Argumenta 4,2 (2019)
Special Issue
Naturalism and
Normativity
in
Hegel’s Philosophy
Edited by
Guido Seddone
The Journal of the Italian Society for Analytic Philosophy
Contents
Hegel’s Jagged Understanding of Self-Conscious Life
Introduction
9
Guido Seddone
Science, Thought and Nature: Hegel’s Completion of
Kant’s Idealism
19
Katerina Deligiorgi
Hegel on the Naturalness of Logic: An Account Based
on the Preface to the second edition of the Science of
Logic
47
Elena Ficara
Spiritualized Nature: Hegel on the Transformative
Character of Work and History
59
David Ciavatta
Hegel’s Naturalism, the Negative and the First Person
Standpoint
77
Stefan Bird-Pollan
Hegel’s Dialectical Art
Antón Barba-Kay
97
Hegel’s Fact of Reason: Life and Death in the
Experience of Freedom
117
Dean Moyar
Some Limits to Hegel’s Appeal to Life
Andrew Werner
143
Hegel’s Jagged Understanding of SelfConscious Life
Guido Seddone
University of Parma - Georgetown University
1. The State-of-Art of the Hegelian Studies
The Hegelian studies have been recently improved and widened by an approach
of analysis aimed at investigating the nature of the human self-conscious dispositions, which represent the core of the Hegel’s thought. In the past, analytical philosophy disregarded thinkers like Hegel and other German classical philosophers
because of their frequent and very broad use of generalist notions like spirit, history, absolute knowledge and, obviously, absolute. From the point of view of the
analytical methodology, resorting to those words prevents the philosophical investigation from being focused and rigorous in the clarification of the human subjective rationality and its faculties such as perception, thinking, using a language,
being an agent and evaluating norms and values. In spite of this previous preclusion, the philosophy of G.W.F. Hegel presents many characters of a rigorous and
consistent investigation about human rationality and agency accounting for several philosophical issues also addressed by the analytical tradition. The present
special issue of Argumenta on Naturalism and Normativity in Hegel’s Philosophy aims
at focusing on the analytical aspects connected to the Hegelian philosophy of
mind and to his theory of self-conscious life in order to pinpoint his relevant contribution for the understanding of human intelligence and the cultural and political history of human kind.1 His thought is indeed based on a rigorous analysis of
the naturalistic requisites of cognitive and practical disposition and on a systematic criticism towards the transcendental philosophy, which does not link the conditions of knowledge to the empirical and natural constitution of subjectivity. This
special issue intends to deal with the affinity of the Hegelian thought to some
aspects of the tradition of the analytical and post-analytical philosophy and to
focus its naturalistic approach to human cognition and practical self-conscious
dispositions.
Actually, Hegel’s philosophy has not been totally extraneous to the analytical interest, in fact, W. Sellars inaugurated the analytical reading of this thought
by pointing out that the question concerning the empiricism and its fallacy had
been already and successfully addressed almost two centuries before him by Ger-
1
This project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and
innovation program under the Marie Sklodowska-Curie grant agreement No 704127.
Argumenta 4, 2 (2019): 9-17
ISSN 2465-2334
© 2019 University of Sassari
DOI 10.14275/2465-2334/20198.int
10
Guido Seddone
man thinkers like Kant and Hegel. Particularly Hegel’s strategy towards the empiricism does not only entail a robust revision of human knowledge, which he
considered as originated from the spontaneous and speculative activity of the selfconscious subject. His criticism also implies a radical revision of rational subjectivity because it takes for granted the assumption that human eagerness to truth
and knowledge does not derive from the correspondence of mental contents to
external facts, but rather on the development of a frame of concepts and ideas
under which reality is explainable and can be grasped. By underlining the spontaneous and inferential character of the conceptual, Hegel like Kant conceives of
rationality as a faculty ruled by the internal and autonomous guideline of articulating and defending reasons and concepts, which results independent from the
empirical given. Since humans know by means of concepts rather than by means
of the information gained from the given and since the given is neither articulated
or inferentially grasped, knowledge and cognition have to rely upon this self-ruling disposition of elaborating and evolving concepts and categories of thinking
that we can apply onto the empirical data. In this point Hegel’s thinking is very
similar to the Kantian conclusion about the cooperation of sensitive intuition and
intellectual logical deduction of categories for achieving a certain knowledge
about reality. It is also very close to Sellars’ idea about the logical space of reason
as the space in which the normative domain of the ideas shapes our historical and
practical dimension and our form of life as rational beings. However, Hegel’s approach to the conceptual results to be much wider that those elaborated by Kant
and Sellars because he stresses the fact that the conceptual is effective even out
the empirical domain of facts, having no internal border of application. In fact,
whereas following Kant and Sellars categories and concepts are inferentially articulated even though their validity is conditioned and limited to the application
to the empirical facts, for Hegel the conceptual has no external borders of application since the distinction between thinking and reality is considered by him as
a moment of a dialectical development of knowledge (McDowell 1996). In other
words, the subject-object opposition is for Hegel the necessary self-distinction of
the subject investigating its own cognitive faculty as an autonomous disposition
differing from the bare empirical fact. The entire modern philosophy from Descartes onwards gives an account of the different roles of reason and sensibility,
i.e. concepts and empirical facts, in achieving knowledge. Following Hegel such
distinction has to be conceived as formal and should not jeopardize the identity
of thinking and reality when thinking is conceived as a matter of self-conscious
life. McDowell (1996) is perfectly right in maintaining that the distinction of mind
and world in the Hegelian philosophy is overcome by making recourse to a deployment of the conceptual that is not strictly bounded to the empirical application like in Kant. The conceptual is for Hegel the cognitive tool by which the
historical and self-conscious subject grasps the formal and a-priori structure of
reality, what makes the reality itself accessible and knowable. In his philosophy
Das Logische, the substantive of the adjective “logical”, is the fundamental normative element characterizing self-consciousness’ disposition to understand reality
under orders of concepts autonomously and inferentially deduced. The Science
of Logic aims at demonstrating that a-priori knowledge is possible even when it
is applied to unconditioned and non-empirical objects, what was precluded by the
Critique of Pure Reason by I. Kant. In this way, Hegel supplies us with a compelling contribution about the nature of the normative and its elaboration by defining
Hegel’s Jagged Understanding of Self-Conscious Life
11
its extension, role and relevance in comparison to mere empirical facts. His position against both empiricism and naive realism is supported by an analytically
well defended conception of the inferential space of reasons in which the conceptual is conceived as the instrument for grasping the logical structure of the relations constituting reality. The Science of Logic should not be interpreted, hence,
as a metaphysical text about the entire, but rather as a book about the fundamental categories of thinking, their application and validity. The question concerning
the ontological status of these categories is just a default question that Hegel answers by underlining that in his system substance is also subject and consequently
the truth of the substance is already held in the subjective cognitive stances. Beyond the idealist question concerning the subjective nature of the substance due
to the fact that the truth of the substance is the thinking subject itself, the Hegelian
philosophy provide a consistent theoretical apparatus by which we understand
the nature of the normative, its inferential articulation and how it applies to reality
by determining knowledge and the socio-historical dimension.
2. Hegel’s Moderate Naturalism
Hegel’s contribution does not only represent the epistemological defense of the
deductive disposition of using and articulating concepts, it also deals with the
question of their naturalistic status evolving an original version of naturalism.
Since the normative character of the concept is tightly linked to a self-conscious
living subject, one cannot understand the nature of the normativity without accounting for the living and biological dispositions connected to the use of the concepts. In this sense, any investigation upon the Hegelian naturalism represents the
evolution of the inferential approach to his Science of Logic and theory of self-consciousness inaugurated by Sellars and carried on by scholars like B. Brandom and
J. McDowell in the ’90s.
Naturalism has been often regarded as a pure analytical outlook to the question related to the outset of the human cognitive stances since it accounts for the
natural conditions of the mental and linguistic contents. The main question of
naturalism is whether any mental content corresponds to a specific and identifiable natural circumstance that can be either an organic and biological property or
a physical feature, which can also be investigated by empirical sciences. Some
naturalists, often referred to as physicalists, go further and claim that for every
mental stance there must be a correspondent physical state that can be exactly
localized in the brain and that there would not be any thought without the fulfilment of distinctive and related chemical-physical conditions in the brain. This
kind of radical naturalism disregards the importance of non-physical factors both
fostering the acquisition and elaboration of linguistic and cognitive dispositions
and also specifying the nature of the individual intelligence. Moreover, radical
naturalism and physicalism are devoted to a sort of physical causation that enormously undermine the role of the autonomous learning and thinking, which are
necessary for human cognition intended as a faculty borne by free and autonomous subjects. They, in fact, maintain a kind of physical determinism in
knowledge without accounting for the process itself of cognitive competencies acquisition, which is the result of a progressive integration into a linguistic shared
surrounding in which these competencies are fundamentally shared and socially
transmitted. Therefore, the localization itself of any cognitive stance by the identification of the related physical status does not explain the constitution itself of
Guido Seddone
12
the rational subject able to bear it. This physicalist attitude has repercussions on
several natural sciences, among them the human brain and cognitive ones, that
are induced to conceive of the neurons activation they can observe with modern
devices as the locus and cause of a specific cognitive content or disposition. However, this alters the logical sequence of thought production because it considers
thinking as an activity caused by a natural phenomenon whereas it is rather the
result of the autonomous elaboration of contents and ideas by a biological and
rational subject. In other words, thinking cannot be triggered by something empirically observable because this would jeopardize the fundamental epistemological principle that thinking is the outcome of autonomous learning and elaboration of contents. The egregious mistake of some natural scientists and neuroscientists is indeed based on the idea that the possibility of observing the brain processing or when some neuron fires is equivalent to the possibility of discovering
what produces the cognitive activity itself. However, since this activity is logically
related to a process of autonomous learning it cannot be externally determined,
namely triggered by factors independent from their bearer. The fact that the bearer
of a cognitive stance is also the body in which brain processing occurs, does not
solve the question of what produces cognition. Firstly because a subject is just not
its own body, but rather a very composite entity with social, adaptive, evolutive
and above linguistic dispositions. Secondly, cognition cannot be reduced to empirical and observable facts because these are the outcome of external causation,
whereas any cognitive capacity is the result of autonomous elaboration, namely
something that has to be explained by accounting for the inwardness of some subject. German classical philosophy represents an outstanding contribution to this
issue because it is properly based on the investigation of subjectivity intended as
the possibility to ground knowledge in a certain basis. As Paul Franks showed in
a compelling book (Franks 2005), the entire epistemological struggle of modern
philosophy aimed at founding knowledge on sure premises and ended when Kant
highlighted that a foundation should start with the investigation addressing the
transcendental conditions on which the activity of thinking the object relies. Hegel’s crucial contribution to this issue is based on the idea that cognition is the
outcome of natural requisites of the subject rather than of transcendental conditions. Relating thinking and true knowledge to the living and natural features of
the individual means assuming a form of moderate naturalism that does not disregard the role of the social, cultural and historical surrounding in the development of self-conscious attitudes.
3. The Continuity of Life and Mind
Instead of taking for granted a natural causation on thinking, Hegel, in fact,
claims that the biological conditions of the living organism render it different from
phenomena deriving from external and mechanical causation, which we observe
through the empirical sciences. In life there are, in fact, logical requisites of selfdetermination and inwardness that presume a teleological conceptuality and a
vital force determining the living individual as an autonomous agent. Since biological functions cannot be accounted for by making recourse to the principle of
cause-effect, they are not caused by some external and independent factor, but
rather by means of an enactive principle explaining how any biological organism
brings into effect rules and norms determining its form of life. How Hegel correctly describes, life changes the way a system interacts with the surroundings
Hegel’s Jagged Understanding of Self-Conscious Life
13
because it brings into the scene the dimension of self-reference and self-determination. Whereas in a mechanism we always describe something as the effect of
some external causation, accounting for life means investigating a system that is
based on a self-referential network of living functions aimed at self-preservation.
This means that external causation has a minor role in the description of the network itself, for which the external environment represents something useful for
the maintaining of itself (oxygen, nutrients and, for evolved organisms, biological
niches). The living organism establishes a surplus of significance over the external
world because the latter does affect the former in terms of providing nutrients and
biochemical substance and not in terms of mechanical causation. In other words,
something is not intrinsically nutrient for an organism, but rather by virtue of relational features linked to the organism’s characteristics. This means that life is a
different kind of relational phenomenon than mechanism, because whereas in
mechanism the effect is consequent to the cause, in life the effect is linked to the
self-relational nature of the living organism. In fact, the assimilation of nutrients
does not change the characteristics of the organism, but rather it is just for sake of
the maintenance of its already given network of functions.
The Science of Logic, stressing the radical difference between life and mechanism, reminds us that also the cognitive disposition cannot be explained in terms
of mechanical causation but rather in terms of attitudes of a living and self-conscious subject. Whereas other living species enact norms for sake of a biological
homeostasis, i.e. the maintenance of the organic network of functions, the rational species brings into effect an universal principle of good life due to its selfconscious trait. In self-conscious life the normative does not barely depend on the
organic functionality, but it is rather shaped by the inferential articulation and
comparison of concepts, which are naturally linked to the self-aware attitude of
the individual belonging to this species. Such articulation is socially sustained because the acknowledgement of ideas is a matter of self-conscious life and not
simply of individual life, namely it determines our species and the course of the
human civilization. Therefore, also having a cognitive stance is primarily a matter
of self-consciousness because it is the result of having specific competencies and
skills necessary for articulating and defending ideas in the different fields of
knowledge. Such skills are socially acknowledged because also knowledge is
evolved by means of shared practices, which are part of the history of the human
civilization (Tomasello 2014). Self-conscious life is a variation of biological life,
which already has elements of self-reference and self-determination in an unaware
form. This is the core of what characterizes Hegel’s moderate naturalism. In fact,
self-conscious life is the form of life able to sustain a self-description, namely the
definition of what is good and what is bad for itself by being aware of what it
means being humans. This has many points in common with Philippa Foot’s philosophy of action particularly when she claims that the good for the humans has
to be found in the natural characteristic of their species rather than in transcendental and moral principles of action. Goodness for humans has to do with a
specific practical intelligence, called by Aristotle phronesis, which defines what has
to be called good for humans and what should not (Foot 2001). This means that
self-conscious life establishes the nature of its own species by means of a general
categorization of what is a good form life, deciding so on the course and development of human culture and civilization. This is possible because it determines the
practical dimension by setting up universal principles of agency and thinking and
Guido Seddone
14
by evolving the concept of truth, which is independent by particular manifestations of the human intelligence. In other words, it creates a social space of reasons
and concept in which ideas, values, virtues, information, knowledge, etc. are assessed and socially acknowledged by the guideline of the force of the better reason
(Brandom 1994). Since Hegel’s thought explains knowledge, self-consciousness
and truth as originating in the naturalistic requisites of our biological species, it
accounts for sociality, culture and history as the outcome of the self-conscious
attitude of deciding what is good and what is bad for our own form of life. Every
expression of human intelligence from the empirical sciences to social interaction,
and to the constitution of advanced cooperative institutions like politics and states
are explainable by making recourse of that kind of self-referentiality we observe
in every living organism that Hegel often refers to as self-referential absolute negative
unity (Hegel SL: 743). This definition describes the kind of relation a living subject
brings into being with the environment: absolute negation of external conditioning by the reference to its own internal network of biological functions. When this
self-referentiality is aware we have human intelligence as the premise of social
space of reasons and the evolution of the world human history.
4. Hegel’s Theory of Self-Consciousness
This kind of naturalism does not conceive of the natural premises as what causes
self-consciousness because this would jeopardize the fundamental truth that human consciousness is based on freedom, independence and self-determination. It
rather maintains that the biological substratum is like inhabited by what we call
consciousness, which is the result of a process of acculturation and acquisition of
universal habits and believes that they are socially evaluated and acknowledged.
In this sense, Hegel’s philosophy of mind is also very close to the modern conception of embodied cognition. The process of formation of self-consciousness is the
result of a dialectics of life and sociality in which consciousness faces the condition of being a subject with both material needs and the disposition to experience
acculturation and integration within a social context. Self-consciousness is hence
not independent from the broader conception of spirit [Geist], which is the frame
of the social rules, rights, laws and historical identity holding together human
cooperation and interaction. This sort of extended mind is what shapes individual
self-consciousness in his process of achieving independence and freedom within
the socio-historical dimension of its present time. As also P. Pettit (1996) claims,
we could not have any human intentionality at all without acknowledging the
effective impact this common mind exerts upon the individual one. Human cognitive dispositions are, hence, the result of a process of integration within a social
surrounding that determines the brain process itself, namely what can be empirically observed by modern devices. This is consistent with what Hegel claims when
he states that “mind has for its presupposition the nature, of which it is the truth
and for that reason its absolute prius” (Hegel PM: 381). This passage points out
that mind is neither a mere outcome of nature or emergent from the natural dimension, but rather it requires to be understood by investigating the reciprocal
dependence and crossed stratification of natural and self-conscious life. In other
words, cognitive dispositions are not to be explained as merely separated and
caused by natural features of the brain, but rather as shaped by the relation they
have with natural prerequisites. This approach is very close to the so called connectivism in the neurosciences that claims that brain’s features are steadily being
Hegel’s Jagged Understanding of Self-Conscious Life
15
changed by the cognitive and moral experiences the subject is exposed to because
in the brain every change is the change of both the software and the hardware
(Goldblum 2001). Mind and brain are not, hence, two different moments of a
bottom-up development because this would undermine the possibility to understand their interdependence and permanent connection.
The fact that there cannot be a mind outside the body and that it needs to be
embedded in order to have the functions it has, is one of the most important
achievement of the Hegelian thinking in comparison to the previous modern philosophical tradition in which soul, mind and thinking are conceived as distinct
from the body because of their divine origin. Following Hegel, it is through the
relation with nature that spirit can both exist and be the truth of nature for it represents the living activity by which self-conscious beings think the practical
achievement of the human life as something different from mere nature (Pinkard
2012: 98-102). Whereas nature is “permanence of the otherness” (Hegel PN: 247)
[Verharren des Andersseins], spirit is a sort of normative and social substance shaped
by the reflexive activity and yielding a “return from otherness” (Hegel PS: 105) of
nature [Rückkehr aus dem Anderssein]. This coming back represents the characteristic of self-consciousness to reflexively refuse the independence of the external
world and to understand it as a framework of normative relations whose focal
centre is self-consciousness itself. This kind of reflexion cannot be exerted by pure
nature in which otherness persists due to the externality and necessity of the natural law of causality (Hegel PN: 248). It must be exerted by a being having an
internal self-regulative system of agency and thinking and a self-sustaining objectivity by which it reproduces autonomously itself. This self-sustaining system of
agency and thinking is based on the dynamism of life because only the biological
organism has the fundamental natural patterns for attaining this sort of self-related
and autonomous characteristic.
Hegel’s conception of human cognition originates from a jagged understanding of self-conscious life that is treated as the fundamental feature to understand
human civilisation, knowledge, agency, ethics, politics, etc. The constitution of
this subject out of natural requisites is the core of its relation to the environment
and what explains the history of the human species and the diverse forms of socialization. When we address Hegel’s naturalism we have, hence, to deal with
several outcomes of his approach to self-consciousness spreading out from epistemological, to sociological, cognitive, moral and historical aspects. This happens
because the simple explanation of the kind of natural relation the self-conscious
sets up with the otherness entails a concatenation of behavioral results that clarify
the nature of our species if they are unitarily grasped. The Hegelian project to
derive human intelligence from a natural and empirical requisite such as the desire, rather than to analyze it transcendental and abstract conditions, brings him
to deliver a consistent conception of human life with multiple repercussions.
5. The Contributions in this Special Issue
All contributions of the present special issue are devoted to investigate how Hegel
deals with the relation between nature and normativity in order to understand the
social, normative and historical dimension out of natural premises. Deligiorgi’s
article tackles the epistemological aspects linked to the Hegelian naturalism and
particularly it deals with the question about the continuity of thought and nature.
Already Kant highlights that he normative dimension of the concepts contributes
16
Guido Seddone
to knowledge by distinguishing itself from the natural domain of the given. However, Kant disunites the two domains of normativity and the given by stressing
the impossibility of knowing the real substance of the noumenon. Following
Deligiorgi, Hegel’s effort to unify knowledge is centered on the notions of selfknowledge and self-consciousness, what changes the characteristics of the cognitive dispositions, rendering them more natural. Hegel’s mindedness appears to be
the mark of his project to unify norms and nature by keeping them together as an
act of self-reference and self-determination. Elena Ficara’s article deals with the
question of the naturalness of the Hegelian logics and defends the idea that the
validity of the conceptual is strictly connected to the natural character of the categories. The natural character of the logical concepts is a classical epistemological
question spreading out from Plato to Russell and representing a crucial point for
the foundation of logics and thinking. Hegel’s novelty consists in connecting the
categories to self-conscious life and to the constitution of a thinking subject out of
natural and biological requisites. As also Deligiorgi maintains, the truth of the
categories is based on the natural character of their own deduction by means of
the synthetic and autonomous disposition of human rationality.
Ciavatta’s contribution introduces the question about the relation/opposition between nature and spirit, which represents the core of the Hegelian naturalism. The author claims that Hegel overcomes this opposition by evolving a notion
of “spiritualized nature”, a domain with a distinctive ontological status that
evolves historically and socially. Bird-Pollan’s article interestingly deals with the
opposing claims that mind (Geist) has to be understood out of natural requisites
and that it is also self-legislating. The opposition is represented by the fact that
whilst a natural element is externally determined, mind is expected to autonomously formulate the principles of its own agency. Bird-Pollan correctly accounts
for the idea that the first person perspective should be the starting point for the
examination of the relationship of nature and normativity. This can explain the
self-unfolding characteristic of self-consciousness, which originates out of natural
requisites but evolves normative frames of agency and thinking by means of a first
person perspective. In fact, only this perspective can explain the negativity of selfconscious life that conceives of nature as otherness, negates it and sets up a selfreferential order of concepts, norms and values.
Barba-Kay’s article addresses the relationship self-conscious life establishes
with the condition of being alienated from the historical dimensions of accepted
and shared norms. Alienation is a distinctive Hegelian topic and this contribution
interestingly deals with it from a naturalistic perspective delivering a novel interpretation derived from the transformative character of the theoretical methodology of the Phenomenology of Spirit. Dean Moyar’s contribution deals with Hegel’s
conception of freedom as the result of what he calls “reversal of consciousness”,
namely the transformative and adaptive character of self-consciousness to evolve
a distinctive shape within the historical contexts. This delivers a conception of
freedom as the result of a developmental process, rather than as a brute fact like
in the transcendental outlook by Kant. Moyar’s merit is to highlight that the adaptive and living character of self-consciousness dramatically changes our understanding of what freedom is by organically connecting life and the normative.
This entails that the notion itself of liberty is not what is transcendentally deduced
by reason, but rather something that is socially acknowledged and embodied by
the historical becoming of consciousness and social interaction.
Hegel’s Jagged Understanding of Self-Conscious Life
17
Finally, Andrew Werner’s article raises objections to the very recent interest
in organic life in the Hegelian studies by underlining the fact that the notion of
organism requires to appeal to something external to the organism itself in order
to understand its development. I personally do not agree with this criticism because it disregards the fact that the compelling aspects of Hegel’s idea of organism
are based on the assumption that life establishes a distinctive relationship with the
external reality, which differs from the relation of cause and effect. The kind of
“surplus of significance” (Varela 1979) of life over mechanical world is what
makes organisms able to enact the normative principles of their own homeostasis,
namely of their own wellness, making this effort the principle of every dialectical
relation to the otherness. Therefore, it does not seem to me inappropriate to link
the speculative character of reason to the features of the organic life at all because
the former already has speculative elements of interaction with the surroundings
even though in an unaware form. Nonetheless, Werner’s contribution has the
merit to point out that we can only understand the living organism if we account
for its relational property, rather than if we conceive of it as an independent and
isolated unity.
References
Brandom, B. 1994, Making it Explicit, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Foot, P. 2001, Natural Goodness, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Franks, P.W. 2005, All or Nothing, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Goldblum, N. 2001, The Brain-Shaped Mind, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hegel, G.W.F. 1997, Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A.V. Miller, New York: Oxford
University Press (PS).
Hegel, G.W.F. 1970, Philosophy of Nature, III, ed. and trans. M.J. Petry, London: Humanities Press (PN).
Hegel, G.W.F. 2007, Philosophy of Mind, trans. A.V. Miller and W. Wallace, New
York: Oxford University Press (PM).
Hegel, G.W.F. 1969, Science of Logic, trans. A.V. Miller, Amherst: Humanity Books
(SL).
McDowell, J. 1996, Mind and World, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Pinkard, T. 2012, Hegel’s Naturalism, New York: Oxford University Press.
Pettit, P. 1996, The Common Mind, New York: Oxford University Press.
Tomasello, M. 2014, A Natural History of Human Thinking, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Varela, F. 1979, Principles of Biological Autonomy, New York: Elsevier North Holland.
Science, Thought and Nature:
Hegel’s Completion of Kant’s Idealism
Katerina Deligiorgi
University of Sussex
Abstract
Focusing on Hegel’s engagement with Kant’s theoretical philosophy, the paper
shows the merits of its characterisation as “completion”. The broader aim is to
offer a fresh perspective on familiar historical arguments and on contemporary
discussions of philosophical naturalism by examining the distinctive combination of idealism and naturalism that motivates the priority both authors accord
to the topics of testability of philosophical claims and of the nature of the relation between philosophy and the natural science. Linking these topics is a question about how the demands of unification—imposed internally, relative to
conceptions of the proper conduct of philosophical enquiry—can accommodate
realism, a key element in establishing disciplinary parity between philosophy
and the natural sciences. The distance that ultimately marks Kant’s and Hegel’s
answers to this question justifies the interpretative claim about completion,
while the conceptual patterns exemplified in the posing of the question and in
their shared assumptions about its philosophical importance justifies the reconstructive claim about “idealist naturalism”.
Keywords: Naturalism, Unification, Realism, Actuality, Regulative and Constitutive ideas, System, Dialectic.
I believe that everything that happens
is natural even if we do not
know the cause of it
(Sophie to Leibniz, 20/30 October 1691)1
1. Introduction: Idealist Naturalism
Characteristic of philosophical naturalism is the aspiration to bring philosophy
close to the natural sciences. From a historical perspective, particularly
interesting is a set of projects that seek to naturalise philosophy in order to
1
Leibniz 2011: 101.
Argumenta 4, 2 (2019): 19-46
ISSN 2465-2334
© 2019 University of Sassari
DOI 10.14275/2465-2334/20198.del
20
Katerina Deligiorgi
secure its traditional ambitions in synthetic theory construction. The aim is to
establish continuity between philosophy and the natural sciences not through
methodological convergence or reduction, but by assigning to the natural
sciences the role of an external tribunal on substantive philosophical claims.2 A
well-discussed example, which illustrates how such a tribunal might function,
uses STR, a scientific theory that does not privilege any frame of reference as
giving the real or most fundamental answer. STR counts against the philosophical position of presentism, which states that only what is present exists; natural
sciences can be called to adjudicate a philosophical dispute.3
The historical positions I want to discuss in this paper share the concern
with testing substantive a priori claims—for Kant, left unchecked, pure reason
risks stultification by antinomy, for Hegel, thought without proper bounds degenerates to mere abstraction and indeterminateness4—yet, instead of turning to
natural science for help, they undertake to renew metaphysics, by showing that
philosophy is capable of self-testing and has a legitimate claim to disciplinary
autonomy.
Without ignoring the force of socio-historical reasons, such as the worldly
success and academic prestige of the natural sciences, there is an important theoretical reason that explains the modern move towards science. Functioning as
a hidden premise is the Humean thought that reason does not have its own domain. If this is accepted, then one can engage in any number of critical renewals
of metaphysics, without seeing a point in defending the disciplinary autonomy
of philosophy. 5 The purpose of the paper is to show what happens when this
premise is not accepted in conjunction with acceptance of the need for testing
philosophical claims and for proximity to the natural sciences. This conceptual
space is occupied, I will argue, by Kant and Hegel. This claim does not amount
to and does not aspire to be a novel interpretation of their work, it is rather an
attempt to cast some familiar arguments in a different light, that cast by the discernibly similar concerns of a group of contemporary naturalists. The main advantage of this way of presenting matters is the broadening of the context of justification of certain idealist theses, beyond the historical one of their gestation
and formulation. To emphasise this point I shall refer to “idealist naturalism” as
a genus with two species.6 I introduce below the salient features of the genus by
2
For a representative range of views that explicitly link meta-philosophical issues, such
as those outlined here, with a favoured version of the relation between philosophy and
science characteristic of contemporary philosophical naturalism, see Hawley 2006,
Maudlin 2007, Papineau 2011. I am not implying that the scientific tribunal is the only
tool in the contemporary naturaliser’s critical arsenal, but it is prominent among metaphysical naturalisers.
3
The rejection of presentism does not render the competing position, eternalism, true.
For illuminating discussion of this example that highlights the complexities of what I call
here, using Kant’s metaphor, a “tribunal” see Hawley 2006.
4
The indeterminacy of bad metaphysics is vividly illustrated in the “Preface” to the Phenomenology of Spirit as “the night where all cows are black” (Hegel 2005: 94).
5
The thought here is that criticism of metaphysics does not amount to its rejection; the
point is nicely made in Callender 2011.
6
Unless otherwise indicated by the context of the discussion and stated explicitly, e.g.
footnote 16, I will not be using “naturalism” in any of its bewildering varieties; since I
find I am in agreement with those who doubt the usefulness of general applications of the
term in philosophy; see M. De Caro’s Introduction to Putnam 2016.
Science, Thought and Nature
21
focusing on a small methodological difference with substantive implications
about the nature of the task at hand. This difference marks out decisively the
idealist from the contemporary naturalist; simply put, the nature of the continuity between philosophy and the natural sciences gives rise to a first order task,
whereas the testing of philosophical claims, without cutting philosophy off from
all other disciplines, with analogous claims to adding to our cognitive stock, is a
second order task.
(i) “Continuity”, as I shall use the term from now on, describes a first order
philosophical task; philosophy must offer support for the work of the natural sciences. Specifically, philosophy must make available to empirical science a realistic account of the relation of thought and nature that does not require supernatural appeal (to a divine epistemic guarantor for example). If philosophy succeeds in this task, the gain is twofold: science is explanatorily self-sufficient and
it is informative about things, not about the ideas in the mind.
(ii) “Testing” describes a second order task: to ensure that the content of a priori
reasoning is sound. The reason that testing is plausibly an internal matter is related to the first order task. On the one hand, the sort of realism sketched as desideratum for the first order task may be unobtainable. So that task may fail. It
is, however, a possible task for philosophy. This not a historical concession. Rather philosophy can engage in the supportive task because the two disciplines belong to the same genus: rationally organised thought. Once this is foregrounded,
it is not unreasonable to expect that philosophy will have something to say
about the nature of this genus. Asking philosophy to say something about the
nature of thought is not outrageous, but does assume a degree of faith in philosophy’s own critical tools and methods. Internal testing in turn presupposes a degree of disciplinary autonomy.
But now it should be obvious that the challenge consists in holding (i) and
(ii) together; other things being equal, one has still to establish the downward
transition from setting out what is philosophically achievable—the second order
task about the nature of thought in general and its implications for sub-species of
the genus—to the first order task. The challenge is to show how and why whatever is found to belong to the genus of rationally organised thought has anything
to do with the world we found.7
2. Kant: Unity and the World
A more prosaic way of saying that philosophical claims answer to a philosophical tribunal is to say that philosophy has its own method, specifically that it has
a method that is distinct from those of the natural sciences. The question then
arises how can the claims its tribunal vindicates have any bearing on the natural
sciences? Kant’s answer is that internally tested claims about the fundamental
character of rational thought, whether such thought is justified a priori or a posteriori, yield results that also have a role in sustaining realism about the relation
between thought and nature. I will seek to show what counts in favour of this
bold claim by reconstructing first Kant’s response to the second order problem
about testing and in the following section his defence of realism that addresses
continuity.
7
I take the phrase, “the world we found”, from Sacks 1989.
Katerina Deligiorgi
22
2.1. Unification as a Goal of Science and of System
Kant solves the problem of testing of philosophical claims by providing a cognitive goal, which names a value that is sought across all domains of rationally organised thought that aims to yield cognitive gains. The assumption that there is
one such goal is debatable.8 Contextually, however, the idea that there is a single
goal to enquiry that can also function as its guiding value, to which any other values are subordinate, makes sense in light of the goal articulated by Kant’s rationalist predecessors, to map in a systematic way asymmetrical ground/grounded relations; attaining this goal enables the enquirer to realise the value of full rational
transparency about all phenomena. One important formulation of this epistemic
goal presented as a principle that directs enquiry is PSR, the principle of sufficient reason. In some of its stronger interpretations, in Leibniz, PSR motivates
the search for a reason that is causally powerful as well as explanatorily complete and given the demandingness of the “why?” question only a supernatural
reason that combines creative power and elective rationality can satisfy.9 One of
the results of Kant’s testing of philosophical claims is that such reason is unavailable. From an external perspective, that Kant reaches this result is of minor
interest, if reaching it requires other commitments that, other positions which
consider themselves theoretically less burdened with such traditional expectations; I will consider some of these arguments, to see how Kant’s position holds
against them.
Kant’s solution to the second order problem about testing is to accept the
intuitive appeal of PSR but turn the principle on its head. PSR assumes that
there is a systematic whole and sets the task of enquiry as tracing the connections that sustain the whole. Kant makes “unification” a goal for thought (Einheit).10 Very generally put, the aim of rationally organised thought is the attainment of unity (see Ak 18:225). The basic function of unity is the identification of
a domain of enquiry through general rules that characterise the objects belonging to the domain, concepts that are appropriate for these objects, in the sense
that they yield claims that can be adjudicated within the domain and set the
standard of epistemic expectations appropriate to the domain.11 Compared to
8
A good reference here is Thomas Kuhn (1977: 330-39), who in attempting to mitigate
the impression of his influential theory of scientific revolution, sought to identify objective values, such as accuracy, consistency, simplicity, scope and fruitfulness, which have
a good claim in fact to drive cognitive efforts in science, but more important can form a
sort of scientific virtue ethics for choice theory. Though Kuhn does not use this terminology, his alertness to the development of each virtue, interpretative nuances and the difficulties of having maximal instances of all in each case suggest sympathy with a virtueethicist approach.
9
By “explanatorily complete”, I mean a thesis that connects truth and explanation: given
some proposition the true reason that explains it belongs to a whole chain of reasons that
even for contingent truths is ultimately a priori and dependent on the divine creative act
and choice (see VE II 275-78; Gr 287-91 and GIV 427-63).
10
Einheit of course is “unity”. I use “unification” to describe the project of unifying, its
conditions, rules and degrees of attainment, that allow the value to be variously realisable. The significance of this will emerge at the end of this section.
11
To clarify: epistemic expectations are about the nature and strength of the criterion
and/or process we use to assess beliefs in the domain (what some epistemologists call
“warrant”). Although Kant deals with the more familiar topics in epistemology about
opinion, knowledge and belief in the end of the Critique, in the third section of the “Can-
Science, Thought and Nature
23
PSR, unification adds an extra step of reflection about the sort of reason we seek
and the sort of object domain in which such a reason can explain.12 Domain
specification allows for specific claims to be tested in their appropriate domain,
but also most importantly it allows kinds of claims about objects in a domain to
be tested in light of the epistemic standard expected and achievable within the
domain. This very general account leaves a lot of questions, such as how are
unifiers for domains chosen, how are epistemic standards set, whether they are
revisable, and so on. I will deal with these larger issues by engaging first with a
much narrower application of unification in the domain of science, both to add
some detail about the attractions of unification and create a foil for the distinctive features of the Kantian variety.
Kant famously describes science as a “a whole of cognition ordered according to principles” (Kant 2004: 14). This claim anticipates twentieth century arguments in favour of unification presented by Michael Friedman, and subsequently, in a more programmatic fashion, by Philip Kitcher.13 Friedman sought
to recover a non-psychological conception of understanding that tells us what is
of value in scientific explanation, namely that it “reduces multiplicity of unexplained, independent phenomena to one” (Friedman 1974: 15). This unification
“increases our understanding of the world by reducing the total number of phenomena that we have to accept as ultimate or given” (ibid.).14 Kitcher (1989) argues that unification can replace available models of explanation, because it reduces fundamental incomprehensibilities and by showing how explanations are
parts of sets, it allows connections to be made across regions of the set. So unification encompasses gains we ordinarily value in scientific enquiry: it is generative—“can be used in the derivation of a large numbers of sentences which we
on of Pure Reason” (A 820/B 848- A 831-B 859) and extensively in his Lectures on Logic.
So throughout this section “epistemic” will be a reference to the set of issues just specified and not the relation of belief and knowledge or knowledge and truth, although limited mention of these latter topics will become relevant while treating the “epistemic” issues just specified. It is also the case that epistemic issues of that sort have a semantic
dimension.
12
The claim rests on the assumption, which I also attribute to Kant, is that explanation is
not the only task reasons fulfill, they also justify, make plausible, make mandatory, make
possible, make good until further notice and so on.
13
Friedman (1974: 8) and Kitcher (1981: 508) trace antecedents in classical work n explanation; that they are also both extensively engaged in Kant scholarship is perhaps not
unrelated to their sensitivity to the value of unification. But just a Kantian look at the
classical nomological account of explanation would find the latter fatally incomplete.
Briefly DN starts from the basic description of scientific tasks as finding answers for
“why?” questions that arise about the “phenomena in the world of our experience”
(Hempel and Oppenheim 1948: 136), these answers take the form of the discovery—or
formulation—of law-like generalisations, which function as major premises in arguments
that particular phenomena to count as instances of the law. What is perplexing, from a
Kantian perspective, is the assumption that there is a link between major and minor
premise. Absent support from a realist conception of a creative divine will, to which
Kant’s rationalist predecessors were able to appeal, law-like generalisations are mere unification devices for a range of different phenomena.
14
Interestingly, the unifiers that permit this overall reduction of what we accept as brute,
need not be intelligible, they render things familiar but may in themselves be “strange” or
“unfamiliar”; since what matters are the relations of intelligibility they make possible
within and across sets of phenomena.
24
Katerina Deligiorgi
accept” (1981: 514) and economical, because uses “few patters of arguments”
and hence minimizes “the number of types of premises we must take as underived” (1981: 529).15
Critics argue that unificationist accounts promulgate a long defunct ideal of
systematicity. Nancy Cartwright, for example, argues that the expectation that
our knowledge of the world can be held together in one unified whole is dubious; a more fruitful approach that is also truer to actual scientific practice is to
embrace local unities (Cartwright 1983: 3-4, and 2000). Accepting the proposal,
renders the use of “world” somewhat forced, since all we may speak of is the regions to which our concepts are addressed or perhaps temporal stretches during
which our concepts hold. The challenge is explicitly anti-realist and antifoundationalist. Shorn of the ambition to have non-discursive content as its object, unification continues to play a useful role directed to cognitive practices, by
alerting us to look at what holds together the community of enquirers, such as,
shared methodology, sets of interests and so on.16
Two important points emerge from this anti-unificationist challenge. First,
and irrespective of how contemporary unificationists defend their positions,
Kant seems vulnerable to the criticism that he is simply in the grip of an obsolete
model.17 However, as I will argue shortly, this picture is back to front: it is the
need for testing that drives Kant’s unificationist proposal, not some residual attachment to systematicity.
Second, the anti-unificationist arguments cast light in the incipient antirealism of contemporary unificationism. It is telling, for example, that, in another
paper, Friedman (1997) vindicates a role of philosophy in science as mediator
between Carnapian external questions; philosophy provides the concepts that
enable communication among different linguistic frameworks, and while these
concepts and the theories to which they belong may be transitory and herme15
“Science uses the same patterns of derivation again and again for different phenomena
and in doing so it shows us how to reduce the types of facts we accept as ultimate or
brute” (Kitcher 1986: 504). There are both more recent versions of unificationism and
some parallels I left unexplored between epistemic and metaphysical aspects of reduction: the ability to place a maximum number of diverse phenomena under a small number that are accepted as brute lends itself to questions about ontological basicness and hierarchy, which are important but not relevant to my argument.
16
I run together here different projects: Catherine Elgin 1996 and Helen Longino 1998—
though they are much closer in their focus on interest than Longino 2001 which emphasises shared method. Elgin develops a Goodmanian argument in favour of a sort of unity
that is the system in reflective equilibrium, i.e. a system that is maximally tenable and
this is a “worthy epistemic goal” (1996: 99) because it is rationally cohesive (“the elements are reasonable in light of one another”, ibid.) and the whole is “reasonable in light
of the objectives we originally espoused” (ibid.). Systems in reflective equilibrium “are
tethered not to Things in themselves but to our antecedent understanding of and interest
in the matters at hand” (1996: 107). Longino 1998 argues for theoretical pluralism and
against monist unification, which aims at the resolution of dissension (1998: 197), the local unities she allows reflect dominant theoretical interests at particular times (1998: 23031). Longino 2001 allows for unity of community of researchers with shared standards
and methods of evaluation (2001:148) but remains agnostic about whether their findings
form a whole or present as a plurality of non-congruent accounts (2001: 140).
17
Kant often contrasts “system” and mere “aggregate” (A835/B863) and describes his
thought as an architectonic whole, which he then defines this as “the art of systems”,
where “system” is “the unity of the manifold cognitions under one idea” (A832/B860).
Science, Thought and Nature
25
neutically mutable, they occupy that external space intelligibly.18 Philosophy
can treat belief revision in the same way as it can revolution in belief systems, by
supplying the tools for classifying them as instances of conceptual transformation, rather than of mere reaction to facts (Friedman 1997: 19). Rational recovery of what can seem arbitrary or merely opaque is essential to securing
philosophically another naturalist commitment, which we have not discussed so
far, and which comes from Quine’s conception of the totality of human
knowledge as a vast interconnecting nexus of beliefs from which no belief is
immune to revision (Friedman 1997: 7). By incipient antirealism I mean that the
defense of the rationality of belief revision and theory choice, more generally, of
scientific rationality depends on positing a convergence over time of the different unifying frameworks and so this is an internal process of adjustment not convergence to an “entirely independent reality”; all epistemic and semantic claims
are framework relative (Friedman 2001: 118). If Kant’s unificationism took this
form, then it would not be suited to the first order continuity task, which is, programmatically at least, to defend realism.
Although Kant has his own versions of the advantages of unification, especially in passages where he defends the importance of a systematic unity in cognition (e.g. A 645/B673), and applications to other domains of rational thought,
what he sees and its contemporary defenders do not, is its testing function; its
promise as a solution to the second order problem of testing of philosophical
claims.
Unification is achieved by a set of rules that set out the object domain for
the proper conduct of the enquiry. The rules can be derived from concepts
which function to unify the domain, e.g. “objects of experience”. As the rules
become clear through analysis and argument, the epistemic expectations appropriate to the domain settle. Unification is not a minimalist achievement, since
no unifier is self-explanatory and most rules have contrastive applications in
other object-domains. Nonetheless having the full theoretical goal in view is not
needed for testing: since in most cases philosophical claims fall short because
they ignore one or more of the rules that set out the object domain of the enquiry. Testing allows for the systematic demarcation of domains to which philosophical claims can be made and the epistemic force they can carry.
The testing procedure is more vividly illustrated in the negative part of the
Critique. Rationalist metaphysics seek to provide secure foundation for natural
sciences by way of unshakeable propositions about metaphysical facts. Kant’s
diagnosis in the antinomy is that such facts do not appear to constrain in any
way the claims made about them (this is a general thesis following from the Copernican Revolution). The solution is to demarcate the kinds of things that can
be said about the objects that belong to the domain. The reflective failure Kant
calls “dogmatism” can be remedied through a systematic programme of reflection on what it takes to predicate anything of anything, ranging from the most
ordinary objects of daily experience, to the most extraordinary ones (e.g. God).
Different rules establish different sets of kinds of objects by establishing, through
critical argument, the kinds of things that can be said about the objects. The de18
The role of philosophy I attribute to Friedman here is highly reminiscent of the mediative role Longino 1998 envisages between concurrent localities that are not congruent but
also the unification model defended by Gemes 1994 who champions a model of unification that aims at reconciling incompatible claims.
26
Katerina Deligiorgi
marcation rules or concepts set out the epistemic aims that are permissible within each domain but also the best in epistemic terms that is achievable, namely
objective judgements about objects in the domain.19
The idea that different rules establish different domains of thought about
objects needs further qualification if we are to avoid ending up with a Kantian
mosaic. At the same time, if rational demarcation is a priori in the sense of unrevisable, the model is implausibly conservative. The full account, which also
shows what is distinctive about Kantian unification requires the following three
crucial qualifications:
(1) The unification of the domain of possible objects of experience holds a special role in the project, since it offers us both conditions of objective judgements
about such objects but also conditions of reference, and empirical cognition.
Although it has all the general characteristics of unification as testing given
above, it is also set apart. Terminologically, Kant marks it out by calling the unifying concepts that serve within the domain, constitutive of the domain. The special role of this unification is justified, because empirical cognition is of a certain
standard, which other putative objects of thought lack. Although this lack has
implications about what can be said about such objects, the positive task of reflection and boundary setting continues with the identification of domains in
which these objects can have a role though what Kant calls regulative ideas.
(2) Regulative concepts or ideas are fascinating because of the great diversity of
unifying domains and epistemic tasks they help define. Some regulative concepts are functionally purposeful for the conduct of a specific enquiry; “fundamental power” (A 649/B677) is recommended as one such example. Such abstracta help unify specific scientific programmes, by making present—providing
a focal point—an item such as “fundamental power” that helps relate empirical
findings across the research domain. The fact that fundamental power is not
subject to cognitive constraints, and so not a cognition, means that the domain
it unifies, while it contains cognitions—claims about specific powers—comes
with different epistemic expectations about the warrant of its claims; which is
simply to say it is a complex theoretical domain not a set of individually verifiable empirical statements. Other regulative ideas have a wider unifying remit,
“world” for example define a domain in which sets of laws apply securing uniformity in their application under the limited warrant of the set unified by
“world”. The testing element consists in accepting that we have no justification—and none is plausibly forthcoming—for thinking that inductive rules apply.
19
In the Anglo-American reception of Kant’s thought there is a strong tradition of interpretation focusing on his epistemology, possibly under the influence of interpretative
choices by Kemp Smith (see Hanna 2006: 6) but most obviously in the so-called epistemic interpretation of appearances and things in themselves most influentially perhaps defended in Allison 2004 (a revision of the 1983 volume; but see Stang 2018 for a fuller account). What I aim to show is that epistemic concerns, such as the conditions of objectivity, epistemic warrant, and both in a priori specified domains and a posteriori ones
(which admittedly Kant does not explicitly tackle except perhaps in the Anthropology) are
an important part of the critical theoretical project but they are sandwiched so to speak
between a foundational layer that aims to establish realism and an upper layer that directs us through a kind of absolute objectivity that is not theoretically available.
Science, Thought and Nature
27
Regulative ideas define domains of enquiry and “regulate” the epistemic
expectations appropriate for the domain; they establish the degrees of objectivity
appropriate for the claims made in the domain. Although Kant treats scientific
enquiries briefly here, it seems that the more mature the enquiry, the more
populated the domain, the more established the rules employed within it, and so
the more “unified” it is. So the greater degree of unification within a domain
goes with the collective achievement of objectivity within the domain (“collective” because it is not a matter of a single rule or insight; this view is very close
to modern unificationism and even accommodates some of their critics). The
testing role of unification with the use of regulative ideas comes from rejection,
not just of specific metaphysical theses purporting to communicate facts, but also, an implication of this traditional and orthodox interpretation of the Critique’s
destructive power is the rejection of rational or divine guarantees about the necessity of some domains and its contents, and, more positively and less widely
recognized, the possibility of a renewal of metaphysics (across the board). What
creates critical friction and tests the regulatively unified domains is that regulative ideas are modally fragile and so conceivably revisable, which means that
some may be found to have exhaust their value, if, for example, a claim of a
kind that is permissible within the domain creates impermissible conclusions
down the line.20
(3) Testing by unification is a systematic process of critical reflection, that is
suited to the task because it works by engaging with the philosophical claims
about objects in order to identify what can be said about such objects. When we
move from constitutive to regulative it is not clear how to understand Kant’s repeated claims that there is a need for unity emanating from reason itself (e.g.
A302/B359). One way to look at this is that there must be a further conception
of unification that can guide our efforts at organised rational thought and be
testing of such efforts as a whole. So far, all unifiers, constitutive and regulative,
come with conditions for their application and domain restrictions. The question is whether a unifier that is free of such limits is conceivable. Kant uses repeatedly a term that specifies what holds objectively without qualification, “the
unconditioned” (see B xx-xxi, and esp. A 322-323)—or “absolute” (A 324-6)—
but only to chastise reason for seeking to know it. So PSR, which would be the
obvious candidate, is already rejected once we take the path of testing by domain demarcation. While Kant withdraws from us the prospect of a theory of all
theories, he opens up the possibility of critical reflection about the aims of rationally organised thought and the goals we set in undertaking such thought
20
I do not have the space to develop my account of regulative ideas and the unities they
make possible in dialogue with existing commentary. With the possible exception of Paul
Guyer who connects with unity with the idea of systematic happiness (Guyer 2001: 94),
most interpreters give variations of the epistemic interpretation I offer here, though not
all agree about the success of Kant’s argumentative strategy (Guyer 1997: 42). Philip
Kitcher discusses the unificatory role of regulative ideas, as I do here, but also their function as meta-rules for the application of the categories, which implicates them in the constitution of experience, in ways that are deeply problematic as I explain below. Hannah
Ginsborg (2017) incorporates regulative ideas and systematicity in an entirely original
reading about the conditions of nature as an object of human judgement. My interpretative aim is to show the possibility of aligning narrow and broad cognitive aims (see Massimi 2017) while allowing a non-reductive architectonic between the resulting unities (see
Gava 2014).
Katerina Deligiorgi
28
through what he calls a “cosmopolitan” idea, which relates “all cognition to the
essential ends of human reason (teleologia rationis humanae)” (A838-39/B866-67).
The rule that gives these ends is objective in the requisite sense, i.e. unconditional, because it is the ought contained in the moral law, which specifies the
practical ends of reason (A832/B860).
What I tried to show in this section is (a) that unification is a procedure for
testing theoretical claims in general and philosophical claims in particular; (b)
that it allows for maximal reflection and reflexivity about a range of specific scientific enquiries, and as a result, it admits of degrees; (c) because the different
regulative unifying projects can be more or less mature, the model fits the more
theoretically developed contemporary unificationist projects; (d) unification incorporates reflection on the broader aims of the unifying project itself, which introduces topic-transcendent axiological concerns, about what enquirers should
have in view as objective guiding standard, and ultimately about their moral
practical identities and the nature of essential human ends; (e) finally, and this
leads to the topic of the next section, although domain specification is key to
unification and the task of testing, the whole edifice is anchored on a conception
of experience that sustains empirical realism.
2.2. Realism and Unity
The concepts that unify the domain of possible objects of experience set a high
standard of objectivity because of their modal force and scope.21 They are testing
because they function as rules determining a priori what is possible to say about
such objects; so classes of claims that fall foul of these rules are ipso facto philosophically adrift. In addition, because they are constitutive, that is, they spell out
all the necessary conditions of “one universal experience” (A 110), when they
fail to obtain, there are no objects of experience (which is not to say there may
not be perceptions).22 By implication, if something meets these rules of unity
(A302/B359), it cannot fail to be an object of experience, that is, no additional
anti-sceptical arguments are needed to exclude putative simulacra (see A
493/B21). The epistemic status of constitutive concepts clearly surpasses that of
regulative ones. Nonetheless, there is no hiding that qua unifiers constitutive
and regulative concepts perform the same role: they define the appropriate epistemic expectations for a domain of objects, the domain that is appropriately unified by the said concepts. And they do so after careful critical argument, that is,
as part of the process of philosophical thought’s self-testing. Crudely: they earn
their status and have their role defined by pure reason.
If, as I claimed at the outset, continuity with science, on the idealist naturalist view, requires the defence of realism, it is not clear how the fruits of this
essentially internal exercise in reflection and mapping can be of help. In what
follows, I will identify a distinctive feature in the unification of the domain of
objects of experience, which, allows for a very different style of thought to
21
For excellent treatment of this topic see Ameriks 2017.
The parenthetical remark aims to draw attention to the distinction between perceptions, which are subjective, objective perceptions, which are “cognitions” and so, given
their conformity a priori to the constitutive rules of the domain for objects of experience,
can become items of knowledge that is objective and of objects; this is the basic claim.
For discussion of “cognition” see Willaschek and Watkins 2017.
22
Science, Thought and Nature
29
emerge alongside its paradigmatic execution of the epistemic tasks of unificationism—indeed unification of the domain of objects of experience functions
like the steel core in the construction of the theoretical system.
Let us start with considering how constitutive concepts fulfil their epistemic, i.e. domain-defining, functions and how they differ from regulative ones.
Consider a regulative concept, “world”.23 When Kant shows that the examination of deductive arguments purporting to state facts about the object thought
through this concept, and so to enrich our concept, fails, the critical reader
learns that the thought about the object does not constrain one way or another
what can be said about it. This discovery affects the concept’s unifying function
for the domain of natural laws, the expectation of uniformity is a concessive rule
for scientific research. Consider now a constitutive concept, “substance”. When
Kant sets out the conditions of its use, he does not examine what facts about the
concept can help establish its credentials (this comes much later in his examination of common misuses of the concept). Constitutive concepts or categories are
picked up from the table of the most general forms of thought, forms that have
general organisational functions and no remit to regulate content (see B 166-67).
In order to become constitutive of the domain of the objects of experience, their
use must be constrained, and it must be constrained not ad hoc but in accordance with a rule; the constraint that applies as an unexceptional rule is the formal features of the objects of the relevant domain, in short, their spatial and temporal form.24 Space and time are the necessary a priori conditions of all outer
and inner experience, they are pure forms of sensibility (e.g. B 66, A 49). These
forms set the basic epistemic rules for the domain by directing the use of the
concepts that have a claim to constitute the domain (a claim that gets its main
defence in the transcendental deduction). Forms of thought about objects of
possible experience bear a special relation to the form of their possible objects
before even the task of vindicating their applicability to such objects is undertaken. This distinctive feature of unification at this level allows Kant to pursue side
by side an epistemic unifying project, which I will outline briefly below, and a
project about reference that sustains empirical realism.
First though, some questions about method are in order. Kant has plenty to
say about the conscious representation of objects of experience, or “objective
perceptions” (A 320/ B 376-77). Why does he avoid talking about the objects of
these representational states as intentional, referring and so on, and insists on
their dependence on an internal relation of unification in a judgement (e.g. A
79, B 105)?25 The unity of judgement is just the application of the basic unifying
rule for the domain just spelt out, it is a unity of a priori sensible and discursive
forms through which alone, as will be shown in the transcendental deduction,
objects of experience can be thought. Note: there is no additional argument
23
Throughout, I use “concept” to mean thought, concepts in the tradition I consider here
are not the same as words, though the distinction is not systematically discussed. But the
deep issue that is at stake and becomes especially urgent for Hegel is about thought and
things and about the form of thought that is about things.
24
Kant announces this already in B73, which constrains judgments to spatio-temporal
objects, before even tackling transcendental logic.
25
The question does not depend on an intentionalist interpretation of judgement, such as
proposed by Aquila 1983, it raises a conceptual issue, the importance of which is recognised by Kant (see A 320/B376; A 491/B 519.
30
Katerina Deligiorgi
about what it takes for such thoughts to be about objects of experience; does
Kant think there are no general conditions of reference? Or is this a secondary
concern?
To understand his method, I think it is important to have in view Kant’s
possible interlocutors. The task of specifying the domain of objects of experience
is undertaken in response to a piece of philosophical inheritance Kant considers
a dead-end. To the untutored mind, the experience of objects in one’s surrounding environment seems plausibly described as a relation the experiencing subject
has with some of those objects; for Kant, the basic realism of this thought is
something to be preserved. The philosophical inheritance he wants to undo describes this same relation as a self-relation, because what is given to the subject
is, on reflection, some idea or impression, in short, mental content. The experiencing subject has direct access to its mental content; it has no direct access to
the worldly objects the content is—presumably—about and is in weak epistemic
position with respect to these objects. One of Kant’s innovations is to separate
epistemic objectivity from reference to real objects, yet address both topics with
the same tools. Here is the problem he inherits: the experiencing subject can get
a criterion for objectivity from the inside, by scanning mental contents to identify qualitative differences. Alighting on features such as clarity or luminosity,
which only some mental items possess, proponents of this method claim success
in identifying what is suitable for inclusion as basic components in a system of
knowledge and candidates for sound premises in an inference that secures reference to extra-mental reality. In recognition of the fragility of their position, they
grant a supernatural being the role of mediator or guarantor for the validity of
such inferences.
If we see Kant as responding to this piece of philosophical inheritance, the
first task is to show that some a priori concepts unify unexceptionally—and
without need of further anti-sceptical argument—the domain of objects of experience. Domain specification is part of an argument that aims to show that an a
priori and systematic distinction between “subjective” and “objective” is attainable.26 This argument is given in the deduction: instead of the epistemic subject
being engaged in the empirical task of scanning mental contents, it gets the a
priori role of unifier of the domain of objects to which concepts apply, and so as
the subject of the judgement we mentioned earlier, it is part of the solution to
the epistemic problem.27
Still the problem of reference remains and is perhaps even more urgent given Kant's entirely a priori answer to the question of what is a possible object of
experience. The deduction, and indeed the discussion that follows in subsequent
sections about the validity of constitutive concepts, assumes the truth of the
26
Note that at this stage, subjective is good enough to stand from what is minddependent, dreams, illusions, but also biases indoctrinations, epistemic egoism as Kant
puts in it the Anthropology need additional analysis because they are more complex
problems (“the idea of a public use of reason” is part of the response).
27
Strawson folds objective validity and objective reference in stating that the requirement
can be satisfied by distinguishing “awareness of objects […] from experiences of them”
(Strawson 1966: 24). The source of the problem is the strong anti-sceptical aims Strawson
attributes to the argument, for which a thin notion of experience as mere sensory input is
acceptable; this leads to a strong transcendental argument of the form [necessarily (a, b)].
Unfortunately the overall strategy leads to irrealism, which is incompatible with Kant’s
aims.
Science, Thought and Nature
31
basic premise of the deduction, which is that a manifold is given to us through
the senses.28 But what is given through the senses is not transparently clear. If it
is mental content, as per Kant’s predecessors, then the problem of reference is
how we can relate it in a principled and systematic way to the objects of experience that causally affect the subject.29 The epistemic account gives us the form of
thought for any putatively objectively referring representations, what is missing
is an explanation of how such representations put us in contact with their objects; correct epistemic form needs supplementation with an account that captures even minimally genuine reference.
All we have is assurance of something given throughout senses (which the
epistemic criteria presumably will allow us to distinguish from illusions or
dream). The given are “representations of the senses” (A 2; see also B1), the
contact that pre-philosophically secures reference is through the senses, and
Kant give is a philosophical role as the purely sensible content of the representation (see B 129; also earlier B 127). The discussion can get side-tracked at this
stage back to epistemic issues about primary and secondary qualities and relational or other knowledge we may have of objects given to us through our senses. But this is not the issue here: it is rather more generally “representation” itself, which while it has a priori form, Kant states, it does not “produce its object
as far as its existence is concerned” (B 125, A 93). The question is what within
the theory sustains this independence claim, while at the same time securing
some contact with the object in terms of such existential independence (otherwise we can have a theory of reference that is too generous and includes even
hallucinated objects). The answer, I will argue, is contained in the distinctive
feature of unification of objects of experience.
The form of thought for any putatively objectively referring representations,
and so judgements about objects of experience, comes down to a rule for correct
use of the copula “is” (B 141) or a rule of the “is” of predication in the relevant
domain: the use of a priori concepts is restricted through a priori forms of sensibility. Shadowing the “is” of predication is a rule for the “is” of existence for objects of experience: that they have spatial and temporal properties, necessarily.
The contact we sought is thus established through the existential interpretation
of the “is” of predication. This is to say simply that the spatially and temporally
modulated “is” of existence captures the most basic features of empirical object
awareness, namely that something is there, now, or that it was there for a period
of time in the past, or that it is now further away, or that it was here and that
now it is are no more. Note that the ideality of space and time does not affect
their role as realist reference markers, since the reference we seek to secure is to
28
We know this from the Aesthetic: “The capacity for receiving representation through
the mode in which we are affected by objects is entitled sensibility. Objects are given to
us by means of sensibility” (A 19, B 33). There is a causal account that describes the
“how?” of this relation (see the quote above and A 86, B 118; B 125), but there is outstanding a philosophical account of the general nature of this relation. Ameriks’s regressive approach helps highlight this and makes space for the realist interpretation I offer;
Ameriks allows a thick notion of experience as truth-evaluable and transcendentally examinable in the form of (a, necessarily b).
29
The causal relation, while true (read A 19, B 33; A 86, B 118; B 125 and of course
plays a role in the “Refutation of Idealism”), is not for Kant the way to deal with either
the epistemic (which are ultimately quid juris?) or the metaphysical questions posed by
objects of experience.
32
Katerina Deligiorgi
objects of experience which are objects of possible experience.30 Time and space
as realist reference markers align with the untutored belief that our senses put us
in contact with objects of experience; that we do not infer them, we are in contact with them. The epistemic and referential “is” work together to give us the a
priori conditions to sort out basic first-hand mistakes of experience, provided of
course there is some empirical judgment made about the experience.
The advantage of this minimalist realism is that it does not commit to a discussion of the referential properties of empirical representations and what truthconditions they have. This is a tricky question in any context, but especially in
the Kantian in which any obvious option (e.g. isomorphism) would be beyond
our capacity to know it (because of our ignorance of things as they are in themselves) and this limitation has traditionally thought to count against realism.
Still, something more ought to be said about the content of empirical representations because if, as some quotes suggest, this is just the “raw material” awaiting
conceptual form, then the objects we encounter will be just spatio-temporal cyphers.31
I will conclude by following a hint given in the claim that empirical representations are cognitions.32 Cognitions are typically representations that are in the form
of judgements, so they are conceptualised content. What is philosophically interesting, however, is that “cognition” stands also for the availability of sensory cognitive content. The topic of availability is of interest because it asks us to think how
such content is about objects. The issue is delicate because the “about” lies between the causal story of our connection to the world (and the proper functioning
of the causal channels that are our senses) and the general terms we use to refer to
it when we do, that is, the words we use and which allow us to do this not because
they are magically connected to the objects they name.
Here is a suggestion for filling that in between space: the senses are causally
involved but it is for a task: they are our species-specific information reception
30
“Possible experience” is the referential equivalent of the epistemic “possible objects of
experience”. The role I give the existential copula is compatible with Kant’s denial that
being is not a real predicate (A 598/ B 626); the existential “is” adds indeed nothing to
the concept of the object.
31
Regarding empirical content see: “the impressions of the senses supplying the first
stimulus” (A 86, B 118), Kant also speaks of impressions in the A and B Introductions he
talks about the “raw material of sensible impressions”. One strong motivation for recent
non-conceptualist readings of Kant is the loss of the heterogeneity thesis that is at the
heart of his theory; see Allais 2004. However, note that an unexpected advantage of formal referring criteria is that Kant can deal with exotic “experiences”, the temporal and
measurable values called “observables” in modern physics which do not inhere on a substance as classical and indeed epistemically well-attributed Kantian properties do.
32
By “beings like” us I mean to refer only to our kind of perceptive powers and functioning; it seems obvious that it is a general phenomenon of an animal’s sensory capacities
putting it in touch with their surrounding environment. But beyond this natural phenomenon that is the province of science, as Gaskin 2006 argues, there is for human experiencers the problem of reference and the genuineness of their sensory input. Though I take
a rather speculative path in developing this point, there is a line of commentary that aims
at similar defenses of realism, which are both detailed and scholarly, see Allais 2004 and
Westphal 2006. My own aim or rather hunch in following this path is that if we allow particulars in the Kantian account, these cannot be just spatio-temporally identifiable, and
then if we make them instantiations of properties in judgements we have lost them as
particulars.
Science, Thought and Nature
33
system, more simply: they are how beings like us learn first-hand about their environment.33 The looks, sounds, feels of things, the manifold of qualitatively varied sensory content is just information about our environment, which once received, needs classification, identification, retrieval and so on, in order to be
recognizable as a “message”—in order to be learning—we pick from our environment; so this first hand awareness of information-rich world, or, more radically our being in information rich states just by virtue of being in informationrich environments, requires reduction into a manifold so that we can put sense
to judgement, to epistemically evaluable units.34 The point of this—admittedly
sketchy—fuller realist picture is that we depend for information on receptivity
and on the channels that convey it and this is the case for sensory content as it is
for email content and so on; and of course the picture is realist while allowing
that something counts as information if some receptor gets it.
Acceptance of this last speculative suggestion does not affect the overall argument that unification of the objects of experience can fulfil both testing and
continuity tasks, all thanks to the dual role of the a priori forms of sensibility,
which restrict the use of a priori concepts, while identifying the necessary properties that existing objects of experience possess, thereby securing reference for
scientific empirical statements.
3. From Kant to Hegel
I hope that the previous two sections have done enough to show how the idealist naturalism I attributed to Kant has at its disposal sophisticated tools to address both the testing and the continuity tasks that it shares with some contemporary naturalist programmes in philosophy. Having Kant’s project in view is
indispensable for understanding Hegel’s starting point about what is philosophically possible, his identification of what is necessary, the so-called “completion”, and his expectation of what is achievable.35
A contextual clarification is perhaps in order here. Already in my use of the
term “idealist naturalist”, I distance myself from two prominent lines of inter33
The novel term is “information”, which I borrow an early formal account of transmission/reception (Shannon [1993 [1943]: 7). Formalism is an advantage because it allows us
to consider empirical content as having a role, a cognitive one in fact, without the need to
enter into the conceptualism/non-conceptualism controversy. In information theory, it is
acknowledged that the word is not context invariant, but rather it changes according to
fields in which it proves useful (Shannon 1993:180). This too is attractive because it fits the
dynamism and variety of our sensory systems. Generally, it is accepted that “information”
can also have a number of physical or material realisations (see Drestke 1981 for an attempt
to offer a semantic account). All this goes against the most famous perhaps philosophical
appreciation of information theory by Daniel Dennett (2017) who sees it as supporting the
exact reverse view of senses I presented here (Dennett 1988). The speculative piece with
which I conclude this section is an invitation I read in Kant’s argument about empirical representations to let go another piece of philosophical inheritance in which the senses are just
a maddening philosophical problem about qualia.
34
I keep deliberately underdetermined these tasks because my proposal can co-exist with
both non-conceptualist and some conceptualist interpretation; the issue being of course
the nature of the manifold of these received contents (for passages suggesting its dependence on concepts see A 77, B 102-103; A 105; B129; for passages that do not see A 116).
35
The original source of the term “completion” is Hegel’s letter to Schelling dated April 16,
1795 (Butler and Seiler 1984: 35).
Katerina Deligiorgi
34
pretation. One, now relatively obsolete, interprets Kant as honorary positivist,
who asks that our knowledge claims be restricted to empirical facts. The other,
still current, interprets the move from Kant to Hegel in terms of the progressive
emancipation of philosophy from the vestiges of rationalist metaphysics, in favour of naturalism, understood now broadly, as a programme for re-orienting
philosophy, by specifying a domain of philosophical enquiry and the type of answers that are acceptable. While seeds for each interpretation can be found in
the relevant texts; they risk recreating, in historical garb, a vexatious twentieth
century choice between the rock of a naturalistic vocabulary that can appear too
restrictive and distorting (Stroud 1996: 48) and the hard place of “expansive”
and “open-minded” naturalism, which reduces to mere attitude of “openmindedness” (Stroud 1996: 54).36
On my reading, Hegel shares Kant’s concern with the autonomy of philosophy and its relation to the natural sciences. He seeks to justify its authority and
its claim to autonomy, by showing how it can successfully perform the testing
and continuity tasks, which he also sees as vital in properly conceptualising the
relation of philosophy to the natural sciences. Despite the element of “completion”, which I shall soon explain, Hegel’s idealist naturalism is no more nor less
“idealist” and no more nor “naturalist” than Kant’s.
Anticipating somewhat, I will argue that Hegel’s need for completion is
presented first in terms of resolving a problem with unification and testing he
identifies in Kant. At the same time, once this problem is resolved, it gives a different shape to the continuity task, the aim remains the philosophical provision
of a realistic account of the relation of thought and nature that does not require
supernatural appeal (to a divine epistemic guarantor for example). The term
“realism” tends to be too broad, so to narrow down its Hegelian sense is the
search for a position in which items do not admit of further interpretations, conceptual schemes or what have you, they acquire a certain stability, how this is
achieved is through the idea that thought is capable of specifying particularity,
perfectly and without any remainder. “Completion” then has both the sense of
this positive claim about thought—thought itself accomplishes itself, so to
speak—and the more traditional, relational sense of engagement in deep and
critical dialogue with Kant.
3.1. Hegel: Unification as Self-Knowledge
Hegel’s commitment to the systematicity of thought is not only explained by the
solution unification offers to the problem of testing philosophical claims. Testing
remains, nonetheless, a central motivation both to expanded and systematically
interlocked unification project he undertakes and to the dialectical logic that
binds the whole together.37 The sense of “completion” that is relevant to this
section is the relational one, because the need for completion arises from the
36
For a defence of resolute naturalism, see Rosenberg 2011; expansive naturalism is defended in McDowell 1994.
37
For an excellent account of the commitment to systematicity see Sandkaulen 2017. On
dialectic see Winfield 1990. At the same time there is considerable overlap in aims with
the epistemic function of unification in Kant and the range of projects to which this is
relevant. For an indication of the range of these projects, empirical and philosophical see
EL §12: 16-18, and also the ideas of “unity” and “system” in EL §14 and §15. The points
are repeated again in EN §250 and Remark.
Science, Thought and Nature
35
identification of a problem with constitutive unification. Specifically, Hegel argues that at the constitutive level, unification fails, because the definition of the
object domain is incomplete, the domain is disunified. The problem is that
alongside the positive account of experience Kant gives, he allows for an “other
world”—the “negative of every image”, the “Thing-in-itself” (EL §44: 72). The
thesis about our ignorance of things as they are in themselves leads to suspicion
of the credentials of the categories as objective forms; they are, Hegel says,
“merely our thoughts, and separated from the thing as it is in itself by an insurmountable gulf” (EL §50: 83).38 The problem, as Sally Sedgewick recently put it,
is that “we have no grounds for supposing that [the subjective form of experience] reveals the reality of the given sense content itself” (Sedgwick 2012: 136).
To say that things as they are in themselves are a problem for testing and
ultimately for philosophical autonomy sounds like an odd diagnosis of Hegel’s
criticism, since, as Sedgwick puts it, it is the reality of the objects of empirical
representations that is threatened by a competing thing with a claim to being real. Note that if we go down this path, it is easy to fold epistemic and referential
issues, since if what we thought was real is merely what we count as real, it is
the “counting” that matters. To put it differently, our ability to make fine epistemic distinctions is not affected (indeed, historically this problem has been taken as an opportunity to transform all questions into epistemic ones).39 I take a
different view of the criticism.
To make the problem Hegel identifies perspicuous let us start by drawing a
parallel between what we may call the positive and the negative application of
the criterion of conformity to the a priori conditions of human sensibility, space
and time. Earlier we saw that the a priori forms of sensibility have an epistemic
role in restraining the application of a priori concepts to possible object of experience, thereby securing their proper use; they also have a role in establishing
minimal realist reference for empirical representations. When it comes to things
in themselves, we have an epistemic thesis about ignorance, the negation of the
same criterion: we do not know things as they are in themselves because they
are not things that appear in space and time. The negative application of the criterion establishes a priori a case of ignorance but also, because this is the only
known feature of the things in question, it yields an a priori criterion for ontological commitment to these unknowns, which states that some things are real
just in case they are in every respect independent of our cognitive abilities. The
problem, which creates a need for “completion”, is the threat of metaphysical
realism, a position that defines a domain exclusively through its transcending
our unifying abilities, yet qua domain of it is unifiable, albeit a unifier with other
38
Sedgwick 2012 gives an exemplary analysis of the standard view of the Hegelian criticism; see Houlgate 2016 and Stern 1999. The reading I attribute to Hegel, which aims to
minimise the ontological commitments of the thesis without entirely suppressing them is
inspired by an early suggestion by Ameriks concerning Kant’s ongoing reflections on his
relation to traditional ontology (2003: 133).
39
The ontological version of the criticism can be found in Hegel (e.g. EL §45: “the things
immediately known are mere appearances—in other words, the ground of their being is
not in themselves but in something else”) but not in order to explain the subjectivism
charge, rather Hegel here criticises Kant for not following through to the “step of defining what this something else is” (ibid.). I think the thesis I attribute to Hegel in the following section can make sense of this claim; for an alternative view see Kreines 2007.
36
Katerina Deligiorgi
abilities, e.g. a divine unifier.40 Even as a possibility, metaphysical realism is a
threat because it unpicks all the hard work of the constitutive unification and
undermines its results, namely that a systematic a priori relation between objective and subjective is possible and within human reach. For this reason, Hegel
complains that we are left with merely our thoughts.
It is worth noting that although Hegel’s criticism fits more naturally the socalled two-world interpretation, it is applicable to the two-aspect interpretation,
which states that we can only know things given certain conditions and that abstracting from such conditions in the hope of identifying features of mindindependent reality is a self-defeating enterprise. We may engage in such abstraction entirely legitimately, when we consider things not as putative objects of
experience but as they are in themselves. From a Hegelian perspective, the claim
that they are thinkable invites a question about the possibility of this thought.
On the two-aspect interpretation, possibility is just the absence of contradiction
in the thought of one thing under two different aspects. The truth of this possibility is put at risk by the unknowability of one of the two aspects and a way to
stabilise the position is to grant these thinkables ontological weight and bring
metaphysical realism back in the picture.
“Completion” is the removal of this threat through strengthening the epistemic gains of constitutive unification. In effect, Hegel’s systematic writings can
be viewed as a heroic project of constitutive unification, which aims to show for
a whole range of concepts how their application is relative to object domains
and how, conversely, object domains as unified through appropriate forms of
thought. For Hegel unification has to be ambitious in order to account for the
diversity and range of human experience, but also systematic in order to resist
the centripetal force of such diversity and range. For each object domain, e.g.
nature or mind, which are the two on which I focus mainly here, unification will
be internally differentiated through appropriate concepts and by the same means
formative of a system. The aim is to achieve a unified whole or a “totality”,
which, Hegel clearly acknowledges, is a philosophical demand: in “our ordinary
thinking the world is grasped as an aggregate of finite experiences” (EN §247
Zusatz, 16) but philosophy requires conceptual order to be established out of this
aggregate. So, for example, “nature is to be regarded as a system of stages one arising necessarily from the other”, this is not “generated naturally”, it is a matter of
the “idea” (EN §249: 20). Given the ambition of Hegelian unification, it seems
hard to maintain that this project can contribute to testing philosophical claims,
or, looking ahead, that it will have anything to contribute to the realist requirements of the continuity task. I will focus on testing here and take up the continuity issue in the next section.
Testing is integral to the unifying process. The test is whether some candidate concept is cognitively up to the task. The testing is entrusted to dialectic,
now upgraded from mere logic of illusion, to thought’s own way of checking on
40
The implied contrast between empirical and metaphysical realism can mislead in various
ways. I attribute to Kant empirical realism, in the sense of realism about reference. I attribute to Hegel the view that metaphysical realism, as here defined, is problematic. Nothing
follows from this about how Hegel deals with continuity, more precisely whether this requires commitment to some form of realism on his part. So, the position I present is sharply
at odds with Tom Rockmore’s diagnosis about Kant and Hegel’s rejection of metaphysical
realism in favour of epistemological constructivism (Rockmore 2005: 219).
Science, Thought and Nature
37
its own claims. Hegel uses dialectic to show the limits of certain forms of
thought, he then allows these forms to play out in full their limits, in the expectation that there is some further as yet indeterminate object or object domain
that the concept, in failing its prior determining task, may yet adumbrate, thus
opening up a new domain of philosophical enquiry.41 The effect of this procedure is twofold: the proper limits of concepts are set, but because they are set in
a dynamic fashion, by allowing over-extension of concepts, there is no absolute
limit to conceptual reach and so no limit to the unifying process as a whole; ignorance is relativized to particular epistemic expectations attached to particular
concepts, which they partly meet partly fail and so on.
Guiding Hegelian unification are three basic theses about cognition, which
I reconstruct below and illustrate with reference to the “Philosophy of Nature”
and the “Philosophy of Mind”.
(a) The first thesis concerns the cognitive insufficiency of concepts use that present as having too few links to other concepts or as inadequately differentiating
between essential and nonessential characteristics of the object studied.
In the discussion of nature, Hegel describes these as giving us the “external” relations of nature. The cognitive problem arises thus: “in the sphere of nature contingency and determination from without has its right, [...] especially
concrete individual forms, [...] the immediately concrete is a form of properties
external to one another and more or less insufficiently related to one another”
(EN §250: Remark 23). Given the task, which is to conceptualise the “infinite
wealth and variety of form” (ibid.) of nature for the purpose of studying it, these
external relations are a problem: “nature everywhere blurs the essential limits of
species and genera by intermediate and defective forms, which continually furnish counter examples to every fixed distinction” (EN §250: 24). Parallel difficulties arise in the study of mind: if we stay in the context of ordinary
“knowledge of men” which is limited to their “particularities, passions and
weaknesses” (§377: E 9). Amassing such knowledge cannot give knowledge of
the “universal”, of “mind itself” (ibid.).42
(b) The second thesis is that for each domain, a systematic set of hierarchically
ordered concepts is discoverable that stands in ordered relations to other domains.
In the case of nature to grasp the idea of it we need to look at the detail of
“its various specifications and then bring them together” (EN §244: 4). The
41
In the “Philosophy of Nature”, for example, Hegel writes that it is through its own dialectic that nature “breaks though the limitation of this sphere” and attains the “higher
stage”, which is “Mind”. This is a prime example of how Hegel uses dialectical overextension of a concept to relate different object domains. From one point of view the
claim is incredible, mere over-extension. From another point of view, notably the section
on the soul in the “Philosophy of Mind”, it opens up for philosophical discussion a
whole range of features such as age, physical location, affective state of being, which affect minds but are also of natural givens, and so help clarify concepts of selfhood and selfcontrol.
42
While Hegel’s way of putting the problem may sound old-fashioned, the problem he
describes has been central to the philosophy of biology, even when pluralism is proposed
as the best solution (see Dupré 2012); and philosophically, it is a legitimate question to
ask after the essential possibilities of things. For a more robust defense of Hegel’s argument see Houlgate 1998.
38
Katerina Deligiorgi
“thinking consideration of Nature” (EN §246: 6) systematises and unifies
through examination of the different “specifications”, that is, theoretical attempts to explain how different elements, features, relations, and so on relate to
one another. The test is whether the concepts by which “progression and transition” in nature can “be made clearer” (EN §249: Remark 20).43 So while the
unificationist aims provide some criteria for testing, it is also the case that the
project is bounded by the theoretical material available to philosophical scrutiny, namely the concepts in use by specific sciences. The idea is that by focusing
more narrowly on the ways in which nature confronts us as an object of study,
in mechanics, physics, organics, it will be possible to generate a dialectic sufficiently potent to identify concepts that have a legitimate claim to objectivity,
which does not derive just from the currency of their use in the natural sciences.
The “totality” (EN §244: 4) that unification ultimately seeks is not a mereological aggregate, nor yet artificially organised; it is a systematic unity that has not
lost its contact to the multiform natural given.
In the study of mind, the dialectic is conducted through criticism of existing
unifying projects, such as rational psychology, for example, the study of the soul
and its attributes, which Hegel dismisses as “pneumatology”, “an abstract metaphysic of the understanding” (EM §378: 11). The problem is that it treats the
mind—or soul—as an inert thing with properties, e.g. simplicity and immateriality. He is equally critical of empirical psychology, which makes the mind object
of scientific study, but effectively dissolves it into a multitude of explanatory notions such as forces and faculties that correspond to the various things minds do
(EM §381: 12). Again, we can characterise unity proleptically as a notion that
makes space for the activities described in empirical psychology, but not as a
“mere aggregate” (EM §381: 12), and makes sense of the properties identified in
rational psychology, but not as belonging to an inert substance. While formally
the process of unification parallels that of the “Philosophy of Nature”, the aim is
no longer objectivity and scientificity—at least as these might be ordinarily understood—but the proper understanding of mind, which is subject and object of
the study; accordingly, the vocabulary describing the success of unification is
more demanding and task specific and, therefore, defies quick summary (see
EM §386: 22-24).
The systematic expansion of object domains, such that include domains
that are conceptually elusive (nature) or only abstrusely characterised (absolute
spirit or mind), amounts to the expansion of the critical study of the range of
conditions of cognition, that is, the relevant unifying concepts. Thesis (b) establishes that if these conditions don’t apply some others do; as a result, Hegel
manages to relativise anything that would play the role of the negative epistemic
criterion which, on his criticism of things in themselves, yields an ontological
one with disastrous consequences. But it is thesis (c), below, that closes the door
on the possibility of some a priori unknowables, by spelling out what exactly is
at stake in unification.
(c) The third thesis is that unification can count as a cognitive gain, if the accomplishment of the unification task is not decided ad hoc, but rather obeys a
43
In the fuller account given in the Logic Hegel describes how the new concept is also
“higher and richer than the preceding—richer because it negates or opposes the preceding and therefore contains it, and it contains even more than that, for it is the unity of itself and its opposite” (SL-dG 33; cf. SL-M 54).
Science, Thought and Nature
39
criterion that is the same across the whole range of domains, yet also internal to
each; the only criterion that fits, and is such that it does not allow for any remainder, is if the achievement is stated as form of self-relation.
Self-relation is not a mark of cognitive gain, if we consider it a trivial matter; nor is it a cognitive gain, of the type sought, it we consider it an eternal
truth. Hegel describes a relation between thought and thought, e.g. the philosophical analysis of the organising concepts of the natural sciences, which aims
at identifying the appropriate form of thought at every stage and with regard to
every object domain of reflective thinking. The systematic and critical demands
that shape this kind of self-relation—which continues, after a fashion, the project of the self-criticism of pure reason—sustain its cognitive ambitions and give
some means by which to judge what is gained at different stages of unification.44
3.2. Open-Mindedness and Particularity
The Hegelian species of idealist naturalism, as presented so far, seems entirely
taken by the tasks of unification and testing, leaving no obvious entry point for
what we called at the start a realistic account of the relation between thought
and nature that can sustain continuity. More generally, the very ambition of
Hegelian unification can raise a question about the possibility of making a convincing case, within the system, about the reality of the source material that
gives us the object of our “thinking study” (EL §1: 4). I will argue that continuity is served by a position that attempts to give more precise shape to the particulars identified in the Kantian defence of realism about reference. The Hegelian
version resembles semantic realism, insofar as it is about the relation between
meaning and meant for a range of value terms. The similarity can mislead
though, because, on Hegel's account, the relation can be one of perfect match,
which would leave the two relata only conceptually distinct. The basic argument, which does not easily fit contemporary philosophical categories and positions, is a defence of “actuality”.
By way of introduction, it is useful to consider a criticism Hegel addresses
to Kant concerning the doctrine of things as they are in themselves, which does
not target the epistemic damage incurred by its ontological commitments, but
rather the limitations of Kant's metaphysical ambition. In the Encyclopaedia Logic, Hegel writes: “the things immediately known are mere appearances—in other
words, the ground of their being is not in themselves but in something else” then
takes Kant to task for failing to take the “step of defining what this something
else is” (EL §45).
One way to interpret this complaint is as if it came from a rationalist metaphysician: the request for ground is the request for what accounts for the things
immediately known. Hegel would then be asking Kant to provide a sufficient
reason why things known are as they are. The request presupposes belief that
such reason exists (whether known to us or not). Such belief is justified on the
basis of commitment to PSR. As we said earlier, PSR is regressive, leading to a
necessary being that stops the regress. But PSR has a logical as well as epistemic
44
The interpretation and indeed the formulation of thesis (c) depends on the unificationist
topic of this section; other more familiar ways of stating (c) include subject-object identity, or the speculative closing of the gap between spontaneity and receptivity (see Sedgwick 2012); or the gap between ontology and epistemology (see Miolli 2018).
40
Katerina Deligiorgi
and metaphysical role, and as such it responds to explanatory demands of a particular subset of events, those that are the product of intelligent action. No
mechanistic explanation provides sufficient reason for those, because mechanistic explanations do not have the requisite internal connection between intelligent choice and action; only reasons do this, and ultimately only reasons that
are formed of valuations concerning what is best to do. This is Leibniz’s deep
insight into PSR: it is intimately connected with the doctrine that actions are
undertaken under the guise of the good. If we look at the world as the result of
divine choice and action, then PSR guides us to the idea of optimality as explanatory for the divine choice embodied in the creative act. It is for this reason
that Kant himself in his pre-critical writings adopts a form of PSR he terms “determining reason”, meaning a reason that explains the existence of contingent
beings. Theodicy just falls out of this set of connections. I think this interpretation of Hegel’s complaint is not the right one, but it is one that matters for understanding his positive claims.
Another way of interpreting Hegel’s complaint about Kant’s silence over
grounds is that he identifies a weakness in Kant’s defence of realism about reference, namely that it leaves something out that matters for realism.45 The thought
is this: a description of experience that only allows for spatio-temporally indexed
instantiations of properties leaves out an essential part of that same experience,
namely that it consists of encounters with particulars. If a way can be found to
attend to this feature of experience philosophically, then that of which we make
a thinking study will have been acknowledged and the continuity demand fulfilled. But how can we attend to this feature of experience? All we have at our
disposal, besides spatio-temporal indices, which don’t give us more than positions in a grid, are concepts and concepts are promiscuous. The sort of attention
Hegel considers appropriate is the sort that explains how a particular is the way
it is; the aim is not to show how it is for some subject, which is the phenomenological way of attending to the particularity of experience, but rather to show
how the particular stands objectively as such in relations that uniquely identify
it. This is what the theory of actuality, he sets it out in the Science of Logic, aims
to achieve.
When Stroud recommends “open-mindedness” (Stroud 1996: 54) as general philosophical policy, he could not have in mind the Science of Logic despite
the fact that it presents itself as an example of extreme open-mindedness, or in
Hegelian terms “presuppositionlessness”. There is a long and interesting debate,
about the nature of “presuppositionlessness”, or whether it is achievable, desirable, and to what extent Hegel achieves it.46 This debate is not directly relevant to
the problem at hand, though of course it does give an idea of the distinctiveness
of the Logic, which is also a unificationist project: the object domain is forms of
thought. But it seems odd to try to describe, in parallel with other unification
45
I believe that what I am about to argue resonates, while differing in detail and material
for the argument, with Paul Redding’s diagnosis regarding the notion of the “singular”
(Redding 2007) and its fate in the analytic reception of Hegel’s philosophy esp. the diagnostic chaps 1 and 2. On a conciliatory interpretation of his work on the logical singular
and my claims about actuality these are two ways of reaching the same goal; however,
Redding has also championed actualist interpretations of Hegel that are at variance with
mine.
46
See e.g. Winfield 1990, Houlgate 2006.
Science, Thought and Nature
41
projects, a relation between forms of thought and concepts. Furthermore, at this
level of abstraction, it seems very difficult to show that the forms of thought are
sufficiently constitutively independent to what it is they determine and so worthy of a dialectical examination to prove their claim to thought. This is where
the rationalist metaphysical position outlined earlier is helpful in clarifying is going on in the Logic. Hegel’s aim is to show that forms of thought can be determined and that their determinations can be shown to be right, without external
rightness criteria.47 How this comes to be a philosophical problem can be illuminated through PSR. If PSR is assumed and the divine mind and will are bracketed out of the account, what is left is a demand for a “determining” reason
(Kant’s adaptation of “sufficient”). Absent the regress-stopper, the demand
translates as a philosophical examination of what sort of determining determining reason does. The logical object is the function of determination, which Hegel calls, determinateness or Bestimmtheit. So, unification aims at the perfect determination of Bestimmtheit.
The logical unifying project is carried out just like other unifying projects,
through a priori reflection on candidate forms of thought that have a prima facie
legitimate claim to persist in thought. Determinateness or Bestimmtheit is the
achievement of determination. After consecutive partial successes and partial
failures of determination, the Logic reaches, in the penultimate section, the topic
of the good. The gradual transformation of the task of determination from logical to axiological corresponds to the Leibnizian insight that PSR and GG are
connected or that there is an explanatory nexus between determining reason and
goodness; goodness is the ultimate explanation. At the same time, in the context
of the Logic, full determinateness is the achievement of the perfect particularisation of the form of thought it is about, so full determinateness is in itself the realisation of a value. That the value of determinateness is achieved in the topic
“good” suggests that the solution to the particularity question is not topic neutral, in other words, that unique determination of particulars is a matter of their
identification as good.
In “The Idea of the Good”, one of the problems is trying to determine the
good or whether something is good.48 This in turn manifests as a problem of determinateness and presents us with the task of identifying what is genuine good
and separating it from impositionist concepts that stamp “good” on a neutral
value-free world—“realm of darkness” (SL 731). Impositionism is unsatisfactory, if we want our ideas to be true. But we are ex hypothesis not in position to
recognise the true good, since we have no prior determination of it or a way of
checking how a thought is to be compared with something real. The solution is
to move away from this static model and think of the good in terms of a practical form thought. A practical form of thought is not an attempt to copy an idea
onto reality, but rather to give weight to certain considerations in doing something, realising some end. With respect to values, or at least good, determination
is not a theoretical matter of adding but a matter of doing something on the ba47
It is worth noting that presuppositionlessness contains another important clue, a relation to the Kantian notion of “unconditioned”. So in a way that parallels Kant, it can
designate the search for a thought that can bring unity across different unifying formal
systems of thought.
48
The following is a simplified summary of arguments I have presented in detail in
Deligiorgi (2020a, 2020b).
42
Katerina Deligiorgi
sis of the good, thus realising the good. But obviously not all such realisations
are guaranteed to be good, people make mistakes, misread situations, misunderstand their own motives and trains of thought.
A basic way of understanding actuality, as Hegel uses it in this section, is as
determination that is full, error-free and leaves no room to doubt. In earlier sections of the Logic, actuality is contrasted with empty possibility and with abstraction; so something would be actual if it is really possible, so instantiable, and also if it is actually instantiated, and has some content. But since our problem
now is with the practical determination of the good, we need a different sense of
actual that tells us more that it is instantiable and that it has some content. We
want an “actual” that gives us the full good and nothing less than that. The notion of “actual” here is explicable in terms of determinateness that is maximal or
“complete” (SL 731). This transformation of determinateness into an axiological term allows actuality to count as a value, because actuality just is maximal
determinateness. But this is not just a cheaply earned terminological equivalence: if we say for some region x is actual we are saying that in that region x is
maximally determined, there is no proposition that is true of that region that
contradicts x and at the same time x is specified in that region fully, without any
gaps.
The upshot of this discussion is that the value of “good” is fully realised, if
the good becomes actual, that is, if reality is considered as the consistent set of
all true value propositions.49 A worry can arise here about how a unificationist
project, which uses contradiction in the dialectical testing of claims, yields all of
a sudden a characterisation of reality that has the virtue of actuality. Reality, as
fully determinate, is the result of the progressive clarification through testing of
the function of determinacy and what is tested is nothing other than the determining powers of forms of thought with a putative claim to capture reality (or,
at the start “being” as such). The criterial role of consistency depends on the
truth of value propositions and this, in turn, depends on the realisation of good,
in a way that admits of no exceptions, no gaps or contradictions, or some unforeseen effect that diminishes the goodness and so on.
Still there are two puzzles about the actuality of the good, the first about
how maximal determinateness is achieved, and the second about why it is
achieved with a value term, namely the good? The first puzzle arises because
Hegel seems to claim that “good”, a notion that is semantically rich, can have
extensional relations of fit, of the sort that are possible only with logical or
mathematical notions. On way to achieve full determinateness is to indefinitely
enrich the meaning of “good” so that it includes exceptions, conditions and so
on. But Hegel is not proposing this. Rather he argues that the good successfully
determines reality if the familiar yet not fully determined notion is correctly attributed in all cases in which it is used. One condition for this is that the subject
term of the evaluation is fully determined, so that there are no hidden, unknowable, or in potentia elements to it. This is just a description of a uniquely identifiable particular. The assignation of goodness as a predicate for such a subject is
the identification of a constituent element of it as its form of goodness: the particular is not identified with the good, nor is yet an instance of the good, rather it
49
I do not use this in a technical sense, “claims” or “sentences” would be just as good,
the drawback being that they distract for introducing in the wrong place the thought of
putative subjects making these claims and uttering those sentences.
Science, Thought and Nature
43
is identifiable as good. This is what allows the goodness of each particular to be
correctly acknowledged while the term remains stable across all its applications.
Unique identification is the corollary of the maximal determination of reality:
this is an abstract definition intended to acknowledge the particular, the missing
“ground” of the things in themselves.50
The second puzzle about the value term is relatively easy to solve because
from the start the enquiry is about the goodness of determinateness and seeks to
achieve such goodness, which is finally actuality. The twist in the end is that
such, shall we say intellectual virtues, are not insulated from, but rather form a
part of a capacious conception of goodness, such that guides actions in practical
syllogisms. And while actual working scientists may not find much that is directly supporting their research is such conclusion, the outline given here of Hegel’s argument about actuality in the Logic suffices, I think, to show the centrality of his concern with showing how thought about reality can be realistic, that
is, answer properly to what is.
4. Conclusion
By way of concluding remarks, I want to draw attention to one distinguishing
characteristic of the genus idealist naturalist, I sought to describe in this paper,
namely its commitment to philosophical autonomy. Autonomy is not just assumed; it is earned thought testing. The idealist conception of testing of philosophical claims borrows from rationalist metaphysics the idea that rational organisation places demands such that mere collections of contingently found
facts do not meet. The transformation of this idea from one with ontological and
theistic implications to a pure demand of rational thought, which rational
thought can and ought to be able to meet through its own resources, is key to
the vindication of autonomy. The upshot of instituting this internal tribunal is a
complex unification project—or set of projects—which correspond to the search
for external checks that contemporary metaphysical naturalisers seek, when they
turn to the findings of natural sciences. At the same time, in its narrow antisupernaturalism, idealist naturalism shows kinship with the broader naturalist
kind, such as expressed, for example, in Sophie’s remarks to Leibniz quoted at
the start of the paper. I qualified the anti-supernaturalism as “narrow” to indicate that there is space for transcendent elements and for a conception of the divine in both Kant and Hegel’s thought, simply not as a result of commitment to
logical or epistemic principles. As for the different ways in which each defines
the supporting role of philosophy in establishing continuity with the natural sciences by fulfilling a realist agenda, matters are complicated. Counterintuitively,
what counts as realism for Kant and for Hegel depends on acceptance of idealist
theses, which are neither straightforward nor uncontroversial even among interpreters of their work. The versions I outlined may well seem outlandish and unconvincing, and therefore inline contemporary naturalists to count their idealist
cousin as a mere historical curiosity. However, in seeking to broaden the context of understanding and justification for these idealist positions is to allow
50
The uniquely identifiable particular in this context is also usefully comparable to the
particularities Hegel dismisses in thesis (a), which we discussed previously, in the context
of motivating his unification project. From the vantage point of the Logic, such particularities can be described as insufficiently determinate.
Katerina Deligiorgi
44
consideration of the reasons shared that explain the philosophical possibilities
Kant and Hegel consider as promising and those they reject. As I argued, key to
their choices is the weight they both put to our capacity to think, and to the fact
that once the active nature of the exercise of this capacity is acknowledged, certain intellectual responsibilities follow that simply cannot be relegated or outsourced.51
References
Allais, L. 2004, “Kant’s One World: Interpreting ‘Transcendental Idealism’”, British
Journal for the History of Philosophy, 12, 4, 655-84.
Allison, H. 2004, Kant’s Transcendental Idealism. An Interpretation and Defense, Revised and Enlarged Edition, Yale: Yale University Press.
Ameriks, K. 1978. “Kant’s Transcendental Deduction as a Regressive Argument”,
Kant-Studien, 69, 1-4, 273-87.
Ameriks, K. 2017, “On Universality, Necessity, and Law in General in Kant”, in
Massimi, M. and Breitenbach, A. (eds.), Kant and The Laws of Nature, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 30-48.
Aquila, R. 1983, Representational Mind, Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Bird, G. 1982, “Kant’s Transcendental Idealism”, in Vesey, G. (ed.), Idealism Past
and Present, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Callender, C. 2011, “Philosophy of Science and Metaphysics”, in French, S. and
Saatsi, J. (eds.), The Continuum Companion to the Philosophy of Science, New York:
Continuum, 33-54.
Cartwright, N. 1983, How the Laws of Physics Lie, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Cartrwright, N. 2000, “Against completability in science”, in Stone, M.W.F. and
Wolff, J. (eds.), The Proper Ambition of Science, London: Routledge.
Deligiorgi, K. 2020a, “The Good and The Actual”, in Honneth, A. and Christ, J.
(eds.), Zweite Natur, Stuttgarter Hegel-Kongress 2017, Veröffentlichungen der Internationalen Hegel-Vereinigung, Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, forthcoming.
Deligiorgi, K. 2020b, “The Idea of the Good”, in Gerhard, M. (ed.), HegelJahrbuch, Berlin: Duncker & Humbot, forthcoming.
Dennett, D.C. 1988, “Quining Qualia”, in Marcel, A. and Bislack, E. (eds.), Consciousness in Modern Science, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dennett, D.C. 2017, “A Difference that Makes a Difference”,
https://www.edge.org/conversation/daniel_c_dennett-a-difference-that-makesa-difference
Dupré, J. 2012, Processes of Life. Essays in The Philosophy of Biology, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Elgin, C.Z. 1996, Considered Judgment, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Gasiorowicz, S. and Langacker, P. 1966, Elementary Particles in Physics, Wiley,
http://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/similar?doi=10.1.1.395.5166&type=ab
51
I am grateful to the editor Guido Seddone for inviting me to think about these issues
and his comments on an early draft. I also thank Joe Saunders for his helpful comments
(despite his relentless advocacy of classical pragmatism).
Science, Thought and Nature
45
Friedman, M. 1974, “Explanation and Scientific Understanding”, The Journal of Philosophy, 71, 1, 5-19.
Friedman, M. 1997, “Philosophical Naturalism”, Proceedings and Addresses of the
American Philosophical Association, 71, 2, 5+7-21.
Gava, G. 2014, “Kant’s Definition of Science in the Architectonic of Pure Reason
and the Essential Ends of Reason”, Kant-Studien, 105, 3, 372-93.
Gaskin, R. 2006, Experience and the World’s Own Language: A Critique of John McDowell’s Empiricism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ginsborg, H. 2017, “Why Must We Presuppose Systematicity in Nature?”, in Massimi, M. and Breitenbach, A. (eds.), Kant and The Laws of Nature, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 71-88.
Gemes, K. 1994, “Explanation, Unification, and Content”, Nous, 28, 2, 225-40.
Hanna, R. 2006, Kant, Science, and Human Nature, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hawley, K. 2006, “Science as a Guide to Metaphysics?”, Synthese, 149, 3, 451-70.
Hegel, G.W.F. 2005, Hegel’s Preface to the Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. and running commentary by Y. Yovel, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Hegel, G.W.F. 2010, Science of Logic, trans. G. di Giovanni, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press (SL).
Hegel, G.W.F. 1975, Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences (1830), Part I, Logic,
trans. W. Wallace, Oxford: Clarendon Press (EL).
Hegel, G.W.F. 1970, Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences (1830), Part I, Philosophy of Nature, trans. A.W. Miller, Oxford: Clarendon Press (EN).
Hegel, G.W.F. 1988, Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences (1830), Part III, Philosophy of Mind, trans. A.V. Miller, Oxford: Clarendon Press (EM).
Houlgate, S. 1998, Hegel and the Philosophy of Nature, Albany: State University of
New York Press.
Houlgate, S. 2006, The Opening of Hegel’s Logic, West Lafayette: Purdue University
Press.
Houlgate, S. 2016, “Hegel’s Critique of Kant”, Hegel-Jahrbuch, 1, 24-32.
Kant, I. 1900-. Kants gesammelte Schriften. vol. XVIII. Metaphysik Zweiter Teil (Ak).
Königlichen Preußischen (later Deutschen) Akademie der Wissenschaften, Berlin:
Georg Reimer (later Walter De Gruyter).
Kant, I. 1998, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. & ed. P. Guyer and A. Wood, The
Cambridge Edition of The Works of Immanuel Kant, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Kant, I. 2004, Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science, trans. & ed. M. Friedman,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kitcher, P. 1981, “Explanatory Unification”, Philosophy of Science, 48, 507-31.
Kitcher, P. 1986, “Projecting the Order of Nature”, in Butts, R.E. (ed.), Kant’s Philosophy of Physical science: Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaft 17861986, Reidel: Dordrecht, 201-35.
Kitcher, P. 1989, “Explanatory Unification and the Causal Structure of the World”,
in Kitcher, P. and Salmon, W.E. (eds.), Scientific Explanation, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 410-505.
Kreines, J. 2007, “Between the Bounds of Experience and Divine Intuition: Kant’s
Epistemic Limits and Hegel’s Ambitions”, Inquiry, 50, 3, 306-34.
46
Katerina Deligiorgi
Kuhn, T. 1977, “Objectivity, Value Judgement, and Theory Choice”, in The Essential
Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change, Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 320-39.
Leibniz, G.W. 2011, Leibniz and the Two Sophies. The Philosophical Correspondence,
Strickland, L. (ed.), Toronto: Centre for Reformation and Renaissance Studies.
Longino, H. 1998, Science as Social Knowledge, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Longino, H. 2001, The Fate of Knowledge, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Massimi, M. 2017, “What is this Thing Called ‘Scientific Knowledge’? Kant on Imaginary Standpoints and the Regulative Role of Reason”, Kant Yearbook, 9, 1, 63-84.
Maudlin, T. 2007, The Metaphysics Within Physics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
McDowell, J.H. 1994, Mind and World, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Miolli, G. 2018, “Hegel’s Theory of Truth as a Theory of Self-Knowledge”, HegelJahrbuch, 11, 1, 128-33.
Putnam, H. 2016, Naturalism, Realism, and Normativity, De Caro, M. (ed.), Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Papineau, D. 2011, “The Philosophical Insignificance of A priori Knowledge”, in
Shaffer, M.J. and Veber, M.L. (eds.), What Place for the A Priori?, La Salle: Open
Court, 61-84.
Redding, P. 2007, Analytic Philosophy and the Return of Hegelian Thought, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Rockmore, T. 2005, Hegel, Idealism, and Analytic Philosophy, New Haven: Yale University Press.
Rosenberg, A. 2011, An Atheist's Guide to Reality. Enjoying Life Without Illusions, New
York and London: W.W. Norton.
Sacks, M. 1989, The World We Found. The Limits of Ontological Talk, La Salle: Open
Court.
Sandkaulen, B. 2017, “Hegel’s First System Program and the Task of Philosophy”, in
Moyar, D. (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Hegel, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Shannon, C.E. 1993, Collected Papers, Gardner, W.A., Sloane, N. and Wyner, A.D.
(eds.), New York: IEEE Press.
Schlösser, U. 2011, “Self-Knowledge, Action and the Language of Confession in
Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit”, Hegel Bulletin, 32, 1-2, 269-68.
Stang, N.F. 2018, “Kant’s Transcendental Idealism”, in Zalta, E.N. (ed.), The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018 Edition), accessed January 2019,
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/kant-transcendental-idealism/
Stern, R. 1999, “Going Beyond the Kantian Philosophy: On McDowell’s Hegelian
Critique of Kant”, European Journal of Philosophy, 7, 2, 247-69.
Strawson, P.F. 1987, Skepticism and Naturalism. Some Varieties, London: Methuen.
Stroud, B. 1996, “The Charm of Naturalism”, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 70, 2, 43-55.
Westphal, K.R. 2006, “How Does Kant Prove that We Perceive, and not Merely
Imagine, Physical Objects?”, Review of Metaphysics, 59, 781-806.
Willaschek, M. and Watkins, E. 2017, “Kant on Cognition and Knowledge”, Synthese, online first: https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s11229-017-1624-4.
Winfield, R.D. 1990, “The Method of Hegel’s Science of Logic”, in di Giovanni, G.
(ed.), Essays on Hegel’s Logic, Albany: State University of New York, 45-57.
Hegel on the Naturalness of Logic:
An Account Based on the Preface to the
second edition of the Science of Logic
Elena Ficara
Universität Paderborn and GC CUNY
Abstract
The preface to the second edition of Hegel’s Science of Logic is crucial for understanding the idea of Hegel’s logic. It is an important text because what Hegel
writes is not an idiosyncratic view about logic, but rather something universally
true about the object, scope, and nature of logic. Something that can genuinely
dialogue with more recent, and perhaps more sophisticated, accounts of logic.
One central aspect of Hegel’s argumentation in the preface is the idea that logic is
natural. In this paper, I focus precisely on this aspect, addressing four Hegelian
theses about the naturalness of logic.
Keywords: Hegel’s logic, Natural logic, Natural language, Logical forms, Dialectics.
1. Introduction
The preface to the second edition of Hegel’s Science of Logic can with full rights
be counted amongst the classic texts of the history of philosophy. It is a classic
text because it presents in a stylistically beautiful (almost poetic) way one key
philosophical idea—the very idea of Hegel’s logic. It is classic in that what Hegel writes is not his idiosyncratic view about logic, but rather something universally true about the object, scope, and nature of logic. Something that can genuinely dialogue with more recent, and perhaps more sophisticated, accounts of
logic.
One central aspect of Hegel’s argumentation in the preface is the idea that
logic is natural. In what follows, I will focus precisely on this aspect, addressing
four Hegelian theses about the naturalness of logic, namely:
1. The forms of thought permeate all our thoughts, actions, feelings, desires,
representations and ideas. They are deposited in human language—they
“pass our lips in every sentence we speak”. They are the natural element in
which human beings live. Hegel calls this linguistic, logico-natural element
in which we live das Logische.
Argumenta 4, 2 (2019): 47-57
ISSN 2465-2334
© 2019 University of Sassari
DOI 10.14275/2465-2334/20198.fic
48
Elena Ficara
2. There is a difference between the unconscious use of the forms of thought
in everyday thinking and reasoning (natural logic), and their thematic consideration (logic as theory).
3. Logic as theory may be carried on in a limitative way, that is, when we
consider the forms either as means for us (whereby we are means for them),
or as merely accessorily attached to the content of our thought (whereby they
are what is basic and substantial about the content of every thought).
4. There is a difference between the treatment of das Logische in the logic and
metaphysics of Hegel’s times and its truly scientific treatment. While the
manuals of Hegel’s times “kill” the forms of thought, the task of logic as science is restoring the natural life of das Logische.
In the following pages I present these theses in more detail, asking: how do
they relate to current ideas about logic, and about the relationship between logical forms and natural language? In this context, I will limit myself to present
Hegel’s account, hinting in the conclusion at one idea suggested by Russell in
1914. It is the view that logical forms are deposited in human language and
thought, and that the task of philosophical logic is to “extract the forms from their
concrete integuments”, and render them “explicit and pure” (Russell 1914
[2009]: 35). This idea, which I call for simplicity E (from extracting forms), is explicitly shared by some contemporary philosophers of logic, among them Lowe
(2013: 1) and Sainsbury (2001: 1). In my view, E constitutes a genuine common
ground for a possible dialogue between Hegel’s idea of logic’s naturalness and
recent accounts of philosophical logic.
2. Das Logische is the Natural Element in which Human Beings
Live
As Hans-Georg Gadamer (1976: 78) pointed out, Hegel coins a new expression,
which cannot be found before him: “the logical” (das Logische). In the Lectures on
the history of philosophy, Hegel talks about the “beautiful” ambiguity of the Greek
language, for which logos means both reason and language. Thanks to this ambiguity, the Greeks were able to express the idea that natural language has a logical nature, an idea Hegel was particularly fond of.1
At the beginning of the preface Hegel writes:
The forms of thought are, in the first instance, displayed and stored as human
language […] Into all that [we think, do, feel, represent] […] into all that we
make our own, language has penetrated, and everything that we have trans1
See Gadamer (1976: 78). In English translations, the term das Logische is often rendered
with “logic” (see for instance Hegel 1969: 36-37), but this could be misleading, as it risks
overlooking important philosophical implications. Nuzzo (1997: 41ff.) considers Hegel’s
distinction between “logic” and “the logical”. See also Nuzzo (1992: 193-98, and 281
note 84). Fulda (2006: 25-27 and 32ff.) stresses that “the logical” is the field of Hegel’s
“first philosophy” or metaphysics. D’Agostini (2000: 95ff.) examines the consequences of
Hegel’s new use for the relation between logic and metaphysics. Labarrière (1984: 35-41)
and more recently Caron (2006: 149-83) propose a theological interpretation of “das
Logische”. Di Giovanni (2007: 85-87) rejects the theological interpretation, stressing that
the expression “das Logische”, in Hegel, stands for the field of language and thought that
constitutes the subject matter of Hegel’s Science of Logic.
Hegel on the Naturalness of Logic
49
formed into language and express in it contains a category—concealed, mixed
with other forms or clearly determined as such, so much is logic [das Logische]
our natural element, indeed our own peculiar nature (Hegel Werke 5: 20).
Hegel uses interchangeably the terms “forms of thought” and “categories”.
This use could seem weird from a contemporary point of view, for which categories, as the basic structures of reality, are dealt with in ontology and metaphysics, while the forms of thought or valid inference are the subject matter of
logic. For Hegel, both essentially belong to the field of das Logische insofar as
they are forms of our thought that claim to be forms of our thought about reality. In short they are, or claim to be, forms of truth. Gadamer puts this aspect in
perhaps clearer terms when he recalls that the expression das Logische, in Hegel,
has roots in both, ancient metaphysics and transcendental philosophy. Gadamer
suggests that Hegel uses das Logische in the same way that the Greek philosophers used the word logos, as an equivalent to “reason”, as the realm of concepts
or forms which are expression of the nature of reality, the universal and pure entities constituting and ruling human language and reasoning.2 At the same time,
Hegel conceives das Logische as self-reflexive thought and, in this, he follows the
Kantian and Fichtian transcendental tradition.
The Hegelian das Logische is not only the field of the forms of reality, but also and at the same time the field of self-reflexive thought. And self-reflection is
natural, for human beings. It is our peculiarly human trait of thinking about
ourselves. As Hegel puts it: “Because human spirit is essentially consciousness,
this self-knowing is a fundamental determination of its actuality” (Hegel Werke
5: 27).
The nature of logos/das Logische/der Begriff as self-reflexive thought will
turn useful later, in the context of the discussion of the fourth thesis.
That das Logische, so conceived, penetrates all our ideas, actions, purposes
etc. means, for Hegel, that our language contains (sometimes conceals) pure
forms and categories: “[we employ] those determinations of thought on every
occasion, [they] pass our lips in every sentence we speak” (Hegel Werke 5: 22).
We always use categories (we use “being” and “quantity” when we say
“two cats are on the mat”), thought determinations or semantic terms (we use
“sentence” and “true” when we say “Blasey Ford’s statements during the Senate
Judiciary Committee hearing are true”). Finally, we always use inferential
forms—to recall a famous Hegelian example:
If any one, when awaking on a winter morning, hears the creaking of the carriages on the street, and is thus led to conclude that it has frozen hard in the
night, he has gone through a syllogistic operation—an operation which is every
day repeated under the greatest variety of complications (Hegel Werke 8: 335).
3. Natural Logic is the Unconscious Use of the Forms of
Thought, while Logic as Theory Makes them the Object of
Inquiry
However, while logical forms may be thoroughly familiar, for the most part we
use them unconsciously.
2
Gadamer 1976: 78.
50
Elena Ficara
The activity of thought which is at work in all our ideas, purposes, interests and
actions is [...] unconsciously busy (natural logic) [...] To focus attention on this
logical nature [...] this is the task (Hegel Werke 5: 26-27)
“Das Logische” and “logical nature” refer to logic as an objective fact, independent from human decision, they denote the natural field in which logical
forms emerge. “Natural logic” expresses the natural and unconscious activity of
using these forms. Our “task” is to focus attention upon the forms of thought,
making them the object of inquiry. They are used unconsciously, and we have
to bring them into consciousness. This enterprise can be carried on in terms of
what Hegel calls “die Logik”, the theory or discipline that isolates and fixes the
forms of valid inferences, “extracting them” from human language and life.
Plato and Aristotle were the first philosophers who managed to
[free the forms of thought] from the material in which they are submerged in intuition, representation, and in our desiring and willing […] and [made] these
universalities objects of consideration (Hegel Werke 5: 22).
The work, initiated by Plato and Aristotle, and carried on by the philosophers, logicians and metaphysicians in the subsequent history of philosophy, of
making the forms of thought the object of the logical consideration, contributing
to establishing logic as theory, is for Hegel of extreme importance. The separation of the forms from their nature (from their natural but impure occurrence in
everyday language, thought, desire, will etc.) is fundamental, for Hegel. It marks
the birth of logic as theory. At the same time, Hegel warns against the limits of
logic as theory.
4. Logic as Theory Misunderstands the Nature of the Forms of
Thought
4.1. Logical Forms are not Means for Us, We are Means for Them
A first limit is that, in making the forms the object of our study, we are led to
taking them as mere means:
Such a use of categories, which above was called natural logic, is unconscious;
and when in philosophical reflection the categories are assigned the role of serving
as means, then thinking as such is treated as something subordinate to the other
activities of mind [my emphasis] (Hegel Werke 5: 24).
Thus treating the forms as means implies thinking about them as subordinate to all our other activities—for example, we take the forms as means when
we consider the knowledge of logical and argumentative laws as a way to think
clearly, to act in a more effective way, to take good decisions in life. This approach, however, is misleading. It forgets that the forms permeate all our ideas,
feelings, impulses, will, and that they rule everything. To go back to Hegel’s
own example, if any one, when awaking on a winter morning, hears the creaking of the carriages on the street, and is thus led to conclude that it has frozen
hard in the night, he has not only gone through a syllogistic operation, but his
Hegel on the Naturalness of Logic
51
very actions and decisions are ruled by that same operation. In another context,3
Hegel writes about the march of cold necessity that inferential rules force upon
us. If this is so, how can the forms be means for us?
Rather […] we are means for them […] they have us in their possession; what is
there more in us as against them, how shall we, how shall I, set myself up
as more universal than they, which are the universal as such? (Hegel Werke 5: 25).
4.2. Logical Forms are not Accessorily Attached to the Content,
They are What is Essential and Substantial About Every Content
A second misunderstanding that can arise in establishing logic as theory is taking the forms as only contingently attached to the content, and not as themselves content:
The activity of thought which is at work in all our ideas, purposes, interests and
actions is, as we have said, unconsciously busy (natural logic); what we consciously attend to is the contents, the objects of our ideas, that in which we are
interested; on this basis, the determinations of thought have the significance
of forms which are only attached to the content, but are not the content itself
(Hegel Werke 5: 26).
Since the forms are present in all our thoughts, actions and interactions,
and since what we are normally interested in when we think, act and interact
are the contents of our thoughts/actions etc., then we may think that the forms
are an accessory part of our actions, purposes, ideas. For instance, to go back to
Hegel’s example, what I am interested in about the reasoning “I hear the creaking of the carriages on the street, and thus conclude that it has frozen hard in the
night” is not the inferential form “if A then B, A hence B”, but rather that it has
frozen and that I cannot take my bicycle to go to school. However, what is erroneous for Hegel is the assumption: I am interested in the content of the inference, hence inferential forms are merely accessory features, and have no relevance whatsoever concerning the content. Hegel reacts against this assumption,
claiming that the forms of thought are the substantial part of every content.
But if […] the nature, the peculiar essence, that which is genuinely permanent
and substantial in the complexity and contingency of appearance and fleeting
manifestation, is the notion of the thing, the immanent universal, and that each
human being though infinitely unique is so primarily because he is a human being, and each individual animal is such individual primarily because it is an animal: if this is true, then it would be impossible to say what such an individual
could still be if this foundation were removed, no matter how richly endowed the
individual might be with other predicates, if, that is, this foundation can equally
be called a predicate like the others (Hegel Werke 5: 26).
Following the ancient Greek account of the universal or logos, Hegel recalls
that the universal is the fundamental predicate that expresses the substance or
essence of individual things: “being a human being” is the foundation without
3
See the preface to the Phenomenology of Spirit (Hegel Werke 3: 15-16).
52
Elena Ficara
which the individual Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel would not be the particular individual being he is, “being an animal” is the fundamental predicate without which our canary Sandrino would not be what he is. To return to Hegel’s
example, the content of the inference “I hear the creek of the carriages on the
street and conclude that it has frozen hard in the night [and that I cannot take
my bike to go to school]” is rooted in its form, and its form is rooted in the universal or notions of the thing.
This means that the universal or das Logische or the logos is the notion (the
conceptual grasp) of the thing, the truth about things. As Hegel claims:
The concept [der Begriff] […] the logos, the reason of that which is, the truth of
what we call things; it is least of all the logos which should be left outside of the
science of logic (Hegel Werke 5: 30).
The last Hegelian thesis about logic’s naturalness can now be addressed:
5. The Task of Logic as Science is to Restore the Natural Life
of das Logische
Traditional logic and metaphysics as theories are, for Hegel, important inquiries. Their materials are a fundamental reference point for any development of
logic as a science, to be acknowledged with gratitude. However, logic and metaphysics as theories present the forms of thought in a fragmentary way, they do
not see their relations, interplays and developments. In so doing, they fail to do
justice to the genuine nature of das Logische. Hegel writes:
The profounder basis is [the pure concept] which is the very heart of things, their
simple life-pulse [...]To focus attention on this logical nature which animates
mind, moves and works in it, this is the task (Hegel Werke 5: 27).
For example, the logic as theory of Hegel’s times fixes the law of identity as
A = A and considers it as a fundamental law of truth (see Hegel Werke 5: 30ff.).
But, as Hegel (as well as most philosophers of his times)4 remarks, nobody
thinks or speaks according to it. Nobody thinks in terms of identity, stating “a
plant is… a plant”, “a casserole is… a casserole”. These rules and forms are not
genuine forms of truth:
The rules of inference […] quite as well serve impartially error and sophistry and
[…] however truth may be defined […] they concern only correctness and not
truth (Hegel Werke 5: 29).
For this reason Hegel underlines that the genuine form of truth is das
Logische or the concept [der Begriff], and not the forms of thought as they are
4
In Hegel’s times the idea about logic’s dullness was common. Hegel criticized the limitative treatment of the forms of thought in the logic and metaphysics as theories, but he
also underlined that traditional and Aristotelian logic must be studied and regarded as an
extremely important reference point for any work in logic. Hegel also sharply criticized
the dismissive attitude towards logic typical of the romantic philosophies of his times.
See on this Krohn (1972: 56) and Ficara 2019b.
Hegel on the Naturalness of Logic
53
fixed by the logic and metaphysics of his times. By this he means the basic selfreferential activity of thought. He writes:
When those determinations of thought which are only external forms are truly
considered in themselves, this can only result in demonstrating […] the untruth
of their supposed independent self-subsistence, that their truth is the concept.
Consequently, the science of logic in dealing with the thought determinations
which in general run through our mind instinctively and unconsciously […] will
also be a reconstruction of those which are singled out by reflection and are fixed
by it as subjective forms, external to the content (Hegel Werke 5: 30).
Hence the task of logic as science is not only to pay attention to the instinctive and unconscious forms of thought sunk in natural language, but also to analyse the forms that the logic and metaphysics as theories have already extracted
and fixed. This analysis shows that they are not the forms of truth they claim to
be, and roots them in the concept or logos, which is the same self-reflexive activity of thought, the process of making our thought processes and forms the object
of our thought.
In sum, if we reconsider the four theses presented by Hegel in the preface to
the Science of Logic second edition, we see that the question about the naturalness
of logic runs through them at different levels.
i. Logic is natural in the sense that the realm of “das Logische”, which includes categories, reflexive concepts, inferential forms, permeates natural language.
Our languages contain names for categories, such as ‘being’, for reflexive or semantic concepts, such as ‘concept’, ‘sentence’, ‘true’; our reasoning follows logical patterns. Most importantly, our languages can contain substantives and
predicates expressing the self-reflexive and dialectical nature of thought, terms
such as “Aufhebung” (which means “overcoming and maintaining” and unifies
two opposites).
ii. Logic is natural in the sense that logical forms run instinctively and unconsciously through all our thinking, reasoning, feeling, acting. The task of logic as
theory is to bring this logical nature into consciousness.
iii. Logic is natural in the sense that it (intended as dialectical logic) “brings
life” into the theoretical treatment of das Logische. The logics and metaphysics of
Hegel’s times extract the forms of thought from the materials in which they are
submerged in a way that “kills” the logical concepts and forms. They fix the
forms, isolate them from one another, from their content and their roots in human life and self-reflexive thought. The task of dialectics (logic as science) is to
trace the forms back to the self-reflexive activity of thought, restoring the natural
dynamicity of das Logische.
6. Conclusion
Is Hegel’s account about the naturalness of logic at all relevant for us today?
How is it related to debates about the relationship between logical forms and
natural language in philosophy and logic? The research on this field is immense
54
Elena Ficara
and has no clear boundaries.5 It ranges from works on naturalness in the systems
of natural deduction,6 to works on “natural logic”—whereby the expression
“natural logic” is not always used univocally,7 to works on the psychology of
reasoning,8 and to more general researches on the scope and meaning of logic.9 I
limit myself here to hint, by way of conclusion, at one common ground for a
possible dialogue between Hegel’s idea of logic and recent accounts of philosophical logic. It is what I have called E, a notion that goes back to Russell
1914.
Points i. and ii. concern the insight that logical forms permeate our language and natural reasoning, we use them unconsciously (they “pass our lips in
every sentence we speak”) and the task of logic as theory is to make them the
object of inquiry. So conceived, i. and ii. are common presuppositions in philosophical logic, shared at least by those logicians who follow Russell’s account of
philosophical logic in 1914. Russell writes:
Take (say) the series of propositions “Socrates drank the hemlock”, “Coleridge
drank the hemlock”, “Coleridge drank opium”, “Coleridge ate opium”. The
form remains unchanged throughout this series, but all the constituents are altered. Thus form is not another constituent, but is the way the constituents are
put together. It is forms, in this sense, that are the proper object of philosophical
logic. It is obvious that the knowledge of logical forms is something quite different from knowledge of existing things. The form of “Socrates drank the hemlock” is not an existing thing like Socrates and the hemlock […] some kind of
knowledge of logical forms, though with most people is not explicit, is involved
in all understanding of discourse. It is the business of philosophical logic to extract this knowledge from its concrete integuments, and to render it explicit and
pure (Russell 1914 [2009]: 34-35).
The Hegelian spirit of this quotation is outright clear.10 Logical forms for
Russell (as well as for Hegel) are always involved in our concrete talking with
each other and understanding each other. They have “concrete integuments”.
Our talking and reasoning follows logical patterns, and this often happens implicitly, without any precise awareness on our part. The task of philosophical
logic is then to “extract the knowledge about forms from its concrete integuments”, making the logical structure of our thinking explicit. Also for Hegel, the
task of logic (as both theory and science) is to make our unconscious, implicit
and impure use of the forms conscious, explicit and pure.
5
For an clarifying overview on the research about the several meanings of “logic’s naturalness” in contemporary philosophy of logic vis à vis Schopenhauer’s account about the
naturalness of logic see Schüler, Lemanski 2019.
6
Gentzen (1969: 68-131). “Natural” is for Gentzen (1969: 68) a calculus that comes as
close as possible to actual reasoning. For a similar account about logic’s naturalness see
Jaskowski (1934: 5-32), Tennant 1990, Ludlow 2005, Sanchez 1991.
7
For Lakoff (1970: 254) natural logic is the empirical study of human language and
thought, for van Benthem (2008: 21ff.) a system of reasoning based directly on linguistic
form.
8
Wason, Johnston-Laird (1972).
9
On logic’s rootedness in the world see Sher 2016. On the role of natural reasoning for
the revision of logic see Priest 2014, Priest (2016: 29-57) and Allo (2016: 3-31).
10
On Russell’s idealistic philosophical formation see Hylton (1990: 2ff.).
Hegel on the Naturalness of Logic
55
Russell’s idea is explicitly shared by some contemporary philosophers of
logic, among them Lowe (2013: 1) and Sainsbury (2001: 1). The idea of logical
forms as (special kinds of) “linguistic facts” “submerged” in natural language
and thought is at the very basis of the preliminary way in which contemporary
philosophy has conceived the notion of “philosophical logic”. Following Russell, many contemporary authors define philosophical logic as the attempt to formalise natural language,11 which might be performed by constructing mathematical models or more or less idealized languages. In any case, “formalisation” still
means, ideally, what Russell calls “extracting” the forms that are entangled in
our ways of speaking and thinking.
The last point (iii.), expresses the need to think about forms in new terms,
and to introduce self-reference and dynamicity into the static field of traditional
logic. It introduces Hegel’s critique of traditional logic, and anticipates reflections on logic revision12 in non-classical logics.13
References
Allo, P. 2016, “Logic, Reasoning and Revision”, Theoria, 82, 1, 3-31.
Apostel, L. 1979, “Logica e dialettica in Hegel”, in Marconi 1979, 85-113.
Berto, F. 2005, Che cosa è la dialettica hegeliana?, Padova: Il Poligrafo.
Caron, M. 2006, Etre et identité. Méditations sur la logique de Hegel et sur son essence, Paris: Passages.
Cook, R. 2009, A Dictionary of Philosophical Logic, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University
Press.
D’Agostini, F. 2000, Logica del nichilismo, Roma-Bari: Laterza.
Di Giovanni, G. (2007), “‘Das Logische’ of Hegel’s Logic in the Context of Reinhold’s and Fichte’s Late Theories of Knowledge”, in Bubner, R. and Hindrichs,
G. (eds.), Von der Logik zur Sprache. Stuttgarter Hegel Kongress 2005, Stuttgart: KlettCotta, 71-87.
Ficara, E. 2013, “Dialectic and Dialetheism”, History and Philosophy of Logic, 34, 1,
35-52.
Ficara, E. 2019a, “Hegel and Priest on Revising Logic”, in Baskent, C. and Ferguson, T. (eds.), Graham Priest on Dialetheism and Paraconsistency, Dordrecht:
Springer, forthcoming.
Ficara, E. 2019b, “Hegel on ‘form’ and ‘formal’”, in Bubbio, D., De Cesaris A., Pagano, M. and Weslati, H. (eds.), Hegel, Logic and Speculation, London: Bloomsbury, forthcoming.
Fulda, H.F. 2006, “Methode und System bei Hegel. Das Logische, die Natur, der
Geist als universale Bestimmung einer monistischen Philosophie”, in Fulda,
11
Sainsbury (2001: 1), Jaquette (2007: 1), Cook (2009: 221).
On logic revision see Priest 2014 and Priest 2016. On logic revision in Hegel and Priest
see Ficara 2019a. The literature on Hegel’s dialectics vis à vis non-classical logics is relatively rich. See Marconi 1979, Routley, Meyer (1979: 324-53), Apostel (1979: 85-113),
and more recently Priest (1989: 388-415), Berto 2005, Ficara (2013: 35-52).
13
The research for this paper is part of a larger project generously funded by the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation.
12
56
Elena Ficara
H.F. und Krijnen, K. (hrsg.), Systemphilosophie als Selbsterkenntnis. Hegel und der
Neukantianismus, Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann, 25-50.
Gadamer, H.G. 1976, Hegel’s Dialectics. Five Hermeneutical Studies, New Haven and
London: Yale University Press.
Gentzen, G. 1969, “Investigations into Logical Deduction”, in Szabo, M.E. (ed.),
The Collected Papers of Gerhard Gentzen, Amsterdam: North Holland, 68-131.
Hegel, G.W.F. 1969ff., Werke in zwanzig Bänden. Theorie Werkausgabe. New edition on
the basis of the Works of 1832-1845, Moldenhauer, E. and Michel, K.M. (eds.),
Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp (quoted, as usual, as Hegel Werke, followed by the
number of volume and page).
Jaquette, D. (ed.) 2007, Handbook of the Philosophy of Science: Philosophy of Logic, Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Jaskowski, S. 1934, “The Rules of Supposition in Formal Logic”, Studia Logica, 1, 532.
Krohn, W. 1972, Die formale Logik in Hegels ‘Wissenschaft der Logik’. Untersuchungen zur
Schlußlehre, München: Hanser.
Labarrière, P.J. 1984, “L’esprit absolu n’est pas l’absolu de l’esprit. De l’ontologique
au logique”, in Henrich, D. and Horstmann, R.P. (eds.), Hegels Logik der Philosophie. Religion und Philosophie in der Theorie des absoluten Geistes, Stuttgart: KlettCotta, 35-41.
Lakoff, G. 1970, “Linguistics and Natural Logic”, Synthese, 22, 151-271.
Ludlow, P. 2002, “LF and Natural Logic”, in Preyer, G. and Peter, G. (eds.), Logical
Form and Language, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Marconi, D. (a cura di) 1979, La formalizzazione della dialettica, Torino: Rosenberg &
Sellier.
Nuzzo, A. 1992, Logica e sistema. Sull’idea hegeliana di filosofia, Genova: Pantograf.
Nuzzo, A. 1997, “La logica”, in Cesa, C. (ed.), Hegel, Roma-Bari: Laterza, 39-82.
Priest, G. 1989, “Dialectic and Dialetheic”, Science and Society, 53, 4, 388-415.
Priest, G. 2014, “Revising Logic”, in Rush, P. (ed.), The Metaphysics of Logic, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, ch. 12.
Priest, G. 2016, “Logical Disputes and the a Priori”, Princípios: Revista de Filosofia, 23,
29-57.
Routley, R., Meyer, R.K. 1979, “Logica dialettica, logica classica e noncontraddittorietà del mondo”, in Marconi 1979, 324-53.
Russell, B. 1914, Our Knowledge of the External World, London: Routledge (references
are to the 2009 edition).
Sainsbury, M. 2001, Logical Forms. An Introduction to Philosophical Logic, Oxford:
Blackwell (first edition 1991).
Sánchez, V. 1991, Studies on Natural Logic and Categorial Grammar, Ph.D. Thesis,
University of Amsterdam.
Sher, G. 2016, Epistemic Friction. An essay on Knowledge, Truth and Logic, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Schüler, H. M., Lemanski, J. 2019, “Arthur Schopenhauer on Naturalness in Logic”
(Draft).
Tennant, N. 1990, Natural Logic, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Hegel on the Naturalness of Logic
57
Van Benthem J. 2008, “A Brief History of Natural Logic”, in Chakraborty, M., Löwe, B., Nath Mitra, M. and Sarukkai, S. (eds.), Logic, Navya-Nyaya and Applications, Homage to Bimal Krishna Matilal, London: College Publications, 21-42.
Wason P.C., Johnston-Laird, P.N. 1972, Psychology of Reasoning: Structure and Content, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Spiritualized Nature:
Hegel on the Transformative Character of
Work and History
David Ciavatta
Ryerson University
Abstract
It is argued that one of Hegel’s main strategies in overcoming the opposition between nature and spirit is to recognize a realm of “spiritualized nature” that has a
distinctive ontological character of its own, one that, though it is rooted in nature,
must be understood in essentially historical terms. It is argued that for Hegel the
activity of work is premised upon a commitment to the independent standing of
such spiritualized nature and its historical character, and a detailed reading of Hegel’s account of the slave’s work in the Phenomenology of Spirit is developed to
show just how it is that work transforms nature into something of historical import.
Keywords: Hegel, History, Naturalism, Master/Slave Dialectic, Work.
1. Introduction
There are various points in Hegel’s writing in which nature is conceived as something fundamentally distinct from and opposed to spirit, where the term “spirit”
is generally meant to capture what is distinctive about us as free, self-conscious,
thinking, and willing beings, and which more broadly includes the various legal,
moral, economic, political, aesthetic, and religious ideals or norms to which we
as subjects are uniquely responsive.1 I will go on to lay out this opposition in what
I take to be its most extreme form, but my aim is ultimately to show that the
opposition, and the way nature and spirit are defined so as to give rise to it, are
not Hegel’s final word. Concerned to develop an overall conception of reality in
which the fundamental opposition is overcome, and so in which nature and spirit,
though maintaining their difference, come to be conceived in light of a more fundamental unity, Hegel would have us recognize a distinctive domain of reality for
which neither nature nor spirit in their one-sided forms can be appealed to as
providing the ultimate terms for analysis. This realm is not simply both natural
and spiritual, some sort of hybrid dimension which contains distinct elements,
1
Among others, see Hegel 1977: par. 381 and Zusatz, and Hegel 1975: 53-55.
Argumenta 4, 2 (2019): 59-75
ISSN 2465-2334
© 2019 University of Sassari
DOI 10.14275/2465-2334/20198.cia
60
David Ciavatta
some of which are explained as one-sidedly natural, others as one-sidedly spiritual. This would only be to defer the issue of how these distinct elements can
come to cohere into a unified account of reality. Rather, Hegel has in mind a
realm populated with realities that have a distinctive logic and ontological character of their own, and that as such arguably require a distinctive set of conceptual
terms to render them intelligible.
I propose that this distinctive ontological realm can be fruitfully conceived as
the domain of “spiritualized nature”. I call it spiritualized nature to highlight the
fact that it only comes to be as a result of a concrete, transformational process, a
process whereby otherwise natural processes or events or objects come to take on
a distinctive, new character that makes them such that they are no longer natural
beings in the narrower, oppositional sense. As I will go on to discuss, another
name for this domain overall is, simply, “history”, for history is, for Hegel, arguably nothing other than this unique transformational process.
The arc of history in its broadest outlines is for Hegel the gradual progression
from purely natural, prehistoric forms of reality, including prehistoric forms of
human life that are dominated exclusively by natural forces and laws, towards
forms of living that are to increasing degrees free and self-determining in character—which is to say, forms of living that are not just the blind instantiations of
fixed and permanently existing natural laws, but that in some sense generate their
own laws, laws that had no real purchase on things until they were actually recognized and put into play by the historically evolving ways of life that concretely
embody them. In other words, history is the gradual development of distinctive
kinds of reality that are increasingly determined, not by nature, but by ideals and
norms—by the forces of right, beauty, truth, and, more generally, by meaning and
rationality.2
While this gradual, transformational process is, in one sense, the victory of
freedom and spirit over nature, it is crucial to note that on Hegel’s account it takes
place only in and through the concrete terms of the spatio-temporal world of nature. So, in another sense spirit and its self-determining character only enter the
scene, become actual, and evolve, by being naturalized—but in such a way that
spirit thereby transforms and surpasses what would otherwise be merely natural in
character, rendering it into spirit’s embodiment. Nature on its own is insufficient
to explain or necessitate the rise of history and so of nature’s own spiritualization
process. For instance, there seems to be good reason to think that Hegel would
not accept any evolutionary account that tried to reduce all that was distinctive of
human spiritual life to the same sorts of natural processes that underlie the evolution of plants and other animal life. For Hegel there is something exceptional
about spiritual reality and its freedom, and Hegel conceives of historical reality as
something that actively distinguishes itself from and works against nature as such,
affirming itself only in and through a suspension or negation of what would otherwise be natural.3 But, on the other hand, spirit’s realization, in its historical inauguration, also renders nature necessary to it as its condition or presupposition:
2
See, for instance, Hegel 1956: 20-27, where Hegel lays out his claim that history is the
gradual realization of freedom by way of action’s turning of nature to freedom’s ends.
3
Compare Hegel’s discussion of how history realizes itself through natural forces that, in
their conflicts with and limitations of one another, give rise to a significance that exceeds
them (Hegel 1956: 26-28).
Spiritualized Nature
61
we see—retrospectively, on the basis of spirit’s actual, historical development—
how nature afforded it what it needed for its self-realization.4 It is essentially this
spiritualizing/ naturalizing process, as something that exists in its own right and
that has a distinctive ontology of its own, that, I suggest, Hegel brings to the forefront as offering us a way of getting beyond the bare opposition between nature
and spirit.
I maintain that, on Hegel’s account, we bear witness to the distinctive ontological status of this process and its transformational character above all by directly participating in it: that is, it is precisely insofar as we are ourselves the active
agents of history, concretely engaged thereby in the process of rendering nature
spiritual and thus meaningful, that we find ourselves committed—committed in
practice, as it were—to the distinctive reality of spiritualized nature, and so to the
surpassing of the fixed nature/spirit dichotomy. For Hegel, action, and particularly the activity of work, affords us an indispensable perspective on the nature of
reality, one that a purely theoretical consciousness, wholly devoid of any concrete
will and of any situatedness within the natural world, would not have access.5 For
this reason, I will go on to offer an extended account of work, particularly as Hegel conceives it in his famous discussion of the master and slave dialectic (Hegel
1977, par. 194-6). This discussion, I suggest, affords us with an exemplary opportunity to explore how both the natural world, and ourselves as natural, desiring
beings, are transformed by work into something that, though still fundamentally
situated in and drawing upon our character as embodied, natural beings, is no
longer natural in the narrower, oppositional sense. I begin, however, by drawing
out the opposition between nature and spirit in what is arguably its most extreme
form, for the sake of putting into better perspective the account of spiritualized
nature and of work that follows.
2. Nature vs. Spirit
To identify the most basic contours of the opposition between nature and spirit,
let’s take nature in its most non-spiritual form to be defined generally as the spatiotemporal domain in which finite things and their various properties exist, interact,
and change in such a way as to instantiate fixed causal laws of the sort that science
uncovers. In his Logic, Hegel points to a kind of mechanistic physics as offering
us a sense for what reality totally devoid of spirit, or of “subjectivity” and its associated processes, would be like (Hegel 2010: 631-34). In Hegel’s thinking, such
a conception of nature is rooted in an ontology that is characterized by privileging
externality and external relations: to the extent that things are individuated and
extended in space and in time, they are typically conceived in terms of discrete
units that are at bottom outside of and relatively independent of one another in
their basic features, such that they act upon one another in an essentially external
4
This, I take it, is how Hegel comes to conceive of nature as spirit’s presupposition, while at
the same time maintaining that spirit is nature’s “truth” (Hegel 1971: sec. 381 and Remark). Spirit enables nature to reach a form that surpasses nature’s inherent limitations,
and in that sense spirit is logically prior to nature, something that cannot be accounted for
solely in natural terms.
5
See Ciavatta 2016 for a more elaborate case for appealing to the resources that the distinctive perspective of practical life offers for the development of an idealist ontology.
62
David Ciavatta
manner.6 Thus, for instance, a spatially distinct body causes some change in another spatially distinct body by exerting some kind of external force on it, a force
that is contingent with respect to the latter’s essential nature. And, if causal laws
are conceived in temporal terms, where “X causes Y” amounts to something like
“if state X is present, state Y will follow”, this typically involves conceiving two
successive episodes of time that are essentially distinct from and external to one
another, in that each has its own set of positive features that do not expressly refer
to those of the other episode, whether in the prospective or retrospective direction.7
In contrast, spiritual reality in its “purest” form—that is, in the form in which
it is most distinct from and opposed to natural reality—could be taken to be exemplified by the sort of pure ideality or intelligibility we associate with rationality
and its essentially internal relations, as when one idea or claim presents us with a
reason to affirm another.8 Such logical or rational relations, or relations rooted in
the meaning of things, are not fundamentally causal in nature, and do not concern
the sorts of individuated things or events that take place in space or time and that
alone admit of causal connection, but rather concern intelligible realities that, as
such, are essentially universal and so are not individuated in time or space. The
relations between otherwise distinct ideas and meanings are not merely external,
as they would be in the case of mere empirical association, where thinking one
idea merely reminds one of another idea, but are essentially internal, and are discovered precisely by our “entering into” the content of an idea. For instance, the
meaning of the term “cause” does not just remind us of the meaning “effect” by
association or by some sort of mechanical memory,9 but is intrinsically linked to
it, for it seems impossible to make sense of what it would mean to cause something if we could not think, or were not already thinking, something like an effect.
The very content or intelligibility of the idea “cause” thus bears an internal reference to content “effect”, and in that sense cannot be what it is without it.10
It is true that we come to recognize or think such intelligible realities and
their relations, and when our thinking is compelled to commit itself to one idea
or claim on the basis of an intellectual grasp of other ideas to which it has already
committed itself, this actual compulsion and this transition of thought are, in a
way, individuated events that, as such, can be said to take place in nature. At the
very least they take place in time, such that we can typically differentiate between
the time before and after which we cottoned on to some implication, and take our
thinking to have changed in some way in the event of doing so. But we do not
6
See Hegel 2010: 631; Hegel 1970: sec. 247-48; Hegel 1971: 381Z.
Compare Hegel’s discussion of the externality of moments of time to one another in Hegel 1970: sec. 259 Remark, where he argues that, in nature, any prospection or retrospection is posited as merely subjective.
8
See, for instance, Hegel’s discussion of pure logical thought in Hegel 2010: 736-37.
9
Though it should be noted that Hegel’s does acknowledge the importance of mechanical
memory in the overall development of spiritual reality (Hegel 1971: sec. 463), and as Julia
Peters has argued, this is particularly revealing of the naturalist strain informing Hegel’s
account of spirit (Peters 2016).
10
Indeed, Hegel’s dialectical account of the cause/effect relation hinges precisely on the
fact the cause is beholden for its intelligibility on the effect, where this eventually leads to
the realization that reciprocity is more basic than the one-way causal relation (Hegel 2010:
500-503).
7
Spiritualized Nature
63
typically take our concrete act of thinking of them to be constitutive of what is being
thought and of the necessity that is borne witness to by our thinking. Rather, our
thinking grasps relations and necessities that, it seems, exist in themselves whether
we, as particular thinkers with the particular psychologies we happen to have,
think them or not.11 For instance, the sorts of pure, logical relationships Hegel
takes up in the Science of Logic—as, for instance, the sort of internal relation I
pointed out earlier between the concepts of cause and effect—concern matters
that were presumably true before Hegel (and any of the previous thinkers he draws
from) demonstrated them to be true, and that would in some sense persist as true
even if we as a species forgot them. Arguably we can say the same thing of aesthetic and moral norms: while the actual recognition of their force or their implications—the recognition of the demands their meaning places on us—may take
hold of us at particular times and in reference to the here and now of the particular
situations we face, we typically take what we bear witness to in such cases to hold
independently of our actual bearing witness to them at the time, to have a sort of
independent weight and reality that is, in itself, atemporal and universal.
If nature and spirit are conceived exclusively or primarily in terms of this,
their most extreme, opposition, the prospects of conceiving how they could ever
be brought together into a unified account of reality seem dim indeed. Moreover,
we can see how such a stark opposition between nature and spirit could lend fuel
to anti-idealist forms of naturalism. For the further away spirit is from nature, and
so from the metaphysical or ontological commitments that underlie modern natural science and its purported successes, the more mysterious spirit seems to become from an ontological point of view. Likewise, any attempt on the part of an
idealist to challenge the contemporary hegemony of nature-oriented ontologies,
by offering an alternate ontology that would make room for the distinctive way
of being of this ideal realm, is bound to seem, to modern ears at least, hopeless,
something akin to a summarily dismissed “Platonism”—even if it is sometimes
granted that the domain of ideality does seem to be irreducible to nature in basic
respects.12
Whether Hegel himself attempts to defend the idea that pure ideality has a
reality and ontological status of its own, independently of any account of concrete
nature, is a matter of some controversy. But I propose to side-step that issue to
explore another side of Hegel’s approach to the nature/spirit relation, one that
focuses, not on spirit in its separation and its pure ideality, but on the way spirit
comes to inhabit the natural world, in effect transforming nature into a material
11
See Hegel’s discussion of philosophical thought as freeing itself from its “historical outwardness” (Hegel 1991a: sec. 14). Though it should be noted that some have read Hegel’s
account of pure thought in the Logic as depending in essential ways on the concrete movement of thinking (see Burbidge 2006) or on concrete language (McCumber 1993).
12
For an insightful overview of the core tensions and attempted reconciliations between
modern naturalism and idealist metaphysics, see Sebastian Gardner 2007. I share Gardner’s view that so-called “soft naturalisms”, which acknowledge the irreducibility of the
normative sphere to nature, but which nevertheless continue to regard nature, narrowly
conceived, as setting the ultimate ontological standard for what counts as real, cannot ultimately evade idealism’s insistence on the need for an ontology that does justice to the
distinctive character of normative reality. Though Gardner does not single out McDowell’s
focus on second nature, Gardner’s worries about soft naturalism arguably plague McDowell’s approach as well (McDowell 1996).
64
David Ciavatta
manifestation of the norms and meanings to which spirit bears witness. From this
perspective, not only spirit, but nature itself, need to be reconceived so as to overcome the starkness of the opposition between them: on Hegel’s account we must
recognize, not only that spirit can and does draw upon and reconfigure the natural
world—that spirit’s self-determination and self-realization occurs precisely in and
through what has been afforded to it and set in motion by nature—but also that
“nature” is revealed, precisely by spirit’s self-realization in it, to be irreducible to
an inherently meaningless domain of spatio-temporal things and occurrences exhausted by physical laws. On the contrary, natural forms and processes come to
show themselves as providing the concrete ground or condition of spirit’s own
self-realization, which suggests that the meanings and norms to which spirit
comes to embody and bear witness in its concrete existence, must themselves have
some sort of basis in natural reality, and so cannot be wholly foreign to it. 13
If the standing norms of beauty or good or truth are not merely ideal, but can
have an actual weight and motivational pull on us—if they make a difference for
us—then at the very least there must be temporally-individuated episodes in
which such norms are actually felt, affirmed, or heeded by our subjective experience at some specific moment in history. But more than that, in the case of some
of these norms at least, what is required is not just an internal, subjective recognition of their weight and implications, but an actual transformation of the world, one
that is informed by and grounded in such norms. For instance, moral norms are
such as to demand that some specific action be taken, and aesthetic norms, when
guiding the hand of the artist, exist as demanding that an object being generated
by the artist take a certain form and not others. Were it impossible for such norms
to ever enter into and shape the spatio-temporal world at all—if everything in the
spatio-temporal world were, by definition, norm-free or without meaning, for instance as wholly exhausted by meaningless instantiations of natural laws—then
such norms, in their demandingness, would in effect be demanding the impossible. Every attempt to enact them or make them effective would be to betray them.
Hegel sees this tension as plaguing Kant’s (and arguably also Fichte’s) moral philosophy, for in his view Kant subscribes to too sharp an opposition between nature and ideality which in effect renders the moral good into an “infinite ought”
that can never be concretely realized in time or in practice (see Hegel 1991a: sec.
60 and Remark). In contrast, Hegel is committed to recognizing a sort of middle
terrain in which not every concretization of an ideal is its betrayal, but where there
can actually be concrete realities that are themselves the living embodiment or
13
While I will be focusing specifically on action and history, a broader defense of this claim
could also turn to the “Anthropology” section of the Philosophy of Spirit, where the natural
and corporeal roots of spirit’s distinctive capacities are explored. However, it is worth noting there is still an implicit historical trajectory underlying Hegel’s account in the Anthropology, for Hegel seems to suppose that historically more evolved humans (that is, those
whose reality is more determined by their own agency and will) are less determined by the
specific limits of these natural roots than less evolved humans, and so that history plays a
role in mediating and cultivating the concrete character of even the most corporeal phenomena Hegel discusses here. Thus, for instance, though all humans have corporeallyexpressed emotions, the content and shape of the emotions of more historically evolved
humans will be more “spiritualized and the materiality of their expression diminished”
(Hegel 1971: 83).
Spiritualized Nature
65
presence of a norm or a meaning—realities that are not reducible to the meaningless stuff of a one-sided nature, but are themselves the direct, material manifestations of spirit.
Actions themselves are what constitute the most basic “objects” populating
this middle realm on Hegel’s account, for Hegel seems committed to regarding
“acting bodies” or “action events” as of a different ontological status than mere
natural bodies or natural events (though we will see, as we turn to Hegel’s account
of work, that action also enables things otherwise external to the agent’s body to
take on this distinct status as well). Generally speaking, action is conceived by
Hegel as a process of enabling the norms whose meaning we bear witness to as
spiritual subjects, to actually inform and in some sense govern the objective goings
on of the concrete, spatio-temporal sphere: action sees to it that these otherwise
ideal norms are no longer merely subjective and ideal, having purchase solely in
our thoughts or intentions or interpretations, but actually make a concrete difference
in the world, gaining a real purchase and explanatory force in the here and now.14
The very project of acting hinges on the notion that it is not enough merely to
interpret or be conscious of a certain given state of affairs as the embodiment of a
certain norm’s meaning—as though this were merely a matter of subjectively projecting meanings onto a realm that, in itself, was essentially meaningless and indifferent to whatever meanings it might take on—but that some sort of concrete
event, some sort of real transformation in the here and now of the spatio-temporal
world—that is, the action-event itself—must actually take place if we are to be
warranted in regarding the relevant state of affairs as the successful embodiment
of meaning. That is, the action takes itself, its actual changing of the world, to be
essential in bringing meaning into play. From the point of view of the engaged
agent, then, the difference between a merely given, natural state of affairs, and a
spiritualized, or “accomplished”, state of affairs—that is, one that is in itself
marked by the embodiment of meaning or by answering to norms—is not merely
a difference in interpretation, a difference “in us”, but a difference rooted in actual
events and their unfolding in the here and now. And the agency of the agent, her
power to make a real difference in the here and now, consists in nothing other
than the capacity to give rise to such a transformational event: her agency is, then,
not simply a matter of being an efficient cause in the stream of law-governed,
natural events, nor is it a matter of somehow letting some norm act as such a
natural cause, but rather a matter of letting meaning actually happen in the world
and thereby come to inform what would otherwise be a meaningless domain of natural events. In effect, her agency consists in giving rise to a different sort of event
altogether—a historical event. I will be arguing that it is particularly in Hegel’s
account of work that this transformative character of human activity is brought to
the forefront. Before turning to the nature of work, however, I will briefly lay out
some of the most basic features of historical reality, with a view to setting up the
contrast between it and nature that will underlie the account of work.
3. History and the Essential Place of Concrete Individuality
14
See, for instance, Hegel 1971: sec. 484, where Hegel speaks of the will’s need to realize
itself in an external objective form, thereby “making the latter a world moulded by the
former”. For similar formulations, see Hegel 1991b: secs. 8, 109-10, and 1956: 22.
66
David Ciavatta
Part of what distinguishes us as humans, on Hegel’s account, is that we are historical beings, and everything that is distinctively human is arguably marked by
its essentially historical character in his view. To say that we are historical is to
say, among other things, that who we actually are is determined, at least in part, by
what happens in the course of our existence—by what we experience and actually
undergo in life, and most especially by what we do in response to these experiences and events.15 It is to say that our identities are not already fully fixed and
written into the nature of things in advance, but are perpetually in question and
develop in the temporally unfolding course of things, such that, not only our
knowledge or consciousness of ourselves, but also who we actually are, can be
fully settled only in retrospect, once our “stories” are decisively over, or once we
have said and done the most essential things we are going to say and do.
It is arguably due to this fundamental historicality of human life that processes like work and education, or life-changing decisions such as getting married
or heroically standing one’s ground in a high-stakes ethical crisis, play such crucial roles in Hegel’s account of human or spiritual life. For these are all essentially
historical processes in that they transform the overall self-identity and sense of
agency of the individuals who are engaged in them, and transform them in ways
that could not have been fully predicted or affirmed in advance of their actual
occurrence—such that the actual, temporal unfolding of what we put into play
comes to have a bearing on determining and revealing who we are.16
To say that what happens in the course of a self’s life can play a role in determining the identity of that self is to recognize the irreducible character of the
self’s spatio-temporal situatedness and individuation. It is to acknowledge that,
though I have a past and a future, though I essentially occupy different “nows”
and “heres” in the course of my life—that is, though I am universal, in the sense
that my identity stands beyond every particular situation I may be in, and is not
exhausted by any one of them, or perhaps even by the totality of them17—there is
nevertheless a sense in which, when I am in some individual situation in the here
and now, the whole of me is potentially at stake, such that what occurs in this
particular, concrete situation can have a bearing on my whole life, my identity as
a whole. For, not only is death possible at any moment, threatening to short-circuit and thereby shape the contours of my overall biography, but there are also
such things as decisive turning points, as a result of which I am never quite the
same the person. For instance, events can arise which finally bring to a point of
resolution my deepest commitments, commitments that, until that point, had perhaps been somewhat indeterminate and had no occasion to fully articulate and
pronounce themselves, but that, under the unique circumstances of the moment,
were allowed to shine through in a decisive and unmistakable way, thereby setting
15
Thus Hegel can say that “what the subject is, is the series of its actions” (Hegel 1991b: sec.
124; Hegel’s emphasis).
16
See Hegel 1956: 27-29, where Hegel takes up the theme of how historical action typically
realizes more than what was intended by the agent. I take this account of the retrospective
nature of action to be generally consistent with that put forward by authors like Robert
Pippin (2008: 147-79), though my suggestion in what follows that there is a distinctive
historical ontology implied in such a conception departs from Pippin’s account.
17
I am invoking here the specific sense of universality that Hegel develops in his account
of sense-certainty in the Phenomenology; see Hegel 1977: pars. 98-99.
Spiritualized Nature
67
up a new standard against which all my subsequent actions (and, indeed, perhaps
even my previous actions) will now be measured.
These are the sorts of heightened events that Hegel regards as especially wellsuited to the manifestation of beauty on the stage, as he considers them to be
among the most successful embodiments of spirit in its concreteness.18 And in his
account of world-historical individuals, Hegel acknowledges that such decisive
events can even have a role in determining the overall shape of history (Hegel
1956: 29-32). Not every moment of a life is of such fateful significance, for, after
all, much of the time we do what is typical given who we already are, and, indeed,
in some respects our most prosaic actions are hardly distinctive of us as individuals and share much in common with those of others. But that there can be such
formative events (or periods), suggests that our concrete situatedness in time and
place is not merely the anticipatable instantiation of standing universals (as the
events in nature instantiate pre-existing, standing causal laws), but rather the concrete institution of new or modified universals or norms.19
That our concrete situatedness matters in this basic way is also expressed in
the fact that we as spiritual beings cannot help taking our own individual lives to
be of absolute or final importance in the grand scheme of things: that is, we cannot
help demanding that our individuality—this, our one and only life—be recognized as important in and of itself, rather than being taken up merely as substitutable instantiations of the general form “human” or “person”. Unlike plants, for
instance, which on Hegel’s account are less fully individuated, and are more like
temporary passing phases of one and the same ongoing genus cycle—the individual plant generating the seeds that lead to it being supplanted by new individuals
that instantiate essentially the same processes that it instantiated, making it and
its predecessor each just repetitions of the same one generic reality20—we as individuals are not simply substituted and replaced by the next generation, but can in
principle make our individual mark once and for all, such that our individuality
stands on its own account and is not merely one among many repetitions. The
distinctiveness of history seems premised precisely on giving individuality its due
in this way, whereas nature presents itself to us, in contrast, as the domain in
which individuality is obliterated and forgotten for good, or in which individuals
are wholly subsumed under the standing universals they instantiate, with the result that there is no fundamental difference between one natural individual and
the others, each being of equal status in being fully accounted for as the instantiation of the same laws. As we will see, this way of framing the contrast between
18
See Hegel 1975: 217-44, for Hegel’s general discussion of how beauty places demands
on what sorts of actions are worthy of artistic presentation, and for his defense of the aesthetic superiority of the sorts of decisive, character-disclosing events typical of tragic collisions.
19
Compare Hegel’s description of the beautiful individual as being “a law to itself”, rather
than being beholden to existing laws (Hegel 1975: 185). Hegel’s description of the worldhistorical individual similarly emphasizes the fact that great historical actions cannot be
adequately understood according to existing norms, but look forward towards the institution of new norms; see Hegel 1956: 29-32.
20
See Hegel 1970: pars. 343-44 and 348. In elaborating on the lack of individuation in
plants Hegel also notes that certain parts of plants can be cut and replanted to form other
individuals, as though the original plant were only a superficial unity of many rather than
a full-fledged individual in its own right.
David Ciavatta
68
nature and history will provide a useful backdrop to Hegel’s account of the slave’s
working relation to the world, to which I will now turn.
4. Hegel on Work and the Generation of History
Work, or formative activity, plays an important role in several of Hegel’s discussions. For instance, as in Locke’s view, work for Hegel transforms otherwise natural, external things into our property (Hegel 1991b: secs. 56-57); work transforms
our immediate, natural desires into a spiritualized second nature, and in doing so
allows us to participate in, and achieve the recognition of, the collectively-generated social order in the civil sphere (Hegel 1991b: secs. 196-98); the “spiritual”
work of the artist brings about inspired artworks that give voice to the community
as a whole (Hegel 1977: pars. 698-704). In each case what is at issue is the distinctive capacity of spirit to realize itself by rendering what was formerly natural and
immediate into something that embodies it. I will focus in particular on Hegel’s
account of the slave’s work and the way this work comes to transform, not only
the world, but also the slave’s own sense of agency: here the actual event of transformation arguably reveals to the slave something that he could not have realized
inwardly, simply through reflection, and so the irreducibility of the concrete, historical event of his action comes to the fore in an especially striking way.
4.1 The Fear of Death and the Unsettling of Nature
To provide the appropriate context for understanding the nature and function of
the slave’s work, it must be noted, first, that the slave is characterized by Hegel as
subsisting in a deep-rooted fear in the face of death, a fear that permeates all of
his interactions with himself and the world (Hegel 1977: par. 194). Hegel conceives of slavery as evolving out of a struggle in which self-conscious agents each
seek to affirm their own freedom in its independence from nature, by risking their
lives in a battle to the death (Hegel 1977: par. 187). The idea here is that the self
seeks to declare that it takes its individual freedom to be more valuable than the
natural life it has been given, and wants the other self to recognize this daring
affirmation of freedom, and so actively puts its life, and so its very attachment to
nature, on the line. This stance in effect embodies a kind of dualism between spiritual freedom and nature: by placing one’s natural life at risk, thereby suspending
life’s claim on one’s concerns and actions, one in effect declares freedom to be
somehow beyond the natural realm altogether. The fear of death arises here, in
response, as the realization that freedom (and so, spirit) requires nature as its condition, that freedom can only be realized in and through one’s individual and concrete life, and so that one’s individual life becomes something that needs to be
preserved at all costs—thus the openness to slavery.21
It is important to note here that the slave’s mortal fear is not the blind, instinctual fear that any animal might possess in the face of some specific danger,
but is a fear founded upon a kind of rational realization of universal scope, the
realization of freedom’s necessary dependence on natural life. 22 That is, the
slave’s dread is already a primitive form of “spiritualized nature”: as a feeling, it
21
As Hegel puts it, “self-consciousness learns that life is as essential to it as pure self-consciousness” (Hegel 1977: par. 188).
22
As Hegel writes, “this consciousness has been fearful, not of this or that particular thing or
just at odd moments, but its whole being has been seized with dread” (Hegel 1977: par. 194).
Spiritualized Nature
69
is still an immediate, and so presumably corporeal, phenomenon, one that manifests itself in a particular disposition of the body; but the specific character of this
feeling that overtakes the slave is grounded in an appreciation of something that
only a self-conscious being, concerned with its life as a whole and specifically in
its prospects of realizing freedom, can have.23 And we can already see that what
this fear presumes, in its moving beyond the sheer separation of spirit from nature,
is some kind of unity between spirit and nature. In effect, the slave’s fear is a kind
of immediately felt, embodied recognition of the need for a spiritualized nature,
and we will see that this is precisely what the slave’s actual work brings about in
practice.
Hegel conceives of this distinctively spiritual fear as providing the essential
backdrop for understanding the specific character of the work the slave does for
his master. It is not that, out of a fear of dying, the slave consciously chooses to
submit to the master and to the work the master would have him do, in the belief
that this is the only way of staying alive. There is no question here of the slave
having an internal capacity to size up his situation on his own terms, a capacity
to hold his life in his own hands and to decide for himself how to save it. On the
contrary, this is precisely the sort of self-possessed agency and sense of independence that the slavish consciousness has been dispossessed of by his fear of death.
The master directly embodies the power that death has over the slave, and so the
slave experiences his life as being wholly in the master’s hands. Thus seized with
this utterly unsettling dread of the master’s control over his very existence, he
finds himself immediately compelled to do as he is told; heeding the master’s
commands is quite literally a matter of life and death, and so these commands are
immediately equivalent, in his experience, to what life itself demands. Thus the
slave’s work for the master is based, not ultimately on his own desires, not even
strictly speaking the desire to spare himself from death—for this presumes he still
regards his life as being in his own hands and under his own control—but precisely on the unsettling character of the fear that disrupts any sense of self-possession. It is out of this fundamentally unsettled state—out of the slave’s complete
loss of control over his own life, and so from a sense of having no stable guarantees or reliable points of reference to turn to in his attempt to affirm himself, the
sense that “everything solid and stable has been shaken to its foundation” (Hegel
1977: par. 194)—that the slave approaches his work and the world upon which
he is to undertake his work.
Interestingly, Hegel claims that the slave’s fear is essentially an implicit or
subjective expression of what, in his work, becomes outwardly expressed and realized in a concrete, objective form. That is, Hegel conceives of the event of work
as bringing about, within the actual world, an unsettling of existing, stable forms,
a disruption that in effect undermines the way things are in their natural
givenness. Upon entering the natural world, work in effect introduces the very
real prospect that things can be other than they in fact are, that what things happen to
be now, in their current, natural form, is not the final word; for instance, trees can
23
Hegel’s account of emotion (Hegel 1971: sec. 401 and Zusatz) hinges on the notion that
spirit must be corporealized, that the “inner” only realizes itself in and through the “outer”.
For an excellent account of Hegel’s theory of emotion, see Russon 2009.
David Ciavatta
70
become a table.24 It is as though nature itself came to experience the unsettling
“absolute melting-away of everything stable” (Hegel 1977: par. 194) that the slave
himself experiences in the face of his own death.25
Work does not simply leave things in this unsettled, indeterminate state,
however, for it is also essential to the nature of work that it bring about a certain
“settling” or resolving of its situation, insofar as it gives rise to new objects that
stand there on their own account as concrete, stable manifestations of its capacity
to negate the existing form of things. As Hegel puts it, “the negative relation to
the object becomes its form and something permanent, because it is precisely for
the worker that the object has independence” (Hegel 1977: par. 195).
4.2 Historical Permanence in the Face of Nature
The worker’s capacity to appreciate the worked-over object’s independence is
conceived in contrast to the movement of desire, which Hegel associates with a
denial of anything independent of it and with a process that perpetually undermines itself and so is doomed to repeat itself again and again, much as natural
cycles do. On Hegel’s rendering, the desiring being attempts to gain an unlimited
feeling of self—attempts to gain satisfaction for itself in affirming itself as the only
being of any real ontological stature—but can do so only by destroying whatever
would claim to limit or be other to it, for instance by consuming it.26 This act of
self-affirmation-through-negation is satisfying in a temporary way, but because it
obliterates the object upon which it exerted itself, and thereby denies this object’s
very otherness or independence from it, it eliminates anything that could serve as
an attestation of its self-affirmation. The process of satisfying oneself, as involving
the actual negating of something that would claim to be other, obliterates the very
thing, to negate which, offers it satisfaction in the first place; that is, the desiring
self needs the other to be precisely in order for its negation or erasure of it (that is,
its satisfaction) to be.27 So, upon satisfying itself, the desiring being finds itself desiring yet another object through which to affirm itself, which it in turn obliterates,
giving rise to yet another desire, and so on.
While the desire for self-affirmation is distinctive of free selves, and so is not
straightforwardly natural in Hegel’s conception, in a way the problem with desire
is precisely its rootedness in nature and in its inability to escape nature’s repetitive,
24
That an agent’s practical stance in relation to the world itself reveals something about
the ultimate character of the world, and in particular that the way things are is not reducible
to their given form, is a recurring theme in Hegel’s thought. For instance, Hegel thinks that
the practical orientation of desire offers a kind of refutation of realism, in that, in devouring
things, it reveals that the apparent independence and self-contained character of natural
things is false; see, for instance, Hegel 1991b: sec. 44, Remark; Hegel 1977: par. 109.
25
Hegel links this “absolute negativity”, which unsettles all given determinacies, with the
essential character of free self-consciousness itself, and so this encounter with death’s disruption of everything fixed and stable is, in a way, just a deeper experience of what it is to
be a self in the first place; see Hegel 1977: par. 194.
26
“Certain of the nothingness of this other, [desire] explicitly affirms that this nothingness
is for it the truth of the other; it destroys the independent object and thereby gives itself the
certainty of itself as a true certainty, a certainty which has become explicit for self-consciousness itself in an objective manner” (Hegel 1977: par. 174, Hegel’s emphases).
27
As Hegel writes, “self-certainty comes from superseding this other; in order that this supersession can take place, there must be this other” (Hegel 1977: par. 175).
Spiritualized Nature
71
cyclical character. The desiring being eats, for instance, only to be faced with the
prospect of having to eat again, and then again. And while each episode of desire/satisfaction may be compelling in its own right, the feeling of satisfaction
disappears, without a trace, along with the consumed object, and is simply supplanted by another discrete episode that is wholly external to and independent of
the last one. It is precisely this externality that above all characterizes this process
as a natural one, in Hegel’s sense. Note that there is essentially no possibility of
historical development here—in which one episode of time carries forward and
builds on the results of episodes that are no longer present—and likewise there is
also no prospect of any individual episode of desire distinguishing itself from other
individual episodes, or of making any lasting mark on the desiring being’s overall
orientation towards itself and the world. For, with the immediately compelling
pull of each new desire, the desiring being is right back where it started last time—
namely faced with the need to affirm itself as the only being that matters, at the
expense of anything other than it. Similar to the plant’s reproductive cycle mentioned above, or any other cycle in nature for that matter, the concrete, individual
moments do not matter in and of themselves and in their differences from one
another, but exist primarily as substitutable instantiations of the same ongoing
process or law that exceeds them and that is itself is unaffected by any of its particular instantiations. The self, here, is the natural universal that claims to be in
no way limited or defined by its concrete encounter with anything other, and it
does this precisely by negating what is other, and along with it the potential ontological weight of any such encounter.
In conceiving of work in contrast to this desiring process—as “desire held in
check” (Hegel 1977: par. 195)—Hegel is proposing that work be defined precisely
in terms of its capacity to affirm and bear witness to what is other to it, and thereby
to somehow interrupt and overcome the externality and recurrent cyclicality of
nature. Rather than simply negating, and thus obliterating the natural object altogether, thereby leaving nothing that stands as an independent, objective attestation of its active engagement with it, work transforms its object into something
that, while it is no longer natural, is nevertheless still there, still present in the world,
and so into something that attests to its engagement with it. Presumably the
worker experiences the worked-over object’s independence most of all once the
object is finished, and so when the work is done; for, until then, the object keeps
calling for further intervention from the worker, and so keeps announcing that it
is not yet ready to stand on its own account.
I take it that, in speaking of the worker’s recognition of the created object’s
independence and permanence (in contrast to desire’s simply consumptive attitude towards it), Hegel does not mean that the object retains an enduring physical
integrity. Perhaps some of a slave’s products will endure in this immediate, physical sense, but of course some of them will be immediately consumed by the master, and presumably even those products that do endure will undergo a more gradual consumption, eventually to disappear. What strikes the worker as permanent
must lie in the significance this concrete object has attained through having been
worked on, in the way its concrete form, precisely in its non-naturalness, directly
attests to the worker’s basic capacity to make a real difference in the concrete
world. What ultimately lasts in the work, then, is not its material presence, but the
fact that what this object actually is, was determined by the work that went into
it, or, we can also say, by the way this individual thing embodies, once and for
all, its formative past.
72
David Ciavatta
We can see this more clearly if we consider that whatever happens to the
produced object is, in a way, also something that happens directly to the worker.
Even if this object is accidentally destroyed by natural forces, this destruction is
now a significant event, something that cannot be a matter of indifference to the
worker who has been invested his work into this individual thing. For work cannot affirm its own undoing, and cannot help willing that its work stand, where
this standing functions as a kind of norm that the rest of reality ideally ought to
respect. Whereas, from the point of view of nature and its standing laws, an earthquake’s leading to the destruction of a delicately wrought vase is nothing more
than a rearrangement of fully present matter—each configuration of which was
just as necessary an instantiation of nature’s causal laws as every other—from the
point of view of the worker who made the vase (and presumably for those others
who recognize the work that went into it, who recognize it as a vase rather than as
mere bit of natural matter), there is a substantial, irretrievable loss here, a real
infringement of something that, in its individuality, claimed a final place in the real.
If nature denies the irreducible importance of individuality by treating every configuration of matter as an equally necessary instantiation of law—like so many
meaningless modes of the same one substance, or, as in our previous example, so
many iterations of the same one cycle—there can be no such thing as real loss or
absence, for there is no individual configuration of matter that stands on its own
as a persisting reference point against which subsequent configurations could be
measured. Upon its completion, however, the work in effect transforms these subsequent configurations of reality into something other than just further, equally
necessary presences in themselves, wholly external to what came before, but instead into negations of what was there, as presences that in themselves mark an absence, insofar as they bear a reference back to that which they have supplanted.28
It is true, nature can take back what the process of work allowed to stand out from
nature, as when an abandoned house is gradually reclaimed by the forest in which
it stood. But even here something of the eerie presence of past living persists in its
broken remains, at least until there is nothing left that is recognizable as having
the distinctive mark of the human hand. This example also shows how the work
of maintaining or preserving a house (or any worked object) is essentially a matter
of keeping the persistent forces of nature at bay, of continuing to suspend the hold
it would otherwise have on things, so as to keep open thereby a domain in which
distinctively human existence can take place.
Thus work defies the meaningless iterations of nature precisely by letting individual things matter as such and stand on their own as indelible reference points
in the real. Given the link I made earlier between history and the appreciation of
the irreducible role of individuality, we can see that what work does, in effect, is
to suspend nature’s ultimate hold on things so as to make historical reality possible.29
28
I am in effect arguing here that Hegel account of work foreshadows Sartre’s account of
the ontological irreducibility of negation; see Sartre 1996: 6-12.
29
In linking work with the rise of history I am here coming to essentially the same conclusion that Alexandre Kojève did in his ground-breaking lectures on the Phenomenology
(Kojève 1969: 37-52), though in focusing on the irreducibility of individuality, and the contrast to nature’s downplaying of individuality, I come at this link from a rather different
angle. I acknowledge, however, Kojève’s argument the intersubjective dimension of the
Spiritualized Nature
73
Hegel’s account of the slave’s relation to his product suggests, further, that,
in investing itself in the worked-over thing, and in thus rendering its individuality
as something that matters, the slave in effect realizes something about his own
individuality, his own individual agency.30 The worker, working on the world,
cannot help regarding the concrete product produced by the work as mattering in
itself, in its independent individuality: work is nothing other than the renderingsignificant of what would otherwise be meaningless nature. But the product’s independent individuality and its mattering is, at once, a standing index of what the
worker himself can do, of the difference the worker makes in the world, and so of
the fact that the worker himself, as a concrete individual engaged with the world,
matters. If work cannot but treat the product of work as mattering, holding open
a domain—the domain of historical reality—in which individuality itself can
stand as a final reference point, then the worker cannot but treat himself, his own
individual meaning-giving capacity, as mattering in its own right and thus as an
independent reference point that must be recognized by all things.
In spite of his unsettling anxiety in the face of death, which revealed the
slave’s very life to be in the hands of forces over which the slave himself had no
ultimate control, the slave comes to find, in and through his own work, the concrete realization of his own individual capacity to make a lasting difference in the
order of historical reality—a difference that natural forces, including death itself,
cannot simply wipe away for good. Rather than identifying himself simply with
his natural life, then, in working the slave comes to identify with a life of his own
making, a life that takes the shape it does due to his own work and that is, in that
sense, in his own hands. This “spiritualized life” can only take root in and through
natural life and through the slave’s interaction with otherwise natural things and
processes, but it is only to the extent that the slave does not leave things in their
natural form, and ceases to be governed by natural processes—interrupts and
transforms them through work—that he comes to realize his own individual
agency as such. In this sense, then, the actual, concrete event of working on the
world, and so of giving rise to objects that matter, becomes a meaningful, spiritual
event, a turning-point that serves to transform the working self’s very identity as
a self.
5. Conclusion
On Hegel’s account, the very agency of the worker is itself realized precisely in
the event of working, and so does not precede it in a straightforwardly naturalistic,
causal way. The agency of spirit, in its giving rise to a meaningful nature, arises
hand in hand with the meaningful work produced, and it seems we must say that
its reality is in this sense bound up with the reality of the work qua work. Thus, it
is not simply that the worker, standing over against nature, imposes a form upon
master/slave relationship is also crucial for understanding the reality of history here, and
a fuller account of the relation between work and history would need to develop this dimension.
30
As Hegel puts it, “in fashioning the thing, the bondsman’s own negativity, his being-forself, becomes an object for him only through his setting at nought the existing shape confronting him. … [H]e destroys this alien negative moment, posits himself as a negative in
the permanent order of things, and thereby becomes for himself, someone existing on his
own account” (Hegel 1977: par. 196).
David Ciavatta
74
it from without. For, this way of conceiving of the matter posits the worker’s distinctively spiritual agency as fully formed, prior to his actually entering into the
work process. Rather, on Hegel’s conception it seems that it is only once there is
work actually happening, only in the actual, transformative activity itself, that there
is both spiritual agency and work. Spirit as such only arises and becomes actual in
and through the process whereby work renders the world meaningful—that is, in
and through the process whereby nature, unsettled by work, gives itself over to
meaningful form, to being spiritualized. This transformational process itself—the
spiritualizing of nature or, what is the same, the advent of a distinctively historical
reality—presents itself here as the core reality, one that is irreducible to either
spirit or nature conceived in their one-sided, oppositional form, and that, indeed,
attests to a deeper unity between them.
Of course, the vase and the table sit in the natural world, are exposed to the
natural elements, and are themselves composed of physical and chemical materials that, as such, are fully compliant with existing natural laws. But to conceive
of these objects in this way is to fail to recognize the vase or table as such, or in
their distinctive character as works. It is in effect to refuse the privileged perspective of the worker, for whom the work stands out as an independent reality that
embodies in itself the significance that his transformative work allowed it to take
into itself, and instead to presume that only what is conceivable in narrowly naturalist terms and according to existing natural laws gets at its basic reality. Indeed,
for the worker making a vase, there is a sense in which the primary “law” being
answered to in the work is the very form or meaning of the vase qua vase, as this
form is what guides her work throughout and what must be appealed to in determining that the work is complete, such we can at some point say that there is now
a vase standing there, where there used to be only meaningless clay. Insofar as the
work-process is above all sensitive to this real distinction, and in practice treats
the vase as something fundamentally different from, indeed a supersession of, the
bare clay, we can say that the worker’s perspective is in practice committed to the
refutation of the narrow naturalist’s view, and has a living stake in maintaining
the independence and irreducibility of what we have been calling a spiritualized
nature.
References
Burbidge, J. 2006, The Logic of Hegel’s ‘Logic’, Peterborough: Broadview Press.
Ciavatta, D. 2016, “Hegel on the Idealism of Practical Life”, Hegel Bulletin, 37, 1, 1-28.
Gardner, S. 2007, “The Limits of Naturalism and the Metaphysics of German Idealism”, in German Idealism: Contemporary Perspectives, Hammer, E. (ed.), London:
Routledge, 19-49.
Hegel, G.W.F. 1956, The Philosophy of History, trans. J. Sibree, New York: Dover.
German edition consulted: Philosophie der Geschichte, Stuttgart: Reclam, 1961.
Hegel, G.W.F. 1970, Philosophy of Nature: Being, in Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical
Sciences (1830), Part 2, trans. A.V. Miller, Oxford: Clarendon Press. German edition consulted: Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse (1830),
7th ed., Nicolin, F., Poggeler, O. (hrsg.), Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1969.
Spiritualized Nature
75
Hegel, G.W.F. 1971, Philosophy of Mind, in Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences
(1830), Part 3, trans. W. Wallace, Oxford: Clarendon Press. German edition consulted: Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften, Dritter Teil, Die Philosophie
des Geistes, in Werke. Theorie-Werkausgabe, Vol. 10, Moldenhauer, E., Michel, K.M.
(hrsg.), Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1969-79.
Hegel, G.W.F. 1975, Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art, Vol. 1, trans. T.M. Knox, New
York: Oxford University Press. German edition consulted: Vorlesungen über die Ästhetik (I/II), Stuttgart: Reclam, 1971.
Hegel, G.W.F. 1977, Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A.V. Miller, Oxford: Oxford University Press. German edition consulted: Phänomenologie des Geistes, Wessels, H.F., Clairmont, H. (hrsg.), Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1988.
Hegel, G.W.F. 1991a, The Encyclopaedia Logic, trans. T.F. Geraets, W.A. Suchting
and H.S. Harris, Indianapolis: Hackett. German edition consulted: Enzyklopädie
der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse: Die Wissenschaft der Logik (1830), in
Werke, 8, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1970.
Hegel, G.W.F. 1991b, Elements of the Philosophy of Right, Wood, A. (ed.), trans. H.B.
Nisbet, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. German edition consulted:
Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1970.
Hegel, G.W.F. 2010, Science of Logic, trans. G. di Giovanni, New York: Cambridge
University Press. German edition consulted: Wissenschaft der Logik, in Gesammelte
Werke, Vol. 12, Hamburg: Meiner, 1968.
McCumber, J. 1993, The Company of Words: Hegel, Language, and Systematic Philosophy,
Evanston: Norwestern University Press.
McDowell, J. 1996, Mind and World, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Peters, J. 2016, “On Naturalism in Hegel’s Philosophy of Spirit”, British Journal for the
History of Philosophy, 24, 1, 111-31.
Pippin, R. 2008 Hegel’s Practical Philosophy: Rational Agency as Ethical Life, New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Russon, J. 2009, “Emotional Subjects: Mood and Articulation in Hegel’s Philosophy
of Mind”, International Philosophical Quarterly, 49, 41-52.
Sartre, J.-P. 1993, Being and Nothingness, trans. H. Barnes, New York: Washington
Square Press.
Hegel’s Naturalism, the Negative and the
First Person Standpoint
Stefan Bird-Pollan
University of Kentucky
Abstract
In this paper I attempt to move the discussion of Hegel’s naturalism past what I
present as an impasse between the soft naturalist interpretation of Hegel’s notion
of Geist, in which Geist is continuous with nature, and the opposing claim that Geist
is essentially normative and self-legislating. In order to do so I suggest we look to
the question of value which underlies this dispute. While soft naturalists seek to
make sense of value as arising from material nature, those who support the autonomy thesis propose that value is something inherent to human spiritual activity.
Following McDowell’s suggestion that value as neither inhering or supervening on
nature, but is rather something we have been estranged from and hence something
to be recovered, I suggested that we adopt the first person perspective as the starting
point for an examination of the relation between nature and value. The first person
perspective is to be understood as a position within value which imbues value to
what it encounters and hence is a process of the reenchantment of nature. Seeing
things from this perspective allows us to place the question of nature as external
materiality (which both the soft naturalist and autonomy view seem to share) in its
proper context as something which develops as the result of the self-unfolding activity of consciousness as it encounters nature as negativity. Understanding Geist in
this way allows us to see value as inherent in nature.
Keywords: Hegel, McDowell, Autonomy, First-person Standpoint, Naturalism,
Negativity
Introduction
In this paper I’d like to consider the question of Hegel’s naturalism not just against
the larger question of the relation between mind and nature but also by considering the perspective from which Hegel thought it proper to do philosophy. The
question of naturalism thus becomes a question about the status of human subjectivity itself, or so I will argue. The thrust of much modern philosophy from
Descartes on has been to come to terms with the fact-value distinction which it
seemed incumber on the modern subject to make. This distinction, however,
brought with it the further question of whether this exclusion of value from nature
is to be embraced and philosophy should simply become a subfield of natural
Argumenta 4, 2 (2019): 77-95
ISSN 2465-2334
© 2019 University of Sassari
DOI 10.14275/10.14275/2465-2334/20198.bir
78
Stefan Bird-Pollan
science (as thinkers from La Mettrie to Jerry Fodor have held), or whether this
exclusion is itself a cultural or ideological phenomenon which should be understood as prompting the project of a reconciliation of human values with nature.
By working through the debate about Hegel’s naturalism I shall ultimately argue
that the latter is the case in Hegel’s philosophy and that the only coherent form
such a project of reconciliation with nature can take is that of a first-person account.
A place to begin entering into the debate is to ask what Hegel means by mind
or Geist. This debate is conceived primarily as a question of how to understand
what Hegel is doing in the Encyclopedia when he moves between its three parts,
Logic, Philosophy of Nature, and Philosophy of Spirit. The question within this
more specialized field of Hegel studies which has recently received a lot of attention centers on what is at stake in the transition point into and out of the Philosophy of Nature. The questions underlying the debate about these transition
points, however, to the larger one of what Hegel is to be understood as holding
some sort of scientific naturalism, that is, as claiming that Geist develops out of
nature. The two views at stake here are what I shall call the continuity view and
the autonomy view.1
While the continuity view holds that Hegel’s conception of Geist beholden to
nature in some deep sense, the autonomy view holds that what constitutes Geist
is its proper separateness from nature, its ability to legislate independently from
nature. The former view is associated with writers who attempt to place Hegel in
the context of Aristotle’s thought that the soul is continuous with nature, while
the latter view is most strongly associated with Robert Pippin’s interpretation of
Hegel. I will suggest that this debate can be clarified by drawing on John McDowell’s account in Mind and World which effectively splits the middle, synthesizing
both.2 As a middle position McDowell’s position does much to clarify but not to
resolve the debate at the epistemic level.
I propose to move the debate forward by looking beyond the Encyclopedia to
Hegel’s position in the Phenomenology which, I argue, frames the discussion in the
Encyclopedia from the standpoint of the development of consciousness. Picking up
on McDowell’s suggestion that the debate around nature is one of overcoming
the disenchantment we have fallen into as a result of the scientific revolution, I
propose the Phenomenology account as an attempted reconciliation between Geist
and nature. Such an account, I argue, can only take place from the first-person
perspective. The first-person perspective of the Phenomenology reveals that all
knowledge, including that achieved in the Encyclopedia, is to be understood from
the perspective of the subject in such a way that we cannot meaningfully speak of
a nature which exists outside or independently of the subject in anything but a
notional way. The relation between Geist and nature is in this way, I shall argue,
1
I should note the parallel (and highly relevant) discussion of a similar set of issues in
contemporary philosophy of mind by Matt Boyle and in Kant studies by James Conant.
Both of these debates challenge what I am calling the continuity view or what Boyle calls
the additive view (cf. Boyle 2016, Conant 2016).
2
It is perhaps odd to suggest that McDowell synthesizes these two approaches since, as a
historical matter, at least one central impetus for the debate arose from the publication of
McDowell’s Aristotelian/Kantian work Mind and World in which Hegel turns out to be the
point of synthesis.
Hegel’s Naturalism, the Negative and the First Person Standpoint
79
always already a value-relation since it arises from consciousness’ attempt to
make sense of itself and its environment.
Part I: The Naturalism Debate
In the first part of the paper I’d like to present what I take to be three ways of
understanding Hegel’s discussion of the relation between Geist and nature: the
continuity view which contends that we can understand Geist as emerging out of
nature on an Aristotelian view, the autonomy view which argues that for Hegel
Geist is to be understood as essentially discontinuous with nature and rather as a
normative self-relation and, finally, the middle position, associated with John
McDowell, which seeks to accommodate both claims. But let me not overstate
the point: recent debates around Hegel’s naturalism have only run the somewhat
tight gamut between what might be called the soft naturalism of the continuity
theory and the fairly strong idealism of the autonomy thesis. The purpose of this
section is thus to set up a debate which is in need of resolution by attending to the
larger question of the perspective from which to understanding of our exclusion
from nature.
1. Soft Naturalism
The project of giving a naturalistic account of Hegel has attracted many few takers
than has the project of giving a metaphysical realist account of his philosophy.
Sebastian Gardner has usefully distinguished between soft and hard naturalism
in this debate. Gardner sees hard naturalism as substituting natural science for the
insights metaphysical has traditionally been said to provide. The move to the idea
that natural science contains the answers to questions of value, however, meant
that human values not authorized by nature had to be rejected as somehow supernatural. The various attempts to make value intelligible as somehow inhering
in nature should, according to Gardner, be characterized as soft naturalism because they seek to add value back into nature.3 Soft naturalism or non-reductive
naturalism tries to show that “there is nothing within naturalistic commitment as
such that threatens the value-interests of natural consciousness” (Gardner 2007:
28).
The paradigm for soft-naturalism is the Aristotelian claim that:
the soul is in the primary way that by which we live and perceive and think, so
that it will be a sort of organization (logos) and a form, but not matter and a substrate. For substance [is either form or matter or] another what is from both; and
of these the matter is potentiality and the form actuality. Since what is from both
is an ensouled thing, the body is not the actuality of the soul, but the soul is the
actuality of some body (Aristotle 2016: 26, 414a12-18).
3
Gardner 2007: 24. For the thesis that soft naturalism adds value back in see p. 31. This
point is also made by Grier (2013: 233-37) who, in the context of an analysis of Hegel’s
understanding of the mind-body problem, argues that contemporary writers in the AngloAmerican tradition on the mind-body problem who are non-reductivist must contend with
various problem in adding back in something non-natural to the view of the brain as material.
80
Stefan Bird-Pollan
Evidence for this soft naturalism can be found in Hegel’s claim that the basis paradigm of Geist developed in the Phenomenology even applies to animals:
Nor are the animals excluded from this wisdom. Instead they prove themselves to
be the most deeply initiated into it, for they do not stand still in the face of sensuous
things, as if those things existed in themselves. Despairing of the reality of those
things and in the total certainty of the nullity of those things, they without any
further ado simply help themselves to them and devour them (PS §109, 66-67; PG
9: 69).4
The secret Hegel refers here is the wisdom of knowing that the sensuous passes,
and hence, in the larger sense, that we as subjects are ourselves part of the cause
of this transformation.5
The general strategy of this approach is to read Hegel’s treatment of nature
as continuous with the psychic life of Geist. This strategy is particularly attractive
within the confines of the Encyclopedia where Hegel’s transitions from Logic to
the Philosophy of Nature is represented as that of the same entity and therefore
as continuous with the previous section.6 A particularly strong version of this claim
is made by Beiser who writes: “Hegel assumes throughout his Naturphilosophie
that nature exists apart from and prior to human consciousness, and that the development of humanity presupposes and only arises from the prior development
of the organic powers of nature”.7 The central claim is that by reflecting on the
development of mind out of nature a non-dualistic account of mind can be developed which nevertheless does justice to the essential mindedness of spirit. This
approach can also be seen in the discussion of habit which forms a key transition
point from the Philosophy of Nature to the Philosophy Spirit in the final part of
the Encyclopedia.8
A different soft naturalist approach has recently been proposed by Alison
Stone who argues that we can understand Hegel’s naturalism on a spectrum, lying
between the two axes of (1) the continuity between the natural science and philosophy and, (2) the level of the rejection of the supernatural. Citing Hegel’s claim
4
In text references to the Phenomenology of Spirit will be to Hegel 2018 (as PS with § and
page number); reference to the German edition Phänomenologie des Geistes, will be to Hegel
1968b (as PG followed by volume number of the Gesammelte Werke and page number).
5
See, for instance, McCumber’s discussion of this passage also with reference to Pippin’s
discussion of the same passage (McCumber 2013: 80, Pippin 2008).
6
There has been significant discussion of the status of these transitions, especially the transition from Logic to the Philosophy of Nature. Recent writers have generally agreed with
Houlgate that the transition cannot be understood as merely the application of the Logic to
the Philosophy of Nature but must be seen as dialectical, with the Philosophy of Nature
clarifying the metaphysical basis of science and natural science articulating some of the
details that the Philosophy of Nature cannot engage with. Houlgate writes: “absolute reason discloses itself actually to be nature itself by proving logically to be immediately selfrelating being” (Houlgate 2005: 107). See also Rand (2007: section II) who argues against
the a priori nature of the Philosophy of Nature as well as Stone’s (2005: 2) claim that Hegel’s position is itself not entirely consistent.
7
Beiser 2005: 68. Other who are tempted by the developmental approach include Winfield
who argues that mind develops directly out of nature in a series of three stages: psyche,
consciousness and intelligence. Winfield 2007: 107-108.
8
For an account of habit, see Testa, forthcoming. For a more general approach to this issue
see Illetterati 2016.
Hegel’s Naturalism, the Negative and the First Person Standpoint
81
that “Not only must philosophy be in agreement with our empirical knowledge
of Nature, but the origin and formation of the Philosophy of Nature presupposes
and is conditioned by empirical physics”, Stone suggests that for Hegel there is
no sharp distinction between science and philosophy since in origin and formation philosophy depends on natural science but in terms of method, science
depends on philosophy9 (PN §246R, 6; 20: 236).10 On the continuity between natural science and philosophy, Stone argues that Hegel is more of a naturalist than
Kant for whom final ends are merely regulative ideals, while on the naturalismsupernaturalism axis Hegel is more naturalistic than Schelling for whom the development of nature and philosophy depends on supernatural polar forces acting
on the universe. For Stone, Hegel’s concept of life is an immanent natural conception of the relation between nature and mindedness (Stone 2005: 73-74).
Peters, from whom I borrow the characterization of the soft naturalist approach as the continuity approach, suggests that while for Aristotle soul was indeed continuous with nature, this cannot be the case for Hegel who also holds an
autonomy view under which nature must be consciously incorporated into subjectivity just as a proposition contains both subject and predicate (Peters 2016:
115, 120). For Peters, there is something irreducible about Geist which emerges
out of nature.
Gardner has some more general reasons for being skeptical of the explanatory power soft naturalist approaches can offer. Gardner argues that the “having
one’s cake and eating it too” approach of soft naturalism is inherently unstable
because in order to add value back in to the naturalist picture, soft naturalism
must rely on a dual aspect view which considers value as both irreducible to nature as well as merely nature depending on which view on takes. But the very
question of where to locate value, Gardner argues, is what is in need of either
metaphysical or naturalistic explanation: how can a phenomenon be both one of
value and also not (Gardner 2007: 30). Indeed, it is precisely the strength of hard
naturalism as a substitute for metaphysics that makes soft naturalism questionable
as a position. Rather, as Gardner suggests, what soft naturalism is actually trying
to do is to approximate idealism’s ability to make sense of value but without giving up on some version of the preeminence of the modern science (ibid.: 28). If
naturalism is not the answer, then we should look to idealism.
2. Idealism and Autonomy
An alternative position to soft naturalism has long been prominent in the interpretation of Hegel and is associated with the positions of Pippin and, I shall argue,
to some extent with that of Terry Pinkard. In moving to this interpretation we are
moving from an interpretive paradigm which seeks to account for value in terms
of what can be learned about nature to one which is thoroughly normative. According to Pippin, the autonomy position endorses the claims “that we are better
off leaving nature out of the picture altogether and that doing so begs no questions” (Pippin 2005: 189). Pippin’s comment comes in the context of a debate
with McDowell about the meaning of just the appropriation of Aristotle by Hegel
that was at issue in the continuity approach. For Hegel, Pippin argues,
9
Stone 2013: 65. For a similar conclusion, see Houlgate 2005: 116.
Hegel 2004: 1968a.
10
82
Stefan Bird-Pollan
Spirit must be conceived […] as some sort of collectively achieved, normative human mindedness if it is to be properly rendered intelligible, but doing this, as already noted, seems to require some very unusual formulations: that spirit is its
own “self-liberation from Nature”, that spirit “is a product of itself” […] and that
its actuality (Wirklichkeit) is that it “has made itself into what it is” (PS, 1: 6-7).11
Against the continuity approach, Pippin argues that Spirit must be conceived as
self-authorizing. Underlying this claim is Pippin’s further claim that Geist is only
“intelligible” as self-authorizing and that other descriptions of Geist as nature are
“inappropriate” (Pippin 2005: 16). The claim about intelligibility, I believe, fits
directly into the debate about whether epistemology can bear the weight of intelligibility: is the something, the item, which perception refers to somehow determinately involved in the conceptual response which follows it, without being nonconceptually contentful. Put differently, can perception be the ground of intelligibility? The dilemma Pippin poses to McDowell and any others who seek to employ an Aristotelian paradigm is this: either nature is contentful by itself and so
can explain the activity of Geist (this is essentially the position of the continuity
thesis) or nature is not itself contentful and hence we do not need to worry about
how nature is taken up into Geist.12
Pippin characterizes the terms of the dispute quite lucidly in a footnote:
It seems quite wrong to deny that a fairly rich, determinate “having the world in
view” (McDowell) can come into focus directly in a sensible exchange with the
world, without my yet being able to resolve just what it is I am seeing, without my
affirmative judgment. But these initial presentations of such a view are wrongly
described, I think, as simply “wrung out of us”. I think that we can call such views
“a way the world is taken to be” without fearing that this will look like takes on
an independently given sensible “material” (Pippin 2016: 69).
Pippin’s point, as he puts it in an earlier version of the debate, is that “the relevant
image for our “always already engaged” conceptual and practical capacities in
the German Idealist tradition is legislative power, not empirical discrimination and
deliberative judgment”.13
The important point for the general dispute sketched here is that Pippin sides
with a normative interpretation against the naturalist view. This view pits the continuity view’s ontology against the normative account of the autonomy. Pippin, paraphrasing Sellars (I think), puts the point thus: “As in Sellars, so, I think, in Hegel.
The core idea: to think of someone as a person is not to ‘classify or explain, but
to rehearse an intention’” (Pippin 2008: 61). The key point for Pippin is that the
normative must categorically frame the natural in the sense that whatever nature
we come in contact with must already be in some way intelligible to us in terms of
our actual normative commitments. Nature, for Pippin, can in this way drop out
of the picture as something that cannot be discussed on its own, as the continuity
view holds.
11
Pippin 2005: 16. The references to Hegel are to Hegel 1978: 1, 6-7.
Pippin (2016: 65) makes the stronger claim, in agreement with Gardner’s claim just above
about the untenability of a soft naturalism, that if we concede that first nature is related to
second nature, then second nature must ultimately be reducible to first nature.
13
Pippin 2005: 197. For a discussion of naturalism which privileges Pippin’s side over
McDowell in the context of the naturalism debate see Papazoglou 2012: 25-27.
12
Hegel’s Naturalism, the Negative and the First Person Standpoint
83
3. McDowell’s Middle Position
The two sides of the debate so far outlined consist on the one side of the claim
that Hegel’s naturalism is to be understood as the development of consciousness
from within nature in accordance with the categories laid down by the Logic. The
other alternative, which I’ve suggested we call the autonomy view or idealism, is
the thought that Hegel is no kind of naturalist at all since for him it is consciousness’ relation to itself which is central.
Having delineated both of these positions, it is now time to look at a proposal
which walks the line between the two and to which both lines are in a sense responding namely, McDowell’s position as it is articulated in Mind and World. We
can think of McDowell’s position as an attempt to draw together the ontological
aspect of nature with the normative aspects of mind as judging in such a way that
each becomes intelligible only in terms of the other. McDowell writes:
My alternative holds on to the thought rejected by bald naturalism, that the structure of the logical space of reasons is sui generis, as compared with the structure of
the logical space within which natural-scientific description situates things. Even
so, my alternative makes room for us to suppose […] both that the very idea of
experience is the idea of something natural and that empirical thinking is answerable to experience (McDowell 1996: xx).
McDowell seeks to make intelligible the continuity thesis, that is, the immanent relation of what he calls the space of nature to the space of reason but in such a way
that it is possible to understand that the space of nature is, by being placed fully
within the space of reason only intelligible in terms of the space of reason but without
thereby losing the distinction between the space of nature and the space of reason.
McDowell seeks to mediate between these positions by suggesting that at the
epistemic level, nature cannot make sense without the work of conceptual uptake.
McDowell articulates this point by using the terms of nature and second nature,
arguing that natural-scientific intelligibility is something that humans come to by
being initiated into the space of reasons through what he calls second nature.14
The point then is to understand the acquisition of experience as the process of
nature the way science would describe it, being brought into the space of reason
in the process of “second nature”. “Human beings acquire a second nature in part
by being initiated into conceptual capacities, whose interrelations belong in the
logical space of reasons” (ibid.).
Peters has sketched a Hegelian version of this particular thought which is
able to go some way in reconciling the continuity view with the autonomy view.
Pointing out both that Hegel praises Aristotle for holding a view of the soul as
activity and that Hegel also understands the soul as self-differentiating, Peters argues for an autonomy view which is nevertheless beholden to nature in a determinate way. Taking as her example the first moment of the Philosophy of Nature,
mechanism, Peters argues that we can understand the externality operating in the
mechanism of, in her example, writing letters, as persisting while also understanding the activity of writing as the fully internalized process of Geist. Peters argues
that the unity which is created between Geist and mechanism can be understood
as the external having become, as external a reflection of Geist (Peters 2016: 126).
14
For an account of first and second nature in McDowell see Testa 2007.
Stefan Bird-Pollan
84
This is an attractive view in the sense that it explicates the necessity of drawing
on nature in our spiritual activity in a way that constitutes an acknowledgment of
our determination by nature as, here, needing to write in order to communicate.
Pinkard’s recent account of Hegel’s position in Hegel’s Naturalism has deepen
the debate significantly. As Pinkard aptly puts it, “The philosophy of nature thus
deals with the kinds of conceptual problems that arise when anything ‘finite’ is
asserted to be the ‘unconditioned’” (Pinkard 2012: 20). Pinkard considers the real
question of Hegel’s philosophy of nature to be the task of rethinking “the nature
of our own mindful agency, Geist, that we come to see nature as the ‘other’ of
Geist. In Hegel’s more dialectical terms, ‘we’ as natural creatures make ourselves
distinct from nature” (ibid.). But in pursuing this question, Pinkard argues, Hegel
distinguishes sharply between the natural and the sort of awareness which is to
be found in self-consciousness. Only the latter, because it is capable of taking its
inwardness as inwardness, has the capacity for making inferences (ibid.: 29, 27).
And this means, for Pinkard, that the human soul is no longer really a soul at all
but rather self-conscious agency (ibid.: 30).
This middle position understands the relation between nature and Geist in
such a way that nature is mediated by the work or activity of consciousness rather
than being given by the “brute facts” of nature. But the middle position is nevertheless careful to acknowledge that this activity is always prompted by consciousness’ determinate embeddedness in nature.
4. Disenchantment
I said at the outset that I wanted to take the discussion of Hegel’s naturalism as the
opportunity to reflect on some of the larger questions connected to our modern
exclusion from nature and what this means for the question of values as either arising out of nature or being the product of human activity independently of nature.
To make some headway here let us look at the question which McDowell’s account
of nature is intended to address at a deeper level, namely the question of disenchantment. This disenchantment consists, says McDowell, in the experience of being faced with a nature which is excluded from the space of reason as the result of
something like the scientific revolution. The choice has either been to accept this
disenchantment as bald naturalism does or to side with supernaturalism or, as
McDowell puts it, with “rampant platonism [which] has what intelligibility it has
as a desperate attempt to keep meaning, conceived as able to come into view only
within a sui generis logical space, while acquiescing in the disenchantment of nature”
(McDowell 1996: 110). Both views, for McDowell, accept disenchantment or, what
Gardner characterized as the disappearance of value from nature.
