Reflections On Violence
Reflections On Violence
Reflections On Violence
Humanitarianism
Talal Asad
In Sources of the Self, Charles Taylor traces the sensibilities that are
central to the modern individual to their Christian (especially Protestant)
roots. Prominent among them is universal benevolence, a virtue closely
connected with a new concern with psychological interiority:
One thing the Enlightenment has bequeathed to us is a moral impera-
tive to reduce suffering. This is not just a sensitivity to suffering, a
greater squeamishness about inflicting it or witnessing it. It is true
that this undoubtedly has occurred, as we can see it in a host of ways,
especially in the softening of penal codes which the Enlightenment
helped bring about, partly under the influence of Beccaria and Ben-
tham. But beyond this, we feel called upon to relieve suffering, to put
an end to it. . .. We routinely grumble about our lack of concern and
note disapprovingly that it requires often spectacular television cover-
age of some disaster to awaken the world’s conscience. But this very
critique supposes certain standards of universal concern. It is these
that are deeply anchored in our moral culture.!
It is this moral culture, it is suggested, that provides the motivation for
varieties of humanitarian action in the modern world, including interna-
tional rules for military engagement, the forcible ending of state-led atroc-
My thanks to the following friends for comments on earlier versions of this piece: Hussein
Agrama, Gil Anidjar, Ayca Cubukeu, Abou Farman, Charles Hirschkind, Mahmood Mamdani,
Nate Roberts, and Anne Stoler. Unless otherwise noted, all translations are my own.
L. Charles Taylor, Sources of the Self: The Making
of Modern Identity (Cambridge, Mass.,
1981), p. 394
Critcal Inquiry 41 (Winter 2015)
© 2015 by The University of Chicago. 0093-1896/14/4102-0003810.00. All rights reserved.
390
2. However, as Uday Mehta has pointed out in his interpretation of Mahatma Gandhi’s
political practice, violence used by the state in pursuit of reformist idealism in peace may not be
as dramatically evident as war is, yet in both there is the destruction of human lives
accompanied by a rhetoric of noble ends. Mehta sees Gandhi’s concept of nonviolence (ahinnsa)
not simply as the principle of abstention from violence but as a sustained spiritual project: the
care for the self that involves entering into the experience of violence as a precondition for
willing abstention from it. In that way, says Mehta, Gandhi sought to break entirely with the
West's conception of war (violence) and peace (the absence of violence) as absolute opposites;
see Uday Singh Mehta, “Gandhi and the Common Logic of War and Peace,” Raritan (Summer
2010): 134-56.
3. See Lynn Hunt, Inventing Human Rights: A History (New York, 2007).
4. See Steven Pinker, The Better Angels of Our Nature (New York, 2011).
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM.
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditon:
392 Talal Asad / Reflections on Humanitarianism
5. See Norbert Elias, The Civilizing Process: Sociogenetic and Psychogenetic Investigations
(Malden, Mass., 2000).
6. For an important account of the violence inflicted on young African Americans before,
during, and after their imprisonment, see Michelle Alexander, The New Jin Crow: Mass
Incarceration in the Age of Colorblindness (New York, 2010).
7. See James Q. Whitman, Harsh Justice: Criminal Punishment
and the Widening Divide
between America and Europe (New York, 2003) and “What Happened to Tocqueville’s
America?” Social Research 74 (Summer 2007): 254.
8. One might add to this difference from Europe another: the presence in the US of private
prisons whose interests are represented in Congress by paid lobbyists who are able to influence
legislation in a way that increases the scope of criminal behavior. That legislation increases the
number of felons whose incarceration in the private prison system increases the latter's
profitability.
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM.
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditon:
Critical Inquiry / Winter 2015 393
In sum, it may not be the benevolent values of “our moral culture” that
matter but the contrary work done by legal disciplines and political struc-
tures. Whitman’s overall explanation seems to me persuasive, although
some might ask why penal ferocity didn’t make itself evident in the earlier
period of America’s history when, according to Whitman, criminal justice
was less violent. The answer, perhaps, is that the major objects of punitive
violence in that period were slaves and Indians, two classes of people who
were regarded not only as a danger to settler freedom but also as an obsta-
cle to the growth and flourishing of civilization itself. Liberal democracies
may not now use violence against one another, as Pinker and others have
maintained, but that doesn’t prevent their populations from using vio-
lence against their own “minorities” (African Americans, East Asians, La-
tinos, and Native Americans) as well as—directly or by proxy—other
states.”
The Enlightenment varied, of course, from one country to another, and
it included religious as well as secular currents; it was also internally con-
tradictory.” This should alert one to the possibility that what the modern
world has inherited from the Enlightenment is not simply the moral stan-
dard that universal suffering should be reduced but a complex genealogy
that is partly older than the eighteenth century in which compassion and
benevolence are intertwined with violence and cruelty, an intertwining
that is not merely a coexistence of the two but a mutual dependence of each
on the other. In this context one might recall Michel Foucault’s observa-
tion that sadism was publicly recognized, theorized, and practiced in the
Enlightenment." Indeed, many writers in the eighteenth century sought to
describe and explain the “natural” attraction to horror that they believed
was a general human condition.* Perhaps Edmund Burke’s account of the
9. See Aziz Rana, The Two Faces of American Freedom (Cambridge, Mass., 2010), an
impressive study that traces the imperial conquest of Indian territory (the appropriation of land
as property) and, more broadly, the shifting connections made, violently, between freedom
(self-rule and equality among citizens) and unfrecdom (the exclusion and subjection of alien
peoples) in US history.
10. Some of the Enlightenment’s diversity is reflected in What Is Enlightenment? Eighteenth-
Century Answers and Twentieth-Century Questions, ed. James Schmidt (Berkeley, 1996).
11.” See Michel Foucault, Histoire de la folie Idge dlassique (Paris, 1972), p. 381.
12. The Earl of Shaftesbury, writing of what he calls unnatural affections, speaks of “that
unnatural and inhuman delight in beholding torments, and in viewing distress, calamity, blood,
massacre and destruction, with a peculiar joy and pleasure.” Such passions, he says, are found
among many—those who are uncivilized or those who, “in some degree, belong to such
tempers as have thrown off that courteousness of behavior which retains in us a just reverence
of mankind, and prevents the growth of harshness and brutality” (Anthony Ashley Cooper, An
Inquiry Concerning Virtue or Merit [Heidelberg, 1904], p. 108). These passions are therefore
“unnatural” in the sense that they have not been disciplined by sentiments that lead men either
to public or to private good.
