The document discusses First Order Predicate Logic. It begins by explaining the limitations of Propositional Logic in representing facts like "Peter is a man". Predicate Logic addresses these limitations by using predicates like MAN(Peter) instead of propositional variables. It introduces terms, predicates, and quantifiers as new logical notions. Predicates map terms to truth values, while quantifiers allow for statements about all or some objects. Interpretations in Predicate Logic involve assigning a domain and values to constants, functions, and predicates. Well-formed formulas are defined recursively using predicates, quantifiers, and logical connectives.
The document discusses First Order Predicate Logic. It begins by explaining the limitations of Propositional Logic in representing facts like "Peter is a man". Predicate Logic addresses these limitations by using predicates like MAN(Peter) instead of propositional variables. It introduces terms, predicates, and quantifiers as new logical notions. Predicates map terms to truth values, while quantifiers allow for statements about all or some objects. Interpretations in Predicate Logic involve assigning a domain and values to constants, functions, and predicates. Well-formed formulas are defined recursively using predicates, quantifiers, and logical connectives.
The document discusses First Order Predicate Logic. It begins by explaining the limitations of Propositional Logic in representing facts like "Peter is a man". Predicate Logic addresses these limitations by using predicates like MAN(Peter) instead of propositional variables. It introduces terms, predicates, and quantifiers as new logical notions. Predicates map terms to truth values, while quantifiers allow for statements about all or some objects. Interpretations in Predicate Logic involve assigning a domain and values to constants, functions, and predicates. Well-formed formulas are defined recursively using predicates, quantifiers, and logical connectives.
The document discusses First Order Predicate Logic. It begins by explaining the limitations of Propositional Logic in representing facts like "Peter is a man". Predicate Logic addresses these limitations by using predicates like MAN(Peter) instead of propositional variables. It introduces terms, predicates, and quantifiers as new logical notions. Predicates map terms to truth values, while quantifiers allow for statements about all or some objects. Interpretations in Predicate Logic involve assigning a domain and values to constants, functions, and predicates. Well-formed formulas are defined recursively using predicates, quantifiers, and logical connectives.
Download as PPTX, PDF, TXT or read online from Scribd
Download as pptx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 29
First Order Predicate Logic
• Limitation of Propositional Logic
• The facts: – “Peter is a man” , : P “Paul is a man” , : Q “John is a man” : R we can be symbolize by P, Q and R respectively in propositional logic, but can’t draw any conclusions about similarities between P, Q and R. • Better to represent these facts as – MAN(Peter), MAN(Paul) and MAN(John). Contd. • Even more difficult to represent sentences like “All men are mortal” in propositional logic. – Such sentences really need quantification. • In Predicate Logic, these limitations are removed to great extent. • Predicate Logic is logical extension of propositional logic. • First Order Predicate Logic is one where the quantification is over simple variables. Predicate Calculus • It has three more logical notions as compared to propositional calculus. – Terms – Predicates – Quantifiers (universal or existential quantifiers i.e. “for all' and “there exists”) • Term is – a constant (single individual or concept i.e.,5,john etc.), a variable that stands for different individuals, – a function: a mapping that maps n terms to a term i.e., if f is nplace function symbol and t1, …, tn are terms, then f(t1, …, tn) is a term Contd. • Predicate : a relation that maps n terms to a truth value true (T) or false (F). – LOVE (john , mary) – LOVE(father(john), john) – LOVE is a predicate. father is a function. • Quantifiers: Variables are used in conjunction with quantifiers. – There are two types of quantifiers viz.., “there exist” (∃) and “for all” (∀). – “every man