Johannes Kabatek, University of Zurich, kabatek@rom.uzh.ch
What is an isogloss?
Abstract
This short contribution discusses the term and concept of isogloss: the space where a linguistic
phenomenon exists or, by metonymic extension, the line that separates a particular linguistic
phenomenon from another. Although the concept is currently used as an established and
canonical term in linguistics, it is reasonable to explore its scope and the real sense that it
carries, as well as to consider its origins and potential ambiguity in use. The main issue with
the concept is that it seems to be theoretically necessary yet at the same time is not empirically
attestable, which runs contrary to essential epistemological principles. We will seek to show
that a) there is no contradiction between the existence of isoglosses as discrete units and the
continuity of phenomena on the empirical level, b) the supposed end of the era of the diatopic
anchorage of language in times of modern migration is a myth, c) that isoglosses should not be
considered as established lines but rather as projections resulting from processes of individual
constructions of spaces, and finally, d) that a central task of dialectology and of historical
linguistics consists of the identification of the multi-layered superposition of different
isoglosses that reflects the complex history of a language or variety.
Keywords
Isogloss, linguistic continuum, dialects, boundaries, dialectometry.
Resumen
Esta breve contribución discute el término y el concepto de isoglosa: un cierto espacio donde
existe un fenómeno lingüístico o, en una extensión metonímica, la línea que separa un
fenómeno lingüístico particular de otro. Aunque este concepto se utiliza actualmente como
término establecido y canónico en la lingüística, tiene sentido preguntarse por su alcance y su
significado real, además de analizar su origen y de señalar cierta ambigüedad en su uso. El
principal problema del concepto es que parece ser teóricamente necesario y al mismo tiempo
empíricamente no demostrable, algo que contradice principios epistemológicos esenciales.
Demostraremos que a) no hay contradicción entre la existencia de isoglosas como unidades
Energeia VIII (2023), 55-81
ISSN 1869-4233
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
56
discretas y la continuidad de los fenómenos en el plano empírico, b) el supuesto fin de la era
del anclaje diatópico de la lengua en tiempos de la migración moderna es un mito, c) que las
isoglosas no deben considerarse como líneas establecidas sino más bien como proyecciones
que resultan indirectamente de procesos de construcción individual de espacios y, por último,
d) que una tarea central de la dialectología y de la lingüística histórica consiste en la
identificación de la superposición en múltiples capas de diferentes isoglosas que refleja la
compleja historia de una lengua o variedad.
Palabras clave
Isoglosa, continuo lingüístico, dialectos, fronteras, dialectometría.
1.
Preliminary remarks
The question in the title of this contribution could be seen as befitting an introduction to basic
linguistics. Indeed, for any seasoned expert in linguistics it sounds superfluous: everyone knows
what an isogloss is, how it is defined, and how the concept can usefully be applied in practical
language description. I believe, however, that in all branches of scientific knowledge basic
concepts should be revisited from time to time, and that it is always necessary to have in mind
what they really mean and to appreciate the objects from which they are derived. A radical
constructivist or a deconstructionalist might well say that this is not necessary, since the
concepts we use serve to construct realities rather than deriving from them. Against such a
circular view, I would argue that behind all concepts are objects and that any reflection on a
concept must necessarily go back to the essence of those objects. In this sense, to ask what an
isogloss is can mean two things: it can be a purely historical-epistemological question about
when, how and by whom a certain scientific concept was defined. But it can also be a
philosophical question that asks what the essence of the idea of an isogloss is, its relation to
what a language is, and how language and space are related. In this sense, let us look first at the
generally accepted definition of isogloss, and then extend the term to the definition of a
language as a “system of isoglosses”. What follows will be a critical, step-by-step analysis of
some of the main issues related to the concept, after previously taking a brief look at the history
of the term. The final section and the conclusions will then argue for the usefulness and
necessity of the concept and its implications for a “multi-layered dialectometry”.
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
2.
57
Defining the term
The term “isogloss” (from Gr. ἴσος isos, Engl. ‘same’ and Gr. γλῶσσα glōssa ‘tongue’
‘language’) is commonly defined as an imaginary geographical line that separates two linguistic
features. In Romance linguistics, one of the best-known examples is the so-called La SpeziaRimini line. According to a Romance tradition that has stressed its importance, especially since
since Walther von Wartburg (1942), this line separates the Western Romance and the Eastern
Romance language varieties (Fig. 1).
Fig. 1: La Spezia-Rimini line (cf. Wartburg 1942)
In fact, the line does not indicate a single dialect feature but several divisions, a “bundle
of isoglosses”. Taking a more detailed map (Fig. 2), we can see the concentration of different
phonetic and morphologic features that are found on both sides of this line, as well as on
another, the “Roma-Ancona” line.
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
58
Fig 2: “La Spezia-Rimini line” (above) and “Roma-Ancona line” (below), the latter according to Rohlfs 1937
Such a concentration normally indicates a dialect border with separate dialects falling
on either side of the line. The question of dialect boundaries – itself intimately related to the
notion of an isogloss – is among the most challenging in dialectology (and, we might say, in
linguistics generally), as the Swabian dialectologist Arno Ruoff aptly noted:
‘From the beginning, the question of language boundaries was the most theory-dependant one in all of
dialectology.’ (Ruoff 1980: 93).1
Definitions of the term isogloss vary to a certain degree. Sara Fedalto, in a study of the
concept, offers the following one:
[an isogloss is an] ‘ideal line that on a linguistic map or atlas graphically represents all points having the
same linguistic phenomenon in common, distinguishing them from those that do not share it’. (Fedalto
1996: 149)2
Fedalto’s definition is rather restricted in nature and refers directly to linguistic maps.
When we explain the concept to students, we often become aware of a degree ambiguity since,
“Die Sprachgrenz-Frage war von Anfang an die theorielastigste in der ganzen Dialektologie [...]”. We use single
quotes to indicate the English translations from other languages, reproducing the original versions in double quotes
in footnotes. All translations are mine.
1
“linea ideale che su una carta linguistica o atlante rappresenta graficamente tutti i punti aventi in comune il
medesimo fenomeno linguistico distinguendoli da quelli che non lo condividono”.
2
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
59
on the one hand, it refers to a dividing line between two dialect phenomena, as in the case of
the La Spezia-Rimini line in the figure above, but on the other hand it also refers, in an analogy
to isobars, to the area covered by one particular linguistic phenomenon. However, these
concepts are of course merely two sides of the same coin, and both are linked by metonymy.
3.
A brief look at the history of the term
Even a cursory glance at the history of the term tells us that it derives from others used in the
natural sciences and based on the same type of word-formation. Previous to the term isogloss,
we find isotherm and isobar that refer to spaces with some characteristic trait determined by
contour lines. The origin of the term isobar is frequently attributed to the British meteorologist
Alexander Buchan and his work published in the 1860s (see Buchan 1867).
Fig. 3: Isobar map by Alexander Buchan (1862)
However, the iso- terminology in fact has an older history: in 1817 Alexander von
Humboldt coined the term isotherm and talked about
‘fixed points through which I pass my lines of isotherms or lines of equal heat’ (Humboldt 1817 in:
Lubrich / Nerlich 2019, III: 473)3
Before Humboldt, the idea of contour lines to trace spaces with equal values had
appeared several times in the history of ideas. Thus, in a river map from 1584 by the Dutch
Pieter Bruinsz showed isobaths (cf. Morato-Moreno 2017), areas indicated as being of the same
depth, although the term itself is not employed; and in 1701 Edmond Halley presented his map
of isogons of magnetic variation (cf. Jardine 1999).
3
“de points fixes par lesquels je fais passer mes lignes isothermes ou lignes d’égale chaleur”.
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
60
The introduction of the term into linguistics (see Freudenberg 1966, Händler / Wiegand
1989: 502, Fedalto 1996, Goebl 2004) can be traced back to the Letonian dialectologist August
Johann Gottfried Bielenstein, who in a 1892 work on Letonian language boundaries states, with
reference to Humboldt’s term:
‘By analogy with the term isotherm, I have dared to invent the name isoglosses for the lines on this map.
It will be easy to understand.’ (Bielenstein 1892: 391)4
Bielenstein notes that the term has only an approximative value, in the same way that
the term isotherm cannot predict the exact limits of plant growth.
Fig. 4: Isogloss map of Letonian dialects
We should mention in this context that prior to Bielenstein’s adaptation of the term, the
concept of isoglosses (even if not the term) was clearly present in Wenker’s Sprachatlas des
Deutschen Reichs (see Lameli 2013), and that Wenker is probably the most important figure in
pioneering the idea of mapping language areas in dialectology.
“Ich habe nach Analogie der Isothermen für die Linien auf dieser Karte den Namen Isoglossen zu erfinden
gewagt. Man wird ihn leicht verstehen.”
4
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
61
A criticism that has been raised repeatedly here is a fundamental difference between
isotherms and isobars, on the one hand, and isoglosses on the other: in the case of isobars we
have arbitrary external criteria – fixed, measurable pressure – and hence we can objectively
trace the divisional lines. In the case of isoglosses there is no external, definitive point of
fixation, but rather an internal view of phenomena that are not objectively attestable in the same
way. This is what ultimately leads to many of the “problems” associated with the term in its
transposition to language, problems that simply have to do with what human language is: not
an external, objectively measurable phenomenon but an internal capacity of human brains (in
the sense of Wilhelm von Humboldt’s energeia) that produces external phenomena (in the sense
of Humboldt’s ergon) (Humboldt 1836: LV).
In a paper on the origin of the concept, Hans Goebl (2004) shows that the use of the
term was ambiguous from the beginning, and that three different senses can be observed. The
first and the second refer to the two sides of the same coin that we described above (territories
and separating lines). The third one became common in Indo-European and typological studies
from the beginning of the 20th century onwards, and refers to a feature shared by two or more
languages and thus to areal phenomena such as the nominal determiners we find in Greek and
in Romance and Germanic languages, or the common features that define so-called Standard
Average European or areas like the Balkan Sprachbund.
As Goebl shows, this is also the way in which the Italian linguists and Indo-Europeanists
Vittore Pisani and Giacomo Devoto (via Antoine Meillet) used the term. As Pisani’s disciple
Bolognesi pointed out (something recently studied by Vincenzo Orioles (2017) and Giovanni
Gobber (2023)), Pisani used the concept in order to present his vision of the Indo-European
languages:
‘[... ] with a historical interpretation of the linguistic development, he considers the ancient Indo-European
languages not merely the result of the progressive disintegration of an original or secondary welldetermined unit, but also, and above all, as the historical development of the languages and dialects
spoken today unequivocally shows, the result of a more complex work of integration due to phenomena
that radiated out from one or more centres into several languages and spread over more or less vast areas,
constituting those bundles of isoglosses that we are able to reconstruct through our comparisons.’
(Bolognesi 1995: 519-520)5
“[…] con una interpretazione storicistica del divenire linguistico, considera le antiche lingue indoeuropee non il
semplice risultato della progressiva disintegrazione di un’originaria o secondaria unità ben determinata, ma anche
e soprattutto, come mostra inequivocabilmente lo sviluppo storico delle lingue e dei dialetti oggi parlati, il risultato
di una più complessa opera di integrazione dovuta al diffondersi in più lingue di fenomeni che si sono irradiati da
5
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
62
From Pisani, who was not only the founder and leader of the ‘Milanese Linguistic Cercle’
(Sodalizio Glottologico Milanese, see Kabatek 2023: 59) but who also had a significant
influence on Eugenio Coseriu (as well as becoming his father-in-law), the concept was adopted
by Coseriu, not only in his writing on dialectology and linguistic geography, but as a much
more general inner term referring to homogeneity rather than to variation: for Coseriu, from his
very earliest work, a language is defined, with explicit reference to Pisani, as a system of
isoglosses. This can be seen, for example, in Coseriu’s 1952 manuscript Evolución de la lengua
española (‘Evolution of the Spanish Language’) 6, where he uses the term isogloss in several
ways:
– In the Indo-Europeanist sense:
‘The Italo-Celtic linguistic unity has been upheld by many scholars during the last century and in our
century especially by Meillet and Ribezzo, who have pointed out the numerous common Italo-Celtic
isoglosses.’ (Coseriu 1952: 31)7
– Referring to a language as a “system of isoglosses”:
‘The Romance languages, the forms under which Latin currently appears, are divided into various
dialectal groups, in a series of isoglossal systems, represented almost in each case by a literary language
of culture.’ (Coseriu 1952: 12)8
– With reference to a language as a “diasystem” with three dimensions of variation:
‘From a purely glottological point of view, every “language” is a conventionally limited system of
isoglosses, within which we can distinguish smaller, more compact systems, differentiated in space, time
or society.’ (Coseriu 1952: 56)9
Coseriu also discusses the concept in his famous and brilliant essay La geografía
lingüística, ‘Linguistic geography’ (1955), a seminal paper on the principles of dialectology
uno o più centri e si sono diffusi in aree più o meno vaste, costituendo quei fasci di isoglosse che riusciamo a
ricostruire attraverso le nostre comparazioni”, translation by Giovanni Gobber.
The manuscript is being published online by Cristina Bleorṭu, Yoselin Henriques and the current author in the
current issue of Energeia, see also https://coseriu.ch/wp-content/uploads/publications_coseriu/coseriu453b.pdf.
6
“La unidad lingüística italocéltica ha sido sostenida por muchos estudiosos en el siglo pasado y en el nuestro
sobre todo por Meillet y por Ribezzo, que han señalado las numerosas isoglosas comunes italocélticas.”
