Institute of Technology (1960–62), and finally Harvard University, where he
was appointed James Bryant Conant University Professor in 1979.
THEORY OF JUSTICE: THE ORIGINAL POSITION
The veil of ignorance acts as a leavening agent. It conceals anything that might
differentiate one person from another. It removes one's personality and
awareness of their circumstances, but not egoistic interests. All is eliminated
except the parties' shared disinterest and reasonable self-interest, and it is
from this situation of sharply diminished personhood, where the person is
reduced to ego and reasoning ability, that justice concepts emerge, embodying
the values of empathy, community, and human dignity. The reader may think
this is an example of irony or paradox, since it is certainly not what one might
predict from such a situation at first glance.
Another consequence of the erasure of personality in the veil of ignorance is
that people become similar to one another, right down to their thought process
and assumptions. Since Rawls' theory requires a unanimous contract as a
starting point, this similarity is part of the point of the veil. In the original
location, there are no conflicts of interest, and unanimity is unavoidable. As a
result,
they might as well be one person rather than a group of people who are all the
same. "Each is convinced by the same arguments," Rawls writes, and, as a
result, each participant in the original position inevitably has the opinion of all
the others.
“Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive basic liberty
compatible with a similar liberty for others” (Rawls, 2006, p.63).
The principle of equal liberty is the first principle of justice to be derived
from the original position. It notes that all people have an equal right to
fundamental freedoms, which include freedom of conscience, religion, speech,
affiliation, and democratic rights.
In addition, Rawls stated that the right to personal property is considered
one of the basic liberties that individuals should have, and that the government
cannot infringe or amend such properties. However, he did not include an
absolute right to unrestricted personal property as one of the liberties that
people can enjoy.
Rawls takes a step forward by enabling each person to partake in
activities as long as they do not infringe the rights of others.
2. Principle of Equality
Rawls’s negative thesis starts with the idea that citizens do not deserve
to be born into a rich or a poor family, to be born naturally more or less gifted
than others, to be born female or male, to be born a member of a particular
racial group, and so on. Since these features of persons are morally arbitrary in
this sense, citizens are not entitled to more of the benefits of social cooperation
simply because of them. For example, the fact that a citizen was born rich,
white, and male provides no reason in itself for this citizen to be favored by
social institutions.
This negative thesis does not say how social goods should be
distributed; it merely clears the decks. Rawls’s positive distributive thesis is
equality-based reciprocity. All social goods are to be distributed equally, unless
an unequal distribution would be to everyone’s advantage. The guiding idea is
that since citizens are fundamentally equal, reasoning about justice should
begin from a presumption that cooperatively-produced goods should be equally
divided. Justice then requires that any inequalities must benefit all citizens, and
particularly must benefit those who will have the least. Equality sets the
baseline; from there any inequalities must improve everyone’s situation, and
especially the situation of the worst-off. These strong requirements of equality
and reciprocal advantage are hallmarks of Rawls’s theory of justice.
JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS
References: