Must Sociology Be Qualitative?
EVAN FALES
Department of Philosophy
University of Iowa
ABSTRACT
This article addresses the question of whether sociology can in principle
become a quantitative science. I distinguish several senses in which a
contrast between quantitative and qualitative science might be understood.
I focus on the central--and traditional--sense: can sociology become a
nomological science, in the way physics is? I argue that it cannot, on the
ontological ground that the determinants of human actions cannot be
analyzed in purely causal terms. In the article I try to characterize this
difference.
Is there a distinction in method between quantitative and
qualitative sociology? If so, which kind is better? Philosophers
and sociologists have debated these questions for a long time;
and among philosophers, at least, they are by no means
resolved. I wish to examine the alleged distinction and some
of its implications. These, I shall argue, embrace not merely
methodological issues but also commitments about the
nature of society. One might say that each method
presupposes a distinct (however vaguely articulated)
ontology; and that these ontologies are antagonistic.
There is, I think, an important element of truth in this
thesis. However, the structure of the issue in question is by no
means simple. An effort to sort out what might be meant by
"quantitative" methods in sociology as contrasted with
"qualitative" ones reveals no neat correspondence between
methodology and ontology, that is, between the choice of
proper techniques of study and our conception of the subject
matter of that study. For one thing, there are different senses
in which a method, or the data collected by that method, can
Requests for reprints should be sent to Evan Fales, Department of Philosophy,
University of Iowa, Iowa City, Iowa 52242.
Qualitative Sociology, Vol. 5(2), Summer 1982
0162-0436/82/1400-0089502. 75
89
© 1982Human Sciences Press
90
QUALITATIVE SOCIOLOGY
be said to be quantitative or qualitative. For another, data,
whether quantitative or qualitative in form, can
characteristically be interpreted from the perspective of any
of the rival ontologies.
This is not to say, however, that there are no essential
differences in ontology and methodology. On the contrary, I
believe it is crucial to sort out these differences in order to
gain a clear view of what is really at stake, and to avoid ways
of framing the issues which deflect attention from the
fundamental problems. The central purpose of this article
therefore is to collect these issues in a way which makes the
problems visible.
Since both quantitative and qualitative measurements in a
science are measurements of the properties of items falling
within the domain of that science, it will be appropriate to
begin by considering what sorts of distinctions in general
might be intended by contrastive uses of "qualitative" and
"quantitative," Which, if any, of these distinctions is such
that some properties are qualitative, and not quantitative,
and vice versa?
On one sense of "qualitative," a measurement or datum is
qualitative if it is given as a rough estimate rather than
precisely specified. But clearly, a qualitative measurement in
this sense is in no way incompatible with more precise
specification, and the distinction mentioned is hardly relevant
to sociology except insofar as many sociologically important
properties (including numerically specifiable ones) can at best
be estimated roughly.
Secondly, the qualitative/quantitative distinction is
sometimes associated with a distinction between subjective
sensations and the causally responsible objective properties.
However, sociologists are concerned with objective facts, so
this distinction will hardly be of use to us.
A more interesting distinction may be allowed between
properties which have a phenomenologically qualitative
character in contrast to those which exhibit a
phenomenologically quantitative character. It is plausible to
say that properties such as distance, duration, and
temperature, for example, exhibit themselves to us, however
vaguely, as quantities; whereas beauty and odor do not. It is
also plausible to argue that a great many sociologically
important properties do not present themselves to us as
MUST SOCIOLOGY BE QUALITATIVE?
91
having quantitative character. I believe there is merit in
attending to this distinction, but I also believe that its
ultimate methodological significance remains in doubt so
long as (a) the distinction is not a clear one, and (b) the
ultimate nonspecifiability of sociologically relevant
properties, such as people's emotional characteristics,
remains in doubt.
But there is in any case a further sense that might be
attached to the qualitative/quantitative distinction, and it is
this sense which has historically played the most important
role in methodological disputes in sociology. One might,
among those properties which can be precisely specified, and
in particular among those which can be assigned a position in
a metric ordering, look for systematic correlations. The
importance of such correlations is, of course, as signposts for
the existence of laws, in particular, laws associating
numerically specifiable ranges of determinate properties in a
mathematically formalizable way. The discovery of such laws
is, on one view, the paradigm mark of any mature science, a
prerequisite for both full explanation and prediction. Here we
approach the central issue of this article: is the existence of a
systematic correlation between ranges of properties a
necessary and sufficient condition for justified assertion of a
sociological law--in the sense in which this would be the
case, pace problems about induction--in the physical
sciences? For, if so, then a primary task for sociology would
be to determine whether such correlations exist, though this
may be a far from straightforward task if, as one would
expect, the underlying laws (perhaps the laws of physics) are
related to sociological variables only via some tremendously
complicated reduction. But it will be felt by most practicing
sociologists, I am sure, that the remoteness of the possibility
of completing this task, if that is its nature, is ameliorated by
(a) the fact that the existence of some fairly accessible surface
correlations may be taken as strong evidence for the
existence of underlying laws, and (b) the fact that knowing
what is "in principle" possible has a tremendous effect on the
nature of our conception of the subject matter, and hence of
the nature of the study of it, however unknown the details. I
shall call the claim that every event which occurs in a system
is governed ultimately by causal laws the thesis of homological depth.
92
QUALITATIVE SOCIOLOGY
Now the conviction that laws underlie the pattern of events
that constitute the history of human affairs does not need to
be sustained by evidence in the form of discoverable
regularities at the level of description which the sociologist
ordinarily uses. Any "complete" set of sociological laws
would obviously have to encompass the description of nonsocial events and properties which influence that history, in
addition to making use of distinctively social predicates, as
has often been observed. For we have no reason to expect, in
a highly complex system which is neither closed under
description in purely sociological terms, nor closed in the
physicist's sense of immunity to external forces, that
exception-free regularities will exist which will enable the
sociologist to formulate laws of a distinctively sociological
character. Similarly, there are no laws which govern all the
turbulences and life cycles in a farm pond "as such." In the
latter case, our conviction is in no way dampened that general
laws govern every event which transpires in the pond.
On the other hand, if there are discoverable patterns in a
complex system, even of an imprecise sort, this fact will
strongly reinforce our conviction that genuine laws lurk
within the woodwork. Such patterns exist within the life of a
pond, and they are a stock in trade among social scientists
and historians. The discovery of such patterns may serve a
number of purposes, of which more will be said presently. But
other purposes aside, patterns of an exact or of a statistical
nature are surely strong evidence favoring the thesis of
nomological depth. Mill (1959), for example, argues that
It is found that when one of the features of a society is in a particular
state, a state of many other features, more or less precisely
determinate, always or usually coexists with it.
But the uniformities of co-existence obtaining among phenomena
which are effects of causes, must (as we have so often observed) be
corollaries from the laws of causation by which these phenomena are
really determined. The mutual correlation between the different
elements of each state of society is, therefore, a derivative law,
resulting from the laws which regulate the succession between one
state of society and another; for the proximate cause of every state of
society is the state of society immediately preceding it.
Mill is arguing here in particular that uniformities of
coexistence entail the existence of laws of succession, from
MUST SOCIOLOGY BE QUALITATIVE?
93
which they derive; but we may more generally suppose that
regularities, whether of coexistence or of succession, are a
clue to the existence of underlying laws of much greater,
indeed complete, precision.
Let us momentarily consider more exactly why surface
regularities in a complex system sustain an inference to
nomoiogical depth, whereas the converse inference is not
permissible. This may be understood in terms of the number
of degrees of freedom assignable to a system. A priori, the
number of possible degrees of freedom for a complex system
is enormous. Were, therefore, a regular pattern in the activity
of such a system to be found, the probability that that
regularity was the product of random variation in the
properties of the system or its parts would surely be
miniscule. We can be quite sure that it is only because of
some underlying constraints upon the system (or its parts) that
such regularities appear. However, the converse is not
generally true; as witness the turbulence in a farm pond or the
shapes of clouds. Here, the degrees of freedom of the system
are so large in spite of the universal constraints operating
upon these systems at the microscopic level, that precise
repetition of earlier states of the system must be exceedingly
rare. And this argument applies even in the special case of a
system which is a closed, deterministic one in which every
earlier state is a nomologically sufficient one for the states
which succeed it. So, we have an apparently asymmetric
situation: surface order (even rough order) counts as strong
evidence for nomological depth; surface "chaos" does not
militate against it.
Nevertheless, it will be the burden of this article to try to
show that Mill was wrong, that the kind of statistical surface
order which quantitative techniques in sociology are so good
at uncovering does not imply the thesis of nomological depth.
This perhaps surprising denial will, however, be shown not to
be equivalent to the claim that statistical regularities are
merely fortuitous, nor to the claim that there are no
underlying constraints operating upon social systems. It will
perhaps be evident that in order to make good the above
assertions, to thread our way between nomological depth on
the one hand and randomness on the other, we shall have to
introduce a distinction, indeed, an ontological distinction,
between nomological constraints strictly speaking on the one
hand, and some other form of constraint on the other. In this
94
QUALITATIVE SOCIOLOGY
way we may vindicate the distinctive place of qualitative
methods, properly understood, in the construction of a
science of society, without, at the same time, undermining the
possibility of such a science by denying one of the
preconditions of any science, namely, the existence of some
form of order in its domain.
The question before us is: are there regulative principles
which properly fall within the domain of sociological inquiry,
which contribute to the regularities found in social systems
(and hence must be appealed to by way of explaining those
regularities), but which are not causal laws in the physicist's
strict sense? If there are, then we may wish to appropriate the
term "qualitative sociology" to designate the study of these
principles, although, as we shall see, it is quite misleading to
describe these principles as qualitative, by way of providing
contrast with the allegedly quantitative nomological
principles of the hard sciences, since both may lead to
functional relationships expressible in mathematical terms.
I believe that there is a critical, ontologically grounded
distinction to be made between two principles of order and
explanations which appeal to them. It is a distinction which
divides the human sciences from the science of inanimate
matter. It is, indeed, the familiar but controversial distinction
between activity which is governed by causes (strictly
speaking) and that governed by reasons. I shall have to
summarize--all too briefly--some of the grounds for holding
that this alleged distinction is not ultimately genuine, and
then my contrary grounds for holding that it is. It will finally
be necessary to consider the part played by reason and
individual action based upon reasons in the explanation of
social phenomena.
To prevent confusion, an initial linguistic observation is in
order. Both the word "cause" and the word "reason" are used
with considerable latitude by speakers of English, and these
usages overlap in such a way as to mask the distinction I wish
to mark with my own contrastive use of these terms. I shall
therefore use "cause" restrictively to apply to physical
causation, leaving it an open question whether human actions
are physically caused.
Indeed, there are a number of reasons for holding (as for
instance Donald Da~idson (1963, 1979) does) that the relation
which binds together the members of the sequence of events
MUST SOCIOLOGY BE QUALITATIVE?
95
leading from the onset of a man's deliberations to the overt
performance of the action which we think of as the product
of that deliberation, is causal. It seems evident, first of all,
that the connections between the events in such a sequence
are regular and nonaccidental. If, secondly, we have had
some experience of human nature, and we know a man's
motives, we can indeed predict his actions with some
confidence. But thirdly, although such predictions sometimes
misfire, predictions in the physical sciences also misfire
sometimes, and the exceptional cases are handled in a
formally similar manner. When a prediction misfires in
physics, we look for extraneous forces which were not
included among our initial boundary conditions; when our
action-predictions fail, we characteristically search for
additional (sometimes hidden) motives or beliefs held by the
actor. Thus in both cases the end result is seen as the product
of some (perhaps difficult to specify) totality of interacting
precedent events. Finally, the connection between produced
event and producing event(s) is in neither case one of logical
necessity, though it is nonaccidental. ~ We may, succumbing
to a rather barbarous expression, describe these relations as
defeasibly determinative. By this I mean that the antecedent
events regularly determine that a consequent event of a given
kind shall follow, other things being equal. The "other things"
which must be "equal" cannot in practice be specified, but
we are of the conviction that if a consequent event of the
expected kind does not follow, then it is always proper to seek
an explanation in terms of some additional intervening
factor(s). For we are convinced that there must be some such
explanation.
These formal considerations weigh heavily in favor of
counting people's deliberations as the cause of their action;
and indeed there is a common and suitably broad sense of
"cause" which implies no more than this. On that usage,
people's motives, desires, and beliefs do count as causes of
their actions (at least their deliberate actions) insofar as they
enter into their deliberations. Of course the fact that such a
broad category of causation exists, as defined by the abovementioned formal criteria, in no way implies that there are no
further crucial ontological distinctions to be made between
the relations which fall within it. It is a common but fatal
mistake to pass directly from the fact that deliberation
96
QUALITATIVE SOCIOLOGY
produces or causes action in this broad sense, to the
conclusion that the causation of deliberate action is to be
conceived as of the same kind as the mechanical causation of
the physicist. But this inference requires an additional, and
dubious, premise: that there is only one kind of relation which
is defeasibly determinative, and that that relation is the
relation of mechanical causation.
There is a particularly crude version of this mechanistic
model of action which once had some appeal: according to it,
felt desires were to be viewed quite straightforwardly as
mechanical pushes and tugs upon the organism's body; the
animal moves in the direction of the strongest pull. This
picture is clearly hopeless. ~ Hence the more sophisticated
strategies of reductive materialism and of epiphenomenalism.
According to these, all the complex events of mental life are
identical to or nomologically dependent upon the causally
determined sequence of events transpiring in our neural
systems. I shall not attempt to explore the multitude of issues
which these strategies raise. The relevant point here is that
desires and motives, though not phenomenologically
presented to us as spatially directed tugs and pushes, are on
these strategies to be explained in terms of physical forces
operating at the more subtle and hidden level of physiology.
Now one would be hard pressed to deny that physiological
mechanisms are explainable in physicalistic terms, and
equally hard pressed to deny that these mechanisms are
intimately related to our mental lives. Unfortunately the
question of just what this relation may be is one which I shall
also have to set aside, if only for reasons of space. We must at
the same time admit that so long as it remains unresolved, a
crucial element in our understanding of human action is
missing.
This fact must not, however, prevent us from asking
whether there are modes of explaining and understanding
human action which rest upon a firm empirical foundation
even though we may lack an answer to the above question. I
say modes of understanding because human action is multifarious in character. There are ramified distinctions between
deliberate action, voluntary action, involuntary action, acting
from habit, impulsive action, and so on. There is a whole
panoply of characterizations bearing upon explanation which
the psychologist and social scientist may have to be sensitive
MUST SOCIOLOGY BE QUALITATIVE?
97
to. This discussion will focus on just the crucial case of
actions which result from conscious and deliberate choice.
I believe that the most centrally interesting feature of the
conceptual framework in terms of which we characteristically
understand deliberate choice is that this framework entails
that such choices are free. For the point of deliberation is
precisely to make a choice between what initially are or are
believed to be genuine alternative courses of action. If the
performance of an action were known by an agent to be
causally impossible for him, then that action could not enter
his deliberations as a viable option; if all actions but one were
known to be causally impossible (and that action were known
to be causally necessary) then the point of deliberating would
be entirely lost. And yet this conception of free will as action
resulting from deliberation is quite compatible with the facts
that (a) the desires and beliefs which form the "input" to an
agent's deliberation may be antecedently determined by
causally governed events, (b) these inputs in some sense determine the outcome of the deliberations (else the deliberations
would be pointless for a different reason), and (c) the agent
must have control over his actions at least to the extent of
being able to determine them on the basis of (the outcome of)
his deliberations. Some philosophers have actually used (c) to
argue that the truth of determinism is a necesary condition for
the exercise of free will (Hobart, 1934). But this does not
follow. The crucial question is whether the kind of
determination mentioned in (b) is correctly described as
causal determination, in the strict sense, and as I see it, it is
not.