is mortal” can be represented as (∀x) (MAN(x) → MORTAL(x)). Examples • A statement “x is greater than y” is represented in predicate calculus as GREATER(x, y). • It is defined as follows: • GREATER( x, y) = T , if x > y = F , otherwise • The predicate names GREATER takes two terms and map to T or F depending upon the values of their terms Contd. • A statement “john loves everyone” is represented as – (∀x) LOVE(john , x) which maps it to true when x gets instantiated to actual values. • A statement “Every father loves his child” is represented as – (∀x) LOVE(father(x), x). – Here father is a function that maps x to his father. • The predicate name LOVE takes two terms and map to T or F depending upon the values of their terms. Well-formed Formula • Well-formed formula in FOPC is defined recursively as follows: – Atomic formula P(t1, …, tn ) is a well-formed formula, where P is a predicate symbol and t1,...,tn are the terms. It is also called atom. – If α and β are well-formed formulae, then ~ (α) , (α V β ), (α Λ β), (α → β) and (α ↔ β ) are well-formed formulae. – If α is a well-formed formula and x is a free variable in α, then (∀x)α and (∃x)α are well-formed formulae. – Well-formed formulae are generated by a finite number of applications of above rules. Example • Translate the text "Every man is mortal. John is a man. Therefore, John is mortal" into a FOPC formula. • Solution: Let MAN(x), MORTAL(x) represent that x is a man and x is mortal respectively. Every man is mortal : (∀x) (MAN(x) → MORTAL(x)) John is a man : MAN(john) John is mortal : MORTAL(john) • The whole text can be represented by the following formula. (∀x) ((MAN(x) → MORTAL(x)) Λ MAN(john)) → MORTAL(john) First Order Predicate Logic • First order predicate calculus becomes First Order Predicate Logic if inference rules are added to it. • Using inference rules one can derive new formula using the existing ones. • Interpretations of Formulae in Predicate Logic – In propositional logic, an interpretation is simply an assignment of truth values to the atoms. – In Predicate Logic, there are variables, so we have to do more than that. Interpretation • An interpretation of a formula α in FOL consists of – a non empty domain D and – an assignment of values to each constant, function symbol and predicate symbol occurring in α. • It is denoted by I and is defined as follows: – Assign a value to each constant from the domain D. – Each n-place function f (mapping from Dn to D) is assigned a value from D such as f(x1, …, xn) = x, where (x1, …, xn) ∈ Dn and x ∈ D. – Assign a value from a set {T, F} to each n-place predicate P (mapping from Dn to {T, F}). Here T represents true value and F represents false value. Contd. • The quantifiers (∀x) and (∃x) are interpreted as follows: – (∀x) will be interpreted as “for all elements x such that x ∈ D” – (∃x) as “there exist x such that x∈ D”. • We use notation I[α] to represents that α is evaluated under interpretation I over a domain D. – I[α] under interpretation I over a domain D can be evaluated to be true or false. Contd. • Let α and β are formulae and I is an interpretation over any domain D. The following holds true. – I[α Λ β] = I[α] Λ I[β] – I[α V β] = I[α] V I[β] – I[α → β] = I[α] → I[β] – I[~α] = ~ I[α] • For any interpretation I and a formula using (∀x) & (∃ x), the following results holds true. – I[(∀x)P(x)] = T iff I[P(x)] = T, ∀x ∈ D = F, otherwise – I[(∃x) P(x)] = T iff ∃ c∈D such that I[P(c)] = T = F, otherwise Example - Interpretation • Let α : (∀x) (∃ y) P(x, y) be a formula. Evaluate α under the following interpretation I. I
D = {1, 2}; I[P(1, 1)] = F;
I[P(1, 2)] = T; I[P(2, 1)] = T; I[P(2, 2)] = F Contd. • Solution: Consider the following cases: – If x = 1, then ∃ 2 ∈ D such that I[P(1, 2)] = T – If x = 2, then ∃ 1 ∈ D such that I[P(2, 1)] = T Therefore, I[α] = I[(∀x) (∃ y) P(x, y)] = T i.e., α is true under above interpretation. Definitions • A formula α is said to be consistent (satisfiable) – if and only if there exists an interpretation I such that I[α] = T. – Alternatively, we say that I is a model of α or I satisfies α.
• A formula α is said to be inconsistent (unsatisfiable) if and only if
– ∃ no interpretation that satisfies α or there exists no model for α.
• A formula α is valid if and only if for every interpretation I, I[α] =
T.