7
“Las lenguas romances, las formas bajo las cuales se presenta actualmente el latín, se dividen en varios grupos
dialectales, en una serie de sistemas de isoglosas representados casi en cada caso por una lengua literaria de
cultura.”
8
“Desde el punto de vista puramente glotológico, toda “lengua” es un sistema de isoglosas limitado
convencionalmente y dentro del cual podemos distinguir sistemas menores más compactos, diferenciados en el
espacio, en el tiempo o en la sociedad.”
9
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
63
and linguistic geography. Here, he also indicates some of the problems that are associated with
the concept itself and with the question of the existence of linguistic borders:
‘Indeed, the existence of dialects does not imply the existence of dialectal boundaries, just as denying
these boundaries does not imply affirming the non-existence of dialects. Dialects do not exist before but
after the verification of the areas in which the concrete phenomena of speech are recorded: they are not
things but abstractions, systems of isoglosses that are structured above the multiformity of speech.’
(Coseriu 1955: 53)10
It would be a fascinating task to reconstruct in more detail the importance of the term
for Coseriu’s theory and its relationship with Pisani. However, I will not venture further into
the reconstruction of the history of the term and its significance in 20 th century linguistics, but
instead will turn to the discussion of a series of problems connected with the term that have
arisen so far:
– it has been claimed that there are no real borders or dialect boundaries but only
continua;
– it has been claimed that the term isogloss is an anachronistic one since there is no
longer a real diatopic foundation for language in our modern times of mobility;
– it has been claimed that isoglosses only exist on the level of a construed abstraction
and that they do not correspond to the activities of real speakers.
I will limit the following discussion to these three points, although briefly mentioning
certain others.
4.
Are there only continua and no categories?
One of the most frequent criticisms to the concept of isogloss is that it is difficult to find clearcut lines in empirical reality. Even if we cross a line such as the aforementioned La SpeziaRimini line, it is probable that speakers on both sides, for many reasons, will not exhibit clear
differences (and this not only refers to the current situation but was already an issue of
discussion at the time the line was originally identified).
“En efecto, la existencia de los dialectos no implica la existencia de límites dialectales, así como negar estos
límites no implica afirmar la no existencia de los dialectos. Los dialectos no existen antes sino después de la
comprobación de las áreas en las que se registran los fenómenos concretos del hablar: no son cosas sino
abstracciones, sistemas de isoglosas que se estructuran por encima de la multiformidad del hablar.” (Coseriu1955:
53).
10
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
64
The problem of continua and clear-cut categorical distinctions goes far beyond the
question of defining isoglosses; it is a general epistemological problem that is relevant in many
fields of thought. In linguistics it arises in the theory of language change as well as in the theory
of semantics; it is seen in creole studies as well and in the theory of grammar; it arises in
variational linguistics as well as in discussions of the apparent conflict between idiolects and
languages. In all these cases, the argumentation is always similar:
– there are, on the one hand, those that describe things using clear-cut categories, such
as dialectologists who clearly distinguish two different dialects or varieties, or
semanticists who clearly distinguish two different meanings;
– and there are, on the other hand, those who are against such a categorical view by
citing examples of continuity: where is the dialect border? If you look at the reality, you
will only find a continuous evolution.
This seemingly contradictory situation is sometimes accompanied by the notion of
progress and evolution in science: there are linguists who claim that categories in an
Aristotelian sense are outdated, that they are an invention of linguists, that they have nothing
to do with reality, and that linguistics should now recognise the fact that everything is in a state
of continuity. The death of Aristotle is thus announced, and whereas he is of course dead, many
of his ideas are not.
The reality of continuous evolutions has been claimed, among others, by Hermann Paul.
In his Prinzipien der Sprachgeschichte he writes:
‘In all fields of linguistic life, a gradual evolution is possible.’ (Paul 1920: 33)11
For him, the idea of a continuum is linked to the concept of “individual languages” and
gradual differences between the speech of individuals.
A field in which criticism of clear-cut categories has been explicitly and repeatedly
formulated over recent decades is cognitive linguistics. Many cognitive linguists are opposed
to the artificial categorisation of structuralism and prefer continua to categories, hence positing
the notion of a continuum between lexicon and grammar, and a continuum between different
meanings (for criticism, see Kabatek 2012: 83-85).
A concrete application of this idea of continuity is grammaticalization theory. As
Company Company (2006) puts it:
11
“Auf allen Gebieten des Sprachlebens ist eine allmählich abgestufte Entwickelung möglich.”
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
65
‘The various structuralist approaches, including generativist approaches, can hardly account for the
fundamental fact that the essence of languages is their constant imperceptible transformation.
Structuralism, in any of its manifestations, emphasised the stability of the linguistic system and
consequently greatly developed studies of a synchronic nature, sidestepping a problem central to
language, although a difficult one to resolve: how to reconcile the instantaneous and acronymic rigidity
of the system with the basic fact that a language is constantly and imperceptibly changing.’ (Company
Company 2006: XI)12
The author claims that overcoming this view allowed for a resurgence of historical
linguistics:
‘Finally, an essential part of this resurgence was undoubtedly making the concept of category more
flexible. In these functionalist frameworks, the categories of language are not discrete spaces, but rather
unstable, flexible, redefined and are creatively manipulated by speakers. The categories do not have a
homogeneous internal composition and, therefore, it is not possible to establish the same characterisation,
either syntactically or semantically, for all their members: linguistic forms usually constitute a categorial
continuum, both between and within categories, with focal zones, where the lexical entries which are the
best representatives of the category are located, and categorial boundaries which are neither clear-cut nor
well established, and some lexical entries may even be located in border zones and exhibit the properties
of two or more categories.’ (Company 2006: XVII)13
Yet within grammaticalization studies there is no unanimity on such a view. In a recent
paper, the Danish linguist Kasper Boye (2023) showed that the gradual lexical-grammatical
continuum assumed by grammaticalization theory is a myth and that categories must be clearly
distinguished, even if behind them there are indeed continua. Between movement and future,
for example, there is a clear distinction on the level of meaning, and if I can observe a
grammaticalization from one element to another (as in the English going to future derived from
a periphrasis originally expressing movement, Spanish ir a hacer algo ‘to go to do something’,
“Los diversos enfoques estructuralistas, incluidos los acercamientos generativistas, difícilmente pueden dar
cuenta del hecho fundamental de que la esencia de las lenguas es su constante transformación imperceptible. El
estructuralismo, en cualquiera de sus corrientes, ponía énfasis en la estabilidad del sistema lingüístico y desarrolló
enormemente, en consecuencia, estudios de naturaleza sincrónica, soslayando un problema central a la lengua,
aunque, en efecto, de difícil solución: cómo conciliar la rigidez instantánea y acrónica del sistema con el hecho
básico de que una lengua cambia constante e imperceptiblemente.”