To argue this claim, it is necessary to become somewhat
clear about what causal determination is, clear enough so
that we can see whether we are familiar with any kind(s) of
determination which is not of that sort. The dominant
traditional way of understanding causation has been the
Humean one in terms of constant conjunction. The glaring
defect of this analysis is that it cannot capture the idea of the
necessitation of the effect by its cause. In fact, the tradition
rejects this idea .-- incoherent, attempting often to replace it
with the notion of natural law--the latter so understood,
allegedly, as not to covertly import any notion of causal
necessity. 3 According to this picture, we cannot explain the
occurrence of any event by appeal to its cause unless we have
98
QUALITATIVE SOCIOLOGY
adequate grounds for believing there to exist some universal
law or laws which, conjointly with the statement that a
preceding event of a certain type occurred (the "cause"),
entail the occurrence of the event to be explained. As a model
for the explanation of human actions, this must come under
suspicion for two reasons: (1) there do not seem to be many (if
any) true universal generalizations connecting human agents'
desires and beliefs to consequent actions, and (2) it is clearly
not the case that in order to understand one's own actions
one (in general) needs to know anything at all about universal
generalizations regarding human psychology. The
philosophical literature has been primarily concerned with
the first objection. But I wish to pursue the second one, which
seems to me to be more decisive. In fact this second point will
lead one directly to seeing the difference between causal
determination and determination by reasons.
The fact is that, in order to understand a conscious and
deliberate action of my own, I need to have nothing over and
above the very understanding of my situation and
deliberation which led to my decision to act in that way in the
first place. 4 Retrospective reflection may of course shed some
new light on my action, but it need not. The crucial mode of
understanding is the very understanding by virtue of which I
was able to deliberate and choose as 1 did. And for me to
understand someone else's deliberate action is for me to
engage in a similar kind of understanding of those
deliberations which were performed by him. This, I take it, is
what Weber had in mind when he spoke of Verstehen, and it is
what Collingwood (1946) meant by construing historical
understanding as a kind of (mental) reenactment.
Both Weber and Collingwood were right, I believe, in
insisting upon the superfluity of any knowledge of universal
laws in sociology. 5 But interestingly enough, one might, if one
is willing to reject the Humean analysis of causation, hold a
similar view with respect to physical causation. Not that
causal relations do not imply the existence of universal laws
[pace Anscombe, 1975), but that knowledge of these laws
need not be a precondition of our knowing of the existence of
causal relations. For if one held that the existence of a causal
relation can be ascertained in some single instances of
causation (i.e., by direct perception) then one could maintain
that knowledge of the causal explanation of an event in such
MUST SOCIOLOGY BE QUALITATIVE?
99
instances was independent of the kind of repetitive evidence
required to inductively establish the existence of a law.
Now the relevant point is that it is open to someone who
holds such a view of causation to argue that knowledge of
psychological laws is not a prerequisite to causal
explanations of human behavior because precisely in those
cases where (at least our own) actions are determined by
desires and beliefs via deliberation and "choice," we are
confronted with a causal relation which we are able to
perceive "directly." Since we are in our own case directly
acquainted with the causal relation, and can by analogy infer
its existence in other rational agents, we do not need to
supply our understanding with whatever general law(s) might
be entailed. And yet, so the argument would go, the perceived
determination of our actions clearly is causal. Or is it?
I should agree that we are directly acquainted, in our own
case, with the "connection" between input and choice in
conscious deliberation; we are acquainted with the way in
which our reasons incline us or determine our choice. But to
see whether this "way" should be assimilated to physical
causation, we shall have to examine it more closely.
The first essential point is that the "mechanism" of
deliberation hinges upon the propositional content of the
premises which go into that stretch of ratiocination. More
explicitly, the direction of our reasoning is determined by the
logical relations between the propositions which are the
objects of our thought. It might be supposed, therefore, that
the kind of determination involved in (rational) deliberation is
that of logical necessitation or validity--the only species of
necessity recognized by Hume. But this is surely incorrect.
The propositions in question will indeed enter into logical
relationships, independently of whether ! entertain them and
recognize those relationships or not. But my having
entertained the premises of an argument in no way makes it
logically necessary that I shall arrive at and accept a correct
conclusion (I might, for example, be killed beforehand). It is
this temporally datable event of reaching a conclusion which
is to be explained. It seems once again, therefore, that we
should invoke a (defeasible) nomological relation between
my entertainment of premises and my acceptance of a
conclusion. Nevertheless, I think this would be a mistake, for
the defeasib[e determination in question is neither logical nor
100
QUALITATIVE SOCIOLOGY
nomological. The above appeal to the propositional content
of thoughts does, however, contain a crucial insight.
This crucial insight concerns the intrinsically intentional
character of thought--and in our case, of deliberation. To
understand one's own deliberations or someone else's, it
would not be enough to know of some universal law
connecting the input with the conclusion reached. For such a
law could be imagined to connect any input with any
conclusion, without damage (if it were true) to its explanatory
force. The explanatory burden of a law is carried by its
universality, not by the propositional content of input and
conclusion, where these are the relata. But it is precisely in
terms of the intentional objects of our thoughts, the
propositions that are thought, that we understand the passing
from input to conclusion. This passage is not logically
necessary, as the making of mistakes in reasoning shows, but
it must be understood in terms of a recognition of logical
relations. This r e c o g n i t i o n
is the intrinsic, and
phenomenologically accessible, feature of reasoning which
drives it non-randomly forward. It is not like physical
causation?
Because reasoning relies upon the recognition of logical
relations between its objects, it is appropriate to apply to it a
whole panoply of normative terms which cannot be applied
to causally produced phenomena. We speak of a conclusion,
but not an effect, as correct or incorrect; we speak of
reasoning, but not causation as good or bad, valid or invalid.
On the Humean account, we never have any experience of
causal necessitation. This by itself would, if true, be sufficient
to distinguish causal relations from the defeasibly
determinative process of deliberation if, as I maintain, we are
directly acquainted with that. However, I am not convinced
by the Humean position. I shall not of course launch a fullscale siege upon it here. But I think I can point, as other
philosophers have (Mace, Stout, Ewing, 1935), to that element
of direct experience which seems to me to be constitutive of
our phenomenal awareness of causation. It is our experience
of physical force upon ourselves. That experience seems to
me to bear a number of features which together yield the
defeasibly determinative character of causal relations. The
central feature, perhaps, is the vectorial character of our
experience of force: it has a direction in space, and a
magnitude. These characteristics are inextricably bound to
MUST SOCIOLOGY BE QUALITATIVE?
101
our apprehension of forces as determining movement. The
effects of forces are not spatially random but directed in the
direction of the forces themselves. The magnitude of a force
is similarly connected to the magnitude of the effect. This is
not, I should maintain, the result of an induction from
repeated experience of force. But a further feature of felt
forces is crucial to our account--namely the property they
have (which we can directly experience) of adding together in
accordance with a vector algebra, if simultaneously appliedF
It is this which tallies with the defeasibility of causal laws. For
a force-law which relates a force to its effect presumes that,
as we say, "other things are equal," that is, that there are no
other forces unaccounted for in the initial conditions. But any
actual application of such a law is generally subject to the
possibility that additional forces may be present, and will
have to be added in. It is from felt forces on our bodies, I
suspect, that we extrapolate to physical interactions at large.
We can now state the point of this digression into the
phenomenological character of our experiences of certain
singular causal relations. It is simply that these experiences
display a completely different phenomenological character
from our experience of the way reasons determine action. In
the end, we perhaps cannot really describe either kind of
experience but must simply point to it. But I think it is enough
to show that our understanding of the experience of physical
force is closely linked to the notion of spatial vectors,
whereas our experience of deliberation is not associated with
this but with the notion of logical relations obtaining between
the propositions contemplated. These, then, are my reasons
for maintaining that causation and reasoning, while both
species of defeasible determination, are distinct.
It will by now seem that we have strayed very far from the
everyday concerns of the working sociologist. Not so, as I
hope to show in some brief concluding remarks. We may take
as our point of departure a suggestion made by Rescher and
Joynt (196t) that, although there may be no universal laws of
human history, we can expect to find laws which apply
restrictively to given cultures or societies. Essentially the idea
is, when in Rome, Romans do as the Romans do. More
formally, we should look for laws of the form:
Any member of culture C who finds himself in situation S will do A.
102
QUALITATIVE SOCIOLOGY
Or, more realistically, for statistical or probabilistic laws of
the form:
If x is a member of C and in situation S, then the chances are P that he
will do A,
It seems entirely reasonable to suppose that the sociologist
might discover such statistical generalizations as these.
Indeed Joynt and Rescher (1959) suggest that the statutory
laws of a society will produce such regularities. I can see no
reason why such statistical regularities might not be of the
greatest interest in informing us of the character of a society
which is under study. In many cases displaying data in some
well-chosen statistical form may make relationships leap to
the eye which would otherwise not have been apparent.
But the question before us is whether, as Mill (1959)
thought, the existence of such society-relative statistical
regularities can be taken as evidence for underlying causal
laws. As will perhaps be clear by now, I think it cannot, or not
always. Such regularities are indeed evidence for something.
They are evidence for the existence of processes underlying
the course of social events, processes which are not purely
random, which are, in a word, defeasibly determinate. But as
we have seen, this is not sufficient to establish the existence
of causal laws. For as we have seen, there is at least one other
candidate for such a defeasibly determinative relation, and it
is clear that this alternative must be relevant to the
explanation of most social statistics. 8 There is no space here
to discuss the interesting question whether human rationality
and strictly causal laws are together sufficient to explain all
the phenomena met within history and sociology. But clearly
both these kinds of underlying mechanisms are at least
relevant.
Because people's reasons determine, in a defeasible way,
what their actions will be, we can, knowing their reasons (and
their character), forecast their actions with a fair, often very
high, degree of probability. Conversely, it is precisely this relation between reason and action which enables us to explain
actions by appeal to reasons. Given a statistically large
sample of people with similar reasons, this explains why we
may expect statistical uniformity in their behavior, provided
MUST SOCIOLOGY BE QUALITATIVE?
103
that other relevant variables (character, cultural traditions,
intelligence, etc.) are either held fixed or suitably randomized
within their respective ranges. An obvious example which satisfies these conditions is the sort of case appealed to by Joynt
and Rescher (1959): the behavior of a nation's citizens vis'a vis
its laws. Assuming cultural uniformity, we have a situation in
which that variable is held fixed, intelligence and intrinsic
temperament are averaged over, the risks of detection and
sanctions imposed by the legal system provide reasons
against law-breaking, and whatever gains are to be had from
illegal activity provide incentive for it. To the extent that risks
outweigh benefits, we may expect people to be reasonably
law abiding--provided that both the risks and benefits considered are sufficiently obvious. The same reasoning applies
to the sorts of statistics Mill cites in support of his historical
determinism. The number of murders, suicides, and marriages
each year (assuming a constant population) will all be predictably influenced by the way in which the social climate
imposes or tends to impose incentives and stumbling-blocks
with respect to the acts in question~ But it is (in most cases) a
chain of reasoning, I maintain, which leads from the imposed
situation a person finds himself confronted with to action. In
this sense, his actions, if deliberate, are not caused, though
they can contribute to statistical regularities.
Thus, if by qualitative sociology we mean the study of
those aspects of social phenomena which are the distinctive
products of human consciousness and thought, then I believe
we can sustain the claim that social science requires distinctive methods of investigation, and a mode of understanding
not found in the physical sciences. But this is in no way
incompatible with the use of statistical or other techniques
which make use of mathematical analysis. Insofar as they are
applied to human consciousness and its products, the information these techniques produce is amenable to being understood and explained in terms of the categories of Verstehen.
This means, if I am right, that it is the proper business of
sociology to uncover the reasons why people think and act as
they do, insofar as this is relevant to the formation and
perpetuation of social arrangements. Statistical uniformities
can reveal much about such patterns of reasoning (among
other things) and the extent of their influence. No single
agent's reasoning will encompass the entire range of circum-
104
QUALITATIVE SOCIOLOGY
stances relevant to a given problem requiring social action, so
much that occurs will involve factors unknown to him or to
anyone and beyond control. Sociology can make us more
aware of such factors, but it cannot hope to ultimately
capture its subject matter in a net of laws. Nevertheless, this
does not mean that sociology must forfeit the project of
explaining what goes on, nor that of forecasting the future.
My conclusion is simple. It is that qualitative sociology (in
the last relevant sense distinguished at the outset) and statistics (properly understood) can live together peacefully, even
happily ever after.