By remaining at the epistemological level the mediating position McDowell
advocates still leaves us undecided between the continuity view and the autonomy
view.15 For it, on the face of it, is equally plausible to construct the complete overlap between nature and mind McDowell suggests as proceeding from the perspective of nature, as in the continuity view, and as proceeding from mind, as the
autonomy view suggests.
15
See Peters 2016: 120. Cf. Grier (2013: 225-26) who sees Hegel’s answer to the problem
of mind-body interaction as lying in his claim that mind and body, spirit and nature, must
overlap to a significant extent without taking a side in the debate between the continuity
and the autonomy view.
Hegel’s Naturalism, the Negative and the First Person Standpoint
85
However, if we attend to McDowell’s metaphor of disenchantment, we can
see in which way to take the idea of a second nature. McDowell argues that using
the concept of second nature allows us to “refuse to equate that domain of intelligibility with nature, let alone with what is real” by constructing a “knowing”
alternative to disenchantment (McDowell 1996: 109). This alternative, McDowell
suggests, would be equip Kantian spontaneity with something like second nature.16 This would allow us to see that “an experiencing and acting subject is a
living thing, with active and passive bodily powers that are genuinely her own; she
is herself embodied, substantially present in the world that she experiences and
acts on” (ibid.: 111). Second nature should to be understood in an experiential or
first personal way rather than as something that merely happens to the subject. Yes,
second nature is still the experience of finding ourselves affected by nature and of
responding to this first nature but this response is now conceived of as the activity
of the subject. Second nature is now revealed to be active, the equivalent to Kantian
spontaneity, while first nature is conceived of as Kantian receptivity.
The fundamental point is that it is only from a first-person perspective that
something like a reenchantment can even begin to make sense because the project
of owning or authorizing one’s response to nature can only ever be something which
the subject can do for herself. Bald naturalism can be exorcized only if we realize
that the account of spontaneity or of meaning making is itself sufficient to generate the meaning we need. To be tempted by more meaning, meaning which goes
beyond nature, would then to be to return to supernaturalism but to settle for less
would be to sell ourselves short.
5. Hegel’s Phenomenology and the First Person Standpoint
I have just argued that the proper way to read the dispute between those who
argue for the continuity thesis and those who argue for the autonomy thesis in the
debate about what Hegel means by nature can be resolved by understanding the
debate itself to be framed by the question of whether a third-person or a firstperson view is to be privileged.17 I’ve just suggested that McDowell argues for the
latter. I will now argue that Hegel’s Phenomenology frames the Encyclopedia account
as a first-personal account.
What is at issue, fundamentally, is the question of how we understand value.
Is value something which exists somehow independently of us in nature and which
can be grasped, does it exist in a supernatural realm which can be grasped as a
“fact”, or is value rather something what we imbue to nature. The first option is,
with qualifications, that of soft naturalism, the second that of a theological perspective which we have not discussed. The third position is held both by autonomy and
the middle position. The contrast between the first two perspectives and the third
can be elucidated, I claim, in terms of two types of perspectives on nature they hold.
Reversing the order let us take the autonomy/middle position first.
Let me call the autonomy/middle position the engineering model and the
soft naturalism position that of philosophical naturalism.18 The engineering
16
For a reading of McDowell on Kant, see Bird-Pollan 2017.
Peters (2016: 121) has noted the fact that the Encyclopedia can be read equally from a first
and a third person perspective but that the standpoint of Geist is essentially that of the first
person.
18
For a similar distinction to the one I am proposing between naturalism and engineering, see Kuhn 1977. The distinction I am tracking is also the one employed by Heidegger
17
86
Stefan Bird-Pollan
model of science takes it, as the name suggests, that our investigations into nature
are essentially in the service of human projects like building better bridges, producing better crops or developing new techniques for teaching literacy. Here it is
science which is made relevant to the human values which precede it. Value is not
something that escapes us but something that we bestow upon nature by turning
nature to our ends.19 I characterize this model as first-personal because nature is
here seen as continuous with human projects, hence as essentially intelligible from
within human life itself.
The second model, philosophical naturalism, might be characterized as the
radicalization of the engineering model, moving from the occasional failure of
our construction projects to the Cartesian notion of radical doubt which presents
nature as essentially other to us and as therefore standing in need of being given
meaning as a whole.20 The reason I characterizes this perspective as third-personal
is that here the conception of nature is one of an outsider looking in, inspecting
something of which she is not part.
McDowell puts the distinction I’ve been drawing thus:
According to my picture, an important element in this clarification of the proper
target of natural science was an increasingly firm awareness that we must sharply
distinguish natural-scientific understanding from the kind of understanding
achieved by situating what is understood in the logical space of reasons; that is,
precisely, that the structure of the logical space of reasons is sui generis (McDowell
1996: xxii).
Reenchantment, as McDowell argues, consists of exorcizing the thought that the
proper way to understand nature is from a perspective which is sui generis, that is,
independent from that of human activity. We need to return to something like the
engineering model.
I’d now like to suggest that the same worry underlies Hegel’s thinking in the
Introduction to the Phenomenology in which he considers the problem of how to
understand a science of consciousness in a way which avoids the picture of the
subject looking in on nature and itself from the outside. The project is to
reenchant nature by making it intelligible that Geist is essentially engaged in the
project seeking to become at home with itself. By this I do not mean to suggest
that we should conceive of Hegel as sanctifying all aspects of the present but
merely as suggesting that certain kinds of anxieties about our relation to nature
have been concerning us in a way which has prevented us from attending to the
full potential of human freedom.
Part II: Hegel’s Introduction: The Path of Consciousness
I’d now like to turn to Hegel’s account of the project he proposes to undertake in
the Phenomenology. The aim is to substantiate the claim that Hegel is interested in
showing that the modern conception of the opposition between consciousness
and nature needs to be replaced by a conception of the reconciled subject and that
in his distinction between the ready-to-hand and the present-at-hand (cf. Heidegger
1962: §22).
19
For a historical perspective on this model see Shapin 1996: ch. 3.
20
This move has been noted by writers in the Anglo-American tradition as well as by those
in the German tradition. See, for instance, Williams 2005: 22; Klein 1936: 208.
Hegel’s Naturalism, the Negative and the First Person Standpoint
87
this account is essentially given from what I’ve been calling the first-person point
of view which is compatible with the view that nature is the site of value.
The task will thus be twofold: first I’ll argue that the first three paragraphs of
the Introduction (§§73-75) give an account of the problem of disenchantment or
alienation of the subject from nature much as it appeared in McDowell. That is,
I shall argue, following for instance Georg Bertram, that the position we find ourselves in at the beginning of the Phenomenology is not the position of any particular
historical position but rather, as Pirmin Stekeler-Weithofer puts it, that of a “philosophical mystification” of ourselves with regard to the world.21
Secondly, I’ll argue that the program articulated in the Introduction should
be read as proposing that only a first personal standpoint can make sense of the
subject’s relation to nature. In proposing to understand Hegel’s project in the Phenomenology as a first-person account I follow suggestions made both by Pinkard
and by Stekeler-Weithofer. Pinkard’s interpretation of the Phenomenology as the
“sociality of reason” which holds that self-consciousness
is not the awareness of a set of internal objects (sensations, mental occurrences,
representations, whatever). To use a metaphor, self-consciousness is at least minimally the assumption of a position in “social space”. We locate ourselves in “social space” when, for example, we reason in various ways; or when we assume
various roles; or when we demand a certain type of treatment because of who we
think we are (Pinkard 1994: 7).
For Pinkard (ibid.: 8), Hegel’s account of knowledge is one of the authorization
of the standards which govern meaning in the community through reason-giving
and the immanent critique of that reason giving. As self-authorization this account is essentially first-person plural. There is no external standard beyond the
community of reason-givers to which one can appeal in understanding the nature
to which the Geist is subject.
Similarly Stekeler-Weithofer suggests that we should construe what Hegel
means by science as a first-personal communal knowing. As he puts it, “das Kriterium des subjektiven Wissens im Ich-Modus ist ein Wissen im Wir-Modus. Ein
solches Wissen setzt entsprechende Wir-Kriterien der Wahrheit voraus, und das
je zu der Zeit oder Epoche, die zu betrachten ist” (Stekeler-Weithofer 2014: 360).
I take it that the position articulated here by Pinkard and Stekeler-Weithofer is
also consistent with positions endorsed, for instance, by Robert Brandom (2019)
and, of course, by Pippin. In turning to the question of the first-person interpretation of the relation between consciousness and nature we are leaving behind
both soft naturalism and the family squabble between McDowell and Pippin in
order to focus on how consciousness is to understand itself as reconcilable with
nature.
1. The Disenchantment of Modern Philosophy
Hegel begins the Phenomenology with a rejection of the problem that he had inherited from philosophical naturalism:
21
See Bertram 2017: 35; “Was also tun wir Sinnvolles, so lautet die Frage, wenn wir unserem Wissen eine Welt gegenüberstellen und unserem Erkennen eine objektive Natur an
sich, die ist, wie sie ist? Und warum tendieren wir dazu, diese Gegenüberstellungen metaphysisch zu mystifizieren und damit misszuverstehen?” (Stekeler-Weithofer 2014: 364).
88
Stefan Bird-Pollan
It is a natural supposition that in philosophy, before one gets down to dealing with
what is at issue, namely, the actual cognition of what, in truth, is, it is first necessary to come to an understanding about cognition, which is regarded as the instrument by which one seizes hold of the absolute or as the means by which one
catches sight of it (PS §73, 49; PG 9: 53).
Hegel is quite clear that he does not regard this “natural supposition” of the division between subject and nature as innocent. For, as he suggests, the idea that we
should employ tools or a method for the investigation of nature is itself based on
a “fear of error” which undermines the more innocent notion of science (as engineering) which concerns itself with laws only to the extent that they help us explain phenomena. The fear of failure is what ratchets up the need for intermediaries, paradigmatically the application of mathematics to sciences.22
[I]f the concern about falling into error sets up a mistrust of science, which itself,
untroubled by such scruples, simply sets itself to work and actually cognizes, it is
still difficult to see why on the contrary a mistrust of this mistrust should not be
set up and why one should not be concerned that this fear of erring is already the
error itself (PS §74, 50; PG 9: 54).
It is a pathology of philosophical naturalism to think that science must search for
more and more severe methods of ensuring its truth. The problem is that the error
cannot be guarded against by a method or tools which are themselves independent of the very problem they are meant to address. Hegel summarizes the problem
thus:
[The new science] presupposes that the absolute stands on one side and that cognition
stands on the other for itself, and separated from the absolute, though cognition is
nevertheless something real; that is, it presupposes that cognition, which, by being
outside of the absolute, is indeed also outside of the truth, is nevertheless truthful;
an assumption through which that which calls itself the fear of error gives itself
away to be known rather as the fear of truth (PS §75, 50; PG 9: 54).
For the moment, let us follow Stekeler-Weithofer’s (2014: 363) suggestion that we
should think of the “absolute” simply as the generic object separate from its particular appearance. Hegel’s point can then be understood to be saying that philosophical naturalism wants to have it both ways: it wants, on the one hand, to claim
that it has the power of knowing how nature is qua generic object (hence stripped
of the way it appears) which means that philosophical naturalism has arrogate to
itself the power of cognition. On the other hand, philosophical naturalism wants
to claim that what it cognizes is not a product of its own activity but lies somehow
in nature ready to be taken. The point is that cognition cannot at once be the authoritative source of knowledge and also the passive recipient of knowledge.
22
This is how I read the passage at the end of §73: “if the testing of cognition which we
suppose to be a medium made us acquainted with the law of its refraction, it would be just
as useless to subtract this refraction from the result, for it is not the refraction of the ray but
rather the ray itself through which the truth touches us that is cognition, and if this is subtracted, then all that would be indicated to us would be just pure direction or empty place”
(PS 50; PG 9: 54).
Hegel’s Naturalism, the Negative and the First Person Standpoint
89
2. Natural Consciousness and the First Person Perspective
We now arrive at the second element in Hegel’s account I propose to investigate.
After looking at the problem of the disenchantment which Hegel diagnoses in the
position of traditional philosophical attitudes, we turn to the question of the
reenchantment of nature by addressing the problem of the standpoint of Hegel’s
investigation. It has been my argument that only from the first person standpoint
can something like the attribution of value make sense because the first-person
standpoint exists prior to the separation of facts from their meaning for our projects.
It is, Hegel says, not enough to have pointed out the mistakes of the position
just encountered, a new understanding of reality will have to be developed. Hegel’s project in the Phenomenology is to make plausible the first-person standpoint
by showing that only it can make sense of the relation between consciousness and
nature. In proposing such a position, Hegel is fully aware of the temptation of the
model of philosophical naturalism and so offers the reader a way of thinking
about philosophical naturalism as something to be overcome through the development of the new model of first-personal consciousness. It is not enough, in
other words, to move from the naturalist paradigm we have just seen to take refuge
in the engineering paradigm I outlined earlier. In these matters “one arid assurance
is just as valid as another” (PS §76, 52; PG 9: 56). The point is rather to show that
only the first-person standpoint can be successful in accounting for our relation to
nature. To do so would be to offer a partial reenchantment of nature in the sense
of revealing that human subjectivity is already involved in the meaning of “nature”.
To this effect, Hegel offers a new beginning in what he calls “natural consciousness”. Natural consciousness is supposed to be a position which does not
take for granted anything or which, we could say, is still devoid of the temptation
to do so.23 Hegel says:
This standpoint [from which the exposition starts] can […] be taken to be the path
of natural consciousness pressing forward towards true knowing, or it can be taken
to be the path of the soul wandering through the series of ways it takes shape, as if
these were stations put forward in advance to it by its own nature, so that it purifies
itself into spirit by arriving at a cognition of what it is in itself through the complete
experience of its own self (PS §77, 52; PG 9: 55).
The key point here is that Hegel places the two basic elements, Geist and nature,
cognition and what is, which traditionally are conceived as spatio-temporally separated, into the subject itself. He is thereby repeating Kant’s Copernican turn of
understanding mind as constituted by spontaneity’s response to receptivity (Kant
1996: A50/B74). This means, in an initial expression of the first person perspective, that the subject has only itself to look to as a source of self-understanding.
Of course this move to the first person perspective hardly settled the issue
since from the perspective of natural consciousness precisely nothing is yet decided. However, and this is the important point for us, the idea of the internal
23
Fulda (2008: 24-25) suggests a long list of preconceptions about natural conscious’ position that are to be avoided, chief among these are that natural consciousness is not to be
supposed to have an “object” independent of itself and that what “truly is” need not be or
belong to nature at all.
Stefan Bird-Pollan
90
relation of mind to nature is, for Hegel, the correct perspective from which to
launch the investigation.
3. Appearance, Negativity and Skepticism
Hegel characterizes the “scientific” position natural consciousness finds itself in
as an appearance, and suggests that science must free itself from this appearance
by “turning against appearance” (PS §76, 51; PG 9: 55). Turning against appearance is something that, Hegel says, happens to the subject immanently: “while
[natural consciousness’ immediately] regards itself rather as real knowing, this
path has negative meaning for it, and what is the realization of the concept will
count instead, to it, as the loss of itself, for on this path, it loses its truth” (PS §78,
52; PG 9: 56). The point is straightforward in the sense that natural consciousness
must regard certain things as true and can do so by applying a concept. However,
because the concept is only limited (an appearance of truth) it will eventually be
revealed to fail but will do so on immanent terms, that is as the failure of a conception that consciousness has itself posited. This failure will then be prompting
natural consciousness to renew its efforts to make sense of its position.
Hegel’s strategy synthetic in that he works through other position to achieve
his own. Accordingly, in the Introduction he presents the process of achieving
knowledge in terms of a conception which is already familiar to his readers, that
of skepticism.24 Hegel characterizes skepticism in two ways, as a meta-conception
connected to philosophical naturalism and as closer to the trial and error model
implicit in the engineering model.
Skepticism is first taken up as the meta-insight of the subject who finds that
repeated failures to grasp the world constitute not just particular failures against
a background of stability or trust but rather a “path of despair” (PS §78, 52; PG
9: 56). Hegel elaborates:
this path is the conscious insight into the untruth of knowing as it appears, a knowing for which that which is the most real is rather in truth only the unrealized
concept. Thus this self-consummating skepticism is also not what earnest zeal for
truth and science surely thinks it has prepared and equipped itself with so that it
might be ready for truth and science (PS §78, 52; PG 9: 56).
The meta-insight offered by skepticism thus returns us to the conceptual level of
philosophical naturalism. Skepticism or philosophical naturalism demands
knowledge without having worked through nature to achieve this knowledge.
Knowledge is thus posited as something of which humans are both capable and
incapable. Skepticism is the positing of a radical spontaneity of mind incapable
of interfacing with nature on the one hand and a concomitant claim that this
spontaneity should also be able to bridge the gap thereby set up to nature. This is
the same thought as the thought that humans are both authorized (actively) to
make claims about nature and that nature (passively) lays itself bare for human
investigation, just with emphasis on the necessary failure of this project rather
24
For a helpful review of the many different interpretations of Hegel’s notion of skepticism
see Speight 2010. Speight himself suggests that Hegel’s notion combines the insight of Pyrrhonism that thought should take nothing for granted with a more modern existential sense
of skepticism (cf. Speight 2010: 149). This approach sits well with the interpretation I offer
here.
Hegel’s Naturalism, the Negative and the First Person Standpoint
91
than on its success. This dilemma is what I take Hegel to mean by saying that
skepticism is “self-consuming”.
In the second “engineering” sense, however, skepticism captures a more pedestrian notion of the persistence of the negative.
[T]he skepticism which is directed at the entire range of consciousness as it appears, makes spirit for the first time competent to test what truth is, by this kind of
skepticism bringing about a despair regarding the so-called natural conceptions,
thoughts, and opinions (PS §78, 53; PG 9: 56).
The persistence of doubt about whether consciousness has in its particular claims
found the right concept is what allows a movement toward truth. Progress is
made, Hegel says, by consistently testing or evaluating knowledge claims which
arise immanently (are “natural conceptions”) in terms of the projects consciousness seeks or is driven to undertake. Here values proceed knowledge claims, making knowledge claims testable in terms of the values the subject wishes to achieve.
The experience of “appearance” (what is thought to be true) turning out to
be merely appearance (merely a claim) is the basic motor of Hegel’s thinking in the
Phenomenology and elsewhere and constitutes determinate negation.25 Through determinate negation, skepticism—rightly understood—is shown not only to be negative but also to have a positive result:
while the result [of skeptical inquiry] is grasped as it is in truth, as determinate negation, a new form has thereby immediately arisen, and in the negation, the transition is made whereby the progression through the complete series of shapes
comes about on its own accord (PS §79, 53; PG 9: 57).
Skepticism, Hegel argues, should not simply be understood as the annihilation of
content but rather as a stepping back from content in order to allow new content
to become available to be considered in its own right.
The idea of determinate negation is already implicit in Kant’s claim that
spontaneity responds to receptivity in the sense that spontaneity, in subsuming
intuition under a concept, gives the intuition a determinate content. Determinate
negation is also implicit in McDowell’s claim that in order for the cognition to
even be involved in the understanding of nature, nature (as receptivity) must be
drawn on in cognition thereby rendering the impingement of nature something
determinate.
If determinate negation is indeed the process which drives the development
of Hegel’s thought this leads to a new conception of the natural. We have already
seen that Hegel’s turn to the first person perspective means that there cannot, at
the outset at least, be talk of the opposition between consciousness and nature as
external since the relation of material externality, such as it is assumed in philosophical naturalism, is still unfounded. I would thus like to suggest that for Hegel
the idea of nature can therefore best be understood in its most generic sense, as
determinate negation, that is, as the continued “appearance” of an incongruence
with the currently employed conceptual scheme. This is the core of the claim I
attributed to McDowell against Pipping, namely that the failure of consciousness’
25
Brandom (2019: ch. 2) characterizes determinate negation as Hegel’s central metaphysical assumption. See also Stekeler-Weithofer 2014: 356. For an overview see Moyar 2011:
28-29.
Stefan Bird-Pollan
92
self-conception arises immanently, that is, in such a way which cannot be normatively explained.
It is the task of Hegel’s Phenomenology in general to reconstruct the various
relation between negativity and consciousness which lead us to talk about materially external relation as well as socially external relations. But the Phenomenology
does not presuppose these relations, it developed them out of the notion of determinate negation as the mere disturbance or impingement of nature on consciousness.
4. Bildung
From this perspective, then, the process of seeking and constructively failing to
grasp the natural can be understood as what Hegel calls Bildung, and what we
earlier saw McDowell describe as second nature. “The series of the figurations of
consciousness which consciousness traverses on this path is the full history of the
cultivation [Bildung] of consciousness itself into science” (PS §78, 52; GW 9: 56).
Hegel’s point is that the succession of attempts is itself the development and extension of the conceptual schema of Geist in general. This is a way of understanding nature as negativity as not merely prompting but also anchoring or grounding
the development of our shared way of understanding the world.
Indeed, the notion of Bildung makes important contact with many of the issues raised in the discussion of Hegel’s naturalism. There, as we saw, one of the
chief questions was to what extent Geist should be understood as an actualization
of some natural properties, as in the soft naturalism reading, or as the achievement of a certain sort of self-consciousness which is particular to spirit but not to
animals, for instance, as the autonomy view held. McDowell himself seems to
remain neutral here, modeling Bildung on initiation into a langue in which “a human being is introduced into something that already embodies putatively rational
linkages between concepts, putatively constitutive of the layout of the space of
reasons, before she comes on the scene” (McDowell 1996: 125). The point of
Bildung in the sense that I am interpreting it is that it is to be understood as the
status of a certain orientation which the subject achieves for itself. On this view,
the idea of an “initiation” has the status both of something that the subject does
and that she undergoes. A subject may, after some time of learning French, find
herself speaking and understanding French. What matters here is that this experience will be something that is intelligible essentially from within the first-personal experience of the subject.
The idea of speaking a language as an achievement allows us to see that while
speaking a language cannot be conceived of as something that one either does or
does not do, according to some external standard, there is nevertheless a strong
sense in which speaking a language is dependent on being able to perform certain
recognizable functions within that language. These tasks are a matter of an intersubjective agreement of what competence in a language consists in. The notion
of Bildung here allows us to see that the first person perspective replaces the internal-external distinction to be found in the soft-naturalism perspective with a firstperson singular-first-person plural distinction.
The development of consciousness can thus be seen as a sort of self-legislation, just as Pippin suggests, in the following sense: consciousness resolves the
problem (negativity) it faces by proposing a conceptual solution. This conceptual
solution, however, is meant to be universally valid, that is, valid not just for itself
Hegel’s Naturalism, the Negative and the First Person Standpoint
93
but for any consciousness. Hence it is meant to be valid in the first-person plural.
But as valid only from a universal perspective, it still may fail to do justice to the
particular of consciousness’ own undergoing and so be called into question again
by the very consciousness which posited the solution. So the dialectic of making
sense of the negative swings back and forth between the first person singular and
plural. The way in which this model diverges from Pippin’s autonomy model, and
the way in which it does not leave nature behind, is that the model I am attributing
to Hegel following McDowell does include an indigestible remnant of negativity
which is not subsumable fully into normativity. Self-legislation is always, on this
model, done in terms of a need which cannot be given a conceptual articulation.
The notion of this negativity most forcefully expressed in T. W. Adorno’s notion
of the non-identical.26
Conclusion
In this paper I’ve tried to move the discussion of Hegel’s naturalism past what I
presented as an impasse between the soft naturalist interpretation of Hegel’s notion of Geist developing out of material nature and the opposing claim that Geist
is essentially normative and self-legislating. In order to do so I suggest we look to
the question of value which underlies this dispute. While soft naturalists seek to
make sense of value as arising from material nature, those who support the autonomy thesis propose that value is something inherent to human spiritual activity. Following McDowell’s suggestion that value as neither inhering or supervening on nature, but is rather something to be recovered, I suggested that we adopt
the first person perspective as the starting point for an examination of the relation
between nature and value. The first person perspective is to be understood as a
position within value which imbues value to what it encounters. Seeing things
from this perspective allows us to place the question of nature as external materiality (which both the soft naturalist and autonomy view seem to share) in its
proper context as something which develops as the result of the self-unfolding
activity of consciousness as it encounters nature as negativity. Understanding
Geist in this way allows us to see value as inherent in nature.
References
Adorno, T.W. 1992, Negative Dialectics, New York: Continuum.
Adorno, T.W. 1970, Negative Dialektik Gesammelte Schriften, Adorno, G. und Tiedemann, R. (hrsg.), Vol. GS 6, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Aristotle 2016, De Anima, trans. C.J. Shields, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Beiser, F.C. 2005, Hegel, London: Routledge.
Bertram, G.W. 2017, Hegels ‘Phänomenologie des Geistes’; ein systematischer Kommentar,
Stuttgart: Reclam.
26
“To define identity as the correspondence of the thing-in-itself to its concept is hubris;
but the ideal of identity must not simply be discarded. Living in the rebuke that the thing
is not identical with the concept is the concept’s longing to become identical with the thing”
(Adorno 1992: 149; 1970: 152).
94
Stefan Bird-Pollan
Bird-Pollan, S. 2017, “McDowell’s Two Readings of Kant”, in Hakl, H. (ed.), Die
klassische deutsche Philosophie und ihre Folgen, Berlin: Springer.
Boyle, M. 2016, “Additive Theories of Rationality: A Critique”, European Journal of
Philosophy, 24, 3, 527-55.
Brandom, R. 2019, A Spirit of Trust: A Reading of Hegel’s ‘Phenomenology’, Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Conant, J. 2016, “Why Kant is not a Kantian”, Philosophical Topics, 44, 1: 75-125.
Fulda, H.F. 2008, “‘Science of the Phenomenology of Spirit’: Hegel’s Program and
its Implementation”, in Moyar, D. and Quante, M. (eds.), Hegel's Phenomenology
of Spirit: A Critical Guide, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gardner, S. 2007, “The Limits of Naturalism and the Metaphysics of German Idealism”, in Hammer, E. (ed.), German Idealism: Contemporary Perspectives, London:
Routledge.
Grier, P.T. 2013, “The Relation of Mind to Nature: Two Paradigms”, in Stern, D.S.
(ed.), Essays on Hegel's Philosophy of Subjective Spirit, Albany: State University of
New York Press.
Hegel, G.W.F. 1968a, Enzyklopädie der Philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse
(1830), Gesammelte Werke, Vol. 20, Frankfurt: Meiner.
Hegel, G.W.F. 1968b, Phänomenologie des Geistes, Gesammelte Werke, Vol. 9, Frankfurt:
Meiner (PG).
Hegel, G.W.F. 1978, Hegel’s Philosophy of Subjective Spirit, trans. M.J. Petry, 3 vols.,
Dordrecht: Reidel.
Hegel, G.W.F. 2004, Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature: Being Part Two of the Encyclopedia of
the Philosophical Sciences (1830), trans. A.V. Miller, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Hegel, G.W.F. 2018, The Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. T. Pinkard, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (PS).
Heidegger, M. 1962, Being and Time, trans. J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson, New
York: Harper.
Houlgate, S. 2005, An Introduction to Hegel: Freedom, Truth, and History, 2nd edit, Oxford: Blackwell.
Illetterati, L. 2016, “Nature, Subjectivity and Freedom: Moving from Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature”, in Testa, I. and Ruggiu, L. (eds.) “I that is we, we that is I”. Perspectives on Contemporary Hegel, Leiden: Brill, 181-201.
Kant, I. 1996, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. W.S. Pluhar, Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.
Klein, J. 1936, Die griechische Logistik und die Entstehung der Algebra, Berlin: Springer.
Kuhn, T.S. 1977, “Mathematical Versus Experimental Traditions”, in The Essential
Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change, Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
McCumber, J. 2013, Understanding Hegel's Mature Critique of Kant. Stanford: Stanford
University Press.
McDowell, J. 1996, Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Moyar, D. 2011, Hegel’s Conscience, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Papazoglou, A. 2012, “Hegel and Naturalism”, Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain, 33, 2, 74-90.
Hegel’s Naturalism, the Negative and the First Person Standpoint
95
Peters, J. 2016, “On Naturalism in Hegel's Philosophy of Spirit”, British Journal for the
History of Philosophy, 24, 1: 111-31.
Pinkard, T. 1994, Hegel’s Phenomenology: The Sociality of Reason, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Pinkard, T. 2012, Hegel’s Naturalism: Mind, Nature, and the Final Ends of Life, Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Pippin, R. 2005, “Leaving Nature Behind, or Two Cheers for ‘Subjectivism’: On John
McDowell”, in The Persistence of Subjectivity: on the Kantian Aftermath, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 186-205.
Pippin, R. 2008, Hegel’s Practical Philosophy: Rational Agency as Ethical Life, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Pippin, R. 2016, “McDowell’s Germans”, in Interanimations: Receiving Modern German
Philosophy, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Rand, S. 2007, “The Importance and Relevance of Hegel’s ‘Philosophy of Nature’”,
Review of Metaphysics, 61, 2, 379-400.
Shapin, S. 1996, The Scientific Revolution, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Speight, A. 2010, “Skepticism, Modernity, and the Origin of Hegelian Dialectic”, in
Limnatis, N. (ed.), The Dimensions of Hegel’s Dialectic, London: Continuum, 140-56.
Stekeler-Weithofer, P. 2014, Hegels Phänomenologie des Geistes. Ein dialogischr Kommentar: Gewissheit und Vernunft, Vol. 1, Hamburg: Meiner.
Stone, A. 2005, Petrified Intelligence: Nature in Hegel’s Philosophy, Albany: State University of New York Press.
Stone, A. 2013, “Hegel, Naturalism and the Philosophy of Nature”, Hegel Bulletin, 34,
1, 59-78.
Testa, I. 2007, “Criticism from within Nature: The Dialectic Between First and Second Nature from McDowell to Adorno”, Philosophy and Social Criticism, 33, 3, 47397.
Testa, I. forthcoming, “Embodied Cognition, Habit, and Natural Agency in Hegel’s
Anthropology”, in Bykova, M.F. and Westphal, K.R. (eds.), The Palgrave Hegel
Handbook, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Williams, B. 2005, Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry, New York: Routledge.
Winfield, R.D. 2007, “Identity, Difference, and the Unity of Mind: Reflections on
Hegel’s Determination of Psyche, Consciousness, and Intelligence”, in Grier, P.T.
(ed.), Identity and Difference: Studies in Hegel’s Logic, Philosophy of Spirit, and Politics,
Albany: State University of New York Press, 103-27.
Hegel’s Dialectical Art
Antón Barba-Kay
The Catholic University of America
Abstract
Most contemporary accounts of naturalism specify, as one of its necessary conditions, a community within which agents can take themselves to be adequately answerable for and responsible to the norms of autonomous practical reason. But
what would it mean to succeed in giving an account of naturalism, absent such
social conditions? What does it mean to think about naturalism from a position of
relative alienation? My contention is that this incongruity between philosophy
and the form of life sustaining it is already present within Hegel’s thought, and
that it should prompt us to reconsider the meaning that philosophy itself has for
him. Philosophical science—along with a proper understanding of naturalism—
is, on the one hand, a historical achievement for him, one that only becomes possible within modern practices and institutions. But he also views modernity’s
forms of subjectivity as fragmented, incomplete, and alienated, on the other. In
order to understand how he reconciles the theoretical possibilities with the practical limitations of modernity, I argue that we need to attend to two features of Hegel’s philosophical account. First, that the Phenomenology of Spirit (and Hegel’s
systematic thought generally) has been patterned after a specifically aesthetic
mode of intelligibility. Second, that Hegel’s philosophy is intended to effect a
transformation on its readers, analogous to the transformation that works of art
are supposed to effect on their audiences (as understood by Schiller, Schelling,
and other post-Kantian thinkers).
Keywords: Naturalism, Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, Aesthetics, Recognition,
Sensus Communis.
Is the situation so uncommon, then, in which
philosophy forbids one to philosophize?
(Lichtenberg)
1. Introduction: Naturalism in Progress
John McDowell (1996: 93-94) observes that “modern philosophy has taken itself
to be called on to bridge dualistic gulfs, between subject and object, thought and
world […] what is debatable is how we ought to respond to the deeper dualism”.
At stake in the question of naturalism, in other words—of the possibility of
communication between nature and freedom as aspects of self-conscious life—is
Argumenta 4, 2 (2019): 97-116
ISSN 2465-2334
© 2019 University of Sassari
DOI 10.14275/2465-2334/20198.bar
98
Antón Barba-Kay
not only the question itself, but the tacit demands that we place on the very asking of it. What task do we take ourselves to be called on to perform, when we
ask for a philosophical account of this relation? In one sense, the answer is obvious (and the question churlish): to clarify the truth of the matter. One of the
most striking features of this particular question, however, is its continuing urgency in the face of a longstanding and lopsided consensus about it. The bête noir
of an outsize region of post-Kantian and then post-Wittgensteinian philosophy
has remained unchanging: dualism (whether putatively Cartesian or Kantian),
some version of the Myth of the Given, eliminativism, or heteronomy—the
threat that something about how the world empirically is should impinge on our
own knowing of it and acting within it as we freely ought. The holy grail of such
accounts has remained, by contrast, an account of the embodied reality of normative life—one that explains how it is that the difference between freedom and
nature is irreducible, while also accounting for our double status as naturally
bodied creatures and as freely minded agents in such a way that the two statuses
enable, rather than constrain, our capacity to lead our own lives. One might say
that post-Kantian philosophy just is a variety of local elaborations of what is basically global consensus on these issues.
To what purpose does the question continue to be asked, then? What remains to be seen? I do not say that agreement at such a terribly high altitude is
the most interesting feature of such accounts—running, as they do, the gamut
from Königsberg to Pittsburgh—nor that empiricism has no defenders left standing (far from), nor that agreement about large areas of inquiry is a reason to discontinue them. It is only on the basis of provisional agreement about desiderata
that there can be meaningful discussion at all. But it has also been a steady feature of the most influential such accounts to point out that the resolution of the
question of our embodied freedom is not merely theoretical—a puzzle that
could be figured out once and for all on paper—but one that involves us necessarily in a social undertaking. I cannot know my nature free from a position of
first-personal privilege, anterior to and separate from my circumstances, but only as a participant in a form of life that sustains the knowing of it. I must be able
to be committed to and held responsible for that knowledge. My knowledge of
myself as a freely embodied agent is, in this sense, a practical achievement within and through my expressive “mindedness” with others.1
Just how to describe the bearing of such mindedness on the very possibility
of normative agency is the subject of a well-known controversy between
McDowell and Robert Pippin. But even for McDowell—arguing against Pippin’s thicker view of agency as a status constituted by communal acknowledgment2—“the idea of conceptual capacities makes sense only in the context of a
communal practice” (McDowell 2009a: 178). McDowell’s defense of secondnature debouches in appeals to Bildung and tradition as formal conditions for being responsible to reason: “When a decent upbringing initiates us into the relevant way of thinking, our eyes are opened to the very existence of this tract of
1
I am borrowing Lear’s (1998: 290-97) well-known phrase. Cf. Brandom’s (2009: 4) remark that “Because the space of reasons is a normative space, it is a social space”.
2
Cf. “Hegel considers the distinct normative status of human subjects (as persons,
agents) not as a reflection of some substantive or metaphysical nature, but as a social
achievement of a kind and so as bound up with an inevitable and distinct form of social
conflict” (Pippin 2011a: 75).
Hegel’s Dialectical Art
99
the space of reasons” (McDowell 1996: 82). As in Aristotle, questions of conceptual capacity entail questions of practical reason, and questions of practical
reason (Pippin would insist) turn out to entail questions of world-history.
McDowell’s strategy in the face of this conclusion is to insist on the fact
that our demand that philosophy “solve” the question of naturalism is misplaced—the problem lies in our interpretation of the question as a problem in
search of a doctrinal or constructive solution.3 But a different corollary one
might draw from this insight—one that, I think, we do not usually take seriously
enough—is that in some sense we cannot settle the question absent the right
form of communal recognition. So long as our forms of practical reason are vitiated by the assumption that there is a fundamental caesura between freedom
and nature, then the question of their relation must continue to come to mind,
and the answer must remain a matter for wishful thinking. It may well be, in
other words, that the bête noir cannot be killed off for good not because we don’t
have the right philosophical silver bullet, but because its power radiates from assumptions embedded in our most ordinary customs, activities, and attitudes
(say: in the institutional status we accord to all manner of quantitative reasoning, in the thin forms of communal recognition available to mass societies, in
our technological, political, and economic forms of alienation, and so on). The
most significant obstacle to settling a second-natural, or neo-Aristotelian, or
emergentist, or transformative, or top-down/bottom-up understanding of our
conceptual capacities is, in this sense, not exclusively and perhaps not even primarily a theoretical one, since it may be that our very forms of practice cannot
sustain such an account (or at any rate permanently destabilize it).4
My question here is therefore not about naturalism’s best version but about
the meta-philosophical role that we ask it to perform—what we expect such a
mediation to “do” for us. So far from being part of a Critical Theoretical despair
about the incapacity of the world to meet our demands for it, the issue already
has this cast within Hegel’s thought. On the one hand, he evidently thinks that
we cannot fully address the question of naturalism without rightly situating ourselves within a teleological account of historical norms: that, in sum, our freedom is only realized within a specific form of (modern) communal answerability
for it, and, in this sense, that the reconciliation of freedom and nature cannot be
a matter for philosophy alone. On the other hand, he also thinks that philosophy
is where this reconciliation happens—that naturalism in some sense takes place
in and through our knowing of it. His position is neither quietist nor revolutionary. To explain the middle position he occupies in this regard, I present two related theses here: that Hegel’s account of the embodied mediation of norms
stems directly from the fruition of his conception of aesthetics as a paradigm for
3
This is how he glosses Wittgenstein’s quietism; see McDowell 1996: 93, and McDowell
2009b.
4
In addition to McDowell’s defense of “second nature” (the best-known version of which
is found in Mind and World), I am referring to Thompson’s (2008) neo-Aristotelian account connecting practical dispositions to social practices, Eldridge’s (2014) account of
Hegel’s naturalism as “emergentist”, Boyle’s (2016) “transformative” view of reason, and
Ikäheimo’s (2014: 36) view of top-down/bottom-up naturalism in the Encyclopedia. My
thesis here echoes well-known arguments that have stressed the dependence of moral philosophy on its underlying forms of life (cf. Anscombe 1958, Williams 1996 and MacIntyre 2007). The relation between the specific question philosophical naturalism and our
forms of life has not received the same scrutiny.
Antón Barba-Kay
100
intelligibility, and that Hegel sees this analogy to aesthetics as responding to the
problem I’ve noted, namely, the mismatch between a philosophical account and
the form of communal life that could sustain it. In other words, that Hegel’s solution to the problem of the incomplete forms of modern recognition is to show
that philosophy can transform the difference between what we are and what we
know. Hegel’s naturalism undertakes to reveal the truth of the ordinary by transfiguring it as a work of art was supposed to do.
2. Aesthetics and Idealism
Let me begin, then, by saying something about the sense in which I take Hegel’s
view of conceptual mediation to be an aesthetic one. To briefly retread some
well-worn ground: the half-century of philosophical activity we designate ‘German Idealism’ might be described as an attempt to square the Kantian circle. It
is as if Kant’s distinctions of intuition and concept, sensibility and understanding, practical and theoretical reason—along with his tantalizing description of
his critical labor as a “propaedeutic” (A11/B25)—were taken as a momentous
provocation, to which Reinhold, Fichte, Hölderlin, Novalis, Schelling, Schiller,
and Hegel replied by developing accounts of what the whole beyond such oppositions might be. It is immensely telling how quickly each of these figures lay
aside the fact that dualism was a deliberate, rather than unintended, feature of
Kant’s position. It was fundamental to his compatibilism, after all, to secure
moral freedom’s autonomy against empirical necessity. But this defensive sequestration of worlds seemed to elicit a further reconciliation, and Kant himself
turned his attention in his third Critique to phenomena that, even if empirically
available, are also evocative of or resonant with our moral vocation.
It makes sense, in connection with this reconciliation, that aesthetics in particular should have come to be of keen interest. Under the influence of Hume
and Hutcheson—in whom the notion of philosophical judgment was initially
fused with the notion of taste—and Baumgarten—who coined the term ‘aesthetics’—Kant’s Critique of Judgment marks out aesthetics as a distinct form of intelligibility. Works of art have no translation into words; they express a significance that is neither fully assessable by nor reducible to some discursive content
separable from their material expression. Their sensible form animates their
conceptual content in such a way as to be able to present us with concrete manifestations of purpose, though it is a “purposiveness without a purpose” (KU
§15)—an intimation of freedom for our senses. They are one-of-a-kind for this
reason—an achievement that rhymes with our own sense of being ends-inourselves within the empirical world. And so even as Kant has a stake in stopping short of saying that sensible purposiveness can in any way ratify his moral
theory, he is nonetheless interested in aesthetics as a sort of sensible “expression
of moral ideas” (KU §17)5 one that is (in a qualified way) congruent with our
moral aims.
While for Kant this congruence is still bracketed as problematic and subordinate to the status of natural teleology, to his immediate successors aesthetics
looked like far the most promising paradigm for thinking about agency and the
relation between thinking and being generally—the best way for integrating
Kant’s dualisms into a form of living freedom. This is manifestly the case in
5
This phrase is, admittedly, restricted to representations of the human body.
Hegel’s Dialectical Art
101
Schiller’s and Schelling’s writings from the decade following the publication of
the third Critique. Schiller’s Letters on the Aesthetic Education of Man, along with
his Kallias Letters and other writings from the period, explore ways in which
beauty can help us harmonize our moral vocation with our natural inclinations,
and in so doing surmount the threat of mechanical, empirical, positivistic reductions of human freedom; while Schelling’s 1800 System places aesthetic experience and its articulation at the summit of the possibilities of freedom’s purposive
manifestations. “The objective world is simply the original, as yet unconscious,
poetry of the spirit; the universal organon of philosophy—and the keystone of its
entire arch—is the philosophy of art” (SW III.349/STI 12).6 Art exhibits the
ground of the inner harmony between subjective and objective, by bringing the
former into concrete manifestation. The book ends with Schelling prophesying
the absorption of philosophy and science into a new type of mythology, within
which form and content will be entirely adequate to each other (SW III.62434/STI 229-36). This reiterates the quasi-millenarian claims made by the socalled Oldest Surviving Program of German Idealism—variously attributed to Hegel,
Hölderlin, and Schelling—which concludes by pronouncing that “truth and
goodness are only siblings in beauty” and that a new rational mythology is needed to make philosophy widely compelling (CRGA 186-87).
In Hegel’s case, this line of aesthetic thinking is more tangled. In some of
his early theological writings, beauty still figures as the signature of embodied
autonomy, as it does in Schiller and Schelling. In the 1798 Spirit of Christianity
essay, for instance, Hegel writes that “the need to unite subject with object, to
unite feeling, and feeling’s demand for objects, with the intellect, to unite them
in something beautiful, in a god, by means of imagination, is the supreme need
of the human spirit and the urge to religion” (ETW 289). Jesus is himself presented there as a beautiful soul (ETW 285), whose central message is formulated
as the overcoming of differences through love: “in love man has found himself
again in other” (ETW 278). Hegel dropped love as the focal point of his thinking
in the early 1800’s,7 but in the first years of the nineteenth century, he nonetheless continued to identify his own conception of philosophical intelligibility with
that of the expressive intelligibility of the Critique of Judgment in particular. In his
1801 Differenzschrift and 1802 Faith and Knowledge, Hegel still follows Schelling in
presenting art as the sensuous equivalent to philosophy—art exemplifies the task
of transforming the divisions of the understanding into concrete unity, so that
“both art and speculation are in their essence divine service—both are a living
intuition of the absolute life and hence a being at one with it” (GW 4.76/DFS
172; cf. LFA 101).
In Hegel’s 1807 Phenomenology, however, the beautiful as such no longer
bears the conceptual weight that it had in his earlier writings; art is now specified as a form of religion, and so as one rung within a much more ambitious
ladder of concepts.8 I want nonetheless to claim that this undertaking is continuous with the aestheticism that dominated the first wave of post-Kantians. By
6
See Dahlstrom 1991: 249-54.
I’ve elaborated this in Barba-Kay 2016.
8
Art, religion, and philosophy—the triad comprising Absolute Spirit—are run together in
the 1805-6 Philosophy of Spirit and in chapters 7-8 of the 1807 Phenomenology. Hegel did
not fully develop the differences between the three tiers until sometime after the 1817 Encyclopedia.
7
Antón Barba-Kay
102
this I don’t mean that Hegel is the author of lovely prose (a thesis scarcely credible), or that the Phenomenology should not be regarded as a work of echt philosophy. What I mean is that this work (like all of Hegel’s subsequent, systematic
writing) relies on a paradigm of apodictic necessity that is borrowed from aesthetics; that is, that Hegel’s conception of his dialectical method rests in crucial
respects on its analogy to organic and therefore artistic form, and that, furthermore, its aesthetic features can help us to identify the kinds of expectations underlying the role that the argument itself is expected to perform for us. The book
as a whole functions as a work of art is meant to for other post-Kantian thinkers:
Hegelian philosophy is to take the place of art as the vehicle of the recognition
by which we are reconciled to our time in reason and to reason in our time.9
3. Phenomenology as a Work of Art
The Phenomenology is a “science of the experience of consciousness”, as the alternative title has it. This science is sui generis not only in that it consists in its
own justification, but in that it is a narrative of telling failures. Each “shape” of
consciousness is sequentially tasked with adapting to the inadequacies of its
predecessor, while motivating through its own specific defeat the formulation of
the issue that it hands off to its successor. The plot begins with straightforward
ostensive judgments—“now is night”, “I am this”—which, unable to explain
how they ostend, are shown to entail richer and richer forms of knowing that
point to the “absolute” form of knowing with which Hegel concludes. As Hegel
insists elsewhere, it is not that every reader must literally reenact each stage in
order to achieve the ending; it is that each position is determinately contained
within the subsequent one (as we might say that the concept of crime is logically
contained within the concept of willing, in that our willing rightly must always
take place against the backdrop possibility of trespass—even if someone in particular happened never to have committed a crime).10 The ensemble of such
necessary mistakes that make up the book must in this way elucidate, underlie,
and constitute the structure of our freedom realized. The procedure as a whole
therefore relies on at least three programmatic commitments, all three of which
in combination suggest that the argument has an aesthetic character, that in
some sense it functions as a work of art: expressivism, teleology, and culmination. I’ll touch on each of these in order.
First, Hegel’s conception of each stage of the narrative is expressive. I mean
this in the sense clarified by Charles Taylor (2010) that the meaning of each of
the figures Hegel examines is neither merely propositional, nor inferential, nor
9
Cf. GW 9.38/PS §52. Some form of this thesis—that there is an important affinity between Hegel’s conception of aesthetics and his conception of philosophy—would perhaps
be hard to miss. For versions of it, see Desmond 1991, Pippin 2011b, Förster 2012 and Taylor 1977. What I am arguing is that we should take seriously the “meta-philosophical” consequences of what this means about how Hegel envisioned the bearing of his system on its
readers.
10
“This conception of derangement as a necessarily emerging form or stage in the development of the soul is naturally not to be understood as if we were asserting that every
mind, every soul, must go through this stage of extreme disruption. Such an assertion
would be as absurd as to assume that because crime is considered in the Philosophy of Right
as a necessary appearance of the human will, therefore the commission of crime is supposed to be made inevitable for every individual” (E3 §408z). See also (E1 §86z).
Hegel’s Dialectical Art
103
available to it through an ex ante introspective view that could be finally adequate to its whole content; rather, while each begins by identifying itself with
some philosophical commitment, it is only through working through that commitment that it is confronted by its implications and inadequacies. Concepts
have lives of their own, in this sense. Without the condition of actualization,
Hegel’s “figures” would not be properly narrative—they would be picturesque
examples, but not really exemplary of the developmental activity that Hegel
wants to describe in opposition to the apriorism he associates with Kant’s first
two Critiques, or to the self-indulgent, vatic ineffability he associates with Schelling’s appeals to Romantic intuition. Our forms of self-understanding, that is,
acquire essential content through their enactment and realization; or, as Hegel
puts it, “we learn by experience [die Meinung erfährt] that we meant something
other than we meant to mean” (GW 9.44/PS §63). It is the possibility of noticing and responding to this mismatch that in turn makes transformations in our
self-conception possible—what Hegel calls the “criterion” (Maßstab) of
knowledge (GW 9.59/PS §§83-84).11
A general commitment to expressivism may evidently have some connection to aesthetics without being closely identified with it—it is not so in Aristotle’s case, for instance,12 even if for most modern expressivists the affinity has
been irresistible (as it was for Herder, Nietzsche, or Dewey). When it comes to
the Phenomenology, however, it is not simply that Hegel has borrowed conceptual resources that he happened to find in the Critique of Judgment to his analysis of
agency. It is that each shape of consciousness is at once particular while bearing
essential universal purport for the larger narrative. In other words, it is not just
that some content is expressed by the actuality of each shape, but that the content
is exemplary of a larger whole that is entirely and inescapably at stake within it.13
It is precisely this investing of concrete instance with universal significance that
allows each of Hegel’s stages to be consequential to the narrative, since each is
essential to Spirit’s coming to know itself in us—every shape of consciousness
bears, for the space of its turn, the full weight of the whole: “every moment, as it
gains concrete form and a shape of its own, displays itself in the universal individual” (GW 9.24/PS §28). Hegel explicitly reaches for an aesthetic description
of these stages, referring to them as Gestalten and tableaux: “a slow-moving succession of Spirits, a gallery of images [eine Gallerie von Bildern]” that penetrates
the whole wealth of all Spiritual substance (GW 9.433/PS §808).14 It is this saturated expressivism—the fact that what is of universal moment is utterly ex-
11
Cf. Pippin’s comment that “in Hegel’s view in the relevant sections of the Phenomenology of Spirit, actually to have an intention is to struggle to express that intention in a public
and publicly contestable deed, subject to great temporal fluidity and to appropriations
and interpretations by others that can greatly alter one’s own sense of what one is about”
(Pippin 2011b: 117).