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM.
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditon:
394 Talal Asad / Reflections on Humanitarianism
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM.
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditon:
Critical Inquiry / Winter 2015 395
15. John M. Headley, The Europeanization of the World: On the Origins of Human Rights
and Democracy (Princeton, N.J., 2008), p. 2.
16. See Richard Tuck, “Scepticism and Toleration in the Seventeenth Century,” in
Justifying Toleration: Conceptual and Historical Perspectives, ed. Susan Mendus (New York,
1988), pp. 21-36.
17. Sce Headley, The Europeanization of the World, p. 1s.
18. See Tuck, “Scepticism and Toleration in the Seventeenth Century,” pp. 33-3s.
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM.
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditon:
396 Talal Asad / Reflections on Humanitarianism
Renaissance theories of natural law and then tells how they were reformu-
lated in the articulation of state law and individual morality on the one
hand and international law and war on the other.” Humanitarianism be-
came inextricably linked to these complex developments of the law.
Despite the discursive connections among humanism, humanity, and
humanitarianism since the European Renaissance, their significance has
differed greatly over time. We know that one of the sources of the concept
of humanism in the nineteenth century was the growth of German philo-
logical and archeological studies. Humanismus (humanism) was the new
word that referred to the new educational system based not simply on
Greek and Latin but more generally on a romantic vision of Hellenism as
the project of a rational European future. In mid-nineteenth-century Eng-
land, on the other hand, humanism became part of a discourse of secular
rationalism and scientific positivism, indicating freedom from supersti-
tion and blind tradition on one side and a perceived threat to the authority
of the church on the other. It was in nineteenth-century elite education
that humanism (as word and concept) found its celebrated liberal values—
the autonomous individual, the private self, and a public world of law and
political order. Not only was classical Greece (as recovered by humanism)
regarded as an origin of European civilization, but it was also viewed as
containing the seeds of Europe’s enlightened future. The “genius” of Re-
naissance Italy closed the “dark” Christian Middle Ages and anticipated
what was subsequently described as the freedom and toleration of secular
life—although looked at closely, what preoccupied the fifteenth- and
sixteenth-century humanists was not a liberated future but a rediscovered
Hellenic past. The private self, so valued in liberalism, was not part of the
humanist’s world. And yet it is precisely the idea of human experience that
emerges among nineteenth-century English authors to refer to the lives of
individuals belonging to different classes and times, an experience con-
trasted with the stylized epics and ritual drama of the Middle Ages. A
secularized human experience became a way of talking about the essence
of humanity (the object of humanist study), an essence at once universal
and historical. But behind an awareness of the infinitely varied conditions
of ordinary men and women throughout the globe hovered the metaphys-
ical notion of Man—as in the Rights of Man. Yet this too was an entirely
modern conception; for fifteenth- and sixteenth-century humanists Man
(humanity) had neither innate rights nor innate dignity—nor, for that
19. See Tuck, Natural Rights Theories: Their Origin and Development (New York, 1979) and
The Rights of War and Peace: Political Thought and the International Order from Grotius to Kant
(New York, 1999).
20. See Arthur O. Lovejoy, The Great Chain of Being (Cambridge, Mass., 1964).
21. See also Margaret T. Hodgen, Early Anthropology in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth
Centuries (Philadelphia, 1964).
22, Jonathan Riley-Smith, “Crusading
as an Act of Love,” History 65 (June 1980): 185.
23. See Headley, The Europeanization of the World, for the suggestion that the modern
concept of equality is simply a secularization of Christian notions.
24. Tzvetan Todorov, The Conquest of America: The Question of the Other, trans. Richard
Howard (New York, 1984), p. 177.
25. In his wonderful study, Beyond Church and State: Democracy, Secularism, and
Conversion (Cambridge, 2013), Matthew Scherer has used the trope of conversion to understand
secularism.
26. Hodgen's Early Anthropology in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries deals with this
subject in splendid detail.
27. Nathaniel Roberts has argued that conversion should not be seen as the “colonization
of consciousness” because that presupposes an authentic consciousness always available to be
colonized, although in fact consciousness is a discursive product of liberal history. He asks why
conversion seems particularly problematic for liberal ethics and points in answer to its
conception of the human subject as essentially characterized by moral autonomy and freedom.
See Nathaniel Roberts, “Is Conversion a ‘Colonization of Consciousness'?” Anthropological
Theory 12 (Sept. 2012): 271.
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM.
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditon:
400 Talal Asad / Reflections on Humanitarianism
28. Lynn Festa, Sentimental Figures of Empire in Eighteenth-Century Britain and France
(Baltimore, 2006), p. 3.
29. Sceibid., p. 7. See also Festa, “Sentimental Visions of Empire in Eighteenth-Century
Studics,” Literature Compass 6 (Jan. 2009): 23-55.
30. See Rupa Viswanath, “The Emergence of Authenticity Talk and the Giving of Accounts:
Conversion as Movement of the Soul in South India, ca. 1900,” Comparative Studies in Society
and History 55 (Jan. 2013): 120-41. Viswanath argues that the emergence in South India of the
so-called modern self (thought to be capable of narrativizing ts authentic convictions) needs to
be set within the context of conversion in which the discourse of sincerity was required only of
outcast agricultural laborers and not of upper caste Hindus.
31 Feeling may be mobilized tactically to support particular causes; see Norman S. Fiering,
“Irresistable Compassion: An Aspect of Eighteenth-Century Sympathy and Humanitarianism,”
Journal of the History of Ideas (Apr. 197
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM.
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditon:
Critical Inquiry / Winter 2015 401
losing oneself in another’s misery might be regarded as amounting to the
displacement of reason. But the sharp theoretical opposition between rights
and emotions always breaks down because of the interconnections between
the two in practice; they each feed off and seek to control the other.* It was
partly the volatility and unreliability of emotions, of feelings of sociability, that
led Immanuel Kant to abandon Europe’s eighteenth-century ethical theory
based on sentimentalism and to adopt instead one based on the supposed
neutrality of law. Because for Kant moral behavior presupposes the autono-
mous subject’s ability to judge and to act according to transcendent rules, it
required a very different kind of theory in which concepts of right and duty
replace ideas of sentiment.® That aspect of Kantianism, with its rights talk, has
become the foundation for humanitarian law.