12
“Finalmente, parte esencial de este resurgimiento lo constituyó sin duda la flexibilización del concepto de
categoría. Las categorías de la lengua son en estos marcos funcionalistas espacios no discretos, sino inestables,
flexibles, redefinibles y manipulables de manera creativa por los hablantes. Las categorías no tienen una
conformación interna homogénea y, por lo tanto, no se puede establecer una misma caracterización, ni sintáctica
ni semántica, para todos sus integrantes: las formas lingüísticas constituyen por lo regular un continuum categorial,
tanto entre categorías como al interior de las mismas, con zonas focales, donde se sitúan las entradas léxicas que
son mejores representantes de la categoría, y límites categoriales no nítidos ni bien establecidos, e incluso algunas
entradas léxicas pueden estar situadas en zonas fronterizas y exhibir las propiedades de dos o más categorías.”
13
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
66
or indeed similar phenomena in many languages) the continuous evolution, and even the
existence of specific ambiguous cases, is not in itself in opposition to the clear-cut existence of
two categories. Movement and future are metonymically connected, but they can be clearly
distinguished, in that something is either movement or future. In a particular case, we may find
interpretations that seem to exist between the two, in metonymic, so-called bridging contexts,
but this does not invalidate the categories as such.
Fig. 5: Continuum of utterances and discrete semantic categories
We must distinguish three levels here:
– first, the continuous level of the facts, in this case the intended meaning of a form in
an utterance;
– second, the interpretation of the form, which can be clearly A, clearly B, or unclearly
somewhere in between;
– third, the level of categories as discrete units that lead us to associate an utterance with
this or that meaning.
Isoglosses are abstract lines that separate discrete units. Even if on the level of the
utterances of individuals we find a continuum of facts, these facts are attributed to different
categories by dialectologists who, however, do not invent the categories out of the blue but
rather try to derive them from the empirical evidence.
5.
“Consciousness”
In this context, it is important to mention that again and again there are linguists who deny that
the third of the mentioned levels, the level of categories, is relevant for speakers, claiming that
it is simply an invention of linguists. Do phonemes exist? Are there in fact any discrete forms?
A problematic discussion frequently emerges here in which two ideas collide: the explicit
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
67
knowledge that speakers might or not might have of linguistic phenomena, and their intuitive
knowledge of how to do things with words.
The question of metalinguistic knowledge and of possible monitoring is something
completely different from intuitive knowledge, and this is also fundamental for positing a
distinction between the existence of dialects and isoglosses, on the one hand, and the
metalinguistic knowledge of speakers and the perceptual dialectology that investigates this
knowledge, on the other: once a speaker is able to express the future by means of a goperiphrasis, he or she is able to transmit a categorical distinction to the hearer, this
independently of any explicit knowledge of such a distinction.
There is even a long tradition in linguistics that denies the fact that speakers know what
they are doing when they speak, that speaking is “unconscious”. One of the most prominent
defenders of this idea is the Saussure of the Cours:
‘reflection is not involved in linguistic practice; [...] speakers are, to a large extent, unaware of the laws
of language’ (Saussure 1916/1984: 106)14
But this is misleading and must be reformulated, as I have claimed on several occasions
(cf. Kabatek 1996).
We must distinguish two different kinds of knowledge, the first of these being the
intuitive knowledge common to human activity and fundamental for language. This primary
linguistic knowledge is only entirely and perfectly expressed in spontaneous utterances, and all
the methods we try to apply in order to elicit utterances rely on another kind of knowledge that
converts the speaker, to however small a degree, into a linguist, an observer of her or his own
dialect.
The metalinguistic knowledge of a speaker might be a very clear and reliable one, for
example when we ask about Wörter und Sachen and suppose that the answers will be adequate.
However, we know from many studies that, since there is no direct access to the speaker’s
primary competence, things might get lost or altered on the way from primary knowledge to
metalinguistic explicitness. There is no lack of anecdotes about informants who deny the
existence of a form and then use it in the very next sentence. This is of course not generally the
case, and it strongly depends on the individual setting, the individual attitude of an informant,
and the metalinguistic “culture” we are dealing with.
“la réflexion n’intervient pas dans la pratique d’un idiome; [...] les sujets sont, dans une large mesure,
inconscients des lois de la langue”.
14
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
68
Doing fieldwork and experiments is not a natural way of addressing language, and this
is something we linguists sometimes forget because for us it has become completely normal.
Speakers use language for communication, and native speakers use their language or variety
normally without insecurity: there are two axioms that are part of the essence of language and
that are often not taken into consideration:
– the axiom of coherence, and
– the axiom of grammaticality.
The axiom of coherence is broadly assumed in text linguistics and in pragmatics:
speakers try to transmit the sense of a message to their hearers, and these hearers have the
confidence to suppose that what speakers say will make sense. If there is something that a hearer
does not understand, the normal approach (corresponding to the human and linguistic principle
of confidence and empathy) leads hearers to believe in the possibility of understanding what
others say; that is, when we do not understand something, our response is not “this is crazy”
but to assume that we have not understood well and hence to reanalyse the utterance or ask for
clarification.
If the former axiom (of coherence) is generally known in pragmatics, the latter (of
grammaticality) is often ignored. Speakers of a dialect will always produce grammatical
utterances. Not grammatical in a normative sense, and not grammatical in a sense that there
might not be anacolutha, incomplete constructions or repetitions, but grammatical in the sense
that they will be constructed according to the rules of the respective language or dialect.
This means that to be asked whether this or that form is “correct” is something unnatural
for normal native speakers and hence their answer might or might not reflect real, natural
linguistic behaviour. Things are far better with tasks like “how do you say this or that”, but
even here the stimulus might have a priming effect, and the answer once again might reflect
real linguistic behaviour or not. Hence the enormous advantage of using visual stimuli, in that
a visual stimulus is a “normal” task, one which is familiar in everyday conversation and very
common, for example, when parents show their children how this or that object can be named
linguistically.
6.
Is there really a “space-apriori”?
The next problem I would like to discuss is that of a possible conflict between clear-cut borders
and mobility. There is, on the one hand, the extreme position that there are clear-cut borders,
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
69
stable isoglosses, and the long-term duration of dialect areas; on the other hand, we find the
rejection of the idea that in the modern world space continues to be the central variational
category. This rejection is sometimes accompanied by observations on mobility, globalisation,
the internet and the dissolution of traditional spaces. Dialects, we sometimes hear, are facts
from the past that are rapidly being lost. Isoglosses, it is said, have ceased to exist, and if we
cross the La Spezia Rimini line today we will hear young Italians speaking more or less standard
Italian on both sides with no clear difference. It is interesting to see that these two positions are
generally defended by linguists from different empirical backgrounds, with dialectologists
engaged in fieldwork tending to believe more in the stability of space than urban sociolinguists
or grammarians.