12
Aristotle compares acts of moral virtue to works of art (“so that we often say of good
works of art that it is not possible either to take away or to add anything”), but immediately qualifies this by adding that moral virtue is “more exact and better than any art”
(Aristotle 2009: 1106b7-15).
13
One might say that they are exemplary of “sensible rational ideas”, as Kant puts it in
KU: §49.
14
Cf. GW 9.56/PS §78.
104
Antón Barba-Kay
pressed into each of its instances, the presence of the whole in the part—that is
more specifically aesthetic.15
Second, Hegel’s view of the demonstrative necessity that connects each of
the stages is aesthetic in that it is appropriated from natural teleology. This logical organicism is perhaps most lavishly in view in the Preface to the Phenomenology, where he compares the unfolding truth of his narrative to the way a bud issues into a blossom that issues into a fruit, refers several times to the “inner-life
and self-movement” of the process, and speaks of his account as a speculative
“rhythm” that makes sense of the relation between subjects and predicates (GW
9.10, 37, 43-44/PS §§2, 51, 61, respectively). Such vitalistic characterizations of
reason are not novel—they are everywhere in Schelling, and have older roots in
Herder, Hooker, and Pascal—but their specific application encapsulates one of
Hegel’s defining insights: that the history of freedom can be read as a series of
developing moments belonging the same activity, rather than as an alternation
of competing views to be endorsed or discarded seriatim. In contrast to the various kinds of epistemological formalism he criticizes in the Preface, that is, his
project is to gather the collective logic of all shapes of sense-making into the unified, purposive form of activity he calls Spirit. Eckart Förster has shown that
Hegel came to this notion by studying Goethe’s Metamorphosis of Plants. Goethe
shows there that the plant is a self-differentiating whole whose parts are coordinated functions of a single process: Hegel came to see this as the right analogy
for the working out of human freedom through time.16
In that it appeals to some kind of analogy between artifice and organism,
Hegel’s Phenomenology would already be, again, “artistic” in a weak sense. But
here too I mean something more specific. Beyond allowing him to make the Aristotelian point that intelligibility is activity and that its different instances may
be organized into parts of a larger whole, the analogy to organism affords Hegel
a sense of implacable deductive necessity. If Aristotle ranks plants, animals, and
human beings as lower and higher, for instance, he never claims to be able to
deduce them from each other, nor is it clear that he thought of himself as having
a system in the modern sense. But Hegel’s anti-foundationalist holism (in the
Phenomenology and Encyclopedia) cannot but make up a complete, deductive, ordered system. He evidently does not view Spirit’s purposive activity as mechanically necessary or theologically pre-ordained, yet he does think that the stages he
15
The visibility of the whole within the part—the notions of analogy and archetype, in
sum—is one of the most familiar motifs in Romantic thinking about art and nature, in
Germany and elsewhere (as in Blake’s “To see the world in a grain of sand, and a heaven
in a wildflower”). For its classic expression, cf. Goethe’s Metamorphosis of Plants (esp. 7678 in Goethe 1989), and this passage from his 1798 poem (also called “The Metamorphosis of Plants”): “All the shapes are akin and none is quite like the other;/ So to a secret law surely that chorus must point,/ To a sacred enigma” (Goethe 2016: 27). There is
an echo of this thinking in Hegel’s epistolary comment that “I saw the Emperor—this
world-soul—riding out of the city on reconnaissance. It is indeed a wonderful sensation
to see such an individual, who, concentrated here at a single point, astride a horse,
reaches out over the world and masters it” (quoted in Pinkard 2000: 228). The Phenomenology, I am arguing, offers us a relay of just such “concentrated” figures.
16
See Förster 2012: 297-301; cf. Goethe’s comment that “In the end, the phenomena
must form a series, or rather, overlap; thus they give the scientist a picture of some organization by which the inner life of the phenomena become manifest as a whole” (Goethe
2010: 984).
Hegel’s Dialectical Art
105
describes are the essential aspects of Spirit’s activity, that they are rightly arranged within the teleologically arranged sequence within which he identifies
them, and that their expression within this order is constitutive of what they
are.17 If this is not the necessity of a mathematical proof, it is necessity in the
sense that any self-impelling organic process exhibits. And it is because narrative
necessity obtains in this sense that Hegel occasionally invokes the notion that
“we”, readers and Hegelians, can be its spectators: “since what consciousness
examines is its own self, all that is left for us to do is simply to look on [nur das
reine Zusehen bleibt]” (GW 9.59/PS §85). History supplants nature as the decisive
framework of human experience that it had been from Thales to Kant: Hegel
puts a period to that trajectory by transforming history itself into a quasi-natural
unfolding that presses on to its own actualization.
Even so, neither expressivism nor teleology would of itself justify the claim
that the Phenomenology is an aesthetic work. The third consideration that still
needs adding is that of Hegel’s conception of the goal: a form of knowledge that
incorporates and harmonizes all the previous chapters of the narrative, thereby
overcoming, absolving, and consummating all failures at interpreting the relation between self and other, thinking and being. Whatever “absolute knowing”
means exactly, it is not omniscience: it is not knowledge of every particular. It
is, furthermore, a kind of knowing that can fully take place only within philosophy itself—Hegel consistently argues that it can only be partially intimated within politics, art, or religion.18 But such knowing is nonetheless “absolute” in that
it can identify all the conceptual links of the world in their necessary order of
concatenation, and that this comprehension is such that it in some sense thereby
changes the meaning of the whole it comprehends: once Spirit understands what
it is about and what it has been at all along, it fulfills its purpose of coming to
know itself in all otherness, of redeeming the reason of the world as what is unconditionally true. Spirit’s self-knowledge replaces the role that love had played
in Hegel’s earlier writings.
This can be made to sound somewhat less outlandish when we hear it as an
echo of another Aristotelian position, that to know the world completes it, that
the cosmos’s purpose is to come to know itself, and that in this sense all being
strives, after its own manner and sub specie aeternitatis, to participate in the life of
the mind. Hegel concludes the Encyclopedia with a quotation from Aristotle’s
Metaphysics to this effect (E3 §577). But the differences here again suggest that
Hegel’s notion of what philosophy can achieve is fundamentally an aesthetic
one. First, because Hegel is committed to the fundamental univocity and commensurability of the logical “content” that emerges from each dialectical transition. Even where Aristotle ranks different species, he does not insist on the point
that lower kinds are fundamentally commensurable with higher, that they are
reducible to some common content. The theoretical life may be higher than the
practical one for him, but the practical domain’s integrity is not simply an ersatz
version of theoretical content. No such aporia presents itself to Hegel, for whom
each dialectical sublation carries over the same content as its lower version, but
17
See esp. GW 9.366-67, 428-29/PS §§681, 801. Cf. “Hegel has taken a decisive step beyond Goethe: not only is it impossible to grasp the idea that philosophy strives to comprehend (the absolute) prior to the conclusion of the complete series of its realization; in
fact it is not what it is until the end of that series” (Förster 2012: 300).
18
Cf., e.g., LFA 99-100.
Antón Barba-Kay
106
in a higher key. Thus, for instance: philosophy realizes the same purport that is
only sensuously intimated in art and religion.19 But, finally, the achievement of
absolute knowing is identified with the culmination of historical time for Hegel,
as of course it is not for Aristotle. This confounds the distinction between art
and history, as it had been previously understood. Aristotle’s observation that
poetry is higher than history because the former is better at identifying universals whereas the latter is mired in contingency no longer holds for Hegel’s narrative system, which is an apotheosis of both into a new kind of science of history.
The final position, the way we are now, is not simply where things stand so far,
but the justification of time and its fulfillment, inasmuch as this means a resolution and incorporation of every previous stage. There is a total identification of
form to content in the finale that is not only expressive, and not only organically
deduced, but wholly necessary and necessarily whole—a work that in some
sense puts an end to all such work: a showstopper.
Recent scholarship on Hegel has tended to underplay this aspect of his position, rather stressing its provisional, proleptic, and corrigible character.20 To
have suggested that anything, let alone history or philosophy, ended in 1807
seems (rightly) premature to us, and I agree that we should distinguish the abiding value of Hegel’s position from some of his more stupendous claims.21 But we
would also miss a crucial aspect of Hegel’s position, were we to overlook the
fact that its ambition evidently extends beyond the correctness of its propositional content—that it lays extraordinary claim not only to actualize or awaken
consciousness to the latent significance of the whole, but to our recognition of it,
Hegel’s system, as the essential vehicle of that awakening. Just what this means
is not yet clear; certainly it is not our way of regarding the work of ordinary
scholarship. What I mean to say so far is that Hegel’s insistence on the perfection of the result—on the notion that the final position is an expressive, developmental, autonomous whole in which form and content are fully harmonized
with each other, and which in this way supplies us with a means for transformative recognition of ourselves—is rightly called aesthetic, and that this bears on
how we are to recognize the Phenomenology’s bearing on us, its readers.
4. The Burden of Philosophy
I have argued so far that these three general features of Hegel’s Phenomenology—
its saturated expressivism, its teleological necessity, and its culminating harmony—render it if not a work of art, then at any rate into a work of philosophy
formally patterned after what had been for Kant a specifically aesthetic mode of
intelligibility. This is not to say that Hegel ever went so far as to conflate aesthetics with philosophy, as some of his contemporaries did. The Phenomenology itself
states that “beauty hates the understanding” for asking it to perform what it
19
Cf., e.g., GW 9.364-65, 368, 420-21/PS §§678, 683, 787.
See, e.g., Pinkard 2012, Pippin 2014, and Dale 2014 for such accounts in three heterogeneous domains.
21
In other words, even as scholars continue to deny that Hegel has a strong end of history thesis, it is a position that readers cannot but continue to attribute to him, because it
follows from his underlying principle that Spirit cannot stop short of achieving the total
identification of being and thinking, that such an identification is properly located in modernity. For discussion of this question, see Dale 2014, Brooks 2007: 157, and Pinkard
2017: 140-68.
20
Hegel’s Dialectical Art
107
cannot (GW 9.27/PS §32), and throughout the 1820’s he continued to describe
art as a distinct practice, subordinate to philosophy. And Hegel is well known
for the thesis that this practice has now ended for us, that it no longer sustains
our deepest spiritual needs (LFA 10-11, 102-103).
Even in the Lectures on Fine Art, however, Hegel reiterates the claim that
philosophy only grasps its own essence precisely along with the essence of art
and nature—an explicit concession of the weight that the Critique of Judgment
carried for him (LFA 56).22 The discovery of philosophical science is also the
discovery of the science of art, he says, because both have a common way of
unifying conceptual oppositions into teleological activity: both are concerned
with the mediated “life” of concepts.23 It is in this sense that I think that by attending to the kind of work that the Phenomenology is—to its character as an organic deduction of a single, concrete, culminating activity—it is plausible to regard it as a philosophical work of art that answers to the modern demand for
certainty by showing, as he says, “that now is the time for philosophy to be
raised to the status of a science”, replacing the “love of knowing” for “actual
knowing” (GW 9.11/PS §5). The work undertakes not only a true demonstration, but a reorientation of our impulse toward knowledge as such: our erotic
restlessness is put to rest.24
I note in passing that it was these very features of Hegel’s account of mediation that were associated with his philosophical hubris by the Left Hegelians in
the generation after him. The sense that Hegel represented a philosophical dead
end stemmed in part from the fact that his system could not be contested or extended in ordinary ways (since every possible distinction is supposed to be always already sublated within it), and so had to be repudiated wholesale. Its very
perfection threatened to leave “us” out: the system’s totality explained away our
own existing, historical subjectivity. And this charge against Hegel’s system was
early on formulated as a problem of confounding philosophy with art. Thus
Feuerbach writes, in his 1839 Toward a Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy, that “Hegel
is the most accomplished philosophical artist, and his presentations, at least in
part, are unsurpassed models of scientific art sense […] The Hegelian philosophy is
thus the culminating point of all speculative-systematic philosophy” (Feuerbach
2012: 68). Similar accusations may be readily found in the writings of Kierkegaard and Nietzsche.25
But setting his reception aside, it will be more helpful to ask how Hegel
himself conceived of the relationship between his system and the form of life
that grounds it. If it is relatively uncontroversial to point out that Hegel’s
thought is “aesthetic” in the sense that it elaborates a notion of mediation that is
in opposition to the scientific formalism of the Enlightenment, the question of
what this means for the role that Hegel’s thought takes itself to be called on to
perform (to return to McDowell’s phrase) has not been adequately addressed.
22
Cf. LFA: 63.
For the connection between this theme in the Phenomenology and in the 1820’s Lectures
on Fine Art, see Pippin 2011b: 104-108.
24
For a telling contrast to Kant, cf. A 850/878: “we will always return to metaphysics as
to a beloved from whom we have been estranged”.
25
Cf. e.g. Kierkegaard (1992: 347); Nietzsche (1997a: §190) and (1997b: 104): “such a
point of view [i.e. the Hegelian one] has set history […] in place of the other spiritual
powers, art and religion, as the sole sovereign power”.
23
108
Antón Barba-Kay
What is the relation between this aesthetic dimension and its supposed function
vis-à-vis us? Does Hegel understand his project as the explicitation or reiteration
of norms already tacitly obtaining within modernity (as the Owl of Minerva
comment suggests)? Or does he regard his own project as making some transformative difference to their full realization? What, in sum, is philosophical mediation for, in his view, and how is this purpose connected to its aesthetic character? Two further issues become salient in this connection: Hegel’s view of the
historical character of his position and his view of the task of philosophy as
such. Either one of these is matter for a much longer study, but let me outline
some lines of thinking on each in turn.
Hegel’s thought is conspicuous, as I’ve said, for tethering itself to a particular historical situation. Philosophy cannot culminate in science before Spirit has
worked out all the practical and conceptual conditions entailed by it; the “end”
of history and the “end” of philosophy (however stipulated) are indivisible for
this reason. As he put it in 1806: “This is the standpoint of the present time, and
for now it is the last in the series of the forms of spirit [geistigen Gestaltungen].—
With this the history of philosophy is concluded” (Werke 20: 479).26 One may put
more or less pressure on that “for now”. But while Hegel balks at anything like
prediction, he sees modernity as making a decisive, qualitative difference that he
is in a position to articulate, and so his project is predicated on spelling out now
what has already been realized in practice. Had it been articulated by any premodern thinker, in other words, the same position would not have been true
(would not have been an expression of its actuality). The philosophical culmination of the Phenomenology—its sublation of the meaning of time itself27—is accordingly presented as evincing or completing the moment’s historical significance:
Ours is a birth-time and a period of transition to a new era. Spirit has broken
with the world it has hitherto inhabited and imagined, and is of a mind to submerge it in the past […] The gradual crumbling that left unaltered the face of the
whole is cut short by a sunburst which, in one flash, illuminates the features of
the new world (GW 9.14-15/PS §11).
And while in the 1820’s Hegel was no longer so euphoric about the thoroughness of the historical conversion taking place,28 he never detached his own position from the fact that modernity represents a decisive shift in key to a higher
historical register, a key that he takes himself to discover and codify, such that
the most flagrant statements he made about the end of history date from that period.29
It would be much easier to shrug this off as a version of C-major Whiggish
triumphalism, however, if there were not an additional, minor key present in
Hegel’s writings from the 1790’s on: an insistence about the crises facing modern institutions. One may be so easily distracted by the heady tenor of the Phe26
See note in Förster 2012: 301.
See GW 9.428-29/PS §801.
28
On this subject, see esp. Pinkard 2012: 173-96. My essay owes much to Pinkard’s description, though he does not press what I’m calling the aesthetic character of Hegel’s position.
29
E.g. “Europe is essentially [schlechthin] the end of history” (Werke 12: 134).
27
Hegel’s Dialectical Art
109
nomenology, for instance, that one may miss the fact that Hegel describes his historical moment as one of decline, in which the traditional meanings of things
have lost their grip on ordinary agents: “Spirit has lost not only its essential life;
it is also conscious of this loss and of the finitude of its own content” (GW
9.12/PS §7).30 Our spiritual situation is as impoverished as that of “a wanderer
in the desert craving for a mere mouthful of water” (GW 9.13/PS §8). Later, in
chapter 5, Hegel says that the narrative he has chosen is one of declension rather
than ascent, because it more appropriate: “in our times that form of these moments is more familiar in which they appear after consciousness has lost its ethical life, and in the search for it, repeats those forms” (GW 9.197/PS §357). It is
(also) the worst of times.
If these descriptions of crisis in the Phenomenology are to be identified with
the collapse of the ancien régime in the first decade of the nineteenth century, the
sense of crisis is even more pronounced in the Philosophy of Right, which, over
ten years later, criticizes modern negative view of the free will, the atomism and
contractarianism that dominates liberal thinking about the state, and the excesses of Romantic subjectivity. Philosophy has fallen into a “shameful decline”
Hegel says; its bent toward merely subjective ends leads to the destruction of
ethics and of the laws of the state (GW 14,1.6, 12/PR 10, 18, respectively). A
remark in the Encyclopedia adds that “the sickness of our time, which has arrived
at the point of despair, is the assumption that cognition is only subjective” (E1
§22z). Hegel is, admittedly, responding to a different political reality here, one
no longer pervaded by Napoleonic optimism. But there is nonetheless a striking
and persistent gap between Hegel’s stake in philosophical modernity—his view
that the modern state alone offers the conditions for the realization of human
freedom, and that he is only articulating the rationality of the actual—and his
observations on modernity, as he finds it. The fact remains that Hegel never uncoupled these two systematically dissonant principles: the historical dependence
of his position, and the incomplete or inadequate character of modern subjectivity. He did not, in sum, view his position either as one that could be out of sync
with its time, nor as one that was a mere explicitation of modernity as he found
it. His position stems from modernity, but he finds modernity, in and of itself,
not quite as it could or should be.
This raises the second issue I noted above, about Hegel’s view of the meaning of philosophy within its historical context: if modernity is, practically speaking, incomplete, then what is philosophy for? What is its status with respect to
the not-quite-yet realization of the form of life that nonetheless makes it possible? It is at least clear that Hegel regarded philosophy as having some role to
perform within this realization, some potentially public function. In contrast to
Fichte, Kierkegaard, or Nietzsche who often write under the presumption of
public incomprehension, Hegel writes that “the intelligible form of science is the
way open and equally accessible to everyone […] what is intelligible is what is
already familiar and common to science and the unscientific consciousness
alike” (GW 9.15-16/PS §13). And: “the individual has the right to demand that
Science provide him with the ladder to this standpoint, should show him this
standpoint within himself” (GW 9.22-23/PS §26). At no point in Hegel’s career
is philosophy presented as esoteric in principle. So much so that around the time
of the Phenomenology’s appearance, he reiterated, in a letter to Niethammer, that
30
Cf. GW 9.14-5/PS §11.
Antón Barba-Kay
110
it was the world-historical role of German philosophy to complete in thought
what the French Revolution had accomplished in practice.31
But what is it that philosophy can be said to “accomplish” for him exactly?
The darker strain of analysis I’ve noted culminates in a passage from the 1820’s
Lectures on Fine Art, in which he says that the harsh opposition between inner
freedom and the necessity of external nature have, in fact, been driven to harshest contradiction in modern culture:
Spiritual culture, the modern intellect, produces this opposition in man which
makes him an amphibious animal because he now has to live in two worlds
which contradict one another. The result is that now consciousness wanders
about in this contradiction, and, driven from one side to the other, cannot find
satisfaction for itself in either the one or the other […] it becomes the task of philosophy to supersede the oppositions […] Philosophy affords a reflective insight
into the essence of the opposition only in so far as it shows how truth is just the
dissolving of opposition and, at that, not in the sense, as may be supposed, that
the opposition and its two sides do not exist at all, but that they exist reconciled
(LFA 54-55).
This ‘amphibious’ view of agency seems on the face of it far from the seamless,
second-natural view we might have expected or desired from him.32 In a sense, it
reverses the priority between practical agency and philosophy, by suggesting
that it is only in philosophy that we are able to make sense of our own amphibious status as creatures natural and free. Philosophy performs the task of showing us the unity underlying a practical conflict, but the insight is one that cannot
as such take place in practice, cannot be actualized within a world that must
remain at harsh odds with itself. We may be Hegelian naturalists in theory, in
other words, even as we must remain Kantian dualists in practice.
The passage nonetheless agrees with the Phenomenology on the point that
our understanding of modern agency is not just a mirror explicitation of circumstances on the ground, as it were, but one that transforms our very view of those
circumstances, by freeing them from their contingency and transposing them into the terms of absolute knowledge. In these passages, philosophy exceeds or
surpasses the possibilities of what is possible or even implicit within our notquite-yet form of life, such that what is asunder in practice may be reconciled
only in theory. In that this reconciliation can only take place in philosophy, it is
a position that was castigated as conformist by Hegel’s revolutionary disciples.
But in that the reconciliation effects, in being thought, a transformative recognition of the very aspect of the world, the position is not the therapy of quietism
either—it proposes not an escape from practice into theory, after all, but the raising to a higher power in theory of what remains latent within practice. I would
suggest that the meaning of Hegel’s position for us crucially depends on what
I’ve called the aesthetic character of his thought: Hegel does not mean his system simply to acknowledge the otherwise practically realized freedom of mod31
See Briefe, vol. II, #233. The notion is likewise implicit in the architecture of the Phenomenology itself, with “Absolute Freedom and Terror” giving way to “Morality” within
chapter 6.
32
One might add that Hegel makes clear that he does not regard an amphibian as an admirable thing to be—referring to them in the Encyclopedia as repulsive and “imperfect
products of nature” (E2: §368z.).
Hegel’s Dialectical Art
111
ern life, but in some sense to bring it into being through a transformation of consciousness, that is, through the shared acknowledgment that Hegel’s thought is
our form of unity. If Hegel’s thought is akin to a work of art, in other words, it is
not simply a work of art that is meant to express the canons of taste of a preexisting community; rather it aims to actively convoke that very community by
giving it an image in which it can recognize itself, to bring into being something
that is at once implicit in modern consciousness but not yet fully present to us
prior to our awareness of it.
In order to motivate this suggestion, I’d like to return to the Critique of
Judgment for a moment. Aesthetic or “reflective” judgments interest Kant, as
I’ve said, as embodied intimation of freedom.33 But they also interest him as a
proxy for intersubjectivity. It is within his treatment of aesthetic judgment that
Kant comes closest to addressing the distinctive character of intersubjectivity,
since he openly entertains the social dimension of such judgments as constitutive to their intelligibility. Aesthetic taste is presented as a sensus communis.34 It is
a shared power of appealing to the collective judgment of human reason in general. Two essential yardsticks of aesthetic judgments are therefore their universal
communicability, and our right to demand (in principle) everyone’s agreement
with our view that such and such is beautiful (KU §§8: 32):
By “sensus communis”[…] must be understood the idea of a communal sense, i.e.,
a faculty for judging that in its reflection takes account (a priori) of everyone
else’s way of representing in thought, in order as it were to hold its judgment up
to human reason as a whole […] Now this happens by one holding his judgment
up not so much to the actual as to the merely possible judgments of others, and
putting himself into the position of everyone else [man … sich in die Stelle jedes anderen versetzt], merely by abstracting from the limitations that contingently attach
to our own judging (KU §40).
Kant does not say much about the social conditions underlying this power of
abstraction, nor about the relation between the universality of judgments of taste
and the specific practices and objects on which we exercise them. Standards of
beauty are not, after all, universal without qualification—they are not even the
same throughout Western Europe, as Kant knew. But this ambiguity as to “the
merely possible judgment of others” is nonetheless a fruitful one. Some of
Kant’s comments suggest that as a condition for this sensus communis we should
understand the unstated presence of Enlightenment cosmopolitanism—aesthetic
judgment would be an expression of the fact that we already been disciplined into a certain way of seeing things with others.35 Art makes explicit the cultural
norms that already inform our vision, in this sense. But Kant’s emphasis in other passages suggests a more ambitious, constitutive role for the sensus communis—not simply as the reiteration of shared European sensibility, but as the
project of calling into being what is shareable par excellence, the solicitation of a
human communion that is not yet realized but that is nonetheless internal to
beauty’s “should”.36 From this angle, art summons us to see what we could be
33
See esp. KU §59.
For the history of this phrase, see Gadamer 2003: 19-30.
35
E.g. KU §§14: 40, 83.
36
See esp. KU §§8: 9, 18, 19, 41.
34
Antón Barba-Kay
112
by showing us what we’ve been all along—it has, in this sense, the performative
function of being the means through which we come to recognize ourselves in
common, “as if from an original contract dictated by humanity itself” (KU §41).
It is this performative role for aesthetics that was most interesting to Schiller in the 1790’s; beauty functions for him in the Letters as the activity conforming a community’s ethical harmony; it both expresses and constitutes a community’s ethical transparence to itself in practice. The same may be said of Schelling, of the young Hegel, and of the author of the Oldest Program, whose project
of a “new rational mythology” had a transformative, rather than simply imitative, notion of beauty. What I’m suggesting is that Hegel’s Phenomenology and
his system as a whole should be seen as aspiring to perform this kind of function. If it is a sort of aesthetic artifact, and if it can be said to be out of sync with
the historical advent to which it nonetheless insists on closely tethering itself,
then it is because his project should be understood neither as reiterating the
norms and attitudes of modern life, nor as misidentifying them, but as aiming to
summon us to a shared a vision of ourselves that could itself bear the weight of
constituting our modern wholeness.
In the Preface to the Phenomenology, Hegel notes that modern education
differs from that of ancient times in that “the individual [now] finds the abstract
form ready-made […] the task nowadays consists […] in freeing determinate
thoughts from their fixity so as to give actuality to the universal, and impart to it
spiritual life” (GW 9.28/PS §33). Not only does the notion of bringing “life” to
the universal have a clear aesthetic resonance—it stems from Kant’s description
of the “quickening” (Belebung) of sense that takes place in reflective judgment37—the suggestion is that the ambition of Hegelian science is neither to recapitulate the world nor to change it: the aim of science is the “recognition” of
what is already the case in some sense, but which is transformed in our selfconception of it. Modernity has the same character for him in many descriptions: it is not a situation of seamless harmony, but rather one in positive need
of harmonization. In the “end of art” passage from the Lectures on Fine Art, Hegel notes that such a harmonizing cannot be done by art any longer, and that
this magnifies our need for philosophy—both for “knowing philosophically
what art is” and for meeting the demands that our spiritual culture places on us.
Philosophy in this way takes the place of art as the practice through which we
recognize ourselves in otherness: more than just conciliating us to (or allowing
us to cope with) our position faute de mieux, it is what restores our nature whole.
5. Becoming Who We Are
I think that we are sometimes misled by the useful textbook fiction that Plato,
Aquinas, Hegel, and Wittgenstein could be said to understand themselves as
providing the same kinds of answers to the same kinds of questions.38 The difference is most jarring, say, when Plato ends a dialogue with a myth, or when
Aristotle gets started by canvassing popular opinions, or when Aquinas offers us
arguments for God’s existence that are not presumed to be independent from
faith. It is not that these moments are inscrutable to us, it is rather that we find
37
Cf., e.g., KU §§12: 43, 49.
For two (very different) elaborations of this thesis, see Hadot 1995 (esp. 101-109), and
MacIntyre 1991.
38
Hegel’s Dialectical Art
113
thinkers working within a terrain in which bearings must be taken differently
from ours. One way to describe this strangeness is the changing relation that
philosophy has to its communal context, the question of who, in each case, the
author is reasoning with and for, and, given the shape of “our” shared commitments, what kinds of investigations are understood to be available for measured
progress. But another way of understanding this relation would be to note that
in each case philosophy takes itself to be called on to discharge different sorts of
functions with respect to its form of life, functions that—like the changing roles
of the fine arts—are themselves historically variable.
The roles most familiar to us now are perhaps revolutionary activism, therapeutic quietism, and scientific (or scholarly) research. Hegel’s position should
interest us all the more because it conforms to none of these patterns, in fact: he
offers us a completion of history that cannot take place within history alone, a
means to effect the transformative recognition that Romantic art was expected
to play by some of his contemporaries. To instance Novalis’ formulation, to
“romanticize” means “to give a higher significance to the commonplace, an appearance of mystery to the ordinary, the dignity of the unknown to the familiar,
the semblance of infinity to the finite” (quoted in Martini 1977: 319).39 Hegel’s
conception of his project is in line with this transfiguration of the ordinary by
revealing its deepest rational grounds; it at once attends to the recurrence of the
alienation to which it is addressed and, in acknowledging the fundamental difference between modernity and its self-conception, aims to heal the gap by
providing us with an invocation of a wholeness in which we may acknowledge
ourselves already whole. It is not revolutionary because this transformation is
not institutional, but nor it is quietist because it supplies us with the means of
recognizing the unity that remains latent within our riven forms of practice.
This characterization doubtless raises a larger crowd of questions than it
answers—about the scope of this “we”, about whether it finally amounts to a
form of obfuscatory escapism, and about the very feasibility of recognizing ourselves as whole in absolute thought. Unlike the amor fati of thinkers ancient and
modern, however—a position solitary in its encounter with eternity—Hegel’s
position accounts for the necessary persistence of the questions that we continue
to address in common. We are permanently encumbered by the question of naturalism, because it is not the kind of question that could be set to rest in theory
or in practice alone: our amphibious form of life is such as not to be a given,
such as to remain in question, and so it cannot but continue to elicit questions
about its own (and our own) status and unity. These questions still speak to us,
in this sense, because we are continually forced to try to realize what it would
mean to say “we” and to mean it. Inasmuch as “we may well hope that art will
always rise higher and come to perfection” (LFA 103), Hegel still becomes us.
References
Works cited by abbreviations
[CRGA] Bernstein, J.M. (ed.) 2003, Classic and Romantic German Aesthetics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
39
Cf. (again) with E1 §22 and LFA 99-100.
Antón Barba-Kay
114
[GW] Hegel, G.W.F. 1968, Gesammelte Werke, edited by the Rhenish-Westphalian
Academy of Sciences and the German Research Foundation, Hamburg: Felix
Meiner.
[Briefe] Hegel, G.W.F. 1969, Briefe von und an Hegel, Volumes 1-4, Hoffmeister, J.
(ed.), Hamburg: Felix Meiner.
[E2] Hegel, G.W.F. 1970, Philosophy of Nature: Part Two of the Encyclopedia of Philosophical Sciences (1830), trans. A.V. Miller, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
[Werke] Hegel, G.W.F. 1970, Werke im zwanzig Bänden, Moldenhauer, E., Michel,
K.M. (eds.), Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
[ETW] Hegel, G.W.F. 1971, Early Theological Writings, trans. T.M. Knox, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
[LFA] Hegel, G.W.F. 1975, Lectures on Fine Art, trans. T.M. Knox, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
[DFS] Hegel, G.W.F. 1977, The Difference between Fichte’s and Schelling’s System of Philosophy, trans. H.S. Harris and W. Cerf, Albany: State University of New York
Press.
[PS] Hegel, G.W.F. 1977, Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A.V. Miller, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
[PR] Hegel, G.W.F. 1991, Elements of the Philosophy of Right, trans. H.B. Nisbet,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
[E1] Hegel, G.W.F. 1991, The Encyclopedia Logic, trans T.F. Geraets, W.A. Suchting
and H.S. Harris, Indianapolis: Hackett.
[E3] Hegel, G.W.F. 2007, Philosophy of Mind, trans. W. Wallace and A.V. Miller,
with revisions by M.J. Inwoo, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
[A/B] Kant, I. 1998, Critique of Pure Reason, translated and edited by P. Guyer and
A.W. Wood, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
[KU] Kant, I. 2000, Critique of the Power of Judgment, Guyer, P. (ed.), trans. P. Guyer
and E. Matthews, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
[SW] Schelling, F.W.J. 1856-61, Sämtliche Werke, Schelling, K.F.A. (ed.), Stuttgart:
Cotta.
[STI] Schelling, F.W.J. 1978, System of Transcendental Idealism (1800), trans. P. Heath,
Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia.
Other works
Anscombe, E. 1958, “Modern Moral Philosophy”, Philosophy, 33, 1-19.
Aristotle 2009, The Nicomachean Ethics, trans. D. Ross, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Barba-Kay, A. 2016, “Why Recognition Is a Struggle: Love and Strife in Hegel’s
Early Jena Writings”, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 54, 307-32.
Boyle, M. 2016, “Additive Theories of Rationality: A Critique”, European Journal of
Philosophy, 24, 527-55.
Hegel’s Dialectical Art
115
Brandom, R.B. 2009, Reason in Philosophy: Animating Ideas, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Brooks, T. 2007, Hegel’s Political Philosophy: A Systematic Reading of the Philosophy of
Right, second edition, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Dahlstrom, D.O. 1991, “The Religion of Art”, in Dahlstrom, D.O. (ed.), Philosophy
and Art, Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 235-54.
Dale, E.M. 2014, Hegel, the End of History, and the Future, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Desmond, W. 1991, “Art, Origins, Otherness: Hegel and Aesthetic Self-Mediation”,
in Dahlstrom, D.O., Philosophy and Art, Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 209-34.
Eldridge, R. 2014, “Hegel’s Account of the Unconscious and Why It Matters”, Review of Metaphysics, 67, 491-515.
Feuerbach, L. 2012, The Fiery Brook: Selected Writings, trans. Z. Hanfi, London: Verso.
Förster, E. 2012, The Twenty-Five Years of Philosophy: A Systematic Reconstruction,
trans. B. Bowman, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Gadamer, H.G. 2003, Truth and Method, second Edition, revised by J. Weinsheimer
and D.D. Marshall, New York: Continuum.
Goethe, J.W. 1989, Botanical Writings, trans. B. Mueller, Woodbridge: Ox Bow Press.
Goethe, J.W. 2016, The Essential Goethe, Bell, M. (ed.), Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Hadot, P. 1995, Philosophy as a Way of Life, Davidson, A.I. (ed.), Oxford: Blackwell.
Ikäheimo, H. 2014, “Hegel’s Concept of Recognition—What Is it?”, in Krijnen, C.
(ed.), Recognition: German Idealism as an Ongoing Challenge, Leiden: Brill, 11-38.
Kierkegaard, S. 1992, Concluding Unscientific Postscript to Philosophical Fragments, Vol.
I, edited and translated by H.V. Hong and E.H. Hong, Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Lear, J. 1998, Open Minded: Working Out the Logic of the Soul, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
MacIntyre, A. 2007, After Virtue, South Bend: University of Notre Dame Press.
MacIntyre, A. 1991, Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry: Encyclopedia, Genealogy, and
Tradition, Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
Martini, F. 1977, Deutsche Literaturgeschichte, 17th expanded edition, Stuttgart:
Kröner.
McDowell, J. 1996, Mind and World, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
McDowell, J. 2009a, Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
McDowell, J. 2009b, “Wittgensteinian ‘Quietism’”, Common Knowledge, 15, 365-72.
Nietzsche, F. 1997a, Daybreak, trans. R.J. Hollingdale, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Nietzsche, F. 1997b, Untimely Meditations, trans R.J. Hollingdale. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Pinkard, T. 2000, Hegel: A Biography, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Pinkard, T. 2012, Hegel’s Naturalism: Mind, Nature, and the Final Ends of Life, Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
116
Antón Barba-Kay
Pinkard, T. 2017, Does History Make Sense? Hegel on the Historical Shapes of Justice,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Pippin, R. 2011a, Hegel on Self-Consciousness: Desire and Death in the Phenomenology of
Spirit, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Pippin, R. 2011b, “The Status of Literature in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit: On
the Lives of Concepts”, in Gray, R.T., Halmi, N., Handwerk, G.J., Rosenthal,
M.A. and Vieweg, K, Inventions of the Imagination: Romanticism and Beyond, Seattle: University of Washington Press, 102-20.
Pippin, R. 2014, After the Beautiful: Hegel and the Philosophy of Pictorial Modernism,
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Taylor, C. 1977, Hegel, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Taylor, C. 2010, “Hegel and the Philosophy of Action”, in Laitinen, A. and Sandis,
C., Hegel on Action, London: Palgrave Macmillan, 22-41.
Thompson, M. 2008, Life and Action: Elementary Structures of Practice and Practical
Thought, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Williams, B. 1996, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Hegel’s Fact of Reason: Life and Death in
the Experience of Freedom
Dean Moyar
Johns Hopkins University
Abstract
This paper shows how Hegel transforms Kant’s Fact of Reason argument for
freedom, and in particular how Hegel takes over the role of experience and death
in Kant’s “Gallows Man” illustration of the Fact. I reconstruct a central thread of
the Phenomenology of Spirit in which Hegel develops his view of freedom and practical rationality through a series of life and death experiences undergone by
“shapes of consciousness”. While Hegel views his fact of reason as a result of a
developmental process rather than as an immediate brute fact, the method of that
development is itself deeply informed by Kant’s argument that the moral law
must be opposed to attachment to life in order to establish the reality of freedom.
By contrast with Kant, Hegel begins with an immediate unity of life and selfconsciousness, and only through a painful trial is the subject of the Phenomenology
educated to free obedience to reason. Hegel departs fundamentally from Kant
both in uniting life and freedom and in simultaneously developing a world of freedom, a socially embodied fact of reason, through which individuals express their
freedom in action.
Keywords: Kant, Freedom, Hegel, Reason, Life, Self-consciousness.
1. Introduction
If freedom of will is strictly opposed to determination by natural causes, then
there is nothing that would, or could, count as evidence of freedom, for all our
evidence comes through the operations of nature. One possible way out of this
bind is to prove freedom of will from freedom of thinking, for the spontaneity of
thinking seems both undeniable and in a medium (consciousness) that is at least
somewhat plausibly undetermined by ordinary natural causes. Kant attempted
such a proof in the third section of his Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals,
arguing that reason shows “a spontaneity so pure that it thereby goes far beyond
anything that sensibility can ever afford it” (Kant.Ak. 4: 452, PP: 99),1 and that
1
I cite Kant’s texts from the Academy edition: Kant.Ak. = Kant 1900ff.; PP = Kant
1996.
Argumenta 4, 2 (2019): 117-142
ISSN 2465-2334
© 2019 University of Sassari
DOI 10.14275/2465-2334/20198.moy
118
Dean Moyar
we can infer from this faculty to membership in an intelligible world above the
domain of causality and appearance. The problem with this kind of argument is
that it leaves unexplained the move from thinking to willing, from theoretical to
practical reason. Kant recognized the deficiencies in his own argument, and in
the Critique of Practical Reason he based his proof of freedom on an explicitly
moral consciousness of the will as governed by the moral law. This is his Fact of
Reason (hereafter Fact), the claim that as agents we are necessarily conscious of
ourselves as standing under a moral law that is supremely binding on the will.
From this Fact we infer that the will really is free, outside of causal influence,
for the Fact would be impossible without such freedom. The difficulty with this
type of proof is that it seems to rely on a practical need: I need to think of myself
as an agent under moral laws, and therefore I need to think of my will as transcendentally free. The trouble is that we could grant all this and still say that
needing to think this way does not make it so. From the demand to conceive of
action in a certain way no fact of the matter follows. The demand could very
well be yet another dictate of life, of nature.2
The only way to prove that life itself is not pulling the strings, so to speak, is
through the willingness to die for the sake of the law. This is the insight of Kant’s
famous Gallows Man example in support of the Fact,3 and, I argue in this paper, it is an insight that Hegel exploits to great effect in his Phenomenology of Spirit. Kant looks for “confirmation” of freedom through willingness to sacrifice
one’s life to obey the moral law, the conclusion of practical reason. He holds
that the motivation of an action risking one’s life can only signify the determination of the will through reason alone. This argument for freedom through conscious opposition to life deeply influenced the development of German Idealism. While Fichte employs it for his political philosophy, Hegel generalizes the
argument in his account of the experience of consciousness in the Phenomenology. In contrast to Kant’s anti-naturalist approach to freedom, Hegel uses the experience of death in the service of an argument that unites nature and freedom.
Hegel too aims to prove the reality of freedom, but he argues that freedom is realized within a social order conceived as a living system of rights and duties.
Hegel’s fact of reason is the ethical consciousness reached at the end of the Phenomenology and at the beginning of Sittlichkeit in the Philosophy of Right.
Rather than analyze the consciousness of the individual in the Philosophy of
Right account of ethical life, or analyze the various passages where he critiques
Kant’s moral philosophy, in this paper I follow a central thread of the Phenomenology in which Hegel argues for his view of freedom through a series of life and
death experiences undergone by “shapes of consciousness”. Hegel views his fact
of reason as a result of a developmental process rather than as an immediate
brute fact. But the path or method of that development is itself deeply informed
by Kant’s argument that the moral law must be opposed to attachment to life in
order to establish the reality of freedom. By contrast with Kant, Hegel’s freedom
begins as a pure self-consciousness, and only through a painful trial is the subject
of the Phenomenology educated to free obedience to reason. The subject does find
the source of the bindingness of norms in her own free will, but Hegel departs
2
For discussion of a version of this naturalistic challenge leveled by Salomon Maimon,
see Franks 2007.
3
I take the Gallows Man label from Grenberg 2013. For a critical discussion of her view,
see Moyar 2015a.
Hegel’s Fact of Reason: Life and Death in the Experience of Freedom
119
fundamentally from Kant in simultaneously developing a world of freedom, a
socially embodied fact of reason, through which individuals express their freedom in action. What Hegel rather mysteriously names die Sache selbst is the concept of an action bearing all the rational structure needed for the agent, in knowing and acting on it, to demonstrate that she is actually free.
2. Kant’s Fact of Reason and the Gallows Experience
Kant’s Fact of Reason is the consciousness of the moral law as supremely binding on the will of a rational being. One is conscious that one must judge actions
according to the principle of the moral law and that the law can be effective on
its own to motivate one to act on it. For Kant this consciousness is not derivative
from a prior consciousness of freedom, but rather is the grounds for our
knowledge of freedom.4 On the side of judgment, Kant gives a version of the universal law formulation of the Categorical Imperative: “ask yourself whether, if
the action you propose were to take place by a law of the nature of which you
were yourself a part, you could indeed regard it as possible through your will”
(Kant.Ak. 5: 69; PP: 196). The motivational component of the Fact comes from
the doctrine of respect, a “moral feeling” that proceeds from the representation
of the law, and from the idea that consciousness of the moral law creates an interest that shows that the law is independent of the mechanism of nature
(Kant.Ak. 5: 31; PP: 164-65). On Kant’s story about transcendental freedom,
this independence must be different from the “relative independence” that
comes from subordinating one inclination to another (Allison 1990: 242). The
only contrast with relative independence, however, is total independence, which
manifests itself in the total elevation above life, namely in the willingness to die
for the sake of the moral law.
The element of death comes out in an illustration that Kant introduces as
experiential support for the priority of the law over inclination.5 He writes,
But experience also confirms this order of concepts in us. Suppose someone asserts of his lustful inclination that, when the desired object and the opportunity
are present, it is quite irresistible to him; ask him whether, if a gallows were
erected in front of the house where he finds this opportunity and he would be
hanged on it immediately after gratifying his lust, he would not then control his
inclination. One need not conjecture very long what he would reply. But ask him
whether, if his prince demanded, on pain of the same immediate execution, that
he give false testimony against an honorable man whom the prince would like to
destroy under a plausible pretext, he would consider it possible to overcome his
love of life, however great it may be. He would perhaps not venture to assert
whether he would do it or not, but he must admit without hesitation that it
would be possible for him. He judges, therefore, that he can do something because he is aware that he ought to do it and cognizes freedom within him, which,
4
I am drawing here especially on Allison 1990: Ch. 13, and Franks 2005: Ch. 5.
Allison emphasizes the importance of the gallows experience for the deduction of freedom from the Fact. “Although this passage occurs prior to the ‘official’ deduction of
freedom in the text, it is crucial to the understanding of this deduction, since it clearly
illustrates the inseparability of the consciousness of the moral law and the consciousness
of freedom (including negative freedom) as two aspects of the fact of reason” (Allison
1990: 242-43).
5
120
Dean Moyar
without the moral law, would have remained unknown to him (Kant.Ak. 5: 30;
PP: 163-64).
The strength of self-preservation is calibrated against the sexual desire or
lust that one claims is uncontrollable. The moral law creates an interest that is so
strong that it can (not that it necessarily will) overcome even the desire for selfpreservation. Especially important here is that Kant is proposing that one identifies with the moral law, and is free, precisely in so far as one is willing to give up
one’s life for the sake of the moral law. Dying for the law would be the real, and
perhaps only, proof of one’s morality.
Kant takes the Fact as a crucial step in his argument for transcendental
freedom because it demonstrates our independence from nature. The mystery in
the account is how Kant can simultaneously assert motivational efficacy (of the
pure interest generated by consciousness of the law) and transcendental freedom
as an exemption from natural causality. Must this interest not also be part of nature if it is to be efficacious in a natural being? Even if we grant that everyone
takes this moral law as a guide to judgment, and through this consciousness can
be moved to risk their life, what grounds are there for the further move to the
claim that this willingness to sacrifice is proof of freedom from determination by
nature? Furthermore, even if we were right that this is proven in such cases as
this one, in which one actually sacrifices oneself for the sake of morality, what
are we to say about the other, prosaic instances of moral action in which no
such sacrifice is called for? Can they plausibly be seen as identical with the lifestaking cases? If the non-naturalism of transcendental freedom is supposed to be
established in the life-staking cases, must that same freedom also be operative in
all actions that have moral worth? One imagines a character who adds to each
moral intention “and I would rather die than fail to do my duty”.
The importance of the Fact for the development of German Idealism has
been brought out best by the Fichtean interpretation of Paul Franks. Franks
stresses the motivational dimension of the Fact, writing that “the moral law
immediately constitutes a reason for acting and a motivation for acting, without
the need for any further desire or interest to accompany it”, and “it provides a
motivating reason that outweighs any and—as we shall see—every possible
competing reason” (Franks 2005: 280). The “as we shall see” points to the Gallows passage, of which Franks writes that it “plays a crucial role throughout the
rest of the Analytic” (ibid.: 281). Franks argues that the Gallows Man invites the
readers of Kant’s text to experience the moral law and thus to raise themselves
to the standpoint of morality in the very process of philosophizing. He thinks
that this appeal to experience answers the objection that the Fact only shows
“that I cannot help but believe that I ought to act for the sake of the moral law and
that I therefore cannot help but believe that I can act as an absolute free agent”
(ibid.: 284). Kant needs to show that I actually can do so, where this is a version
of what Franks identifies as the general “Actuality Problem” with transcendental, first-person arguments (ibid.: 246ff.). This actuality is established in the feeling of respect that is produced in considering the Gallows Man: “in considering
the exemplary choice between duty and death, we actually produce the feeling of
respect. So Kant is claiming that in reading the Analytic, we demonstrate the reality of freedom by producing an effect necessitated by the moral law” (ibid., 286-
Hegel’s Fact of Reason: Life and Death in the Experience of Freedom
121
87). The deduction functions properly only when the reader has taken up the
example and has been transformed through moral feeling.6
The Kantian Fact finds a broader application in Fichte’s philosophy, for
Fichte claims that consciousness of the moral law is necessary for taking up the
standpoint of transcendental philosophy. He aims to derive rational content
starting from the self-positing I, the transcendental self-consciousness that is the
condition of the possibility of all other consciousness. This is already an act of
freedom, and one known, in line with Kant’s view, only through the consciousness of the moral law. In Franks’ view, the moral law is not itself the first principle of Fichte’s philosophy, but consciousness of it is required for the philosopher
to “acknowledge real activity as the absolute first principle of philosophy” (Franks
2005: 319). For my account it is important to stress that Fichte derives content
from this original unity by engaging an idealized subject in an experiment,
namely by positing obstacles to that original unity and then reincorporating
those obstacles into a further determined unity. Fichte writes,
The part played by the philosopher is no more than this: His task is to engage
this living subject in purposeful activity, to apprehend it, and to comprehend it as
a single, unified activity. He conducts an experiment. The Wissenschaftslehre contains two very different series of mental acting: that of the I the philosopher is observing, as well as the series consisting of the philosopher’s own observations
(Fichte 1971, I: 454; Fichte 1994: 37).
The “living subject” is confronted by a world opposed to her activity, and
the philosopher’s job in reconstructing an idealized experience of that activity is
to show how in each case that freedom can be restored through the positing of a
new conceptual determination. I take the philosopher’s role in conducting the
experiment to be in part the reiteration of the requirement of freedom at each
point that the limitation by the object is on the verge of eliminating the possibility of self-consciousness. It is as if the philosopher repeatedly calls the subject
back from immersion in, or attachment to, the object. This is a calling back in
each case to something akin to Kant’s Fact of Reason because if you were to
stop with the object your freedom and your ability to follow the moral law
would be compromised. There must be another concept, Fichte argues, that
would unite your previous activity with this new object. In his best known work
of practical philosophy, Fichte argues that the only kind of object that is compatible with the self-determination of the subject is another subject who summons
the first to free activity. This argument continues into his theory of right as a relation of mutual recognition, the basic freedom secured by political institutions.7
3. The Experience of Consciousness and the Actuality of Freedom
My argument is that in the Phenomenology of Spirit Hegel demonstrates
(among other things) the actuality of freedom through an “experience of con-
6
Grenberg (2013) also emphasizes the Gallows example, but she holds that the Fact is an
experience first and foremost of restraint, not of an activity.
7
See Fichte 1971, III: 41-53 and Fichte 2000: 39-49.
122
Dean Moyar
sciousness” that draws on Kant’s Fact and its Gallows Man illustration.8 Recall
that Kant cannot argue straight from the consciousness of the moral law to the
actuality of freedom, for the freedom at issue for him is the transcendental freedom from causal determination, and that is something to which introspective
consciousness has no access. The best case we can make for actuality is that exhibited in the Gallows Man example, whereby one establishes the reality of
freedom by one’s ability (willingness) to sacrifice one’s life rather than violate
the moral law. Hegel’s argument in the Phenomenology, by contrast, demonstrates the actuality of freedom through a series of experiences, many of which
involve staking one’s life for the sake of freedom. While drawing on Kant’s argument Hegel also radically transforms it, for in Hegel’s view proving the actuality of freedom does not involve establishing an inner freedom from nature. Rather, such a proof consists of showing how the outer expression of freedom in
ethical activity, by living beings situated within “the life of a people”, just is the
actuality of freedom. Hegel’s ultimate picture is of an inferential totality in
which individuals are embedded in a complex system of ethical roles, and that
picture may seem to have little to do with Kantian pure practical reason and its
Fact (see Moyar 2017). But Hegel does have a view of individual practical reason within the social system, a view that he discusses under the title of actual or
true conscience. What I focus on in this paper is not so much the final view itself, which I have explored elsewhere (See Moyar 2011), but rather how Hegel
derives the view through experience in the central chapters of the Phenomenology.