As word, concept, and practice, humanitarianism emerged in the nine-
teenth century with the consolidation of European nation-states, the ex-
pansion of European colonial empires, and the global development of
capitalism. Yet the first usage of the words humanitarian and humanitar-
ianism was theological; they were expressions by which the orthodox ma-
jority referred disapprovingly to Christians who subscribed to the
exclusively human nature of Jesus.* One derived application was its refer-
ence to those, like the nineteenth-century socialist Pierre Leroux, who
professed the “Religion of Humanity.” The word humanitarian thus car-
32. This in part is the argument in William M. Reddy, “Sentimentalism and Its Erasure:
The Role of Emotions in the Era of the French Revolution,” Journal of Modern History 72 (Mar.
2000): 109-52. Reddy proposes that emotives (expressions that affect internal emotions) are a
third category between performatives (statements that bring something about legally or
socially) and constatives (indicative statements), popularized in anthropology through a
particular reading of J. L. Austin, How to Do Things with Words (New York, 1976). But Austin’s
book begins by expressing his dissatisfaction with the simple distinction between the latter two
as alternatives and elaborates instead a more sophisticated conceptualization of what words do
through simultaneous locution, illocution, and perlocution. Employing these three concepts
critically — that is, through his notion of emotives — instead of remaining with the original
constative/performative binary would have allowed Reddy to highlight the fragile character of
rights based on rational principles. The exercise of the citizen’s right in liberal democracies to
elect his president is widely criticized for being deeply affected by highly emotional
(“irrational”) media campaigns. But the right is no less of a right for that
33. Fora brief discussion of Kant's problem with making sympathy the basis of morality,
see Samuel Moyn, “Empathy in History, Empathizing with Humanity,” review of The Fragility
of Empathy after the Holocaust by Carolyn J. Dean and History in Transit: Experience, Identity,
and Critical Theory by Dominick LaCapra, History and Theory 45 (Oct. 2006): 397-415, and
Dabney Townsend, “From Shaftesbury to Kant: The Development of the Concept of Aesthetic
Experience,” Journal of the History of Ideas 48 (Apr. 1987): 287-305.
34. See Oxford English Dictionary, s.v., “humanitarian.”
35. See Louis Pierre Leroux, “Pierre Leroux’s Doctrine of Humanity,” Fortnightly Review, 1
Mar. 1872, pp. 324-31. And on his connection of aesthetics to politics, see Warren Breckman,
“Politics in a Symbolic Key: Pierre Leroux, Romantic Socialism, and the Schelling Affair,”
Modern Intellectual History 2 (Apr. 2005): 61-86.
way or another, with the result that they can easily become entangled
with US interventions in the South.»*
In what follows I focus on military humanitarianism. I stress that this
form is not a “perversion” of genuine humanitarianism, such as MSF, but
another articulation of impulses and contradictions in the initiatives un-
dertaken by and for human beings. As I have been arguing in this essay, the
exercise of violence is intrinsic to the modern concept of the human. In
military humanitarianism violence serves at once as defense (as in war)
and as punishment (as in criminal justice).
Gary Bass focuses on nineteenth-century Europe in his history of hu-
manitarian intervention. He is aware that this period also happens to be
the highpoint of European imperialism but warns against confusing hu-
manitarianism with it: “Imperialism is about domination and superiority,
not the empathy of humanitarianism. . . . Humanitarians do not want to
govern other people, let alone the world; they, at their best, just want to
resist atrocity.Ӵ Bass, like many others, links a new Euro-American sen-
sitivity to atrocities in foreign lands to the growth of liberties and demo-
cratic politics at home:
As domestic liberalism grew up in Britain, the United States, and, to
some extent, France, the governments there found their foreign policy
being pushed by their own homegrown freedoms: above all the power
of a newly unshackled free press that could report on foreign atroci-
ties; and then a free society that could react with horror at those
atrocities, and politicians inside and outside the government jockey-
ing for political power by trying to capture that public passion.*®
36 Thus in 2004 MSF decided to leave Afghanistan and issued a bitter denunciation of US
strategy there, saying that it had worked in the country for almost a quarter of a century—right
through the Taliban interregnum—and never encountered such danger from the warring sides:
‘The violence directed against humanitarian aid workers has come in a context in which the
US backed coalition has consistently sought to use humanitarian aid to build support for its
‘military and political ambitions. MSF denounces the coalition’s attempts to co-opt human-
itarian aid and use it to ‘win hearts and minds.". .. Only recently ... MSF publicly con-
demned the distribution of leaflets by the coalition forces in southern Afghanistan in which
the population was informed that providing information about the Taliban and al Qaeda
was necessary if they wanted the delivery of aid to continue. [Médecins sans Frontieres,
“MSE Pulls Out of Afghanistan,” 28 July 2004, www.msf.org/article/msf-pulls-out-afghanistan;
emphasis added]
Whether these leaflets were intended as a threat or as a plea for assistance s difficult to
determine.
37. Gary Bass, Freedom’s Battle: The Origins of Humanitarian Intervention (New York,
2008), . 379.
38. Ibid., p. 6.
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM.
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditon:
Critical Inquiry / Winter 2015 405
jects, so ““Christianity” was replaced in the final version by the word “‘hu-
manity.””* Whatever the motive behind this verbal change, what we have
here is the translation of a particular into a universal: The moral content
given to the term humanity as the synonym for Christianity reveals the
assumption that whereas actual human beings are finite and particular—
Turkish killers, Armenian victims, say—international law remains univer-
sal, a site that transcends differences between Christians and others. It is
the ambiguous sense of humanity that gives it a degree of plausibility in
this context. In order to reconcile the opposition between universal law
and particular incidents of violence it was necessary to place humanity (at
once an abstract class and a compassionate attitude) as a mediator between
the two—between the right of sovereign individuals to life and security
and the right of sovereign states to use violence.
This brings up the question of how the political community is imagined
by humanitarianism. Bass does not clarify who deserves empathy and why:
Victims, because they suffer death and destruction? Or perpetrators, be-
cause they believe they confront internal enemies who threaten the conti-
nuity of their collective existence? Michael Walzer writes that:
The commitment to continuity across generations is a very powerful
feature of human life, and it is embodied in the community. When
our community is threatened, not just in its present territorial exten-
sion or governmental structure or prestige or honor, but in what we
might think of as its ongoingness, then we face a loss that is greater
than any we can imagine, except for the destruction of humanity it-
self. We face moral as well as physical extinction, the end of a way of
life as well as a set of particular lives, the disappearance of a people
like us. And it is then that we may be driven to break through the
moral limits that people like us normally attend to and respect.*
Walzer articulates a familiar liberal paradox: on the one hand, a strict
recognition of moral limits to what one may do to others; on the other
hand, a justification for doing anything, using any kind and degree of
violence (so long as it works), if collective ongoingness is seen to be threat-
ened. This prompts the following question: Do the acts to found and pre-
41. “The declaration originated in the Russian foreign office and was only reluctantly
subscribed to by Sir Edward Grey. The French government saw to it that the originally
proposed phrase, ‘crime against Christianity and civilization,’ was replaced by ‘crime against
humanity and civilization,” in order to spare the feelings of the Moslem population in the
French colonies” (Ulrich Trumpener, Germany and the Ottoman Empire, 1914-1918 [Princeton,
N.J,,1968], p. 210 n. 26).