Criticism of the priority of spatial variation over other variational dimensions could lead
to the reduction of the three classical Flydal-Coseriu dimensions of variation (Flydal 1951,
Coseriu 1980) to only two – diastratic and diaphasic variation – and to consider spatial or
diatopic variation as an (empirically rather frequent) case of group-specific variation due to
settlement culture (see Halliday 1978, Dufter / Stark 2002, Kabatek 2023). So there would be
no “space apriori” (in the sense of Schmidt-Herrgen 2011): only two universal dimensions, one
deriving from the fact that languages are social phenomena and associated with groups, and
another one that has to do with individual, situationally determined variation. Dialects would
simply be group phenomena, and as such a metonymical correlate of settlement cultures. If
settlement becomes flexible again and people turn into “modern nomads”, dialects cease to be
the primary manifestation of language.
This sounds attractive, but it is problematic in two senses:
- it ignores, often from the urban perspective of rather mobile observers, that underlying
individual mobility there is still an enormous stability of settlement and that mobile
individuals frequently integrate into new, already established linguistic spaces. Thus, I
live in Zurich and I (try to) speak Zurich German, despite being originally from
Germany. The existence of varieties remains first and foremost associated with places,
and one of our initial questions when we meet someone we don’t know is “where are
you from”, on the supposition that this is a meaningful question relating also to linguistic
identity. The spatial indexicality of language is more than accidental (cf. Tacke 2015:
53ff).
I spend my weekends often in a small village in the Grisons, the Rheto-Romance area
of Switzerland, and in that village, which numbers some 100 inhabitants, there currently live
eight children. The village was monolingual in Sursilvan Rheto-Romance until 1920, and has
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
70
been strongly germanized since then. All the children play on the street in the traditional local
language even if their parents are all Germanophone. This is of course due to the particular
language policy in force, with a monolingual school, plus the high esteem which RhetoRomance enjoys. But it also illustrates an intrinsic force of humans, that of showing their
attachment to a certain place, their locality, through linguistic behaviour.
Finally, we must also consider here the influence of age-grading, that is, a shift from a
dialect to the standard language at a certain age and then a (perhaps partial) shift back at a
subsequent moment in the individual’s life, this probably due to exactly the same need for
locality. Age-grading is quite a widespread phenomenon, and serves to underline the fact that
dialect loss is not a one-way street.
- another problem is that it also ignores the empirically surprising stability of dialect
areas, even in regions where it is supposed that dialects no longer exist (cf. Coseriu
1955: 49). A striking example is Hans Goebl’s fascinating comparison of quantitative
analyses of Ancient Gallo-Romance scriptae with the dialectometrised data of the Atlas
Linguistique de France from the beginning of the 20th century that show very similar
regions six or seven centuries later (cf. Goebl / Smečka 2017). And the continuity of
areas can be extended yet further, as we see in recent work by Marco Robecchi on the
Nouveaux Atlas Linguistiques de la France and on lexicographic work (Robecchi 2021).
Old borders can persist for very long periods of time, indeed, longer than the expansion
or reduction of isolated phenomena might suggest. Jürgen Erich Schmidt showed that certain
expanding dialect phenomena retain their expansion at traditional dialect borders. The reason
for this probably lies in speakers putting limits on own their adoption of new phenomena from
other dialects: elements from dialects considered as “foreign” or “different” are not adopted
and isoglosses are not only maintained but even strengthened.
In German-speaking Switzerland, the well-studied phenomenon of l-vocalisation has been
expanding for a long time (Haas 1973, Leeman et al. 2014), and some linguists have already
claimed that it might go on to conquer one area after another. However, what is interesting here
is that, as a phenomenon originating in Berne, it only expands into certain dialectal areas, ones
that are in lesser competition with other very visible dialects such as those of Zurich or Basel.
Once the phenomenon expands to more salient or stronger dialect borders, it seems to stop
expanding, at least for the moment.
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
7.
71
Isoglosses, sound laws and levels of analysis
Historically, the idea of isoglosses is closely related to the Neogrammarian idea of sound laws
and their inviolability. For Wenker, isoglosses somehow had to exist as diatopic projections of
sound laws, and if isoglosses showed stepwise extensions in the geographical linguistic reality,
this was comparable to a diatopic projection of the wave-like spread of a diachronic innovation.
In both cases we are dealing with a certain projection of language, and in both cases it is as
wrong to reject this projection as non-existent as it would be to claim it to be the absolute reality
of language rather than as a heuristic instrument (Goebl 2004: 528). Here we can once cite
Coseriu’s and his masterpiece Sincronía, diacronía e historia (1958) with the discussion therein
about the inviolability of sound laws. Paradoxically, sound laws are absolutely valid, contrary
to all empirical exceptions, just as isoglosses not only exist, contrary to all empirical evidence,
but must exist, as has already been argued.
We can observe the synchronous effect of sound laws and their inviolability in language
contact. If a German realises English <th> as [s], he or she will probably not say [‘sɛŋkju] and
then in another context [θiŋk]; rather they will pronounce [s] in both cases. Substitution works
systematically and it is discrete. Systematisation is the application of a law (see Weinreich
1953). In spatial projections we basically find just this: one side of the line where, for example,
Germ. Apfel is said systematically and another one where the usual form is Appel (according to
the so-called the “Speyer line”, see Fig. 6).
Fig. 6: The “Speyer line” (Germ. Apfel-Appel) and the “Benrath line” (machen-maken)
But what is language? Simply a collective projection of a homogeneous phenomenon?
Yes and no! The existence of abstract boundaries and laws does not contradict the individual
realisation of language and linguistic variation – to reiterate Coseriu’s point: ‘dialects’ – as the
primary forms of languages – ‘are not things but abstractions, systems of isoglosses that are
structured above the multiformity of speech’ (Coseriu 1955: 53, see footnote 10).
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
72
As in the case of the individual “sound law”, it is possible that a speaker learns a
different pronunciation in isolated forms without systematically applying a different law, or
that he or she is sometimes, with effort, able to perform one form and without effort another
one.
And this also happens on the geographical projection, where the only reality on which
this projection is based are the individual utterances of speakers who are able to perform several
varieties (or, at least, elements from several varieties). The same speaker on the north of the
Appel-Apfel line who might say Appel in informal settings might say Apfel in a more formal
situation, and might even say both forms within the same utterance. This is why traditional
dialectological work consists of isolating the syntopic, synstratic and symphatic homogeneous
form of the base dialect that is supposed to reflect the “most authentic” diatopic reality, without
denying its coexistence with other realities. And this is what the Swiss Louis Gauchat (like the
French P. Rousselot before him) had already criticised:
‘To the unity of the whole I oppose the diversity of detail, the individual languages opposed to the dialect’
(Gauchat 1905)15
In this context, I remember an anecdote that the Galician linguist Rosario Álvarez once
told me (and there are many similar anecdotes among dialectologists). In parts of Galicia, /g/
followed by /a, o u/ is pronounced as an aspiration [h] or as a fricative [x] but not as velar voiced
stop [g] or approximant [ɣ] as in other Galician, Spanish and Portuguese varieties. Delimitating
the border of this phenomenon (called gheada in Galician linguistics) is quite tricky since it is
a highly stigmatised stereotype in the Labovian sense. Once during fieldwork for the Galician
Atlas (ALGA), after long sessions of interviews in one of the places in a zone which had still
not been assigned a position on one or the other side of the line, the informant had not uttered
a single instance of gheada; then, on saying goodbye, he said “hasta luegho” [astaˈlwɛho].