Hegel does not think he can take any of the components of this view of ethical
action for granted, and his account of what makes ethical judgments true is quite
a bit more complicated that Kant’s universal law account, but the same elements
of judgment, motivation, and bindingness inform both views. In the next section
I focus on Hegel’s naturalizing account of self-consciousness and desire, while
in this section I unpack the Phenomenology’s method to show how it could
demonstrate freedom’s actuality.
Hegel’s argument in the Phenomenology very much follows Fichte’s lead in
using an experimental method designed to “engage” a “living subject in purposeful activity” and to draw lessons from the experimental results. Of course
this is a reconstructed, idealized experience; such an experimental method is a
perspicuous way to test various claims to knowledge through examining the
consequences that follow from those claims. The goal for both Fichte and Hegel
is to develop or generate conceptual content and validity from minimal presuppositions. They were responding to a dissatisfaction with Kant’s mere assumption
of content, especially in the theory of the categories in the Critique of Pure Reason.
The goal is to derive the categories, both theoretical and practical, in a way that
would not be subject to skeptical challenges. Hegel’s method departs from Fichte’s in so far as Hegel holds that an account must start with immediate content rather than immediate form. Fichte begins with the immediate absolute form of the
I=I, the pure self-consciousness that is the condition of the possibility of all content. Hegel, by contrast, begins with immediate content and develops its inner
negativity in order to reveal the form latent within it. He thinks that Fichte just
begs the question of freedom by beginning with unconditioned freedom rather
than proving it, and that such a position ends up (not surprisingly) having no
argument that the other side could possibly find persuasive. Fichte’s view also
8
The original title of the work was “The Science of the Experience of Consciousness”.
Hegel’s Fact of Reason: Life and Death in the Experience of Freedom
123
departs too much from common sense, for resting idealism on such an absolute
starting point asks the ordinary consciousness “to walk upside down all of a
sudden” (PS 26, GW 23). 9 Hegel begins the Phenomenology with “Sensecertainty”, the most immediate claim to knowledge. From there he works up to
a conception of self-consciousness and eventually, with “Reason”, to the standpoint of idealism. The Fichtean self-positing I always hovers above ethical action as an unattainable standard, whereas for Hegel freedom always is situated
within a context of life.10
What Hegel calls a “shape of consciousness” consists of a specific concept
and subjective (conceptual) capacities, on the one hand, and an object characterized as the truth that the concept is aiming to capture. The realist assumption of
each shape is that the object to be known is something different than the activity
of the subject attempting to know it. The experimental test involves the comparison of the concept of knowing/acting with the object of knowing/acting once
the subject has made specific judgments or performed specific actions. Hegel
calls the Phenomenology a “self-consummating skepticism” (PS 78, GW 56) because the experience demonstrates the internal breakdown of each shape of consciousness (the skepticism) in order to eliminate the gap between subjectivity
and objectivity presupposed by that shape (the skepticism is “consummated”
when this gap is completely eliminated and idealism is achieved thereby).11 In
the practical domain the concept is a purposive concept that does not seek to mirror an already constituted world of objects but rather aims to bring its purpose to
fruition through altering the world in some way. Success in such an endeavor
cannot be the mere consumption of the world, for then the subject would be
eliminating its object rather than realizing the purpose objectively. The practical
consciousness must be productive in some sense, must have as its purpose the establishment or constitution of objects with standing in the world. Because the
practical domain has a certain idealism built into its very purposive character,
the challenge is to establish the agent and a world such that the agent can conceive of her purpose as reflecting an order that is already constituted as purposive. This task will require developing a social world from individual practical
reason, and then, conversely, showing how the modern social world has become
one in which individual conscience is at home.
The key to Hegel’s method in the Phenomenology is the determinate negation
involved in the breakdown of a shape and in the subsequent reversal of consciousness that produces a new shape. Each breakdown provides the raw materials for
a new shape of consciousness that contains the lessons of the previous one.
When a shape of consciousness fails at its knowing or acting, it fails for a certain
reason, typically because of a certain abstraction or incompleteness in its conception. Quite often Hegel portrays the failure in intersubjective terms: two individuals with the same conceptual resources make conflicting judgments, interpret their actions in conflicting ways, thereby negating the truth-claims of the
other. It is crucial for Hegel to characterize this experimental result in a specific
way, typically by showing that the result reveals that there was a universality
implicit in the original concept. So in “Sense-certainty” the knower thought to
9
Citations of the Phenomenology give the paragraph number from the Pinkard translation
followed by the page number in volume 9 of the Gesammelte Werke.
10
See Moyar 2015b for a more detailed explication of the method.
11
See Pippin 1989: Ch. 5, esp. 108.
124
Dean Moyar
grasp a singular “this”, but the result of the experience is that the knower in fact
could only grasp an indexical, a universal “now” or “here”.12 In the practical
case of Faust that we will look at below, Faust thinks he is going to grasp life as
singular pleasure, but instead he grasps only death, a universal. In such cases of
action matters are more complicated because Hegel thinks of the result as itself
containing a kind of process of action and reaction. The death that Faust experiences is actually the necessity that Hegel identifies with fate, a certain blank causality that is the immediate consequence relation.
Once he has adequately characterized the result of the breakdown of one
shape, Hegel makes a move to a new shape through what he calls the “reversal
of consciousness” (PS 87, GW 61). The reversal takes the “being-for-consciousness
of the in-itself” (PS 87, GW 61), namely what the previous object turned out to be
for consciousness in the failure of its knowing/acting, and converts (reverses) that
content into a new object. This reversing and the simultaneous connecting of
shapes to each other is the philosopher’s contribution to the overall argument. It
is in fact a version of the philosopher’s reiteration of the requirement of freedom
in Fichte’s method mentioned above, and it bears some similarities to the methodological use of the Fact that Franks identified in Kant and Fichte.13 Hegel’s
method involves a split into a participant consciousness and phenomenological
observer, which is his version of Fichte’s split between the living subject and the
philosopher. While in Fichte the philosopher comes in to say that selfconsciousness would be impossible if we do not find a new synthetic concept,
for Hegel the philosopher arrives at the new concept/object pair simply by relocating the lessons of the previous experience. Those lessons are made constitutive of the new object, but they are also transferred to the new concept, or to the
new subject who is aiming to know that new object.
The argument that I will follow in the rest of this paper leads from selfconsciousness to reason to spirit, with each major step in the development representing a progression on the side of the concept and the object. In selfconsciousness the subject does not really get beyond considering anything other
than itself truly objective; in reason there is an objective world, and the individual rational subject believes that in her reason she has all the resources she needs
to comprehend that world; in spirit the subject is a collective social subject, a polis, culture, etc., and the objective world is a social world of customs and laws. In
all three domains the same basic moves are repeated, with death playing a central role in overcoming the immediacy of desire and establishing the supremacy
of rational judgment. Death is the central player, so to speak, in Hegel’s dramatic development of the actuality of freedom. The motivational dimension of
the Fact tracks the development of desire, through interest, to utility, each of
which is natural and yet reflects the development of conceptual capacities. The
development of judgment takes place through the building out of the rational capacities of the subject and the rationality of the ethical world. The issue of the
12
For a reading of the opening of the Phenomenology, see deVries 2008.
Franks sees an affective transformation for the readers of Kant’s text and the philosopher elevating herself to the Fichtean standpoint. Hegel does call the Phenomenology “the
path of despair” (PS 78, GW 56), and he is elevating the ordinary consciousness to the
standpoint of idealism. The difference is that it is not clear that Hegel expects the phenomenological observer to experience any of that despair, or to be transformed along the
way.
13
Hegel’s Fact of Reason: Life and Death in the Experience of Freedom
125
bindingness of moral norms is in some ways the trickiest, for Hegel moves towards what looks like a social obligation theory, and yet he ends his account
with an appeal to individual conscience that is a clear successor notion to the
Kantian conception of self-binding.
The encounters with death have both subjective and objective consequences that
track the two side of the reversal of consciousness. On the subjective side, the
attachment to the immediate objects of desire is disrupted when facing the prospect of death. This is clearest in the cases (especially the case of the initial
struggle to the death) in which no one actually dies but the fear of death shakes
one to the core. Its correlate in Kant’s example is the giving up of lust when confronted with the gallows. One is forced to subordinate all desires to the one desire for self-preservation, and such a move prepares one for the next step of restructuring desire through a subordination to a new conceptual structure. That
is, self-consciousness or reason infuses the subject’s motivational structure after
that structure is disrupted or rendered “fluid” through the confrontation with
death. For the issue of naturalism it is important to see that this is how Hegel
moves beyond mere life and its immediate instinctual processes. Death is of
course a category of nature, but it also represents a finality and absolute limit to
life. Death represents the move towards universality, towards the reflexivity of
cognition and intentional action, because it represents the persistence of the universal genus in the face of the loss of individual living beings.14
The objective side of the lessons of death is much more complicated. Hegel
employs death as a necessary consequence of a free deed, and through his method
of reversal the consequence relation (necessity) comes to constitute the subject’s
thinking and the object’s constitution, eventually giving both sides the inferential
structure of reason. Hegel’s name for the necessity that connects action to death is
fate, and he employs it repeatedly to bring the structure of lawfulness into the picture. The free deed is counter to the normativity of natural or mere species life,
but through it and the sacrifice of life it brings about, the act-consequence relation and a robust modality (necessity) enter the will and the world. The normative landscape is expanded in the recognition that it must take the individuality
that can perform such counternormative deeds into account. This recognition is
central to the modern ethical life in which individual particularity is reconciled
with the universal purposes of the state.
4. The Fear of the Lord and the Fact of Service
At the outset of the famous Chapter IV of the Phenomenology Hegel sets up his
naturalistic account of practical freedom with an exposition of life and selfconsciousness. The demanding introductory text lays out the structure of life that
is the basic model of Hegel’s conception of rationality. What Hegel calls the
“whole cycle [that] constitutes life” (PS 171, GW 106) is a complex process of
the self-constitution (self-differentiation into functional subsystems) of an individual organism through processes of assimilation and reproduction.15 While I
cannot go into the details of this account in this paper, it is important to recog14
In his Science of Logic Hegel directly uses death to make the transition from Life to Cognition at SL 12: 191-92, 688-89.
15
For this treatment of life I have drawn on Kreines 2015, Englert 2017 and Ng forthcoming.
126
Dean Moyar
nize that this structure is the replacement for Kant’s law of nature formulation of the
moral law. While Kant would have you imagine your maxim as a law of nature
in a world in which you are a part, Hegel would have you locate your judgment
within a highly differentiated system of ethical institutions and ethical roles. The
same action could be required by both accounts, but the modality is fundamentally different because Hegel rejects the idea that the bindingness of ethical action is conditional on a test of permissibility performed by an individual subject.
On Hegel’s account one is always already situated within a form of life, which if
it is well-ordered will have educated you to a second nature that brings motivation along with it.16 Hegel infamously provides little guidance in the Philosophy of
Right for how to characterize the individual judgment within ethical life: one of
the main advantages of the Phenomenology account is that he actually spells out
what this looks like from the individual’s point of view, and how such a functional account is justified to the individual. But that is only achieved at the end
of “Spirit”. He first needs to derive the subject’s capacity to evaluate the world
through concepts, to establish the dependence of practical reason on social practice, and then to show how the ancient Greek polis developed into the modern
state.
Hegel initially presents self-consciousness as a “pure I” (PS 176, GW 108)
that resembles Kantian apperception. But for Hegel this is only the first of three
“moments” of the concept of self-consciousness. In the second he emphasizes
that this pure I also stands in relation to the objective world apprehended by
consciousness. The pure I taken together with the consciousness of objects is in
fact an activity of mediation that he sums up with the statement that “selfconsciousness is desire in general” (PS 167, GW 104). I take this statement to be
a declaration that self-consciousness is fundamentally purposive, oriented by uniting the external with itself, evaluating the world in relation to its purposes.17
This basic view goes together with the naturalist theory of value par excellence according to which something is good because I desire it. This initial immediate
self-consciousness embarks on a developmental process when it realizes that
immediate desire makes the objects of desire, rather than its own activity, the
16
For my understanding of Hegel’s naturalism I am drawing on Pinkard’s (2012) excellent treatment. My defense of Hegel as giving a naturalistic account is an argument mainly about a certain contrast with Kant’s moral anti-naturalism. I am not touching on the
interesting and complex question of how Hegel’s official philosophy of nature relates to
his philosophy of spirit, nor am I answering the general question of whether or not Hegel
counts by today’s standards as a naturalist. I do think he falls into the “soft naturalist”
camp, but defending this view would require a lengthy parsing of the many varieties of
contemporary naturalism and a treatment of the overall architectonics of Hegel’s system.
For an account of the general nature-spirit problematic in Hegel, see Quante 2011. For an
excellent account of Hegel’s relation to contemporary naturalism debates, see Ostritsch
2014. There are deeper questions about whether Hegel’s system as a whole can be considered naturalistic. Some of these are raised by Gardener 2007.
17
I am in broad agreement with Pippin’s comments on this move that “its apperceptive
self-awareness is not of an object but rather is something like the avowing of a practical
commitment of a sort, something like a projecting […] of oneself outward into the world
and the future” Pippin (2011: 65). See also Jenkins’ (2017) survey of possible interpretations. It is important to keep in mind, as Jenkins says, that “it would be a mistake to regard any particular claim about self-consciousness or ‘a self-consciousness’ in this chapter
as articulating a Hegelian theory of self-consciousness” (ibid.: 84).
Hegel’s Fact of Reason: Life and Death in the Experience of Freedom
127
dominant factor in the relationship. The only object of desire that could satisfy
the freedom implied by the unity of self-consciousness would have to possess this
same capacity of unification, or would have to be an object that is also a selfconscious subject. When Hegel introduces this point, he puts the stress on the
need for the object to be the genus, or another of one’s same kind.18 He thus
transposes Fichte’s deduction of right from mutual recognition into a deduction
of species life, the need to conceive of the world through the mediation of another member of the species. One achieves freedom, then, not by achieving universality in the sense of a universal exceptionless law, but rather in the sense that
one is united with one’s species.19
We need to understand better how Hegel can give a naturalistic account of
the move from action on value-conferring desire to something akin to Kant’s
Fact of Reason, namely self-determining ethical agency within a self-organizing
form of life. Hegel’s account retains a conception of subjective value, with the
term interest taking over the role of desire. But this value-as-interest is also transformed into a rational account of value, and the question is just how that rationality, and the bindingness of the reasons, enters the picture. Hegel gives an account of the “pure concept of recognition” (PS 185, GW 110) that suggests
some kind of formal transcendental account of the possibility of selfconsciousness. But that pure concept is misleading, for while full mutuality of
recognition is the goal of the account, every stage on the way is part of the process of constituting the self-conscious subject and the world in which such a subject can act ethically. These stages are developed through attitudes and actions
that lead to the transformation of subject and object through lessons learned
from the failure of nascent attempts at recognition and self-realization.
The one move whose naturalistic credentials could be called into question
is the movement of the “reversal of consciousness” whereby the lessons are converted into new subjective capacities and attitudes, on the one hand, and new
objects or standards, on the other. We will see the first such reversal in the move
from the master-servant relation to the Stoic sage later in this section. These reversals represent above all a switch from an action-consequence relation in experience to a deontic requirement within the subject and a corresponding rationality in the world (though this correspondence can be defective in various ways,
as it is in the Stoic case). If there is a problem here vis-à-vis naturalism, it is with
how you could move from an experience within a process of life, with living individuals, to a strict necessity of a deontic requirement. This is exactly why death
plays a central role. Death represents necessity within the process of life, so it is
from the experience of death that there arises the deontic raw materials, as it
were, for a reversal into a more rational shape of self-consciousness. Kant’s Gallows Man experiences the threat to life that proves his greater attachment to life
than to lust, and then in the second gallows he experiences his greater attachment to the moral law than to life. The two experiences together prove that the
moral law really is supremely binding on the will of a rational agent. For Hegel
the initially merely desiring subject must develop this self-binding and selfdirection through repeated negations of life experienced as consequences of the
18
See Siep 2014a: 92. For a guide to Hegel’s theory of recognition in general, see Siep
2014b.
19
This talk of species is of course not completely foreign to Kant’s philosophy, but it is
not prominent in his writings on the foundation of morality.
128
Dean Moyar
subject’s own deeds. The philosopher who reverses these consequences is in a
sense constituting the rational will, but only with materials provided by desire
and by the subsequent attitudes of interacting agents.
Hegel does not merely assert mutuality of recognition as a normative ideal,
but rather develops a multi-layered conception of freedom and rationality
through a series of conflicts. In the most immediate form of recognition between
desiring individuals who are driven to prove their freedom, they present themselves as free from attachment to life, as risking their own life and thereby “showing that it is fettered to no determinate existence, that it is not at all bound to the
universal individuality of existence, that it is not shackled to life” (PS 187, GW
111).20 The result of this struggle is the scenario in which both individuals survive and one surrenders to servitude. The meaning of the surrender is that “selfconsciousness learns that life is as essential to it as is pure self-consciousness”
(PS 189, GW 112). This first main reconciliation or unification of freedom and
life is the first main expressive naturalization of freedom. The desiring element of
life is co-essential with the pure self-ascription of self-identity, so that purity
must find expression within the finite world of life.
Hegel’s famous depiction of the superiority of the servant’s selfconsciousness to the master’s can be seen as expressing a fact of service akin to
Kant’s Fact of Reason. Along the dimension of bindingness the servant remains
simply in obedience to the master (bound by threat of force). The servant progresses dramatically beyond the master along the motivational and judgmental
dimensions. The motivational dimension concerns, first of all, the results of the
negative dimension of fear:
It felt the fear of death, the absolute master. In that feeling, it had inwardly fallen
into dissolution, trembled in its depths, and all that was fixed within it had been
shaken loose. However, this pure universal movement, this way in which all stable existence becomes absolutely fluid, is the simple essence of selfconsciousness; it is absolute negativity, pure being-for-itself, which thereby is in this
consciousness (PS 194, GW 114).
This shaking loose, this absolute fluidity and negativity, is a key move towards freedom in the constitution of the servant. The servant is in a position of
surprising strength in relation to the master because he is in a position to be
transformed through obedience to the master’s will and through practical education in laboring on the material world. Although the master maintains the freedom of pure self-consciousness, at the level of life the master still only aims at
immediate satisfaction, and thus has not developed. The servant, on the other
hand, is distanced from immediate desire in having to work for someone else,
20
Robert Brandom captures the general connection of commitment and sacrifice in writing, “So we should ask: what is it that one must do in order properly to be understood as
thereby identifying oneself with some but perhaps not all elements of one’s self-conception?
The answer we are given in Self-Consciousness is that one identifies with what one is willing to risk and sacrifice for. Hegel’s metonymic image for this point concerns the important case of making the initial transition from being merely a living organism, belonging to the realm of Nature, to being a denizen of the normative realm of Spirit. The key
element in this index case is willingness to risk one’s biological life in the service of a
commitment—something that goes beyond a mere desire” (Brandom 2019: 238).
Hegel’s Fact of Reason: Life and Death in the Experience of Freedom
129
and can see in labor the activity of self-consciousness made objective. Hegel
contrasts the servant’s work to the master’s satisfaction:
In the moment corresponding to desire in the master’s consciousness, the aspect
of the non-essential relation to the thing seemed to fall to the lot of the servant, as
the thing there retained its self-sufficiency. Desire has reserved to itself the pure
negating of the object, and, as a result, it has reserved to itself that unmixed feeling for its own self [Selbstgefühl]. However, for that reason, this satisfaction is itself only a vanishing, for it lacks the objective aspect, or stable existence. In contrast,
work is desire held in check [gehemmte Begierde], it is vanishing staved off, or: work
cultivates [bildet]. The negative relation to the object becomes the form of the object; it becomes something that endures because it is just for the laborer himself
that the object has self-sufficiency (PS 195, GW 114-15).
Work is cultivating and forming, giving an objective shape to desire by investing the objective world with distinctions that have their origin in a subject’s
desire, but, importantly, not in the servant’s own desire. Hegel calls work “desire
held in check”, a vanishing that is nonetheless “staved off”. The servant creates
value by investing the objective world with form, in cultivating objects or fields,
and it is that form-investing activity that Hegel views as the essential step in the
move from nature to freedom.
Hegel states the full import of the fact of service in connecting the inner and
outer transformations of the servant. The servant comes to find in the world
what is meaningful or valuable, and Hegel stresses that the servant could not
have done so without the experience of the full fear of death.21 The key point in
the servant’s development is when he comes to see his own “being-for-itself” or
self-conception as identical with the expression (what Hegel calls “posited as external) of form in formative activity. In the following crucial passage, Hegel
links the servant’s “mind” or “meaning” [Sinn] to the internalization of the
formative activity:
In formative activity [Bilden], being-for-itself becomes for him his own being-foritself, and he attains the consciousness that he himself is in and for himself. As a
result, the form, by being posited as external, becomes to him not something other
than himself, for his pure being-for-itself is that very form, which to him therein
becomes the truth. Therefore, through this retrieval, he comes to acquire through
himself a mind of his own, and he does this precisely in the work in which there
had seemed to be only some outsider’s mind (PS 196, GW 115).
But how does this switch from work to mindedness function? What formative activity and mindedness/meaning have in common is that certain patterns
of inference are present in both. Formative activity can be conceived as action
according to instrumental reasoning. One has been given a task, and one must
learn the means to accomplishing that task. The objects take on form in so far as
they acquire a shape that serves the goal. In work one comes to see one’s own
being-for-self in that form “posited as external”. By seeing that identification
21
“Without the discipline of service and obedience, fear is mired in formality and does
not diffuse itself over the conscious actuality of existence. Without culturally formative
activity, fear remains inward and mute, and consciousness will not become for it [consciousness] itself [wird nicht für es selbst]” (PS 196, GW 115).
130
Dean Moyar
with oneself is the same connection (I=I) that is present in connecting premises
in an inference, where the formative steps are the particular means to the (universal) goal of producing food. The identification of the connections between
formative steps is the mind at work, the self that sees its being not in an immediate self-relation but as a relation to itself through the connections between universal goals and particular means to those goals.
When through a “reversal of consciousness” Hegel makes the switch from
the working servant to the Stoic sage, the account is squarely back in the orbit of
Kantian ideas, for the Stoic was Kant’s leading example of the correct view of
the good (the view that the good applies only to people and not to things or
mere states of affairs).22 The basic idea behind this reversal is that the element of
form, which previously had been imposed on a recalcitrant world in formative
work, is now taken simply to be the essence of the world. The reversal is from the
form as for-consciousness to the form as what is in-itself or objective. This objective form does not really exist in its own right, but rather only in relation to the
thinking individual who claims mastery over the world through thought. The
world is now seen to be only in so far as it is an expression of the unity of selfconsciousness. The master-servant relation was of course a failed attempt at mutual recognition, and the Stoic is an advance in so far as the Stoic unites the
sides of form and the binding power of the master. Instead of an external master, one is now the master of one’s own thoughts and thereby of all reality.23 The
Stoic does not confront a world with standing of its own, but rather the subject
treats the world as containing meaning or significance only in relation to itself as
thinking. The fundamental shift on the side of the bindingness of norms is to now
locate the subject’s thinking as the source of what “is true and good for it” (PS
198, GW 117).24
The biggest failure of Stoicism comes along the dimension of judgment, for
its inner standard for judgment is too divided from the rich content of desirebased life. Stoicism has an inner standard of judgment, and is conceptual or a
thinking self-consciousness, but it has an overly simplistic standard of value that
cannot account for the differentiation of life. In contrast to the “multiple selfdifferentiating spreading out, isolation, and complexity of life […] with respect
to which desire and labor are active”, it “consists in being free within all the dependencies of his singular existence, whether on the throne or in fetters, and in
maintaining the lifelessness which consistently withdraws from the movement of
existence, withdraws from actual doing as well as from suffering” (PS 199, GW
117). It thus purchases the overcoming of the master-servant dialectic with a
withdrawal that results in “lifelessness”. One maintains one’s mastery over value and truth in thought as a “simple essentiality”, yet this means that the “freedom
22
He refers to the Stoic’s attitude towards pain in the Critique of Practical Reason discussion
of good and evil. See Kant.Ak. 5: 60; PP: 188-89.
23
Hegel writes, “To think does not mean to think as an abstract I, but as an I which, at the
same time, signifies being-in-itself, or it has the meaning of being an object to itself, or of
conducting itself vis-à-vis the objective essence in such a way that its meaning is that of
the being-for-itself of that consciousness for which it is” (PS 197, GW 116).
24
As Hegel puts it in his compressed description of stoicism, “Its principle is this: Consciousness is the thinking essence and something only has essentiality [Wesenheit] for consciousness, or is true and good for it, insofar as consciousness conducts itself therein as a
thinking being” (PS 198, GW 117).
Hegel’s Fact of Reason: Life and Death in the Experience of Freedom
131
of self-consciousness is indifferent with respect to natural existence and for that
reason has likewise let go of natural existence, has let it be free-standing […] a truth
without any fulfillment [Erfüllung] in life” (PS 200, GW 118). This is a failure of
judgment, though one that also reflects the poor social reality in which Stoicism
found itself. The point is that Stoicism is “not living freedom itself but only the
concept of freedom” (PS 200, GW 118) While the servant had been able to see
the world as an expression of himself in his labor, the Stoic has forfeited this expressive relation to life and the world.25 The problem of lifelessness is the problem of determinate content; the challenge going forward is to unite the pure form
of self-consciousness with the content of “the living world”. The living world
must be a differentiated social world, and the individual must be able to locate
her judgment within the system of norms that constitute such a world. That
world is not good simply by virtue of being living, yet only a living world can be
the vehicle of the rational realization of the good.
5. Fate and the Object Born of Self-consciousness
Looking at the two sections of “active reason” in the Phenomenology in light of
Kant’s Fact and Gallows Man, it is quite striking that Hegel begins with a tale of
the gratification of lust that leads to a death sentence and ends with an account
of Kantian autonomy as reason testing laws through a standard of universality.
It is as if Hegel aims to derive the moral psychology and principles of judgment
that would take us from the lusting man, through the self-preserving prudential
man, to the man willing to give up his life for the sake of the moral law. The account is also in an important sense a repetition of the movement that we traced
in the last chapter: “reason will also once again pass through the doubled
movement of self-consciousness, and then from self-sufficiency it will make its
transition into its freedom” (PS 348, GW 193).26 We thus begin again with basic
desire (pleasure) and a process of recognition, but now with a background conception of a social world rather than a one-on-one confrontation of abstractly
conceived self-conscious beings in mere nature.27 We move closer here to typical
modern attempts to justify the political order through self-interest, and indeed
Hobbes’ war of all against all makes an explicit appearance within these sections. But “Reason” only gives one side of the derivation of Hegel’s fact of rea25
Hegel writes, “However, while individuality, as acting, is supposed to show itself to be
living, or, as thinking, is supposed to grasp the living world as a system of thoughts, so
too within the thoughts themselves there must be for the former expansion [of action] a content for what is good, and, for the latter expansion [of thinking], a content for what is true”
(PS 200, GW 118, my bold).
26
So Reason B corresponds to Self-consciousness A and Reason C corresponds to Selfconsciousness B.
27
Hegel frames the entire account of active reason with a portrayal of “the life of a people” (PS 350, GW 194), his basic or immediate model of life enriched through freedom.
This is a proleptic account of the goal of reason, and Hegel introduces it in part to justify
his unusual choice of methodology for the shapes of practical reason. They are shapes of
a consciousness that has lost the ethical order, rather than (what would have been the
normal mode) shapes of increasingly universal motivational and justificatory structure
that have ethical life as their goal (PS 356, GW 196). The argument still charts a progression from immediacy to mediation, but its shapes have a dramatic tension that comes
with the dynamics of loss and recovery.
132
Dean Moyar
son, namely the side “within which consciousness sublates its purposes” (PS
357, GW 197). The complement to this picture is the derivation within forms of
life themselves, namely the development of spirit, “the aspect according to
which it [morality] comes forth from out of the substance” (PS 357, GW 197).
Goethe’s Faust is an especially effective initial shape of active reason because Hegel has transitioned from “Observing Reason”, the domain of natural
science, leaving it behind just as Faust leaves his scientific endeavors behind
when he makes his deal with the devil.28 In terms of our three dimensions of the
Fact, Faust has abandoned judgment to enjoy unmediated desire through binding himself to the devil. Faust has given up the dead knowledge that could inform judgment, and has embraced pure hedonistic motivation. In Goethe’s
drama, Faust “plunges into life” (PS 361, GW 199) in seducing Gretchen: as
Hegel puts it, “a ripe fruit is plucked” (PS 361, GW 199). The consummation of
Faust’s sexual desire is not supposed to be the literal destruction of Gretchen;
she is supposed to be the vehicle for the “doubling” of rational selfconsciousness.29 In the drama Faust actually comes to love her and tries to save
her when she has been imprisoned and sentenced to death for killing their child.
Faust’s deed does stand for a kind of freedom, but the meaning (or truth) of that
freedom comes in its consequences, namely death. Hegel writes,
Instead of having plunged from dead theory into life, the only singular individuality, which at first has only the pure concept of reason for its content, has thus
instead plunged into the consciousness of its own lifelessness, and, to itself, has
come to be only as empty and alien necessity, as dead actuality” (PS 363, GW
200).
The alien necessity or dead actuality is the result of Faust’s experiment in living.
His deed results in unintelligible but necessary consequences, and in doing so
sets the stage for the introduction of necessity into the will and into the world.
Hegel’s best explanation of this deed’s relation to life comes in a passage
from the Science of Logic in which Hegel links the concept of fate to selfconsciousness and freedom. He contrasts fate proper with “the fate of a living
thing”, which “is in general the genus, for the genus manifests itself through the
fleetingness of the living individuals that do not possess it as genus in their actual
singularity” (SL 12: 141, 639). With Faust’s free deed clearly in mind, he continues,
Only self-consciousness has fate in a strict sense, because it is free, and therefore
in the singularity of its “I” it absolutely exists in and for itself and can oppose itself
to its objective universality and alienate itself from it. By this separation, however,
it excites against itself the mechanical relation of a fate. Hence, for the latter to
have violent power over it, it must have given itself some determinateness or
other over against the essential universality; it must have committed a deed. Selfconsciousness has thereby made itself into a particular, and this existence, like ab28
“Insofar as it has elevated itself to its being-for-itself from out of the ethical substance and
from out of the motionless being of thought, the law of custom [Sitte] and existence
[Dasein], together with the knowledge related to observation and theory, only lay behind
it as a gray and gradually vanishing shadow” (PS 360, GW 198).
29
See Pinkard 1994: 95 for the claim that Faust plays the role of the master in this repetition of the earlier dynamics.
Hegel’s Fact of Reason: Life and Death in the Experience of Freedom
133
stract universality, is at the same time the side open to the communication of its
alienated essence; it is from this side that it is drawn into the process. A people
without deeds is without blame; it is wrapped up in objective, ethical universality, is dissolved into it, is without the individuality that moves the unmoved, that
gives itself a determinateness on the outside and an abstract universality separated from the objective universality; yet in this individuality the subject is also divested of its essence, becomes an object and enters into the relation of externality
towards its nature, into that of mechanism (SL 12: 141-42, 639-40).
Faust’s deed is an expression of freedom, of the individuality asserting itself
against the merely objective or universal essence of communal life. The deed
sets the individual out of the ordinary course of species life, but outside of that
species life there is only blank causality, the process that makes no sense but that
one nevertheless cannot avoid. In the Phenomenology account Hegel is saying
that such an individual deed is necessary to separate the self-conscious individual from mere life. But he is also saying that disconnected from the “ethical universality” of the innocent community, such a deed is captured in a mechanical
process with deadly consequences. What in the above passage Hegel identifies
as mechanism is the same thing he calls “lifeless necessity”, “a pure leap into the
opposite”, and “a riddle” (PS 365, GW 201) in the Phenomenology.
In his characterization of the Faust episode’s experimental result, Hegel
makes a crucial move towards overcoming the agent-world split that characterizes the Kantian Fact. I have stressed that Faust’s fate shows the overcoming of
the practical concept/purpose of immediate pleasure, and thus lines up with the
first phase in Kant’s Gallows example. But the necessity of the result, of the
“dead actuality” that Faust finds as a consequence of his deed, has the deeper
meaning of shifting the conception of reality from something to be observed (as
in the natural sciences) to something constituted fundamentally by and through
self-consciousness. We had an early abstract version of this move in the transition to Stoicism, but in that case the knowing subject stood aloof from life in order to maintain its simple judgments of the true and the good. The move here is
trickier, but Hegel’s goal is clear: to transform the world into a rational world
through the necessity revealed in experience. He writes,
Its essence is therefore only the abstract category. However, it no longer has the
form of immediate, simple being, a form which it had for the observing spirit,
where it was abstract being, or posited as alien, or was thinghood itself. Here, being-for-itself and mediation have entered into this thinghood. Therefore, they
come on the scene here as a circle whose content is the developed pure relation of
the simple essentialities. The attained actualization of this individuality thus consists in nothing more than this, namely, that this cycle of abstractions has been
cast out from the self-enclosed confines of simple self-consciousness into the element of being-for-itself [Für es seyns], or into the element of objective expansion
(PS 363, GW 200).
The “essentialities” Hegel refers to here are pure unity, pure distinction,
and their relation, which as the “absolute relation and abstract movement constitute necessity” (PS 363, GW 200). Self-consciousness is “this cycle of abstractions” that constitutes the basic logical rules governing all inference. Even
though this fate or necessity is empty and blind, it is “the simple and empty but
nonetheless inexorable and impassive [unstörbare] relation” and a “firm connec-
134
Dean Moyar
tion [feste Zusammenhang]” (PS 363, GW 200). Taking on board from Kant’s theoretical philosophy the idea that all necessity and normativity has its roots in the
unity of self-consciousness, the move here is to thinking of that necessity and (at
this point entirely formal) rationality as governing human action and interaction. It is a first step within “Reason” towards converting desire into practical
reason and towards converting individual rationality into the social rationality
that constitutes a form of life. At the end of the process the ethical action as conceived by the individual subject will be already set up as a concrete possibility
within the objective world, and thus not something the subject needs to isolate
from the purposes that structure that world.
The reversal of consciousness that follows the Faust episode produces what
Hegel calls “The Law of the Heart”. In this shape the necessity of fate has been
internalized as law. The consciousness that has the law as residing in its own
heart has the source of bindingness in itself. Yet that internalization remains deficient, for “[t]he law is immediately self-consciousness’ own law, or it is a heart
which in itself has a law” (PS 368, GW 202). Hegel thus characterizes it as “the
contradiction between the law and singular individuality” (PS 369, GW 202). This
consciousness has not progressed to the Kantian viewpoint where one is willing
to sacrifice individuality for the sake of the law. In Hegel’s presentation the individual self-consciousness determines the content of the law through its own
heart, through the immediate desire that is its natural individuality. The shape
has made some progress towards freedom on the motivational level, but in its abstraction it is not motivated to perform specific actions. Rather, this figure is only motivated to judge the world of hard necessity as a corrupt world opposed to
its own lawfulness. The other agency towards which the agent’s activity is directed (the successor to Gretchen as the object of desire) is now represented by
“humanity”, a universal. But this consciousness finds its assumption that its law
is the law of the actual world frustrated, for it does not see others sharing this
same law, and thus “[t]he heart-throb for the welfare of mankind therefore passes over into the bluster of a mad self-conceit” (PS 377, GW 206).
The objective world is also constituted by necessity, but the law of that
world is one of competition in which each individual works to get the better of
the others. Hegel calls it “the way of the world” (PS 379, GW 207), which looks
like nothing so much as the Hobbesian state of nature—“this universal feud
within which each in itself wrests for himself what he can, in which each executes justice upon the singular individuality of others” (PS 379, GW 207). We
are at the level of ordinary prudence or self-interest. We can think of this as the
intermediate stage of Kant’s Gallows episode, the point at which selfpreservation is placed above the immediate lust. Those actual agents, in a world
determined by the loss of ethical life, are motivated to pursue their own good.
This self-consciousness is obviously lacking along the dimension of universality
of content, but Hegel will show (in the subsequent battle with virtue) that it “is
better than it thinks” (PS 392, GW 213). In uniting virtue with the way of the
world, Hegel unites moral and non-moral value in a single conception of individuality that realizes the good through its own nature.
One could say that the high point of Hegel’s naturalism is what he calls
“The Spiritual Kingdom of Animals”, but it is a rather dubious high that unites
nature and normativity in a way that makes judgments of good vs. bad impossi-
Hegel’s Fact of Reason: Life and Death in the Experience of Freedom
135
ble.30 The hallmark of these shapes is the individual’s confidence that she is
united with the world and thus does not need to set her purposes against the
world in order to realize reason. There is now no contradiction between the
power of self-consciousness over the action and the fact that the action stems
from one’s nature. The focus is on the value of action as an accomplishment rather than on the purity of motive. Hegel identifies four components of action:
circumstances, purpose, means, and realized action (that he also calls the
“work”). These components are the correlates, at the level of rational willing, of
the components of life (environment, self-preserving individual, process of assimilation, and reproducing genus). Determined immediately by nature, the individual does not yet connect all four moments in a rational unity that would
guarantee that one’s intentions are expressed in the world. In this agent’s experience, “It is fortune [Glück] that decides in favor of a badly determined purpose
and badly chosen means just as much as it decides against them” (PS 406, GW
222). Another move must be made for the individual’s authority to extend beyond the intention to the completed action.
The perishing of the deed in the contingency of the external world precipitates the introduction of one of the most important and least well understood
concepts/objects in the Phenomenology. Hegel’s term for this object, die Sache
selbst, is virtually untranslatable. Translations include “the fact of the matter”,
“what really matters”, “the crux of the matter”. It would not be too much of a
stretch to translate it as “the fact itself”. In my view die Sache selbst is the object
that the agent is conscious of in ethical action, and I propose that this is the intentional object of Hegel’s fact of reason. That is, die Sache selbst is the successor
to Kant’s conception of a maxim of action evaluated by the categorical imperative. It has been hard for commentators to see this because Hegel introduces die
Sache selbst in an immediate and thus subjectivist way as the object (including
circumstances, purpose, means, and accomplished purpose) that stands fully
under the authority of self-consciousness. He is very clear that this is another
case in which self-consciousness continues its “objective expansion”: “It is an
object born out of self-consciousness as its own object, without thereby ceasing to
be a free-standing, genuine object” (PS 409, GW 223). The problem with the
immediate version of die Sache selbst is that self-consciousness treats it as a predicate, and takes itself to be entitled to judge which of the four components is essential to the action. Die Sache selbst is thus at first just a way for selfconsciousness to manipulate the aspects of action to claim credit for whatever it
wants (this is what Hegel calls the “honest consciousness”). The key point to
keep in mind is that the subsequent concepts and objects of reason are themselves versions of die Sache selbst, attempts to locate that view of intentional action that could express the necessity of self-consciousness in the social world. At
the end of Spirit Hegel returns to die Sache selbst and thereby confirms that is the
objective side of his fact of reason.
The agent must come to accept that its deeds only have meaning in so far as
they are open to the deeds of others. In a striking metaphor in which humans
figure as insects, Hegel writes that others come to one’s deed “like flies to freshly
poured milk” (PS 417, GW 227). We feed off of each others’ actions, an experience that Hegel turns into a new conception, the crucial idea of a spiritual es-
30
More precisely, “all of it is good” (PS 402, GW 219).
136
Dean Moyar
sence. Hegel writes, “it is an essence, whose being is the doing of singular individuals and of all individuals, and whose doing is immediately for others, or it is a
fact [Sache] and is only a fact insofar as it is the doing of each and all, the essence
that is the essence of all essence, that is spiritual essence” (PS 417, GW 227). The
move that Hegel makes from individual to universal authority does dislodge the
singular individuality and thus follows the same general dynamic as the other
transitions we have seen. But unlike the fate of tragic action, this witness to
one’s deed’s consumption involves reciprocal agency that is intelligible to the
agent. It is the basis for expressive recognitive success, for a teleological relationship in which one’s purposes are recognized. Rather than a way to introduce
bare necessity into the world, this transition sets up a return to life as the ethical
life of a people.
Having apparently reached the living social substance divided into a living
system of estates,31 Hegel reminds us that we are still dealing with the individual
self-consciousness burdened by immediacy. The agent has to capture the content
of the spiritual essence through “healthy reason” (PS 421, GW 229), with
“healthy” a final mark of nature in reason that indicates a problematic attempt
to isolate universal content in the form of individual reason. As in the previous
cases, law is the first form of universality. Hegel turns to the shapes of law-giving
and law-testing reason as the immediate forms of reason that meet the standard
just discovered in the spiritual essence. The individual and universal must coincide in the ethical laws, such as “Everyone ought to speak the truth” (PS 423,
GW 229), and “Love thy neighbor as thyself” (PS 424, GW 230). These laws
founder on the ceteris paribus clauses that must attach to them once counterexamples are brought into play. In the concrete actuality of life things are seldom
“all equal”, so laws that are binding only on that condition are useless.
If these laws do not reveal the true rationality of the spiritual essence, perhaps the Kantian testing of laws for non-contradictoriness would fare better. But
the retreat to formality in “Law-testing Reason” is an even less promising way
to capture the content of the spiritual essence. What for Kant had been the undeniable bindingness of the form of reason is for Hegel a pale reflection of the
bindingness of actual laws, what is actually right, in the ethical life of a people.
He thus turns in the closing sections of “Reason” to the ethical viewpoint embodied in Antigone’s relation to the divine laws set by the gods of the community. The point of this shift is to say that we cannot make the bindingness of the
law conditional on the universalization test of reason as pure form. Kant’s Fact
thus fails on the issues of judgment and bindingness. Both aspects have to be
more fully anchored in the life of a people, for only with such a life can the actuality of freedom be proven. It is only there that his account of ethical habit or
second nature can be united with freedom. Hegel does not thereby give up on
the Fact, but he thinks he has to exhibit morality as it “comes forth from out of
the substance” (PS 357, GW 197). At the end of his account of Spirit he brings
back die Sache selbst, casting it in terms of conscience, as an actual or fulfilled
universal that incorporates the experiences that substance has passed through in
the course of world history.
31
Passage on division: “The object is the real object in its own self as object, for it has in it
the difference of consciousness. It divides itself into social estates [Massen] which are the
determinate laws of the absolute essence” (PS 419, GW 229).
Hegel’s Fact of Reason: Life and Death in the Experience of Freedom
137
6. The Fact Fulfilled through Spirit
The agent in “Spirit” is the entire city-state, beginning with the immediate ethical life of the Greeks. The downfall of the Greek city-state’s ethical life and the
subsequent rise of Roman personhood follow much the same logic, at the social
level, as the episode of Faust. With the breakdown of the immediately individual Greek city-state that Hegel depicts through Sophocles’ Antigone the result is
once again fate, the empty necessity that followed upon the deed of Faust and
the death of Gretchen. In Hegel’s portrayal of the Greek case, the deed belongs
to Antigone as the representative of the divine law, the law of the family and the
individual. The divine law and human law are interdependent, and the tragedy
brings out the incompatibility that stems from the immediacy of nature in this
seemingly harmonious, but in the end merely individual, ethical life.
The human law, represented by Creon, maintains a living universality only
through the periodic threat of death in warfare, and this means that it is dependent on the divine law that governs burial rites and the afterlife. Hegel writes,
The spirit of the universal gathering is the simplicity and the negative essence of
these self-isolating systems. In order not to let them become rooted and rigidly
fixed within this activity of isolating themselves, […] the government must from
time to time shake them to their core by means of war” (PS 454, GW 246).
In war, the individuals “are made to feel the power of their lord and master,
death” (PS 454, GW 246). The immediate, true, beautiful ethical life of the
Greeks was parasitic on warfare and death.32
In Hegel’s diagnosis, the twin shortcomings of the Greek polis are the insufficient integration of individuality and, relatedly, the suppression of the women
whose primary job was to keep the divine laws of the family intact. The divine
law requires that Antigone bury her brother, and the strength of her commitment to that law is seen in her willingness to die in order to uphold it. Individuality is not genuinely recognized as such, but only as natural, as blood and family, and thus it is not recognized by the human law (PS 463, GW 251). As Hegel
puts it, “In the life of a people, self-consciousness descends from the universal
only down to the point of particularity; it does not get as far as the point of singular individuality, which in its doings posits an excluding self, an actuality
negative to itself” (PS 467, GW 254). Antigone’s deed is both the act of a free
individual and an act performed for the sake of an individual. Hegel writes,
Ethical consciousness is more complete and its guilt more pure if it knows beforehand the law and the power against which it takes an opposing stance, takes
them to be violence and wrong, to be an ethical contingency, and then, like Antigone, knowingly commits the crime” (PS 469, GW 255).
The point of this deed, according to Hegel, “is that the ethical must be actual” (PS 469, GW 255). The non-actuality of Creon’s human law just is its failure
32
This problematic immediacy was also reflected in the dependence of the human law on
the divine in the sense of the oath that binds the community together. Hegel writes, “the
people’s self-reassuring certainty possesses the truth of its oath which binds them all into
one only in the mute unconscious substance of all, in the waters of forgetfulness” (PS
473, GW 258).
138
Dean Moyar
to recognize the individual who is the actuality of the state. Antigone steps out
from this living but immediate universality and stakes her life for the divine law,
for the proper burial of her dead brother. She dies, Creon’s son and wife both
die, and the city is caught up in the fate that is instigated by Antigone but whose
guilt is shared by the whole.33
Just as the successor to Faust was law and the world of hard necessity, so
the successor to Greece is the legal status of personhood and the harsh ethical
reality of the Roman empire. Once again death (and fate) is productive of the
form of lawfulness. The experience of necessity in the tragic ending of Antigone
provides the material for the actuality of lawfulness. This move to personhood is
another entry of self-consciousness into the actual world. Unlike the shapes of
“Reason”, this move occurs within the social domain of spirit, inaugurating a
new rights-based form of social reason that remains to this day at the core of European legal practices. In Hegel’s portrayal, the very spirit of the dead and unburied Polyneices rises up to be the formal recognition of the singular individual:
As this singular individual, he was the selfless departed spirit, but now he has
emerged from out of his non-actuality. […] He is that substance as the positive
universal, but his actuality is to be a negative, universal self. – We saw the powers
and shapes of the ethical world immersed into the simple necessity of an empty
fate. This power of the ethical world is substance reflecting itself into its simplicity, but the absolute essence reflecting itself into itself, the very necessity of empty
fate, is nothing but the I of self-consciousness (PS 476, GW 261).
The cost of this elevation, this resurrection as it were, of individual selfconsciousness, is quite high. Based on the bare I of self-consciousness and nothing more, the public power of the human law has no substantive ethical constraints. In the figure of the Roman emperor, the “monstrous selfconsciousness” (PS 480, GW 263) who exercises “destructive violence” (PS 481,
GW 263) on his subjects, we can see the consequences of cutting off the individual from the life of a people.
The formality of right leads to the “Self-alienated spirit” of early modern
Europe, a culture of aristocracy and faith that eventually succumbs to the Enlightenment. At the end of the account Hegel presents “Absolute Freedom” as
the result of the Enlightenment’s drive to bring all value to the level of utility.
The extreme consequentialism of the Enlightenment hollows out the world of
intrinsic value, and then flips into an extreme deontology in which the principle
of the general will is the only thing that matters in any and all action. The unity
of the individual and universal is immediate and absolute, but this means that
there is no room for mediation of the two; the individual must give way to the
universal. The terror, whereby the self that would be universal in fact becomes
the instrument of death in the figure of Robespierre, is an inversion of Kant’s
Gallows scene. Not willingness to die, but rather willingness to put others to
death becomes the mark of freedom: “The sole work and deed of universal freedom is in fact death, namely, a death which has no inner extent and no inner ful33
“It is in the equal subjection of both sides that absolute right is first achieved, and ethical substance, as the negative power that devours both sides has emerged. That is, fate,
omnipotent and just, has come on the scene” (PS 471, GW 256).
Hegel’s Fact of Reason: Life and Death in the Experience of Freedom
139
fillment, for what is negated is the unfulfilled point of the absolutely free self. It
is therefore the coldest, emptiest death of all, having no more meaning than
chopping off a head of cabbage or swallowing a mouthful of water” (PS 590,
GW 320). Such is the consequence of the Enlightenment disavowal of the differentiated living social order. This ruler puts you to death on mere suspicion of
not doing as the universal law says. And you cannot protest, for his will is your
will, the very universality that constitutes your reason. But this self-destructive
will precipitates the birth of the moral will proper: “this will is unmediated oneness with self-consciousness, or it is the purely positive because it is the purely
negative, and within its inner concept the meaningless death, the unfulfilled
negativity of the self, changes over suddenly into absolute positivity” (PS 594,
GW 322). The lesson of absolute freedom is that one cannot locate that freedom
in the activity of the point-like individual participating in a political process or
sentencing the suspicious to the guillotine. Individuality has to be thought of as
the universality of pure knowing and willing that is the heart of Kantian morality.
In order to move from Kant’s moral theory as presented in “The Moral
Worldview” to his own version of ethical agency in conscience, Hegel characteristically employs a mismatch between one’s presentation to others and one’s
own knowledge of one’s deeds. The main problem with Kant’s view is that he
cannot properly locate the role of happiness or interest; he excludes it from considerations of moral worth and yet he admits that it is an ineluctable part of finite human action. This problem can be solved, and Kant’s Fact transformed, by
rethinking the role played by the authority of self-consciousness in relation to
the action as a whole. Instead of thinking of the unity of the rational will strictly
and exclusively in terms of lawfulness, as Kant does, Hegel thinks that the unity
of the subject has the relation to the various aspects of action of whole to
parts/moments, and he holds that the universality or lawfulness of an action is
only one of those moments. We saw in the last section that Hegel’s term for the
holistic ethical object is die Sache selbst. The problem with it in its initial appearance is that the whole-moment relation is too unstructured, thus allowing the
agent to simply choose which of the moments of action is the essential one. The
answer in that episode was to bind action to “the spiritual essence” as a socially
recognized standard, and that move led to the full account of “Spirit” and then
finally to Kantian moral teleology.
When Hegel contrasts conscience with Kantian duty, he emphasizes the
role that interest plays in its action and the role that recognition plays in the formation of conscience’s intention. The interest is the element of subjective value,
and more specifically of utility, that gives to the action its determinate relation in
the world to the purposes of others and the institutional purposes. Mutual
recognition figures in the account as the presumption and requirement that one
act on reasons that one can communicate to others.34 Above all, Hegel emphasizes that this is no free-floating authority of self-consciousness, for it is bound to
the previous development from which it has resulted. Contrasting it with the
earlier account, he writes,
34
“Conscience has not abandoned pure duty, or the abstract in-itself; rather, pure duty is
the essential moment in its conducting itself as universality towards others” (PS 640, GW
344).
Dean Moyar
140
This crux of the matter [Sache selbst] was there a predicate, but in conscience it is for
the first time the subject which has posited all the moments of consciousness as
residing in it and for which all of these moments, namely, substantiality as such,
external existence, and the essence of thinking, are contained in this certainty of
itself” (PS 641, GW 345).35
Conscience captures die Sache selbst, the ethical action, “in its fullness,
something which conscience gives it by way of itself” (PS 641, GW 345). Like
Kant’s Fact, the consciousness at issue here is the power of self-binding, of
judgment, and has motivating force in its incorporation of interest. It is not based
on the opposition of freedom and nature, but rather on the transparency of selfconsciousness to the moments that structure the action. It is this transparency
that makes the individual’s self-binding simultaneously a responsiveness to reasons that are recognized by other agents.
Yet the authority of self-consciousness over its moments can nonetheless
appear absolute to the reasoning subject, for there is nothing that can be opposed to self-consciousness, and this presents yet another hazard of freedom.
The hazard goes by the name of the beautiful soul, which for Hegel is the result
of withdrawing so completely into the fluidity of self-consciousness that one
balks at the re-externalization required for actual action. “It lives with the anxiety that it will stain the splendor of its innerness though action and existence” (PS
658, GW 354). Hegel seems to think of this as a special hazard of speculative
philosophy, as he comes close to identifying the beautiful soul with the standpoint of absolute knowing itself (see PS 795, GW 425). The ultimate warning
sign and block to this withdrawal is yet another figure of death and/or madness
in which some have seen allusions to the fate of Hegel’s once best friend,
Hölderlin. Hegel writes, “In this transparent unity of its moments it becomes an
unhappy, so-called beautiful soul, and its burning embers gradually die out, and,
as they do, the beautiful soul vanishes like a shapeless vapor dissolving into thin
air” (PS 658, GW 355). In this case Hegel makes death equivalent to the inability of self-consciousness to externalize itself in nature. This death thus motivates
not only the embrace of getting one’s hands dirty in willing specific actions, but
also the controversial move from logic to the philosophy of nature.
The story of “Spirit” is not quite over, for there remains a question of
whether the self-binding of conscience has been genuinely united with the social
binding of the substance-like community. The version of the beautiful soul that
does not simply dissolve is the self-righteous judge, the hard-hearted individual
who despises the self that acts on interest. In the final scene of “Spirit”, the
breaking of this hard heart effects the final reconciliation with reason as universal and reason as individual, an act of forgiveness. Even here we have a reference to death in the very act of mutual recognition whereby the two sides of morality are united.
The former dies back from its being-for-itself [jenes stirbt seinem Für-sich-sein ab],
relinquishes itself and confesses; the latter disavows the rigidity of its abstract
universality and thereby dies back from its self devoid of liveliness and its unmoved universality (PS 796, GW 427).
35
I have discussed this passage at greater length in Moyar 2011: 93-100.
Hegel’s Fact of Reason: Life and Death in the Experience of Freedom
141
This is a fitting end to Hegel’s engagement with Kant’s Fact. We do not realize our freedom in the possibility that we could sacrifice life for the sake of the
moral law, but rather we realize our freedom in sacrificing our abstract selfdetermination for the sake of a life with others who recognize us as the finite,
living, free beings that we are.
References
Henry, A. 1990, Kant’s Theory of Freedom, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Brandom, R. 2019, A Spirit of Trust: A Reading of Hegel’s Phenomenology, Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
DeVries, W. 2008, “Sense-certainty and the ‘this-such’”, in Moyar, D. and Quante,
M. (eds.), Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit: A Critical Guide, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 63-75.
Englert, A. 2017, “Life, Logic, and the Pursuit of Purity”, Hegel-Studien, 50, 63-95.
Fichte, J.G. 1971, Sämtliche Werke, Fichte, I.H. (ed.), Berlin: De Gruyter.
Fichte, J.G. 1994, Introductions to the Wissenschaftslehre and Other Writings (1797-1800),
ed. and trans. D. Breazeale, Indianapolis: Hackett.
Fichte, J.G. 2000, Foundations of Natural Right, Neuhouser, F. (ed.), Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Franks, P. 2005, All or Nothing: Systematicity, Transcendental Arguments, and Skepticism
in German Idealism, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Franks, P. 2007, “From Quine to Hegel: Naturalism, Anti-Realism, and Maimon’s
Question Quid Facti”, in Hammer 2007, 50-69.
Gardener, S. 2007, “The Limits of Naturalism and the Metaphysics of German Idealism”, in Hammer 2007, 19-49.
Grenberg, J. 2013, Kant’s Defense of Common Moral Experience: A Phenomenological Account, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hammer, E. (ed.) 2007, German Idealism: Contemporary Perspectives, Routledge: New
York.
Hegel, G.W.F. 1968ff., Gesammelte Werke, Hamburg: Meiner (GW).
Hegel, G.W.F., The Phenomenology of Spirit, ed. and trans. T. Pinkard, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press (PS).
Hegel, G.W.F., The Science of Logic, ed. and trans. G. di Giovanni, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press (SL).
Jenkins, S. 2017, “Self-consciousness in the Phenomenology”, in Moyar, D. (ed.), Oxford Handbook of Hegel, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 81-101.
Kant, I. 1900ff., Gesammelte Schriften, Berlin: Königlich Preussischen Akademie der
Wissenschaften (Kant.Ak.).
Kant, I. 1996, Practical Philosophy, ed. and trans. M.J. Gregor, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (PP).
Kreines, J. 2015, Reason in the World: Hegel’s Metaphysics and its Philosophical Appeal,
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Moyar, D. 2011, Hegel’s Conscience, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Moyar, D. 2015a, “The First Person and the Moral Law”, Kantian Review, 20, 2,
289-300.
142
Dean Moyar
Moyar, D. 2015b, “The Inferential Object: Hegel’s Deduction and Reduction of
Consciousness”, Internationales Jahrbuch des Deutschen Idealismus, 11, 119-44.
Moyar, D. 2017, “Hegelian Conscience as Reflective Equilibrium and the Organic
Justification of Sittlichkeit”, in James, D. (ed.), Hegel’s Philosophy of Right: A Critical Guide, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 77-96.
Ng, K. (forthcoming), Hegel’s Concept of Life, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ostritsch, S. 2014, Hegels Rechtsphilosophie als Metaethik, Münster: Mentis.
Pinkard, T. 1994, Hegel’s Phenomenology: The Sociality of Reason, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Pinkard, T. 2012, Hegel’s Naturalism: Mind, Nature, and the Final Ends of Life, Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Pippin, R. 1989, Hegel’s Idealism: The Satisfactions of Self-consciousness, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Pippin, R. 2011, Hegel on Self-consciousness: Desire and Death in the Phenomenology of
Spirit, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Quante, M. 2011, Die Wirklichkeit des Geistes: Studien zu Hegel, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp.
Siep, L. 2014a, Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Siep, L. 2014b, Anerkennung als Prinzip der praktischen Philosophie: Untersuchungen zu
Hegels Jenaer Philosophie des Geistes, Hamburg: Meiner.
Some Limits to Hegel’s Appeal to Life
Andrew Werner
Yale University
Abstract
For two hundred years, people have been trying to make sense of Hegel’s socalled “dialectical method”. Helpfully, Hegel frequently compares this method
with the idea of life, or the organic (cf., e.g., PhG 2, 34, 56). This comparison has
become very popular in the literature (in, e.g., Pippin, Beiser, and Ng). Typically,
scholars who invoke the idea of life also note that the comparison has limits and
that no organic analogy can completely explain the nature of the dialectical
method. To my knowledge, however, no scholar has attempted to explain exactly
where or why the organic analogy falls short. In this paper, I propose to remedy
this lack by exploring in depth two different organic models. In brief, I argue that
both versions of the organic model require an appeal to something external to the
organism, and no such appeal can be made sense of within the dialectical method.
Keywords: The Dialectical Method, Speculative Knowledge, Life, The Organic,
Hegel’s Logic.
1. Introduction
Since Hegel first wrote, people have been trying to make sense of his so-called
“dialectical method”. This method, everyone acknowledges, is incredibly difficult to understand and Hegel says some very puzzling things about it. But, to
many, understanding it holds out the promise of solving a vast host of philosophical puzzles—indeed, it can seem like understanding it would yield knowledge of
the most fundamental nature of being.
In fact, Hegel preferred to call what now goes by “dialectical method” the
“speculative method”, as dialectics was the non-ultimate aspect of this method
(cf. EL §§81-82).1 By calling it speculative, he meant in particular to mark out a
1
Citations of Hegel will be as follows: citations to the Phenomenology will use the abbreviation PhG, and cite by paragraph number (e.g. PhG 40). Citations of the Encyclopedia
Logic will use the abbreviation EL, and cite by the section number (e.g. EL §23). Citations
of all other works by Hegel will use the volume/page number of the two versions of his
collected works (Suhrkamp followed by Felix Meiner), separated by a ‘/’. All translations
from Hegel are my own, though I have consulted Terry Pinkard’s translation of the Phenomenology and George di Giovanni’s translation of the Science of Logic. Finally, when I
Argumenta 4, 2 (2019): 143-157
ISSN 2465-2334
© 2019 University of Sassari
DOI 10.14275/2465-2334/20198.wer
144
Andrew Werner
special form of knowledge. This in turn suggests that even the term “method” is
potentially misleading: method suggests a way of coming to have knowledge of
some claim, where a different method might yield knowledge of the very same
claim. In fact, Hegel is interested in a distinctive form of knowledge, where part
of what is distinctive about this form is that what it knows is inseparable from it
and so cannot be known in any other way. Thus, it would be better to talk not of
a special method, but of a special form of knowledge. So, rather than using the
term “dialectical method”, I will use the term “speculative knowledge”.
In the first instance, the distinctiveness of speculative knowledge was intended by Hegel to mark it off from the two more standardly recognized forms
of knowledge: theoretical and practical knowledge. Theoretical knowledge is
knowledge of what is whether it is known to be so or not. Practical knowledge
is knowledge that is productive of its object in the sense that it brings its object
about. These forms of knowledge are perfectly valid, Hegel thought, but are not
suitable to the distinctive task of philosophy—knowledge of the absolute.2
Whatever he meant by that, he didn’t think knowledge of it could be either theoretical or practical, and that sets up the problem of explaining just what form of
knowledge would comprehend the absolute.
Hegel was writing against the backdrop of both Aristotle and Kant. So it
makes sense that to clarify the nature of speculative knowledge, he might reach
for various ideas in their work. One idea he invokes fairly often is the idea of
life, or the organic (cf., e.g., PhG 2, 34, 56). This idea has become very popular
in the literature on Hegel. In particular, scholars appeal to organic models to try
to clarify the manner in which speculative knowledge progresses from one concept to another. Here are three representative quotations from scholars:
One of [Hegel’s] frequent complaints about the presumed stability and classificatory “deadness” of traditional categorial schemes is that they do a great injustice
to the “organic” nature of thought, that thought should be understood, to say
everything at once, as “life” (Pippin 1989: 236).
For all Hegel’s thinking essentially proceeds from an organic vision of the world,
a view of the universe as a single vast living organism. Hegel saw the absolute as
the “one and all”, the Hen Kai Pan, of the pantheistic tradition. But, like Herder,
Schiller, Schelling and Hölderlin, he understood this structure in dynamic, indeed organic, terms. The absolute develops in the same manner as all living
things (Beiser 2005: 80).
The form of thinking is not dependent on “external objects” for content, but generates and is its own content insofar as it is a living, spiritual object […]
use the term “Logic” I mean to refer to Hegel’s account in both the Science of Logic and the
Encyclopedia Logic.
2
Hegel explicitly says that speculative knowledge is neither theoretical nor practical, but
he also says that it is “the identity” of both (cf. 6.548-9/12.236). This (and related comments in Hegel’s Philosophy of Spirit) might lead one to think that Hegel denies that there
is a strict distinction between theory and practice. As I read the claim, however, Hegel is
not claiming that speculative knowledge takes the place of theoretical and practical
knowledge; those forms of knowledge, in their distinctness, are perfectly valid, but unsuited for philosophy. I will not try to explore the sense in which speculative knowledge
is the identity of theoretical and practical knowledge here. (My thanks to an anonymous
reviewer for pressing me to clarify this.)
Some Limits to Hegel’s Appeal to Life
145
[T]hought is said to be living because it gives shape to itself, actualizes itself, and
gives itself its own content through this negative process (Ng 2013: 61).
Typically, scholars who invoke the model of life also note that the comparison has limits and that no organic analogy can completely explain the nature of
speculative knowledge. Some kind of limit is implicit in Ng’s discussion of a life
that is also spirit (or of a distinctively human kind of life) and a limit is explicit
when Pippin describes the appeal to life as a “highly metaphorical notion” in the
sentence following the quoted passage.3
To my knowledge, however, no scholar has attempted to explain exactly
where or why the organic model falls short of being an adequate model for
speculative knowledge. In this paper, I propose to remedy this lack by exploring
in depth two different organic models and showing exactly why each falls short
of being an adequate model for speculative knowledge. For ease of exposition, I
focus on the account of speculative knowledge in the Logic, but what I say about
it should fairly obviously also hold true of speculative knowledge as it figures in
Hegel’s other works (e.g., the Phenomenology). In brief, I argue that the organic
model always requires an appeal to something external to the organism, and no
such appeal can be made sense of within speculative knowledge.
One last note before I begin: as I discuss the two models, I will note the respects in which they get something right about speculative knowledge in addition to noting why and where they fail. A consequence of this approach is that
one may, for any model, note that we can just accept that model as completely
adequate if we abandon whatever feature of it causes it to be inadequate as a
model. I have no objections to doing that, so long as we are clear about what we
are doing and the argumentative burden it places on us of making sense of the
now altered model.
2. Speculative Knowledge
In this section, I want to outline two features of speculative knowledge in the
Logic that will serve as starting points in the sections that follow. In particular, I
will argue that the Logic offers an explanation of the most basic forms of
thought, and that this explanation is meant to avert the skeptical threat that our
forms of thought are parochial. These starting points are meant to serve as relatively minimal ways of characterizing the project of the Logic: certainly the Logic
is more than simply an account of the objective validity of the most basic forms
of thought, and there are certainly other skeptical challenges that the Logic is
meant to dissolve. But these minimal characterizations will be sufficient for the
arguments that follow.4
3
Noting such limits is not universal among scholars, though: Beiser, for instance, thinks
that the analogy has no limits, and that informs his claim that Hegel thinks that the universe is a vast living organism. On this point, as I will show in §§2-4, the texts fairly clearly bear out Pippin and Ng as against Beiser.
4
To say that these are minimal characterizations is not to say that they are uncontentious. The second characterization is certainly not accepted by all Hegel scholars. I will
try to show that there is good textual evidence in favor of it. If the characterization is
nevertheless rejected, then the arguments in the following sections will not (just as they
stand) be compelling.
146
Andrew Werner
First, the Logic offers an explanation of the various fundamental forms of
thought. The evidence for this claim is plain. Hegel begins the Encyclopedia Logic
by noting that one of the ways of describing his Logic is as “the science of thinking, of its determinations and laws” (EL §19; cf. also §§19z2, 23, 24). And, similarly, towards the beginning of the Science of Logic he notes that the subject matter
(“Gegenstand”) of the Logic is “thinking or more determinately conceptual thinking”
the concept of which has to “emerge” in the course of the Logic itself
(5.35/21.27).
That the Logic explains the fundamental forms of thinking is not controversial. What is controversial is how its explanation of these forms relates to an account of what is. And, indeed, such controversy makes good sense, since Hegel
spends the bulk of his introductions to the two versions of the Logic trying to describe the (obviously difficult to grasp) relation between the activity of thinking
and what is. Most notably, he spends fifty-two sections (§§26-78) in the Encyclopedia Logic describing and challenging the way in which other philosophers have
accounted for the relation between thinking and “objectivity” to try to motivate
the distinctive way the two are related in the Logic. Clearly, Hegel thinks that the
fundamental forms of thinking are the fundamental forms of what is, but it is
very unclear how he thinks about that “are”. For my purpose in this essay, we
do not need to start with any controversial assumptions about this important
topic.5
Second, the explanation of the forms of thought that the Logic offers is
meant to avert the threat that they are parochial. A “parochial” form of thought
would be such that an adequate explanation for why we judge as we do when
using that form would leave open whether the judgment was true. When we err
and even when we just accidentally happen to be right, our judging is parochial:
our so judging is not explained by the fact that the world is as we judge it to be,
but rather by some fact about us which explains why the world seems to us to be
that way. For instance, I might err because I have poor eyesight, or because my
community raised me to believe in ghosts, or because human beings cannot hear
a particular pitch. Such explanations, which appeal to something about me as a
way of explaining why I do not judge truly, are incompatible with my judgments
being knowledge. Because we judge as we do whether our judgment is true or not,
our judgment does not “track the truth” in the way that is required for it to be
knowledge.6 Of course, the Logic is not meant to avert the very possibility of error—it is not meant to avert the threat posed by the possibility that I have bad eyesight, or was taught superstitious beliefs as a child. But it is meant to avert the
threat of parochialism about our fundamental forms of thought: for instance, it is
meant to show that the fact that we think about the world as causally structured is
not parochial to us, that the world is indeed causally structured.
The worry that our forms of thought are parochial is meant to be generic
enough to encompass both Cartesian and Kantian worries.7 According to Carte5
Further, the issue of how the Logic relates to our activity of thinking is extremely important for determining the vexed and complicated relationship between the Logic and
Hegel’s Philosophy of Spirit. Again, however, my purpose in this essay do not require that I
take a stand on this topic.
6
For a more thorough development of this idea, cf. Rödl 2007 and 2018.
7
For a helpful account of the differences between these two kinds of worries, cf. Conant
2004.
Some Limits to Hegel’s Appeal to Life
147
sian skepticism, we can form beliefs about the world without being able to exclude the possibility that those beliefs are false. According to Kantian skepticism, we cannot so much as make sense of our capacity to form beliefs about the
world, such that we cannot even make sense of our forms of thought as being
about the world. Both forms of skepticism share the feature that our forms of
thinking reflect something that renders thinking in general (or at least, our thinking in general) unfit to arrive at knowledge of the world. Both, then, are worries
about the parochiality of the forms of thinking at which they are directed.
The generic nature of the worry about parochiality as I have spelled it out
here does not make it the most incisive tool for examining Hegel’s response to
skepticism.8 But its generic nature does enable me to say, without raising many
objections, that the method of Hegel’s Logic is designed to avert the threat that
thought is parochial. One sees evidence of some version of the parochialism
worry plainly present in Hegel’s criticism of the Kantian philosophy, for instance. Hegel writes,
When the critical philosophy understands the relation of these three terminorum
such that we place the thoughts between us and the matters [Sachen] as means in
the sense that this means closes us off from the matters instead of merging us
with them, this view is opposed by the simple remark that even these matters,
which should stand at the other extreme beyond us and beyond the thoughts that
refer to them, are themselves thought-things (5.25-6/21.14).9
A lot can, has, and should be made of these remarks (which recur frequently in Hegel’s discussions of Kant). What I want to note is simply that Hegel is
concerned to avoid a conception of thought which locks us up within subjectivity and thereby prevents us from understanding how our thoughts are able to arrive at knowledge of the world.
Moreover, it is clear that he thinks that the method of the Logic is one of the
keys to overcoming this conception. So he notes that we need to avoid the conception of the forms of thought that “hangs together with” the critical philosophy: we need to avoid the conception of forms of thought “as external forms”,
forms that are only “in the content [Gehalt]” and are not conceived of as “the con8
At least, it is not incisive when it is only developed as far as I develop it here, in the interests of remaining non-controversial. I develop a much more controversial account of it
in connection to Hegel in other work.
9
Another helpful formulation occurs in a student transcript of his lectures: “To experience what the truth in things would be is not done [abgetan] with mere attention, but rather belongs to our subjective activity which reshapes [umgestaltet] the immediately available [Vorhandene]. At first glance, this appears totally perverted and to be contrary to the
end that cognition concerns itself with. Nevertheless one can say that it has been the persuasion of all times that the substantial is attained first through the re-working of the immediate effected by means of reflection. […] It is the sickness of our times that has come
to despair that our cognition is only something subjective and that this subjective is the
final [das Letzte]” (EL §22z). The sickness of the times is to think that the nature of the activity of thinking makes thinking parochial, unfit to arrive at knowledge of what is. In this
quote Hegel refers to a specific source for this worry, that thinking somehow changes our
perceptual representation of the world (cf. EL §22). But we can abstract from that specific
suggestion (which is more controversial in the literature) to note that Hegel’s conception
of thought’s relation to the world, as it is developed in the Logic, was meant to avert parochialism.
Andrew Werner
148
tent itself” (5.26/21.15). One of the principal characteristics of the method of the
Logic is to take the forms of thought as themselves the “truth” and the content of
the investigation (cf. 5.29/21.17). And so it follows that the method of the Logic is
supposed to avoid closing thought off from the world. Or, positively stated, the
method of the Logic is supposed to make sense of the objective validity of thought,
the capacity to get, non-accidentally, at the true nature of things by thinking.
3. Organic Growth
I want now to turn to the first of the two organic models I will discuss in this essay: the Aristotelian model of organic growth. This model is suggested by Hegel’s frequent claim that the progress in the Logic is self-determining. For instance, he describes “the demand for the realization of the concept, which does not
lie in the beginning itself, but rather much more is the aim and work of the entire
further development of cognition” (6.554/12.240).10 I will first articulate the
model and then show in what respect and why it fails to be an adequate model
of the logical progression.
In an account of organic growth, we distinguish between immature and
mature states of an organism. The immature state is posterior to the mature state
in account, or conceptually, because what it is to be the immature state is to be
that which tends towards the mature state. So, an account of the immature state
must refer to the mature state, as that which makes the immature state intelligible as what it is. Moreover, the immature state tends towards the mature state
through its own activity.11 An acorn, on this view, is an immature oak tree;
without grasping that the acorn is an immature oak tree, or at least that it contains a seed and so something that becomes a tree, you would not have any idea
what an acorn is. That is, what it is to be an acorn is to be that which tends towards being an oak tree (or, more immediately, tends towards being an oak sapling). Moreover, the acorn becomes an oak through its own activity: by taking in
nutrients from the soil, for instance, and—when it is a little more mature—by
taking in sunlight.
The first claim, that what it is to be an immature state is defined in terms of
the mature state, explains how we can think of the progress as an enrichment—
the acorn has not yet realized its nature, to be an oak tree, and in realizing this
nature it is enriched, in that it is now actually what it was merely potentially.
Moreover, it explains how this can be combined with the thought that the enrichment is already contained (implicitly or in an undeveloped form) in the starting point, since the acorn is defined in terms of the oak tree. Finally, it does this
while providing a clear model for thinking about the progress as grounded in the
starting point, the immature state (the acorn). The acorn itself tends towards becoming an oak tree. This tendency would explain Hegel’s language of “selfdetermination”.
10
Or, as he puts it a little later, “[T]he progress consists much more in that the universal
determines its self and is for itself the universal […] Only in its completion [Vollendung] is
it the absolute” (6.555-6/12.241). He elsewhere describes the progress in the Logic as “this
way that constructs its self” and claims that its “self-movement is its spiritual life”
(5.17/21.8). Cf. also EL §17, §28z, §238, 5.35/21.27, 5.43/21.33, PhG 2.
11
Cf. Aristotle, Metaphysics Θ8 1049b12-1050a16.
Some Limits to Hegel’s Appeal to Life
149
However, if we apply this model to speculative knowledge, we make
thought parochial. To see this, note again that organic growth is defined by the
transition from an immature state to a mature state. These two states are incompatible with one another, and the immaturity is eliminated by the time one arrives at the mature state. So, in organic growth there are distinct states of the existence of the organism, each one exclusive of the others: seed, sapling, tree. The
immature state is a way in which the organism can exist, while also being a state
in which the organism is a potentiality (potentially mature). So, it belongs to the
idea of an immature state that it can fail to realize its potential, that it can fail to
become mature.
Aristotle makes this point quite well in his discussion of potentiality in Metaphysics Theta. He writes,
Every potentiality is at one and the same time a potentiality for the opposite; for,
while that which is not capable of being present in a subject cannot be present,
everything that is capable of being may possibly not be actual. That, then, which
is capable of being may either be or not be; the same thing, then, is capable both
of being and of not being. And that which is capable of not being may possibly
not be; and that which may possibly not be is perishable, either without qualification, or in the precise sense in which it is said that it possibly may not be.12
When we apply this general point to our example of the acorn, we get the
following: the sapling is potentially an oak. That means that it might not be an
oak. That is, it might fail in its striving to become an oak.
Since the organism can cease to be without becoming fully mature, there
must be conditions outside of or other than it which enable it to become mature:
when those conditions are not met, the organism cannot reach maturity; when
they are met, it can. I do not mean that there are conditions on the continued
existence of the organism in its present state, though there are such conditions:
for instance, that all of the air not suddenly become acid, or that the sun not explode. These are enabling conditions on the existence of the organism—in Aristotle’s terms, enabling condition on the organism’s continuing to be “without
qualification”. I mean that, in addition to these, there must be distinct enabling
conditions on the growth of the organism—those concerned with the possibility
that it “perish” in “the precise sense” at issue in maturation, by failing to become mature. The need for these distinct enabling conditions comes with the
idea of growth. If the acorn already had that which it needed to be mature, it
would not be possible that it would fail to be mature. So, it would not be potentially mature—it would be actually mature, and it would not relate itself to its
environment in a process of becoming mature. As merely potentially mature,
the immature organism lacks that which it needs to be mature: that is why it
must become mature, in an activity of acquiring that which it needs. But this
means there are distinct enabling conditions on growth: whatever those conditions are which enable the organism to acquire what it needs to become mature.
So, I have shown that organic growth rests on enabling conditions by the
presence of which the organism can mature. Now let’s see what happens if we
apply this thought to the “maturation” of the forms of thought in the Logic. The
need to appeal to something external to the mere notion of thought, the appeal
12
Aristotle 1984: Metaphysis Θ8 1050b8-15.
150
Andrew Werner
to an enabling condition, means that the account of thought we start with is not
by itself enough to secure the objective validity of the various forms of thought
that are developed within the Logic. The acorn needs the soil and the sun to
grow, and the acorn is not sufficient to secure these for itself. And so, applying
this model to the Logic, the form of thought requires something analogous to the
soil and the sun, some enabling conditions that the form of thought cannot secure for itself. It follows that on this model it is in some sense accidental to the
notion of the form of thought that it is actually objectively valid: accidental, because thought does not suffice of itself to explain its objective validity. So for all
we know from the bare notion of thought alone it might not be objectively valid,
and that means an explanation of it does not suffice to ensure that it can yield
knowledge. Hence, it is parochial.
To spell this out a bit: if thought had to rely on something external to itself,
which it does not supply, to secure its objective validity, then the mere notion of
thought would be compatible with not being able to be objectively valid. To
claim this is to claim that the world might well be unthinkable, at least so far as
we can tell from the notion of thought as such. We are forced to conclude this
from the organic growth model of the development of thought: for if the enabling conditions are absent, then the form of thought cannot come to maturity
and so cannot develop those forms requisite to think about the world in general
(perhaps we could think only about some aspects of the world). But we cannot
actually conclude in that fashion: we cannot so much as think of the possibility
of an unthinkable world (or an unthinkable aspect of the world)—that is simply
nonsense, since we cannot think of what is unthinkable. And yet we cannot really claim that it is nonsense, or anyway we cannot secure our right to dismissing
it as nonsense. Rather, we have to conclude that it is merely a limitation on
thought: thought is unable to think of an unthinkable world. We are forced to
think as though the only way the world could be was by being thinkable, when
in fact (but we cannot think this fact) it is only contingently thinkable. It follows
that our account of thought makes it parochial: we think as we do only because
of the nature of thought and not because of the way the world is. For all we
know, for all we are able justifiably to conclude, the world is not thinkable, since
we cannot explain or ground or justify its thinkability. And yet we are forced to
take up the world as thinkable. This is an unstable cognitive position, to be sure,
but it is the one we are forced into insofar as we accept that speculative
knowledge essentially requires appealing to something not provided for by the
mere notion of thought (some matter to be worked on).
The idea of incorporating matter central to the model of organic growth
cannot capture the nature of speculative knowledge. And Hegel describes speculative knowledge in a way which reveals that he would reject the organic growth
model: its progression is “unstoppable, pure, taking in nothing from outside”
(5.49/21.38). As unstoppable, the non-final stages of the progression are not
merely potentially mature (for potentiality implies possibly not, and so it implies
that the progression can be stopped). As taking in nothing from the outside, they
must rely on no external matter to develop further. The non-final stages must
contain within them everything they need to be the final stage.
I think we can see Hegel relying on exactly this point in his discussion of
the limits of thinking about life as a model for thinking about the absolute. In
the course of discussing arguments for the existence of God, he notes that the
“truthful [wahrhafte] determination of the idea of God” cannot be grasped from
Some Limits to Hegel’s Appeal to Life
151
“merely living nature” for “God is more than living, he is spirit. The spiritual nature is alone the most worthy and truest origin for the thought of the absolute”
(EL §50A). His argument for this conclusion is that our observation of the ends
of “living nature” “can be contaminated” by “insignificance” (EL §50A). That
is, the ends that living beings set cannot demand as their explanation the absolute, because those ends are insignificant enough that something less than the
absolute would suffice to explain them. Why? I suggest that these ends are insignificant because they are conditioned by that which they take as their matter.
Hegel notes specifically about animals that they do not transform that which
they perceive and intuit into anything absolute, but relate to the sensible world
as what conditions them (for this reason, Hegel claims, animals “have no religion”) (EL §50A). He must have a similar point in mind for all merely living nature: all of it is conditioned, in its capacity to set ends, by the world which it relates to.
Hegel says that we, on the other hand, are not conditioned by that which
we think: we “transform [verwandeln]” the “empirical world” in thinking about it
by raising it up “into the infinite”, that which is without conditions, the absolute, God (EL §50A). It is hard to understand how we do this in thinking about
the sensible world, especially if we take seriously traditional notions of God.13
But, even without clarifying that connection, we can see that Hegel’s claim provides textual evidence for attributing to Hegel the argument against the organic
growth model I presented above.
So, the organic growth model breaks down because it involves the idea of
external matter, or something not provided for by that which grows, and, with
it, potentiality.14 Nevertheless, the evidence cited at the outset of this section
remains: we need to retain from the idea of organic growth that the logical pro13
Hegel’s argument should be compared to Kant’s discussion of physicotheology and
ethicotheology in §§85-6 of the third critique: Kant, like Hegel, notes that we cannot arrive at the concept of God merely from the idea of a natural end, or a living being, because we could conceive of an author of that being which lacked the infinite, unconditioned attributes of God (a being that is relatively more powerful than us, but not omnipotent). Further, Kant, like Hegel, notes that we should instead start with rational nature.
Unlike Hegel, however, Kant thinks that the aspect of our rational nature which grounds
theology is our moral nature: we must posit God as that which enables us to realize the
highest good, a world in which happiness is proportioned to virtue. Hegel rejects this argument from Kant, arguing that we cannot arrive at the absolute from within practical
reason in this way but must instead advance to speculative knowledge, thereby grounding
(and, even more radically, realizing) God: this is one consequence of his argument about
the Idea of the Good at 6.547-8/12.235.
14
It is important to note that what makes the organic growth model inadequate is not the
bare fact that it involves an appeal to something external to thought; it is that what is external to the organism is not able to be fully provided for by the organism itself. (I try to
convey this by noting that what is external serves as material for growth, implicitly referencing the fact that form is dependent upon and does not provide for the matter that it informs, as well as Hegel’s claim that the form/content distinction breaks down for speculative knowledge precisely because there is nothing not provided for by the form itself: cf.
6.549-550/12.236-7). There may well be a sense in which speculative knowledge is related to what is external to it, so long as it is sufficient to provide for itself that which is external to it. Perhaps this is involved in Hegel’s idea that freedom consists in “being with
oneself in one’s other”. (My thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pressing me to clarify
this.)
Andrew Werner
152
gression involves a realization of thought, and also that this realization involves
thought’s own activity. But we need to think of a kind of realization which has
no enabling conditions on its realization, such that it is genuinely unstoppable
and such that it takes in nothing from outside.
Before moving on to consider the next organic model, I want to note one
respect in which my argument in this section is incompatible with some of what
Karen Ng says in her recent work on Hegel and life. In particular, if I am right,
then her claim that the logical concept of life provides the “formal outlines” for
the absolute idea is at least in part wrong (cf. Ng 2016: 10). As she rightly notes,
life-form activity is characterized by a relation to what is external to it: “living
activity relates itself to an external world to which it stands in opposition” (Ng
2016: 8). But she also claims life-form activity provides us with part of “an understanding of the logical Idea as a philosophical method”, that it “shap[es] all
our modes of knowledge” (Ng 2016: 10), and that it provides part of a description of “a form of activity that captures reason in toto, describing the fundamental shape of reason in all of its functioning and development” (Ng 2016: 6). Each
of these claims goes too far, because each of them saddles thought in all of its
forms—including the form it takes in speculative knowledge—with a dependence on some external matter. Part of her point in claiming that life is central to
thought or reason is to note that thinking beings must be living beings. That is
an important insight into Hegel’s account of life. But we can accept that insight
without committing Hegel to the further claim that speculative knowledge is a
kind of life-form activity that inherits the traits of life-form activities—including
the trait of requiring some external matter. This, I have tried to show, is not how
Hegel understood speculative knowledge, because he recognized that this view
would entail that our forms of thinking are parochial.
4. Organic Unity
A different model which also invokes the idea of an organism appeals not to organic growth but to the organic unity that binds different organs together in an
organism. On this view of the Logic, we advance from an account of one part of
an organic whole to an account of the entire organic whole. This idea is typically connected to the Aristotelian and Kantian idea that we can only understand a
part of an organism through relating it to the whole organism. From this idea, it
follows that an account of the part will necessarily lead to an account of the
whole.
This model goes back at least to John McTaggart (cf. 1896: §122). More recently, it has been adopted by Christian Martin in his excellent book on the Logic, Ontologie der Selbstbestimmung. After noting that the parts of an organic whole
are dependent on the whole, he argues that
Knowledge of such a whole is […] won if one of its aspects is initially so observed as if it were constituted independently from the whole. If such a determination really has its existence only in its connection with others, this must show
itself in a (performative) contradiction between its self-standing appearance [Auftreten] and the hidden relations essential for its determinacy—a contradiction that
can be corrected [behoben] only through the explicit inclusion of further determinations, whereby the starting determination is lowered to an un-self-standing aspect of an overarching connection (Martin 2012: 27-28; my translation).
Some Limits to Hegel’s Appeal to Life
153
According to Martin, in speculative knowledge we start with a part of
thought and recognize a contradiction in our account of it that drives us forward
to an ever richer account that eventually captures the whole of thought. This
works, on his view, because the parts are dependent upon the whole in the way
that the parts of an organism are dependent upon the whole organism.
So, on this model, we advance from, say, quality to quantity or from concept to judgment as we would advance either from one organ to another, or possibly as we would from an account of one organ to a larger system of organs.
Just as I cannot grasp the liver or the heart in isolation from the rest of the body
(on this Aristotelian and Kantian view of the organism), so too I cannot grasp
one form of thought in isolation from the other forms of thought.
The starting point for these claims might be taken from Kant’s account of
natural ends in the Critique of the Power of Judgment, in particular §65. In a
body judged as a natural end “each part is conceived as if it exists only through
all the others, thus as if existing for the sake of the others and on account of the
whole, i.e., as an instrument (organ)” and each part “must be thought of as an
organ that produces the other parts (consequently each produces the others reciprocally)” (Kant 5:373-4; Guyer-Matthews translation). So, the parts depend on
the nature of the whole, such that we can grasp their natures only in grasping
the way in which they contribute to producing or sustaining the organism and
thereby themselves. Thus, a grasp of the nature of the whole is required to make
sense of the activity or functioning of the parts, as the whole is that which the
parts produce or sustain in their activity. So, the characteristic activity or functioning of quality is in some sense to produce or sustain thought as a whole.
Within life, there are a multiplicity of organs in an organism and these organs are all interdependent on one another. This interdependence licenses the
claim that the nature of the many organs is determined by the nature of the organism, because they all belong to the one organism.15 This claim in turn requires a contrast between the nature of the organism and the natures of the organs that make up that organism: no organ is identical with the organism, each
is merely a part (or “member”, in Hegel’s terms) of it (6.476-7/12.184). The
simplest way to bring out this contrast is to note that there is only one organism,
while there are many organs.
The contrast between the organism and its organs makes sense, within life,
only because the nature of the organism does not fully and completely determine the nature of the organs. There is something in the organs that is “external” to the nature of the organism, and this externality is essentially appealed to
as the only possible grounds for distinguishing one organ from another. If the
nature of the whole fully determined the organs, then there could be only one
organ: there would be absolutely no difference between the whole and the organ
that made it up, and so there could be no sense in saying that one thing, the part,
is determined by another at least notionally distinguishable thing, the whole.
(What is external or not fully determined by the nature of the organism? As we
will see, it is the manner in which each organ sustains the whole.)
Hegel puts this in his own complicated way. He describes the nature of the
organism or what he calls the “soul” of the living being as a kind of “being for
itself” that is “the identity”: that is, it provides the unity such that each organ is
15
In addition, of course, each organ is determined by the nature of the other organs, but
that determination is less germane for my present purpose.
154
Andrew Werner
a member of the same, identical organism. And there is nothing that qualifies as
part of the living being that isn’t informed by the soul. But the identity, or nature
of the organism, is “sunken in its objectivity” and it is “the inhering [inwohnende]
substantial form” (6.487/12.192). That is, the organism “dwells” (wohnen) within each of the organs, it is their form, but it is not identical with the organs: the
organs provide the matter. That is, there is and must be a contrast between the
organism considered as the substantial form, and the organs considered as matter or that which the soul informs.
This point is really quite obvious when we reflect on the kind of progress
that can be made within biology. Consider that even after we know what activities characterize an organism we do not yet know how it performs those activities.16 We might know that a cow eats grass without knowing that it does so by
processing the grass through four stomachs. Or we might observe a dog feeding,
say, or chasing prey, or breaking down food with saliva. We can then ask how it
does these things. We do not know, simply from knowing that it performs these
activities, how it does so—figuring that out takes a great deal of scientific inquiry. We might find out that saliva breaks the food down because it contains an
enzyme that breaks down certain kinds of chemicals found in the food. We
might in turn ask how this enzyme is able to break down these chemicals, and
appeal to the relative strength of various chemical bonds, and so on. At each
level we have identified a certain kind of activity, and at each level we can ask
again how this activity is performed. When we answer that question, we will
have uncovered yet another activity (another level) about which we can ask the
same question.
Moreover, on the organic model we are considering, each “lower” level of
explanation will itself be organic. For example, I might first identify the tongue
as an organ of the dog, but then the tongue will serve as a kind of “organism” or
whole that is essential for explaining the “organs” or parts that are involved in
the tongue’s activities. The enzyme in the tongue will have the nature that it
does only in its dependence on the nature of the tongue, just as the tongue has
the nature its does in its dependence on the nature of the dog. (This is why there
can be no Newton for a blade of grass on this way of thinking about organisms:
at no point in explaining an organism by its parts (and sub-parts, etc.) do we
reach parts that are intelligible independently of the whole they make up.) But
despite the manner in which the parts always depend on the whole, we must still
investigate the parts to understand how the whole performs its activities. And
we do not know the nature of those parts just in knowing the nature of the
whole—otherwise we would already know how the dog ate just in knowing that
it ate. The fact that we do not reveals that the dependence of the organs on the
whole involves an aspect of independence.
Now let’s try to apply this model to speculative knowledge. In the Logic, the
whole would be thought and the parts would be forms of thought—quantitative
thoughts as opposed to qualitative thoughts, judgments as opposed to syllogisms. On this model, the nature of thought would not suffice to explain the different forms of thought. Whatever is in those forms of thought that is not explained by thought as such must have a different explanation or basis. This
means that the nature of thought does not exclude the possibility of other, possibly incompatible forms of thought—forms of thought that we do not possess,
16
I owe this consideration to Sebastian Rödl.
Some Limits to Hegel’s Appeal to Life
155
that would be alien to or even incompatible with the ones we do possess, but
that would be compatible with the very idea of thought. Again, this is obvious,
for the fact that a dog runs leaves open many different possible “hows”, corresponding perhaps to different organizations of the bones, muscles and ligaments, about which we have no idea just knowing that the dog runs. Similarly,
just knowing what thought is would not in any way rule out the possibility that
there are many forms of thought different from the ones we happen to possess;
and it would not be sufficient to generate or account for the multiplicity of forms
of thought contained in the Logic. This makes it impossible for us to know the
legitimacy of the forms of thought that we employ, to know that they are ways
of arriving at the truth and of knowing the world. For while it is no threat to a
science of the dog that there might be other bodies similar in some respects but
different in others, the idea of a science of thought (as Hegel understands it)
would be ruined if it did not, simply as a science of thought, contain all forms of
thought.
So, the model fails because the nature of the whole is distinguished from
the natures of the parts, such that it cannot fully explain them. The failure of the
model lies again in the parochialism that results from its application: my forms
of thought are merely mine, and I cannot exclude the idea and equal legitimacy
of other, different forms of thought that I do not possess. Of course, I cannot
think of these other forms of thought (for if I could, then they would be available
to me, which means they would be mine). But, on this view, that reflects my inability, and the same cognitive instability articulated in the previous section results.17
Despite its failure as an adequate model, we need to retain certain features
of it in an account of speculative knowledge. In particular, we need to retain the
idea that the stages are dependent upon the whole. But we have to reject the externality of the parts from the whole—in particular, we have to abandon the idea
that the whole does not suffice to explain the parts.18
On the organic unity model, identifying something as one stage rather than
another is like identifying something as the heart and not the liver. Properly
speaking, however, speculative knowledge does not advance from the part to the
whole, for there is no nature to the part different from the nature of the whole,
nor is there a nature to the whole that is different from the nature of the part.
That is, one stage is not like the heart while the next stage is like the liver; ra17
The failure of the organic unity model does not lie in the fact that, according to it, there
could be heretofore undiscovered forms of thought. Hegel’s understanding of philosophy
involves some appeal to development and philosophical progress. As such, it might well
involve the idea of a development in the form of thought itself. I neither want to rule that
out nor endorse it. With respect to such a development, were it to be possible for Hegel,
my point would be that it must be fully explained by the very idea of thought; it must not
admit the possibility of other developments. (Thanks again to an anonymous reviewer for
pressing me to be clearer about this.)
18
Interestingly, McTaggart foreshadows this idea when he invokes the organic unity
model, because he claims that the relation of the parts to the whole in the Logic is “still
more close and intimate” than that found in organism (McTaggart 1896: §122). His elaboration on this claim gives up on the idea of parts, however. He recognizes that the parts
are crucial in Hegel’s account, but cannot see how that can be. The result is an account of
speculative knowledge on which there is really no kind of multiplicity that remains within the whole (a monistic understanding of Hegel’s absolute).
Andrew Werner
156
ther, each stage is the whole, even and precisely in its difference from the other
stage. (Of course, at this point it might be best to abandon talk of “part” and
“whole”, as the conditions for their application seem to have fallen away.)
The inadequacy of the organic unity model comes out fairly explicitly at
one point when Hegel is describing the special character of the progression of
the Logic. Unlike other conceptual progressions (for instance, unlike the conceptual progressions we effect when engaged in biology), in the Logic there can be
no appeal to anything external to the starting point or whole. That is true even
though the progression involves a kind of division, or multiplicity. As Hegel puts
it, “the division must hang together with the concept or much more lie in it itself.
The concept is not undetermined, but rather determined in it itself” (5.56/21.44).
So, in the Logic, the determinations—the different forms of thought—must not
come from “elsewhere” (5.56/21.44). They must rather already lie in the concept—the nature of thought in general—being further determined. That is, jettisoning the appeal to life, we have to say that the principle that unites the forms
of thought (their soul) is the same principle that differentiates them (their matter). That is the apparently boggling character of speculative knowledge. Perhaps we can make sense of that. Indeed, I think we can. But here I have only
tried to argue that we cannot hope to make sense of that unless we carefully note
the ways in which speculative knowledge is unlike life.
5. Conclusion
In this essay, I have explained why and how the appeal to the organic falls short
as a model for thinking about speculative knowledge (“the dialectical method”).
Both the organic growth model and the organic unity model fail in that they require an appeal to something outside of the organism as part of the ground for
the growth and as part of the ground of the unity. Absent the right environment,
an organism cannot grow, and an organism does not by itself suffice to explain
the presence of the right environment. Absent some particular manner in which
it performs its characteristic activities, an organism cannot live, and the nature
of the organism does not by itself suffice to explain that manner (the organs). In
each case, the appeal to something external which the organism depends on and
does not fully ground is fine for the case of life, but if applied to the forms of
thought renders those forms parochial. Hegel, I have further argued, was aware
of the respect in which each organic model falls short of providing an adequate
model for speculative knowledge. He saw that organic models require an appeal
to something not fully provided for by the organism, and that no such appeal
can be made within speculative knowledge.19
References
Aristotle 1984, Complete Works of Aristotle, Vols. 1-2, Barnes, J. (ed.), Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
19
For helpful comments on earlier drafts of this essay, I would like to thank Robert Pippin, Paul Franks, Wolfram Gobsch, the audience at the conference on German Classical
Philosophy and Naturalism at Georgetown University, and the two anonymous reviewers for this journal.
Some Limits to Hegel’s Appeal to Life
157
Beiser, F. 2005, Hegel, New York: Routledge.
Conant, J. 2004, “Varieties of Skepticism”, in Wittgenstein and Skepticism, McManus,
D. (ed.). New York: Routledge, 97-136.
Hegel, G.F.W. 1968- , Gesammelte Werke, Jaeschke, W. (hrsg.), Hamburg: Felix
Meiner.
Hegel, G.F.W. 1969, Werke in zwanzig Bänden, Moldenhauer, E. und Michel, K.M.
(hrsg.), Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Kant, I. 2000, Critique of the Power of Judgment, trans. P. Guyer and E. Mathews,
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Martin, C.G. 2012, Ontologie der Selbstbestimmung, Tübingen: Morh Siebeck.
McTaggart, J.M.E. 1896, Studies in Hegelian Dialectic, New York: Cambridge University Press.
Ng, K. 2013, “Life, Self-Consciousness, Negativity”, in The Freedom of Life, Khurana, T. (ed.), Berlin: August Verlag, 33-68.
Ng, K. 2016, “Life and Mind in Hegel’s Logic and Subjective Spirit”, Hegel Bulletin,
39, 1, 23-44.
Pippin, R. 1989, Hegel’s Idealism, New York: Cambridge University Press.
Rödl, S. 2007, Self-Consciousness, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Rödl, S. 2018, Self-Consciousness and Objectivity, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Advisory Board
SIFA former Presidents
Eugenio Lecaldano (Roma Uno University), Paolo Parrini (University of
Firenze), Diego Marconi (University of Torino), Rosaria Egidi (Roma Tre
University), Eva Picardi (University of Bologna), Carlo Penco (University of
Genova), Michele Di Francesco (IUSS), Andrea Bottani (University of
Bergamo), Pierdaniele Giaretta (University of Padova), Mario De Caro
(Roma Tre University), Simone Gozzano (University of L’Aquila), Carla
Bagnoli (University of Modena and Reggio Emilia), Elisabetta Galeotti
(University of Piemonte Orientale)
SIFA charter members
Luigi Ferrajoli (Roma Tre University), Paolo Leonardi (University of
Bologna), Marco Santambrogio (University of Parma), Vittorio Villa
(University of Palermo), Gaetano Carcaterra (Roma Uno University)
Robert Audi (University of Notre Dame), Michael Beaney (University of
York), Akeel Bilgrami (Columbia University), Manuel Garcia Carpintero
(University of Barcelona), José Diez (University of Barcelona), Pascal Engel
(EHESS Paris and University of Geneva), Susan Feagin (Temple University),
Pieranna Garavaso (University of Minnesota, Morris), Christopher Hill
(Brown University), Carl Hoefer (University of Barcelona), Paul Horwich
(New York University), Christopher Hughes (King’s College London), Pierre
Jacob (Institut Jean Nicod), Kevin Mulligan (University of Genève),
Gabriella Pigozzi (Université Paris-Dauphine), Stefano Predelli (University
of Nottingham), François Recanati (Institut Jean Nicod), Connie Rosati
(University of Arizona), Sarah Sawyer (University of Sussex), Frederick
Schauer (University of Virginia), Mark Textor (King’s College London),
Achille Varzi (Columbia University), Wojciech Żełaniec (University of Gdańsk)