42. Michael Walzer, Arguing about War (New Haven, Conn., 2004), p. 43.
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM.
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditon:
406 Talal Asad / Reflections on Humanitarianism
43. na striking thought, Stephen Greenblatt suggests that what modernization theorists
celebrate as the universalizing of empathy (putting oneself in the other person’s place) William
Shakespeare calls lago, that the idea shared by the abstract process of modernization and the
theatrical figure is improvisation: “the ability both to capitalize on the unforescen and to
transform given materials into one’s own scenario” (Stephen Greenblatt, Renaissance Self-
Fashioning |Chicago, 1980], p. 227).
4. Sce Colonel C. E. Callwell, Small Wars: Their Principles and Practice (1896; Lincoln,
Nebr.,1996), and United States Marine Corps, Small Arms Manual (1940; New York, 2009).
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM.
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditon:
Critical Inquiry / Winter 2015 407
manitarian dimension: converting the barbarians to the freedom and progress
that their humanity demands, and when that is not possible then eliminating
them because of their inhumanity. The occupying army’s project is the resto-
ration of stability and legitimacy in what the handbook always calls the “Host
Nation”: “Military action can address the symptoms of a loss of legitimacy,”
the handbook states. “In some cases, it can eliminate substantial numbers of
insurgents. However, success in the form of @ durable peace requires restoring
legitimacy, which, in turn, requires the use of all instruments of national
power. A COIN [counterinsurgency] effort cannot achieve lasting success
without the HN [Host Nation] government achieving legitimacy.” In other
words, the conversion of an entire society is the means of according it legiti-
macy, whose loss, incidentally, is signaled not by the US invasion but by resis-
tance to it. The paradox is that for a government to “host” a foreign army it
must already be legitimate and sovereign, and yet that army’s mandate is to
restore the legitimacy and sovereigntyof a “failed state.” The interesting lesson
this paradox teaches is that sovereignty is much more than the affirmation of
state rights within the Westphalian system; in its negative form sovereignty is
also part of a strategy for military intervention in other states, especially on
humanitarian grounds.
A Note on Juridification
Colonialism has long ended, but the United Nations has recently justified
military intervention into ex-colonial countries for humanitarian purposes by
adopting a new legal norm known as the responsibility to protect. Its support-
ers stress that the norm underwrites a duty to protect and not a right to inter-
vene. Critics worried by the license this might give the Great Powers to violate
the sovereignty of vulnerable states are assured that this would happen only in
exceptional cases and as a last resort—after it was clear that the state in ques-
tion was not really sovereign because it was unable to perform the primary
function of sovereign authority: the ability to control its entire national terri-
tory and to protect its national population. This definition of sovereignty as
effective power opens up the possibility of using violence legitimately by other
political agents who can claim competence and/or justice. This means that
sovereignty may be challenged by humanitarian military intervention from
outside even as militants and terrorists from inside challenge it.*
45. Department of the Army, U.S. Army Counterinsurgency Handbook (New York, 2007),
1.22; my emphasis.
46. In his intriguing article “Le Souverain, humanitaire et le terrorist,” Vacarme 34 (Jan.
2005), www.vacarme.org/article48s.html, Adi Ophir identifies the humanitarian and the
terrorist as two new actors who challenge the sovereignty of states. But strictly speaking this
applies only to the military humanitarian.
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM.
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditon:
408 Talal Asad / Reflections on Humanitarianism
But the connection between the duty to protect human life and the
human right to life is not self-evident. While the right is regarded as uni-
versal, belonging to every human, not everyone is expected to step forward
to defend it—or can do so. So whose responsibility is it to protect? This
question was easier to answer in colonial times: the rulers of empire de-
cided because they had the power to do so. During decolonization, how-
ever, the claim to sovereignty against the occupying power, and therefore
to the right to use violence legitimately, was made on moral-legal grounds.
According to the UN charter, where a state was entitled lawfully to occupy
foreign territory, or an international organization to administer a terri-
tory, this was authorized for a limited time and purpose. In other words,
nothing was to be done to contravene existing sovereign rights in that
territory. The responsibility to protect is significantly different. It assumes
that the rights of sovereignty are based on the de facto ability to control its
territory and provide effective protection to its entire population. In the
absence of this function the claim to sovereignty is itself undermined and
the obligation to carry out the state’s basic functions devolve automatically
on the international community (on the Euro-American powers). “This
de facto grounding of authority,” writes Ann Orford, “marginalises the
more familiar claims to authority grounded on right, whether that right be
understood in historical, universal or democratic terms.” The claim to
the right to use sovereign violence by nationalist rebels against colonial
authority, or by revolutionaries against an oppressive ancien régime, is
now accorded to external powers who are expected to perform their hu-
manitarian duty—but without giving them all other rights of sovereignty.
It is partly for this reason that the external powers are not hampered by any
responsibility for the consequences of their military intervention. The mo-
tive for the new norm is thus founded on compassion as an ethical prin-
ciple, but its application lies in a domain that excludes ethics in favor of
pragmatism (what is doable). Besides, there is no legal requirement to
justify publicly what is actually doable and what is not, and why—hence
the accusations by critics of hypocrisy and double standards. But these
criticisms miss their target because they presume that the modern nation-
state should behave in ways it cannot. It is in the nature of the modern
nation-state to act rationally and objectively, without passion or compas-
sion in its own interests, precisely because it is not a human subject. Thus,
unlike individual human beings, the nation-state cannot sacrifice itself for
a transcendent ideal.
47, Anne Orford, International Authority and the Responsibility to Protect (New York, 20m),
p.16.
48. Michal Byers, “Alleged War Criminals,” London Review of Books, 22 July 2004, p. 31;
hereafter abbreviated “AWC.”
49. “Even trials in absentia,” writes Byers, “can be subject to political pressure: in Brussels,
an investigative prosecutor had to abandon an attempt to try Sharon last year after the Belgian
government succumbed to Isracli and American pressure to modify the legislation on the basis
of which the prosecution was taking place” (“AWC,” pp. 30-31).