Instead of ending the session, the fieldworkers then extended the interview, to discover that the
gheada was used quite systematically in that place but that the informants had avoided it when
talking to these strange people from the university who were asking uncommon questions.
8.
15
Layers of isoglosses
“à l’unité de l’ensemble j’oppose la diversité du détail, au dialecte le langage individuel”.
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
73
The last point concerns the heterogeneity of isoglosses at the level of linguistic projection. Even
if we disregard individuality and “individual language”, we find a surprising amount of
heterogeneity. Of course, there are bundles of isoglosses; in extreme cases boundaries of
historical languages, and within historical languages clear dialect boundaries. But what we also
find are contradictory, co-existing spaces. A dialect space is also the result of a certain hierarchy
or prioritisation of competing, discordant isoglosses, which arise from the historical
stratification of the dialect area. Thus, dialectally speaking Bavarian Swabia is traditionally
Swabian but also overlaps with Bavarian; and Swabia and Baden are both part of the Alemannic
area yet perceived as different by their speakers. We see here the great advantage, yet also the
dilemma, of dialectometry: on the one hand, the synthesisation of dialect data allows for a
quantifying summation of individual isoglosses and thus a common view on otherwise isolated
data; however, it does not allow for the automatic hierarchisation of the relevance of the
individual isoglosses for the (active as well as passive) construction of linguistic spaces by the
individuals that inhabit these areas.
The intuition of dialectologists helps here, in that they can determine the relevance of
different features if they are well acquainted with the corresponding situations. However, the
well-known issue that this implies is ‘a high degree of arbitrariness’16 (Meyer 1874 apud Ascoli
1876: 386; cf. also Fedalto 1996:153 and Lang 1982: 68-70). On the other hand, the relevance
of features can be studied through methods of perceptive dialectology, which has made
enormous progress in recent decades (cf. Sauer / Hoffmeister 2022).
As in the case of sound change and the lexicon, where Yakov Malkiel, with allusion to
Schuchardt, claimed that each word has a history of its own, it is sometimes the case that the
multiple shape of isoglosses and the lack of bundles has led to the claim that the concept of
isoglosses is itself useless.
We see, however, one of the points of greatest potential in the application of the concept
in the non-uniformity of isoglosses in a given space. Each word can in theory have a particular
expansion, and so too does each sound phenomenon, each syntactic phenomenon, and each
morpheme. Normally we do not find a complete chaos, but rather clusterings of isglosses. And
on many occasions these clusters correlate, at least partly, with levels of linguistic structure;
this means that syntactic phenomena may tend to cluster differently from phonic ones and from
morphology. Each isogloss and each “family of isoglosses” is a mirror of a historical layer, and
by superimposing all these areas we get a picture of the historical background of a language.
16
“une grande part d’arbitraire”.
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
74
Since the different layers indicate different historical moments, they sometimes serve to resolve
apparent contradictions in the analyses. So, the old discussion about whether Catalan is more
Ibero-Romance or Gallo-Romance, as is well known, depends largely on the linguistic level of
analysis chosen, and the result will be different if we consider the lexicon than if we focus on
certain grammatical phenomena. As mentioned above, in traditional German dialectology, the
Black Forest that separates Baden from Swabia is not a strong border, and dialects on both sides
pertain to the same Alemannic zone. If the speakers do not recognise this, it might be because
besides lexical and grammatical similarity, there are rhythmic and intonational patterns that
differ and that are in part responsible for this non-identification. Peter Gilles (2005), in his
challenging studies of regional intonation in Germany, showed that there may be intonationally
separate regions within one dialectal area, and these may stem from rather old areal
differentiations. To cite another example, Galician and Portuguese have historically almost the
same grammar and lexicon, and traditionally most linguists considered Portuguese to be just
Galician carried southwards during the Reconquista. Yet the prosodic differences between
Lisbon Portuguese and Galician are so striking (the two languages are of a different prosodic
type, Portuguese being accent-counting and Galician syllable-counting, cf. Auer 2001) that this
leads to a lack of mutual identification by the respective speakers and hence to differences that
do not seem to have emerged in recent centuries or without some deeper historical
underpinnings. Traditionally, we look at phonetics or at the lexicon or, increasingly in recent
times, at syntactic phenomena. But we still lack information on intonational spaces and on other
prosodic realities. However, prosody is quite tricky because there can be, for example, multiple
layers projected on one single intonational contour. Prosodic areas sometimes reflect very old
borders (Macklin-Cordes / Round 2015), but we can also observe prosodic accommodation
phenomena in current language contact that instead point to short-term evolutions.
Layers are of course not limited to linguistic phenomena, and the reconstruction of
dialect areas and historical layers will not ignore, in the tradition of Wörter und Sachen studies,
any cultural phenomena that show areas, such as agricultural traditions, food or clothing.
On the linguistic side, spaces of discursive traditions can be added: text traditions, and
those of saying specific things in particular situations. Traditions of politeness formulae,
traditions of answering the phone, of speaking and of silence. These may or may not be linked
to linguistic areas. Certain politeness traditions in Switzerland, for example, go beyond
language borders but are typically “Swiss”. Discourse traditions (DT) can shape areas: better
said, people shape areas through DTs, and the relationship between their isoglosses and other
layers of isoglosses must be explained.
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
75
In the best of all worlds, the overall disposal of multi-layered data (different levels of
linguistic structure, including prosody, objects, and discourse traditions) would allow for a
“multi-layered dialectometry”. Such a dialectometry would be concerned with both the weight
and the hierarchy of phenomena, not simply adding them together, and here perception would
again come into play. Apart from individual studies on this or that area, this should also allow
for progress in areal typology and for the development of hypotheses on possible universal
tendencies in the values of the layers, for example, whether intonation or phonotactics indicates
normally older areas than the lexicon. Far from being utopian, the near future, with all the
technical possibilities at our disposal, is promising in this respect and will open up new horizons
in big data dialect studies, including advances in the typological generalisation and
interpretation of isoglosses.
9.
Conclusions
As we have seen, the concept of isogloss is a central one in linguistics, although it is used with
a certain ambiguity due to a series of metonymies. The concept relates to some central problems
of dialectology and of linguistics in general: the existence of borders and the coexistence of
borders of different kinds.
In trying to identify isoglosses, we do so on an abstract level. Isoglosses exist on the
level of the language, yet language can only be adequately explained by individual acts.