• A formula α is a logical consequence of a set of formulae {α1, α2,
..., αn } if and only if – for every interpretation I, if I[α1 Λ …Λ αn ] = T, then I[α] = T. Inference Rules in Predicate Logic • Modus Ponen Rule: Lemma 1: If α : (∀x) ( P(x) → Q(x) ) and β : P(c) are two formulae, then Q(c) is a logical consequence of α and β , where c is a constant. • Modus Tollen Rule: Lemma 2: If α : (∀x) ( P(x) → Q(x) ) and β : ~ Q(c) are two formulae, then ~ P(c) is a logical consequence of α and β, where c is a constant. Example • Show that δ is a logical consequence of α and β α : (∀x) ( P(x) → ~Q(x) ) β : (∃x) ( Q(x) Λ R(x) ) δ : (∃x) ( R(x) Λ ~ P(x) ) • Solution: Let I be any interpretation over any domain D. Assume that I models α Λ β i.e., I[αΛβ] = T over D. – i.e., I[(∀x) ( P(x) → ~Q(x) )] = T (1) – and I[(∃x) ( Q(x) Λ R(x) )] = T (2) Contd. • From (2), there exist some constant c∈D such that – I[(Q(c) Λ R(c) )] = T (3) – i.e., I[Q(c) ] = T (4) – and I[R(c) ] = T (5)
• From (4), – I[~ Q(c)] = F (6)
• From (1), – I[P(c) → ~Q(c)] = T , where c is the same constant – I[P(c)] → I[~Q(c)] = T (7)
• From (6) and (7), we get
– I[P(c)] = F – I[~ P(c)] = T (8) Contd. • From (5) and (8), we get – I[R(c)] Λ I[~ P(c)] = T i.e., – I[R(c) Λ ~ P(c)] = T • According to the definition of interpretation, we get – I[(∃ x)( R(x) Λ ~ P(x))] = T i.e., – I[δ] = T • Hence, – δ is a logical consequence of α and β. • This is a direct proof, often difficult. Semantic Tableaux (Pred Logic) • There are four more rules handling variables in a predicate formula in addition to one given for Propositional logic. • Let us denote a formula containing a variable x by α[x]. • Rule 10: (∀ x) α [x] α [t] for any ground term t, where t is a term free from variables. Contd. • Rule 11: ~ {(∀x) α [x] } ~ α [c] for any new constant c not occurring in α • Rule 12: (∃ x) α [x] α [c] for any new constant c • Rule 13: ~ {(∃ x) α [x] } ~ α [t] for any ground term t Few Definitions • A path in a tableaux is contradictory or closed if some atomic formulae α and ~ α appear on the same path. • If all the paths of a tableau are closed, then it is called a contradictory tableaux. • A tableau proof of a formula α is a contradictory tableau with root as ~ α . • Let α be any formula. If tableaux with α as a root is a contradictory tableaux, then α is said to be inconsistent otherwise α is said to be consistent. • A formula α is said to be tableau provable (denoted by |- α ) if a tableau constructed with ~ α as root is a contradictory tableau. Example • Show that the formula (∀x) (P(x) Λ ~ ( Q(x) → P(x)) ) is inconsistent. Solution: We have to show that – tableau for [(∀x) (P(x) Λ ~ ( Q(x) → P(x)))] as a root is a contradictory tableau. Then by definition we can infer that the formula is inconsistent. Contd. • {Tableau root} (∀x) (P(x) Λ ~ ( Q(x) → P(x)) (1) {Apply R10 on 1} P(t) Λ ~ ( Q(t) → P(t)) (2) where t is any ground term {Apply R1 on 2} P(t) ~ ( Q(t) → P(t)) (3) {Apply R7 on 3} Q(t) ~ P(t)
Closed {P(t), ~ P(t)}
Soundness and completeness • Theorem: (Soundness and completeness) : • A formula α is valid ( |= α ) iff α is tableau provable ( |- α ). Example: Show a validity of the following formula using tableaux method. (∀x) P(x) → (∃x) P(x) • Solution: If we show that ~ [(∀x) P(x) → (∃x) P(x)] has a contradictory tableau then α is tableau provable and hence by above theorem (∀x) P(x) → (∃x) P(x) is valid. More Definitions • A set of formulae { α1, α2, ….,αn } is said to be inconsistent if a tableau with root as ( α1 Λ α2 Λ ….. Λ αn ) is a contradictory tableau. • Proof of a formula α from the set ∑ ={α1, α2, ….. , αn ) is a contradictory tableau with root as ( α1 Λ α2 Λ ….. Λ αn Λ ~ α). – Alternatively, we say that α is tableau provable from ∑ and denoted by ∑ |- α. • A formula α is a logical consequence of ∑ iff α is tableau provable from ∑ and is denoted by ∑ |- α.