50. “The United States has legislation that provides the president with the authority to use
‘military force to secure the release of any American serviceman detained by the International
Criminal Court, in the form of a statute popularly known as ‘The Hague Invasion Act”
(“AWC,” p. 30).
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM.
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditon:
410 Talal Asad / Reflections on Humanitarianism
51 See Scott Veitch, Law and Irresponsibility: On the Legitimation of Human Suffering (New
York, 2007), esp. chaps. 3-4.
On Inhumane Killing
What exactly is the metaphysical conception of life? Clearly the word
itself is used in many senses: social and public life, mode of life, life sen-
tence, the principle of vitality, the divine gift of eternal life. But its central-
ity for the concept of humanity requires further consideration.’* One way
of approaching this question is to explore the feelings evoked by the killing
of human life as opposed to the slaughter of animals for food.
I argued earlier that humanitarian interventionism is not satisfactorily
explained by increasingly refined sensibilities (Taylor) or by the emergence
of democratic politics (Bass).”* What gives it its moral force is horror at the
violation of human life. But what precisely does the horror consist of? In
posing this question I am not interested in the well-known fact that the
media select and present acts of violence by legitimizing some sentiments
and intensifying others, but in the concepts that underpin the way horror
is produced as a response and that make it effective.
The horrific nature of the slaughter of “innocent” human beings is
deeply implanted in the social imaginary of modern Euro-Americans as
barbaric and savage—as morally intolerable to civilized sensibilities. It is
this sensibility that also fuels the cause of military intervention (“we can-
52. Gil Anidjar, “The Meaning of Life,” Critical Inquiry 37 (Summer 2o1): 697723, deals
with the ambiguity of life, and it was this that provoked me to think further about its relevance
for the argument of my essay.
53. When and how people are emotionally affected by the perpetration of cruelties on
helpless victims in distant places is a complicated matter. The scale of losses is obviously
central. Thus there was no popular revulsion at the fact that American troops on a
humanitarian mission in Somalia may have massacred up to 10,000 persons (including
civilians) while losing only thirty-four soldiers; sce Charles W. Maynes, “Relearning
Intervention,” Foreign Policy 98 (Spring 1995): 96, 98. The disaster inflicted on Iraqi civilians
after the US invasion in 2003, retrospectively described by many of ts supporters as
humanitarian, has been even greater, and the expressions of horror in Euro-America very
minor. On the other hand, the considerable American military losses in Vietnam, the fact of
‘middle-class conseription, and the disastrous progress of that war were clearly critical in
eventually making anti-Vietnam War protests effective. Contra Bass, in liberal democracies
most people are not inclined to exert sustained pressure on their government as long as they
live in reasonably comfortable circumstances.
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM.
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditon:
412 Talal Asad / Reflections on Humanitarianism
not watch and do nothing!”). Barbarians and savages do not have the
notion of collateral damage, which explicitly allows the civilized to kill
noncombatants in military action, because only the civilized have concep-
tions of legal responsibility in warfare. The question of intentionality in
modern war is directed at defining legal—that is, responsible—Kkilling; it is
generally acknowledged that a military strike against a civilian target will
kill a surplus and that those excess deaths will be legally covered as long as
the killing is thought to be proportionate and necessary. And there is al-
ways, as a matter of modern military etiquette, the obligatory public ex-
pression of regret at such killing. Moderns believe that unlike barbarians
and savages, civilized fighters act within a legal-moral framework; the law
of war is a crucial way of restraining killing, in manner and in number.
Barbarians do not have such a framework. Not only do they not have
external rules to restrain them, they have no conception of redemption (or
secular regret) after having killed. This is why, so it is said, moderns find
the unrestrained and unrepentant killing by barbarians and murderers
shocking.s*
But why is dismemberment by a machete, for example, more shocking
(more barbaric) than the same result obtained by a missile? The interesting
point is that being hacked to death by a machete (or blown up by a suicide
bomber) is regarded as inhuman, a notion that presupposes there are hu-
man ways of killing and dying as well as inhuman ones. Indeed, ways of
killing and dying are part of how we define the human. But the question
remains: Why are some representations of inflicting pain and death felt as
5. See Mary Douglas, Purity and Danger: An Analysis of the Concepts of Pollution and
Taboo (London, 1966).
56. This is reflected in the final item of the list of “injuries and usurpations” attributed to
George Il in the Declaration of Independence: “He has excited domestic insurrections amongst
us, and has endeavoured to bring on the inhabitants of our frontiers, the merciless Indian
Savages, whose known rule of warfare, is an undistinguished destruction of all ages, sexes and
conditions.”
57. See Edward Burns, Character: Acting and Being on the Pre-Modern Stage (New York,
1990).
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM.
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditon:
414 Talal Asad / Reflections on Humanitarianism
nize cruelty for what it is. Thus for many people the trouble with tor-
ture is not the absence of rules but the fact that its practice evokes
horror. And horror is not an interpretation but a sedimented predi:
position. Hence the typical debate about torture in liberal society:
Should it be condemned as a self-evident evil or judged (reluctantly) as
occasionally necessary that therefore needs to be defined by legal rules
in order to avoid gratuitous cruelty?
Most people (other than torturers) are horrified at witnessing torture.
Ironically, torture by state officials can sometimes be reconciled with—
even if not quite authorized by—the law that prohibits it by resorting to
legal argument, especially when it has to do with saving the lives of nation-
als. Thus, when the Israeli Supreme Court refused to give a legal rule
specifying conditions under which torture can be used, it proposed that
the torturer may have a “necessity defense” were a criminal charge brought
against him.5* It is not his character that is in question but his legal capacity.
“Necessity defense” is based on the principle that the nation-state is invi-
olable and must be defended at any cost. As there is no question of terror-
ists being able to claim such a defense, their violence meets with greater
moral condemnation. Paul Kahn—who cites this opinion—elaborates the
notion of the sacred attached to the nation-state: “what is most important
about our political culture [is] our willingness to kill and be killed. . .. At
stake in the existence of the nation-state has been the presence of the
sacred. The polity begins as a particular community with its own history
only when the finite goings-on of individuals are touched by the sacred.”
Of course the state is not a living human individual, but it is accorded the
sacred quality that individual human life has. This may be because, as
Thomas Hobbes famously described it, the state is a “mortal god,”® but it
may simply be because the state is endowed with (a claim to) life eternal.