Individuals essentially want to communicate, and there seems at first glance no reason why
they might seek to build linguistic borders.
However, to be human is also to construct an identity, an individual identity different
from those of other individuals, and a collective identity different from other collectives. This
seems to have been fundamental to human language from the very beginning, and it is
challenging in this sense to think about Nicholas Evan’s claim that human language was from
the beginning not monolingual but multilingual (Evans 2017): isoglosses probably existed not
only after an initial period of a common Ursprache, but emerged as part of the subsequent
evolution (in a Babelian sense) into the linguistic diversity of different languages. Language
diversity is not an accident but part of the essence of our genetically determined being and our
predisposition to diversity (Matthews 2003).
This is why we need isoglosses; they are merely the consequences of our building or
constructing identities.
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
76
The Aristotelian-Humboldtian-Coserian notion of energeia is the driving force
underlying the building of language diversity. Humans are universally humans and they
communicate in individual acts. But humans are not only born into historically determined
communities that are different from others, they not only learn how to discover linguistic
communication by means of historically existing signs; they also build communicative spaces
with limits that they metonymically link to geographical space. The essence of human language
is not just to have language, but to speak a concrete language, a historically distinct way of
communicating. This areal aspect of language must be seen as part of the energeia, as a
“Verraumung” – a “creating space” – of language, as an anchoring of linguistic signs in space.
Dialectology has never ignored this, in that it focuses precisely on such a difference and
sometimes even more on the fact that there are borders, rather than on the fact that there are
communities. For dialectologists, it is clear that there must be isoglosses in the sense of
linguistic boundaries, and this implicitly includes the other side of the same coin: the existence
of systems of isoglosses that are created by linguistic communities. In this way, the concept of
isogloss can be seen as not just another notion in linguistics, but as something that encapsulates
our essence as being humans that speak languages linked to places. 17
References
Ascoli, Graziado Isaia (1876): “P. Meyer e il Franco-Provenzale”, Archivio Glottologico
Italiano 2, 385-395.
Auer, Peter (2001): “Silben- und akzentzählende Sprachen”, in: Haspelmath, Martin / König,
Ekkehard / Oesterreicher, Wulf/Raible, Wolfgang (eds.), Language Typology and
Language Universals. An International Handbook, vol. 2, Berlin / New York: De
Gruyter, 1391-1399.
Auer, Peter (2005). “Europe’s Sociolinguistic Unity, or: A Typology of European
Dialect/Standard Constellations”, in: Delbecque, Nicole / van der Auwera, Johan /
17
I would like to thank Hans Goebl, Jürgen Erich Schmid and Alfred Lameli for references and inspiring
discussions on the issue of this essay. Thanks also to two anonymous reviewers for their useful comments, to
Héctor Álvarez Mella for including this text in the current thematic issue and to John Barlow for the proofreading
of a prefinal manuscript.
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
77
Geeraerts, Dirk (eds.), Perspectives on Variation: Sociolinguistic, Historical,
Comparative. Berlin: De Gruyter, 7-42.
Bielenstein, August (1892): Die Grenzen des lettischen Volksstammes und der lettischen
Sprache in der Gegenwart und im 13. Jahrhundert. Ein Beitrag zur ethnologischen
Geographie und Geschichte Rußlands (Mit einem Atlas von 7 Blättern). St. Petersburg.
Bolognesi, Giovanni (1995): “Vittore Pisani”, Studi Etruschi LXI, 517-524.
Boye, Kasper (2023): “Grammaticalization as Conventionalization of Discursively Secondary
Status: Deconstructing the Lexical-Grammatical Continuum”, Transactions of the
Philological Society 121(2),1-23, DOI: 10.1111/1467-968X.12265.
Buchan, Alexander (1867): A Handy book of Meteorology. Edinburgh / London: Blackwood.
Christen Christen, Helen (1998): “Convergence and Divergence in the Swiss German Dialects”,
Folia Linguistica 32, 1-2, 53-67.
Company Company, Concepción (2006): “Introducción”, in: Company Company, Concepción
(ed.), Sintaxis histórica de la lengua española, Primera parte: la frase verbal, vol. 1,
México: Fondo de Cultura Económica, XI-XXX.
Coseriu, Eugenio (1952/2023): Evolución de la lengua española. Zurich: University of Zurich,
edited by Johannes Kabatek / Cristina Bleorțu and Yoselin Henriques Pestana, online:
https://coseriu.ch/wp-content/uploads/publications_coseriu/coseriu453b.pdf,
last
accessed 29/10/2023 [also in this number of Energeia].
Coseriu, Eugenio (1955): La geografía lingüística. Montevideo: Universidad de la República,
Facultad de Humanidades y Ciencias, Instituto de Filología, Departamento de
Lingüística.
Coseriu, Eugenio (1958): Sincronía, diacronía e historia. Montevideo: Universidad de la
República, Facultad de Humanidades y Ciencias, Instituto de Filología, Departamento de
Lingüística.
Coseriu, Eugenio (1980): “‘Historische Sprache’ und ‘Dialekt’”, in: Göschel, Joachim / Ivić,
Pavle / Kehr, Kurt (eds.), Dialekt und Dialektologie, Outcomes of the international
conference: Zur Theorie des Dialekts (Marburg/Lahn, 5-10/09/1977). Wiesbaden:
Steiner, 106-122.
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
78
Dufter, Andreas / Stark, Elisabeth (2002): “La variété des variétés. Combien de dimensions
pour la description? Quelques réflexions à partir du français”, Romanistisches Jahrbuch
53, 81-108.
Evans, Nicholas (2017): “Did language evolve in multilingual settings?”, Biology & Philosophy
32(2), 905-933.
Fedalto, Sara (1996): “Genesi e vicende della nozione di ‘isoglossa’”, Bollettino dell’Atlante
linguistico italiano, III, 20, 149-165.
Flydal, Leiv (1951): “Remarques sur certains rapports entre le style et l’état de langue”,
NorskTidsskrift for Sprogvidenskap 16, 240-257.
Freudenberg,
Rudolf
(1966):
“Isoglosse:
Prägung
und
Problematik
eines
sprachwissenschaftlichen Terminus”, Zeitschrift für Mundartforschung 33, 219-231.
Gauchat, Louis (1905): “L’unité phonétique dans le patois d’une commune” in: Aus
romanischen Sprachen und Literaturen. Festschrift Heinrich Morf. Halle: Niemeyer,
175-232.
Gilles, Peter (2005): Regionale Prosodie im Deutschen: Variabilität in der Intonation von
Abschluss und Weiterweisung. Berlin / Boston: De Gruyter.