NOTES
~Some philosophers, e.g., A.I. Melden (1961) have argued that the connection does
involve logical necessity, since an action cannot be relevantly identified except in
terms of the prior intentions of the actor. Was it a left-turn signal? Or merely a
pointing to a butterfly? A physical description of the motion of the arm does not
suffice to determine which. Nevertheless, there is no logical contradiction involved in
asserting that A intended to do (an action of type) X and that A did not do X. For it is
possible--not merely logically but physically possible--to have the intention but fail
to do X. One might {accidently) do Y instead. Or one might fail to perform any action
as a result of one's intention (a bullet in the brain might intervene). So intending to do
X is neither a necessary nor a sufficient condition of someone's doing X.
2Balaam's ass, as the facetious medieval story had it, starved to death when placed
midway between two equally succulent bales of hay. By extension, if he had been
placed elsewhere on the perpendicular bisector of the line connecting the bales, he
would have become a damped harmonic oscillator, moving along that perpendicular
and expiring in the same spot as before.
3There is some consensus now among philosophers that no analysis yet offered of
the concept of a law of nature which abjures the notion of nomological necessity has
been successful.
~Thus the knowledge that my behavior conforms to some universal behavior
pattern is immaterial to personal understanding of my action. This is somewhat
imprecise. One could, for example, ask about the physical details of the process
whereby the decision to act is translated into action--i.e, into bodily movement. But
to understand the making of the decision itself we need nothing more than is alleged,
at least in unproblematic cases not involving irrationality or other abberration,
SWeber's (1977) central argument for the distinction between Verstehen and the
causal description of nature is, however, a very bad one in my opinion. Weber's
argument is based upon the idea that any concrete event or event sequence is
infinitely complex, that no finite description can exhaust all of its features. Laws,
however, relate events only insofar as the,,, satisfy some finite characterization, and
hence laws inevitably involve abstracting away from full concreteness. Weber sees
the method of Verstehen as moving toward grasping particular event-sequences in
human affairs in their full concreteness, which involves a movement away from
abstraction. This is correct in its denial that repetition is the key to understanding
human affairs. But the causal determinist can and would easily deny that causal laws
fall short of determining concrete events, no matter how wide in complexity. It is just
a matter of finding all the constituent forces and component particulars relevant to
answering any question that might be asked about a system.
MUST SOCIOLOGY BE QUALITATIVE?
105
6This object-directedness of thought explains why, in my own case, I will not
appeal, as I might in explaining another's action, to the contingent fact that I had
such and such thoughts. Rather, in explaining {and justifying) my action, I point to the
content of the propositions themselves. Someone who did not understand these
propositions and their logical relations would fail to understand my action as I
understand it, whether he possessed knowledge of some suitable laws or not.
70f course sophisticated inferences are required to obtain the general
mathematical form of this algebra.
~Which is, of course, not to deny that causal necessities may also be relevant. If
there are certain regularities in the behavior of people in times of famine, these will
inevitably require, as part of their explanation, those causal laws in accordance with
which lack of food leads (statistically) to feelings of hunger, poor health, and
enervation. But human rationality (and irrationality) will also play a role.
REFERENCES
Anscombe, G.E.M.
1975 "Causality and determination." Pp. 63-81 in E. Sosa (ed.), Causation and
Conditionals. New York: Oxford University Press.
CoIlingwood, R.G.
1946 The Idea of History. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Davidson, D.
1963 "Actions, reasons and causes." Journal of Philosophy 60:685-700.
1979 "Mental events.*' Pp. 218-238 in T. Honderich and M. Burnyeat (eds.),
Philosophy As It Is. New York: Penguin.
Hobart, R.B,
1934 "Free will as involving determination and inconceivable without." Mind
63; 1-27,
Joynt, C.B. and N. Rescher
1959 "On explanation in history." Mind 68:383-87.
Mace, C.A,, G.F. Stout, A.C. Ewing
1935 "Mechanical and teleological causation." Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society. Supp. Vol. 14:22-82.
Melden, A.I,
1961 Free Action. New York: Humanities Press.
Mill, j.S.
1959 "A System of logic." Pp. 85-86 in P. Gardiner (ed.), Theories of History,
New York: Free Press
Rescher, N. and C.B ]oynt
1961 "The Problem of uniqueness in history." History and Theory 1:150-62.
Weber, Max
t977 Critique of Stammler, translated by Guy Oakes. New York: Free Press.