The state is not itself human—in fact its transcendence may be part of its
claim to sacredness (Emile Durkheim thought that that was what defined
society)—but it gives essential form to individual humans. Its ongoingness
comes to be seen as the force that increasingly gives shape to individual
lives, and, like the Kantian moral subject, the state produces and imposes
on itself laws of its own.
58. Quoted in Paul W. Kahn, Sacred Violence: Torture, Terror, and Sovereignty (Ann Arbor,
Mich., 2008), p. 182 n. 9.
59. Ibid., p.173.
60. Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. A. P. Martinich and Brian Battiste (New York, 20m), p.
161,
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM.
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditon:
416 Talal Asad / Reflections on Humanitarianism
65. See André Pichot, Histoire de la notion de vie (Paris, 1993), p. 937.
66. See Michael Dillon and Julian Reid, The Liberal Way of War: Killing to Make Life Live
(New York, 2009), on the political implications of the shift to information that merged biology
with other sciences, thus going beyond Foucault’s idea of biopolitics. For an anthropological
study that covers some of this ground (and more), see Abou Ali Farman Farmaian, “Secular
Tmmortal” (PhD dis ., the City University of New York, 2012). T am grateful to both these
works—and particularly to the latter—for having alerted me to the question of redefining
human life through modern developments in science and technology.
67. A very preliminary gencalogy of the sacred is attempted in Talal Asad, Formations of the
Secular: Christianity, Islam, Modernity (Stanford, Calif., 2003), pp. 30-37.
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM.
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditon:
Critical Inquiry / Winter 2015 417
ciated with all that is mysterious in religion, with the generation of fear and
awe in believers, and with the imperviousness to rational explanation. Its
secular uses—as in talk about the sacred character of the sovereign terri-
tory, constitution, and the spirit of one’s own nation—are metaphorical
but not therefore without force of their own. It should be noted that in the
history of the church profane things, persons, and spaces were rendered
sacred. The lives of saints, hagiographies, were presentations of sacredness
to be heard as a story of wonderful signs, a narrativized life beginning with
miraculous birth and ending with wondrous death. What is special, what is
sacred, is the power expressed in and by the story to those who would hear
and the reverence such hearing demanded. Of course sacredness was never
actually distributed equally among all human lives—and I refer here not
just to the difference between the killing of Christians and of infidels. The
killing of Christ himself (the violent ending of a divine/human life) was the
sacred event for Christianity. But the visible church did not (could not)
declare that that sacrifice, that killing, made life inviolable—although it
did teach that Christ’s death on the cross was at once sacred and redemp-
tive, that it gave birth to life eternal to all who would believe.
Usages of the Christian term sacred (and its cognates) differ from words
that are commonly offered as equivalents in other languages and that are
attached to different behaviors and sensibilities, to different language
games, different forms of life.® If a word by which repugnance, awe, dis-
tance, censure, reverence, circumspection, and fear (among other emo-
tions and attitudes) are varyingly combined in different practices, then the
assumption that the sacred is a universal concept is rendered highly prob-
68. For example, in Islamic religious discourse, harin is used to prohibit particular kinds of
behavior—not because it has horrific consequences but simply because it is forbidden by God. Some
transgressive behavior (hariim) may evoke horror, some may not. The verbal form harrama is used
repeatedly in the Qur'an with the sense of “forbidding,” as in the injunction “la taqtult al-nafs allati
harrama allahu illa bi-l-haqq” (do not kill any person, [something] God has forbidden, except
lawfully) (6:151). (The word harrana in this verse is often rendered into English s “that which God
has made sacred.” I regard this a questionable translation because [a] it implies that the prohibition
relates only to lie that has been made “sacred” by God, and [b) it renders the verb harrama to mean
“made sacred,” with all the overtones of that mysterious status and not simply “he has forbidden.”)
‘The verb harima not only means to be “forbidden” but also “to make something immune,” and “to
deprive or bereave,” and “to withhold or deny” hirmin, much used in contemporary political
thetoric, refers to sociocconomic deprivation. The geographical center of Iskam, the Ka'ba in Mecea,
is called a haram, a space in which the shedding of blood and the carrying of arms—in fact, any
display of violent behavior—are strictly forbidden. At another level, harm belongs to the ethical-
legal-political tradition of the shari‘a, part of a five-fold evaluative scale ranging from mandatory,
through approved, and neutral, to disapproved and forbidden; it does not thercfore have a polar
opposite in the way that sacred is contrasted with profane. My most general point i that the English
word sacred together with its cognates (as well as equivalents in other major European languages) is
rooted in a modern secular form of life and has no parallel as a concept in premodern times.
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM,
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditons
418 Talal Asad / Reflections on Humanitarianism
69. Sce, for example, New Jersey Code of Criminal Justice, “Title 2C,” 2009, sect. 2C:22,
law justia.com/codes/new-jersey/2009/title-2c/scction-2c-22/2¢-22-1/:
1.2 A person commits a crime of the second degree if he: (1) Unlawfully disturbs, moves or
conceals human remains; (2) Unlawfully desccrates, damages or destroys human remains;
or (3) Commits an act of sexual penetration or sexual contact, as defined in N.J.8.2C:14-1,
upon human remains. b. A person commits a crime of the third degree if he purposely or
knowingly fails to dispose of human remains in a manner required by law. c. As used in this
act, “human remains” means the body of a deceased person or the dismembered part of a
body ofa living person but does not include cremated remains.
70. “Marine ‘Urination’ Prompts Investigation,” CNN.com, www.cnn.com/2012/01/12/us/
video-marines-urinating/index htmlzon.cnn=4
71. Quoted in Raf Sanchez and Dean Nelson, “US Defense Secretary Leon Panetta Condemns,
“Utterly Deplorable’ Bahaviour of US Marine ‘Urination Video, 12 Jan. 2012, Telegraph,
wwnw.telegraph.co.uk/news/worldnews/asia/afghanistan/go11075/US-defence-secretary-Leon
~Panetta-condemns-utterly-deplorable-behaviour-of-US-Marine-urination-video. html
72. Hillary Rodham Clinton, “Remarks with Algerian Foreign Minister Mourad Medelci,”
US Department of State, 12 Jan. 2012, www.state.gov/secretary/20092013clinton/rm/2012/01/
177969.htm
73. The proper treatment of corpses varics, of course, among different cultures: burial,
burning (on a funeral pyre or in a modern incinerator), exposure to natural decay and to
vultures (as in the Zoroastrian Towers of Silence). Members of each culture often regard the
death customs of the others with contempt, loathing, or amusement.