Goebl, Hans (2004): “Eine Glosse zu Isoglosse”, in: Krisch, Thomas / Lindner, Thomas /
Müller, Ulrich (eds.), Analecta Homini universali dicata. Arbeiten zur Indogermanistik,
Linguistik, Philologie, Politik, Musik und Dichtung. Festschrift für Oswald Panagl zum
65. Geburtstag. Stuttgart: H.-D. Heim, vol. II, 525-537.
Goebl, Hans / Smečka, Pavel (2017): “Trois regards dialectométriques sur l’aménagement
géolinguistique du domaine d’oïl, basés sur une synthèse des données médiévales réunies
par Anthonij Dees en 1980 et 1983, et celles de l’ALF”, in: Kristol, Andres M. (ed.), La
mise à l’écrit et ses conséquences. Actes du troisième colloque “Repenser l’histoire du
français”, Université de Neuchâtel, 5-6 juin 2014. Tübingen: Francke, 15-49.
Gobber, Giovanni (2023): “Coseriu in Milan – and other things”, contribution to the round table
«The future of Coserian linguistics», Școala de vară on-line Actualitatea concepției lui
Eugeniu Coșeriu, Universitatea Babeș-Bolyai, Cluj-Napoca, 01/09/2023.
Händler, Harald /Wiegand, Herbert Ernst (1989): “Das Konzept der Isoglosse: methodische
und terminologische Probleme”, in: Besch, Werner / Knoop, Ulrich / Putschke,
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
79
Wolfgang, Wiegand / Herbert Ernst (eds.), Dialektologie. Ein Handbuch zur deutschen
und allgemeinen Dialektforschung, 2 vols.. Berlin / New York: De Gruyter, 501-527.
Haas, Walter (1973): Zur l-Vokalisierung im westlichen Schweizerdeutschen, in: H. Bausinger
(ed.), Dialekt als Sprachbarriere: Ergebnisbericht einer Tagung zur alemannischen
Dialektforschung. Tübingen: Tübinger Vereinigung für Volkskunde, 63-70.
Halliday, Michael A. (1978): Language as social semiotic: the social interpretation of language
and meaning. London: Edward Arnold.
Humboldt, Wilhelm von (1836): Über die Verschiedenheit des menschlichen Sprachbaues und
ihren Einfluß auf die geistige Entwickelung des Menschengeschlechts. Berlin: Dümmler.
Jardine, Lisa (1999): Ingenious Pursuits: Building the Scientific Revolution. New York: Nan
A. Talese.
Kabatek,
Johannes
(1996):
Die
Sprecher
als
Linguisten.
Interferenz-
und
Sprachwandelphänomene dargestellt am Galicischen der Gegenwart. Tübingen:
Niemeyer.
Kabatek, Johannes (2012): “Nuevos rumbos de la sintaxis histórica del español”, in: Montero
Cartelle, Emilio and Manzano Rovira, Carmen (coords.), Actas del VIII Congreso de la
AHLE. Santiago de Compostela: AHLE / Meubook, 77-100.
Kabatek, Johannes (2015): “Sprachkultur und Akkomodation”, in: Bernsen, Michael / Eggert,
Elmar / Schrott, Angela (eds.), Historische Sprachwissenschaft als philologische
Kulturwissenschaft. Festschrift für Franz Lebsanft zum 60. Geburtstag. Bonn: Bonn
University Press / Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 165-177.
Kabatek, Johannes (2023): Eugenio Coseriu. Beyond Structuralism. Berlin / Boston: De
Gruyter.
Lameli, Alfred (2013) (ed.): Georg Wenker: Schriften zum “Sprachatlas des Deutschen
Reichs”. Gesamtausgabe, 3 vols.. Hildesheim / New York / Zürich: Olms.
Lameli, Alfred (2014): Erläuterungen und Erschließungsmittel zu Georg Wenkers Schriften.
Hildesheim / New York, Zürich: Olms.
Lang, Jürgen (1982): Sprache im Raum. Tübingen: Niemeyer.
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
80
Leemann, Adrian / Kolly, M.-J. / Werlen, Iwar / Britain, David / Studer-Joho, D. (2014): “The
diffusion of /l/-vocalization in Swiss German”, Language Variation and Change 26(2),
191-218.
Lubrich, Oliver / Nerlich, Thomas (eds.) (2019): Alexander von Humboldt: Sämtliche Schriften
(Studienausgabe). München: DTV.
Macklin-Cordes, Jayden L. / Round, Erich R. (2015): “High-Definition Phonotactics Reflect
Linguistic Pasts”, DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.15496/publikation-8609.
Matthews, Peter Hugoe (2003): Linguistics: a very short introduction, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Morato-Moreno, Manuel (2017): “Orígenes de la representación topográfica del terreno en
algunos mapas hispanoamericanos del s. XVI”, Boletín de la Asociación de Geógrafos
Españoles 73, 155-199.
Orioles, Vincenzo (2017): “Echi della stagione milanese (1945-1950) nel primo Coseriu.
L’influenza esercitata da Vittore Pisani”, in: Negri, Mario / Rocca, Giovanna /
Muscariello, Marta (eds.), L’opera scientifica di Vittore Pisani nel quadro della
glottologia indeuropea fra Ottocento e Novecento. Atti del Workshop del L Congresso
Internazionale SLI (Milano, 22/09/2016), Alessandria. Rivista di Glottologia 11 (2017),
57-64.
Paul, Hermann (1920): Prinzipien der Sprachgeschichte, 5th edition (1st edition 1880). Halle:
Niemeyer.
Robecchi, Marco (2021): “La localisation de témoins oïliques médiévaux. Le DRFM comme
levier méthodologique”, Zeitschrift für romanische Philologie 137, 744-796. DOI:
https://doi.org/10.1515/zrp-2021-0029.
Rohlfs, Gerhard (1937): La struttura linguistica dell’Italia. Leipzig: Keller.
Ruoff, Arno (1980): “Probleme der Sprachgrenzen und -übergänge”, in: König, Werner / Stopp,
Hugo (eds.), Historische, geographische und soziale Übergänge im alemannischen
Sprachraum. München: Vögel, 93-109.
Saussure, Ferdinand de (1916/1984): Cours de Linguistique Générale, critical edition prepared
by Tullio de Mauro, (1. ed. 1972, based on the original version by Charles Bally / Albert
Sechehaye and Albert Riedlinger from 1916). Paris: Payot.
Kabatek, Johannes, What is an isogloss?
81
Sauer, Verena / Hoffmeister, Toke (2022): Wahrnehmungsdialektologie. Eine Einführung.
Berlin / Boston: De Gruyter.
Schmidt, Jürgen Erich / Herrgen, Joachim (2011): Sprachdynamik. Eine Einführung in die
moderne Regionalsprachenforschung. Berlin: Erich Schmidt.
Tacke, Felix (2015): Sprache und Raum in der Romania. Fallstudien zu Belgien, Frankreich,
der Schweiz und Spanien. Berlin / Boston: De Gruyter.
Wartburg, Walther von (1942): La posizione della lingua italiana. Firenze: Sansoni.
Weinreich, Uriel (1953): Languages in Contact. The Hague: Mouton.