74. Daniel Ellsberg, Secrets: A Memoir of Vietnam and the Pentagon Papers (New York,
2002), pp. 58, 59. Ellsberg adds that NATO retains a first-use policy.
use of nuclear weapons. The court eventually replied that there was neither
authorization nor prohibition in international law, that such weapons
were unlawful if they failed to meet all the requirements of the UN Charter
or all the principles and rules of humanitarian law. Its final conclusion
stated that “in view of the present state of international law . . . and of the
elements of fact at its disposal, the Court is led to observe that it cannot
reach a definitive conclusion as to the legality or illegality of the use of
nuclear weapons by a State in an extreme circumstance of self-defence, in
which its very survival would be at stake.”” Clearly, the phrase “extreme
circumstance” in this statement refers not to the massive slaughter of en-
tire populations but to the life of a political entity. In that sense the sen-
tence I quoted earlier from Foucault on “the biological existence of a
population” is not quite correct. The court’s reference to “extreme cir-
cumstance” indicates that limitless violence (and the terror unleashed by
such violence) may be necessary if that is held by a sovereign state to be a
matter of its survival. The law, as enunciated by the court, is based on the
assumption that the sovereign state is a legal person, that as such it has the
right to exist and therefore an absolute right to defend itself. Thus if the US
government—or Israel or Pakistan or India for that matter—decided at
some point that its survival as a sovereign state was at stake, then the
genocidal use of nuclear weapons would not be illegal. (Think of the Cu-
ban missile crisis.) Put in patriotic language, the state’s being must be
defended against enemies whatever the cost.”® This claim to sacredness is at
once familiar from Christian history and yet entirely new in its secular
perspective.
My point is not that the court gave a nuclear first strike the stamp of
legality. What it said, in effect, was that given the assumptions on which
international law is based (state sovereignty, the certainty of the law, the
right to use violence necessary for self-defense), it could not declare deci-
sively whether the perpetration of such an act against an opponent was
legal or illegal, even if its use were to lead to the destruction of humanity.
The court is simply concerned to determine legal responsibility for the
perpetration of violence against a foreign population even before war has
been declared (the decision to discharge nuclear warheads must be made
and acted on in seconds). It must give one clear answer; the judgment’s
certainty requires that it be singular, and its authority requires the final
elimination of all other possible answers. (Therefore the panel of judges’
75. International Court of Justice, Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons, 8 July
1996, p. 263, ww rg/docket/files/9s/7.495.pdf
76. On Israel’s nuclear policy, see the ominousy titled study by Seymour M. Hersh, The
Samison Option (New York, 1991), esp. the epilogue.
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM,
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditons
Critical Inquiry / Winter 2015
split decision had to be resolved by the president’s vote.) The panel pres-
ents its judgment as the application of a universal principle to a particular
case. Legal certainty is achieved in this act of judging, even though the
content of the judgment affirms uncertainty. The judgment pushes the
question of responsibility aside but not in an arbitrary way. It establishes a
singularity of meaning by pointing to a space that is at once a product of
the law and yet a space where acts stand beyond legal responsibility. The
court has no jurisdiction (the legal right to pronounce the law). The geno-
cidal violence of a nuclear first strike cannot be addressed directly because
it is a potential act, not an actual one. But the substance of the judge’s
decision, at once within and without the law, makes it possible for the
nuclear state to threaten to wage nuclear war without incurring responsi-
bility.”” The reason for this is, partly, that the state (Leviathan) claims
eternal life and is hence entitled to defend itselfby any means possible, even
by waging or threatening to wage nuclear war in which all of humanity
might be destroyed. But perhaps more important is that because the state
is not itself human its involvement in massive violence—especially the
violence of a possible future nuclear holocaust—pushes horror outside
popular consciousness. It is the perpetration of violence by human agents
against other humans that is emotionally graspable, even though the way
in which modern law works often serves to diffuse the responsibility of
agents for violence and cruelty when they act on behalfof the state.
77. Even today the US arsenal contains 5,113 warheads, and yet little public attention s paid
to this fact. The irrationality of this kind of violence, as having no one responsible for it, should
be evident. Vigorous attempts, including threats of war, are being made by the United States
today to prevent small countries from acquiring nuclear weapons—although the doctrine of
nuclear deterrence maintains that the possession of such weapons by states that are at enmity
with cach other guarantees peace between them.
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM,
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditons
422 Talal Asad / Reflections on Humanitarianism
circulates; and we do that out of loathing for ourselves and for this
world. . . . Rejecting the world seals one’s sense of its loathsomeness
and of one’s own, insofar as one is part of it. . . . Dostoevsky . . . gives
an acute understanding of how loathing and self-loathing, inspired by
the very real evils of the world, fuel a projection of evil outward, a
polarization between self and world, where all evil is now seen to re-
side. This justifies terror, violence, and destruction against the world;
indeed, this seems to call for it. No one, I believe, has given us a
deeper insight into the spiritual sources of modern terrorism or has
shown more clearly how terrorism can be a response to the threat of
self-hatred.”
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM,
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditons
Critical Inquiry / Winter 2015 423
80. Sec H. E. J. Cowdrey, “Bishop Ermenfrid of Sion and the Penitential Ordinance
following the Battle of Hastings,” Journal of Ecclesiastical History 20 (Oct. 1969): 225-42.
81 This sense that the ambiguity of the sacred requires rites to approach it—on pain of
death to the violator as well as to others—is the theme of Henri Hubert and Marcel Mauss,
Sacrifice: ts Nature and Functions, trans. W. D. Halls (Chicago, 1967).
82. Bernard of Clairvaux, “On the Life Style ofthe Knights of the Temple,” In Praise of the New
Knighthood, trans. Conrad Greenia, www.the-orb.net/encyclop/religion/monastic/bernard html
83. See, for example, John Blake, “How Obama’s Favorite Theologian Shaped His First Year in
Office,” CNN.com, 5 Feb. 2010, www.cnn.com/2010/POLITICS/o2/0s/Obama.theologian/index
html
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM,
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditons
424 Talal Asad / Reflections on Humanitarianism
ties and flouting of international laws in that war. The fearful citizenry
seems to agree that evil cannot be fought if state violence is limited a priori.
(Carl Schmitt’s definition of politics in terms of friend-enemy is closer to
liberalism as it now finds itself than either he or his liberal critics would be
prepared to concede.)
The intellectual to whom American policymakers owe most ideologi-
cally is Reinhold Niebuhr, a theologian who has been and remains today a
strong influence on the makers of American foreign policy—from George
Kennan to Barack Obama. Central to Niebuhr’s theology is his doctrine of
sin. Sin is not simply the propensity to do evil. Paradoxically, in the form of
institutionalized killing and destruction, sin can become a means of com-
bating evil as St. Bernard of Clairvaux had argued centuries earlier. For
Niebuhr this is tragic because in using power to defend the world against
great evil one is often obliged to act sinfully, and so one sacrifices one’s
virtue—perhaps one’s soul—in performing this duty. In this view, the
perpetration of cruelty by the military is ultimately motivated by compas-
sion when it aims at ending greater human suffering; means and ends are
discursively linked together so that they can be viewed as essentially and
not accidentally connected. Obama put his endorsement of Niebuhr this
way: “there’s serious evil in the world, and hardship and pain. And we
should be humble and modest in our belief that we can eliminate those
things. But we shouldn’t use that as an excuse for cynicism and inaction.”®+
It is not immediately clear what Obama means. He does not simply mean
that there are conditions (and people) that threaten American lives and the
interests of the US; he refers theologically to an ineffable power confront-
ing the spirit of God, a power that evokes horror among the faithful be-
cause it corrupts and destroys all that it touches in the world. Whatever
Obama means, evil is a notion frequently employed by humanitarians to
describe the disasters they seek to address.
The connections among religion, ethics, and violence remain compli-
cated even in our age of secularity. And of course the terrorism of nonstate
actors is not the only place where those connections can be traced. Thus on
12 September 2001, William Cohen, one-time secretary of defense under
President William Clinton wrote: “In a very real sense, America itself must
embark on its own holy war—not one driven by hatred or fueled by blood
but grounded in our commitment to freedom, tolerance and the rule of
law and buttressed by our willingness to use all means available to defend
84. Quoted in David Brooks, “Obama, Gospel and Verse,” New York Times, 26 Apr. 2007,
www.nytimes.com/2007/04/26/opinion/26brooks.htmlz_r=1&
Epilogue
The exercise of violence that is startlingly new, that breaks with so much
of what has gone before, lies in the techniques for reconstructing human
beings through genetic engineering and artificial intelligence and through
the marketing of copyrighted information by which robots, cyborgs, and
genetically enhanced neo-humans can be made.* As Arendt once noted,
all activities directed at making or remaking natural material involve an
85. William S. Cohen, “American Holy War,” Washington Post, 12 Sept. 2001,
www.cohengroup.net/news/op_ed/op_edogizon.cfin; my emphasis.
86. The social science literature on this subject is already very considerable. James Hughes
writes enthusiastically of the new developments: “In the twenty-first century the convergence of
artificial intelligence, nanotechnology and genetic engincering will allow human beings to
achieve things previously imagined only in science fiction. . .. We will merge with machines,
and machines will become more like humans” (James Hughes, Citizen Cyborg: Why Democratic
Socicties Must Respond to the Redesigned Human of the Future [Cambridge, Mass., 2004], p. xii).
People opposing this new trend Hughes labels contemptuously “bioLuddites,” those “rejecting
liberal democracy, science and modernity” (p. xii). The only rational challenge of the scientific
future, in his view, consists in ensuring that liberal democratic government provides all with an
equitable distribution of access to the new developments. A far more thoughtful response to the
implications of genetic enginecring is Michael Sandel, The Case against Perfection: Ethics in the
Age of Genetic Engineering (Cambridge, Mass., 2007).
87. See Arendt, Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Thought (New York,
1983), p. 111,
88. The production of killer robots is no longer science fiction. A campaign has recently
been launched by a number of NGOs in the UK urging the government to strengthen its formal
renunciation of the development and use of autonomous weapons; see Campaign to Stop Killer
Robots, www.stopkillerrobots.org/2013/04/campaign-launch-in-london/. The US defense
department has stated its policy regarding the development of autonomous weapons in a
directive; sce Department of Defense, “Autonomy in Weapons,” Department of Defense
Directive, no. 3000.09, 21 Nov. 2012, fas.orgirp/doddir/dod/d3000_o9.pdf. For a critical review
of the directive by Human Rights Watch, see International Human Rights Clinic, “Review of
the 2012 US Policy on Autonomy in Weapons Systems,” Human Rights Watch (April 2013),
www.hrw.orgsites/default/files/ related_material/2013_arms_killerrobotsdodmemo.pdf. Critics
point out, however, that apart from practical problems (most weapons research carried out in
the US is done in the private sector), the definition of critical terms (human intervention, in
other words) remains unclear.
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM,
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditons
Critical Inquiry / Winter 2015 4 7
the actual perpetrator, and punishing the killer robot would deprive vic-
tims of the satisfaction that retributive justice has finally been done.* To
kill a guilty robot would simply be to punish a machine. But since lethal
violence in modern war is made possible only through complicated
mediations involving many hands and minds, why can’t manufacturers,
programmers, and commanders be held accountable? In any case, neo-
humans may be endowed with all the crucial qualities of the paleo-human:
autonomy, intelligence, information, and will. What is it that makes them
unsuitable for punishment? The answer that suggests itself lies in their
inability to suffer—their lack of passion. The neo-human cannot be the
object of retributive justice because he or she cannot
feel pain. The ability
to feel pain is a precondition not only for compassion but also for
punishment.
Most critics of the new developments have been largely concerned with
distinguishing the lawful use of violence from its unlawful use and with
liberal expressions of disquiet about the construction of robots as soldiers.
Human killers are acceptable—indeed necessary—both as participants in
just warfare (especially in military humanitarianism) and as violators of
the laws of war, but robots are not. Is this a reflection of the deep-
rootedness of the modern commitment deriving from theology to life as
sacred? Perhaps the imminent prospect of autonomous weapons should
prompt us to think more critically not only about the continual (and con-
tinually failed) efforts to tame collective violence and reduce human suf-
fering but also about the contradictory character of humanitarianism as
the painful redemption of humanity. The mutually subversive principles
of information about life and autonomy of the subject (so deeply anchored
in our moral culture) may not be sustainable together for much longer in
our interdependent, capitalist world.
89. Human Rights Watch, together with International Human Rights Clinic, has
published a useful report entitled Losing Humanity: The Case against Killer Robots, 19 Nov.
2012, www.hrw.org/reports/2012/11/19/losing-humanity. I am grateful to Tom Porteous for
providing me with this report.
“This content downloaded from 165.123.34.86 on Wed, 21 Jan 2015 01:16:11 AM,
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditons