Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

The Philosophy of Spinoza (Volume 1)

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 468

m< OU_160797m

OSMANIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARY kS8f(> Call No. /fJ G Accession No, {/


*

Author
Title

*^

/^y<"^7^^**

'//'I

This book should be returned on or before the date last marked below.

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


VOLUME
I

LONDON HUMPHREY MILFORD


*.

OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS

THE PHILOSOPHY
OF SPINOZA
UNFOLDING THE LATENT PROCESSES OF HIS REASONING
BY

HARRY AUSTRYN WOLFSON


NATHAN LITTAUER PROFESSOR OF JEWISH LITERATURE AND PHILOSOPHY IN HARVARD UNIVERSITY

VOLUME

CAMBRIDGE MASSACHUSETTS

HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS


1934

COPYRIGHT, 1934

BY THE PRESIDENT AND FELLOWS OF HARVARD COLLEGE

PRINTED AT THE HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS

CAMBRIDGE, MASS., U.S.A.

PREFACE
To THE
trained observer the simplest thing in nature has a structure and a history; to the naive mind the most com-

plicated product of human device appears simple and spontaneous. Imagine a primitive man, brought up in natural

surroundings and without ever having witnessed human art in its making. Placed sudde/ily.in one of the canyon-like
a primitive man would think of the flanking sky-soaring structures of undoubtedly
streets of a

modern metropolis, such

and workmanship as something which grew like trees and grass. Similarly, imagine a student of philosophy, trained in some miraculous manner
intricate design

out of the

soil

concepts and vocabulary of the without any inkling of their past history. Conpresent day, fronted suddenly with the Ethics of Spinoza, such a trained
in the usages of philosophic

student would undoubtedly think of

it

as

something which

sprang forth full-grown and completely armored, like Minerva, from the brain of its author, and he would quite
naturally try to interpret
tions
it

it in

evoked

in his

mind.

the light of whatever associaOf course, there is no such pre-

posterously trained student of philosophy, any more than there is such a naive-minded primitive man as he to whom
a student of Spinoza comes very near treating his Ethics in the fantastic fashion which we have described. Like the Bible, the Ethics of
still,

we have compared him. But,

many

Spinoza has often been the subject of homiletical interpretations. It has been treated like an amorphous mass of floating clouds in which one's fancy may cut whatever figures it
pleases.

vi

PREFACE
Now,
I will

not deny that we must allow for philosophic license as we allow for poetic license, and that the cutting of

When Goethe

imaginary figures in Spinoza's Ethics is not without its uses. confesses that he cannot tell what he got out of the Ethics and what he may himself have put into it, we

can only say that we are grateful to Spinoza for having served as a stimulus to the thought of Goethe. In the same way, and permany a worthy thought of men less distinguished

haps also

less

frank

than Goethe has had

its

birth in a mis-

interpretation of Spinoza or else has received due attention by its having been mounted, gratuitously, on Spinoza's writings.

But
is

it

would be carrying the analogy of the

license too

far if

we should say
to be as little

tion

that the philosopher in his interpretabound by the truth of scholarship as the

poet in his imagery

is

by the truth of science.

It is certainly
is

no compliment

to a philosopher of the past

who

prominent

study him to say that only by being misenough understood does he become philosophically important. Indeed, the entire field of the history of philosophy would be placed outside the bounds of exact disciplined study if we
for us to

should maintain that


tance only

its

study

is

of philosophical impor-

meaning
effort to

superciliously disregard its objective as established by research, or indolently make no


it,

when we

acquaint ourselves with


it.

selves in ignorance of

The

fact

is,

or blissfully keep ourwhat is often called

subjective interpretation in philosophy is nothing but the explanation of a text in terms of the haphazard knowledge

that one happens to possess, just as what is called popularization means nothing but the explanation of a text in terms

of the ignorance supposed to be possessed by the readers for whom it is intended. In either of these cases, whatever merit
the particular form of presentation possesses is derived from the fact that it helps to give currency to the results of historical

PREFACE

vii

scholarship, which in its proper sense means the interpretation of a text in terms of everything that can be known about

which a systematic search must be made. The first the basic step, in the understanding of any philosopher, step, one upon which any subjective form of interpretation or
it,

for

any

literary

form of presentation must

rest,

is

the deter-

mination by the method of historical criticism of what the philosopher meant by what he said, how he came to say what he said, and why he said it in the manner in which he

happened

to say

it.

It is this threefold task that

we have

set ourselves in the

really
it

present study of Spinoza. Now, the historico-critical method means the presupposition that in any text treated by
there

who

a sort of dual authorship an explicit author, himself in certain conventional symbols and expresses
is

patterns, and an implicit author, whose unuttered thoughts furnish us with the material for grasping the full significance of those symbols and patterns. In the case of the Ethics of

Spinoza, there

is,

on the one hand, an


It
is

explicit Spinoza,

who speaks in definiand propositions; it is he, too, who reasons tions, axioms, according to the rigid method of the geometer. Then there is, on the other hand, the implicit Spinoza, who lurks behind
shall call Benedictus.

whom we

he

and propositions, only occasionhimself in the scholia; his mind is crammed ally revealing with traditional philosophic lore and his thought turns along
these definitions, axioms,
shall call Baruch.

the beaten logical paths of mediaeval reasoning. Him we Benedictus is the first of the moderns; Baruch is the last of the mediaevals. It is our contention
that

unless

we cannot get the full meaning of what Benedictus says we know what has passed through the mind of Baruch.

Starting with the assumption that the Ethics is primarily a criticism of fundamental problems of philosophy as they

viii

PREFACE
we proceed
to analyze these

presented themselves to Spinoza,

problems, to set forth their salient features, to construct


hypothetically the arguments which constitute the criticism, and to show how these arguments and criticism underlie the

statements which we have before us in the Ethics.


result of this procedure, the Ethics

As a

emerges as a logically conis

structed

work throughout which there


propositions,

order and sequence


disconnected,

and

continuity:

apparently

group themselves into unified and coherent chapters; words, phrases, and passages, apparently meaningless or commonplace,

assume meaning and


in a

significance;

and the philosophy


all its

of Spinoza, as a systematic whole and in


detail,

fulness of

light setting and perappears Into the fabric of this work, which in form follows spective. the order of the Ethics we have also woven relevant passages
in a
',

new

and

new

from the other writings of Spinoza, so that the study of his philosophy herein presented is based upon his Ethics as well
as

upon

all

his other writings in so far as

they are related to

the Ethics.

This work can be read as a self-explanatory systematic presentation of the philosophy of Spinoza. It can be read
with greater profit as a companion volume to the Ethics and a running commentary on it. It can be read with still
greater profit together with some standard works or special studies on Spinoza, for, with the exception of general references to the literature on Spinoza whenever they were neces-

sary either for the bibliographical guidance of the reader or as an acknowledgment of indebtedness on certain points,

and with the further exception of an occasional expression of disagreement, we have refrained from entering upon an examination and comparison or criticism of the various extant
a subject which, if dealt with interpretations of Spinoza at all, is deserving of a study by itself. Independently of

PREFACE

ix

Spinoza, this work can be read as a study of the development of certain fundamental problems in the history of philosophy,
or of the understanding of certain points in the teachings of the authors brought into the discussion and of certain signifi-

cant texts in their writings. Students who are interested in the relation of Spinoza to other philosophers will find in
this

work an abundance of undreamed-of new material,

culled

from the writings of various philosophers ranging from Aristotle to Descartes, though we do not say that every author

whom we

useful or necessary to quote is to be considered a forerunner of Spinoza or as having had a domiit

have found

nant jnfluence upon


it

his philosophy. The principles on which the ^election of this material was made, the manner in which

was used in the interpretation of Spinoza, and the method by which its direct literary relationship to Spinoza and its influence upon him can be determined, are discussed in the
opening chapter. The analytical table of contents at the beginning of each volume and the several Indexes at the end of
various uses to which the book
the second volume will serve as guides to the reader in these may be put.

Chapters

III, IV,

V, and VIII were published

in

Chronicon

Spinozanum, Vols. I (1921), pp. 101-112, II (1922), pp. 92117, III (1923), pp. 142-178, and IV (1924-1926), pp. 79103, respectively. Chapter VI appeared in Italian translation in Ricerche Religiose^ Vol. IX (1933), pp. 193-236. All these chapters are reprinted here with some revisions. The original title and description of this work were announced
in the Chronicon

Spinozanum

as

"Spinoza the Last of the

Mediaevals: a Study of the Ethlca Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata in the light of a hypothetically constructed Ethica

More
to be
title

Scholastico Rabbinicoque Demonstrata." This title had abandoned, as it did not seem advisable to have the

begin with the word "Spinoza."

PREFACE
The
protracted delay in the completion of the work was for by the promptness with which its publi-

amply made up
cation

was undertaken when the manuscript was finished. This was made possible by the Fund for the Support of the Humanities at Harvard University provided by the General
Education Board.

For

this I

also deeply indebted to

am profoundly grateful. I am Miss Christabel Garner, of the Har-

vard University Press, for her searching reading of the proofs

and

for valuable suggestions.

HARRY AUSTRYN WOLFSON


CAMBRIDGE, MASSACHUSETTS

May,

1933

CONTENTS
VOLUME
CHAPTER
BEHIND THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD
Method of procedure
in the study of Spinoza's Ethics in this work,
i. ^Grouping of propositions into logically ordered topics, 5. The problem of Coherence of propositions within each group, 6.

documentation,

8.

Hebrew and Latin

literatures the sources of

The common tradition Spinoza's knowledge of philosophy, 8. The literary languages of Spinoza, underlying these literatures, 10.
n.

Hebrew

literature as the basic source of Spinoza's


12.

knowledge

of philosophy, be studied, 14.

How the literary background of Spinoza is to How immediate sources of Spinoza are to be de-

The method used in this work in the collection termined, 15. of literary sources, and the form in which this work is written,

The importance of the literary background as an aid to the 17. The ellipticalness and alproper understanding of Spinoza, 20. lusiveness of the Ethics, and the reason therefor: personality of The application of the scientific Spinoza, 22. to the study of the Ethics, 25.
method of research

CHAFFER
THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD

II

32
Central idea of
all his

Classification of Spinoza's writings, 32.

writings, 33.
35.

Titles of his works, 35.

Why

the

title

Ethics?

Historical background for the variety of literary forms

em-

ployed by Spinoza, 39.


its

Analysis of the geometrical method and

Was the geometrical method demanded by the history, 40. nature of Spinoza's philosophy? 44. Analysis of Descartes' state-

ments about the geometrical method: distinction between geometrical method and geometrical form and the identity of the geometrical and syllogistic methods, 45. Analysis of Meyer's statements about the geometrical method, 51. Extent of Spinoza's mathematical

No metaphysical conception of the way of looking at things, 52. Hebrew language in Spinoza, 54. Aesthetic reasons for the demands of the use of the geometrical form in philosophy in the seventeenth century, 55. The Ethica more scholastico rabbinicoquc
demonstrata behind the "Ethica ordine geometrico demonstrate" 59.

xii

CONTENTS

(ETHICS,

T)

CHAPTER
DEFINITION OF SUBSTANCE AND

III

MODE

61

Division of Being into cateTraditional division of Being, 61. Difficulties in Spinoza's gories and into substance and accident, 62.
definitions of substance
difficulties,

Method of solving these and mode, 63. Traditional classifications of substance, 67. Hypothetical construction of Spinoza's criticism of these classifications, 68. Spinoza's reduction of substances to one, and his defini66.

tions of substance

and mode,

71.

Substance as "whole": meaning

of "whole," 73.

Substance a sum mum genus and unknowable, 76. Substance "prior in nature" (Prop. I): meaning of "prior in

nature," 77.

CHAPTER
UNITY OF SUBSTANCE
.

IV
.

...

79
Pur-

I. The philosophic dualism of traditional philosophy, 79. pose and method of Spinoza's criticism of this dualism, So. Hypothetical construction of mediaeval arguments against a duality of

gods as they formulated themselves in the mind of Spinoza, 81. Reduction of Propositions II-VI to a syllogistic argument, 85.Detailed explanation of these propositions: restatement of mediaeval dualism (Prop. II), 86. Refutation of mediaeval dualism, by showing untenability of the theory of creation, especially that of

emanation, to which
(Props.

it

must

resort (Prop. Ill), 88.-

Tentative

defence of emanation, 91.

Rebuttal of that tentative defence

IV-VI),

91.

Explanation of Corollary to Proposition

VI, 94II.

tenability of creation, as treated in Short Treatise, 96. B. Nor could it world could not have created itself, 98.

Criticism of mediaeval philosophic dualism, by showing the unA. The

have been

created by God, for (a) creation is incompatible with God's immutability, omnipotence, and benevolence: history of this argument, 99;
(b] creation is incompatible with God's simplicity: history of this argument, 105. Impossibility of the Platonic theory that the world was created out of eternal formless matter: influence of Ger-

sonides, 108.

Argument against an immaterial prime mover, no.

CONTENTS

xiii

CHAPTER V
SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE
I.
. .

112
. .

Simplicity and Attributes

112

How the topic of the discussion in Propositions VII-X and XII-XIII


Twofold meaning of the traditional exhas been determined, 112. Threefold implication of the tradipression "unity of God," 113.
tional insistence

upon the simplicity of God:

(a)

Exclusion of acci-

dents,
(c)

Exclusion of distinction of genus and species, 114. Exclusion of distinction of essence and existence, 115. This
1

13.

(b)

threefold implication of simplicity as reflected in Spinoza, 115. Background of Spinoza's definition of God: influence of Albo, 116.
-

119.

Simplicity and personality of God and the problem of attributes, Logical structure of Propositions VII-X, XII-XIII, 120.
. .

II.

Essence and Existence


121.

121

The two main sources of Spinoza's discussion of essence and existence,

-How

the problem of essence and existence originated: the

views of Aristotle, Avicenna, and Averroes, 122. Spinoza on essence and existence (Prop. VII), 125. Meanings of causa sui:
(b) positive, (a) negative, 127; as treated in Short Treatise ^ 130.

129.

Essence and Existence

IIF.

Definition of the

Term

"

Infinite"

...
'

133

Historical background of Spinoza's definition of the terms "infinite" and "finite," 133. Meaning of the various kinds of finite" and "infinite" in Spinoza, 135. Meaning of "infinite" when applied to God, 137. Spinoza's analogy between his own "substance"

and the traditional God (Props. VIII-X),

139.

IV.

Relation of Attribute to Substance

....
names of God

142

God unknown

His essence but known through His attributes, 142. Certain points of agreement among mediaevals on the nature of
in

attributes, 143.

The

interpretation of the

in the

Bible as attributes, 144.


tive

Spinoza's definition of attribute: subjec-

and objective interpretations, 146. These two interpretations are analogous to mediaeval controversies, 147. Analysis of mediaeval problem of essential attributes, 147. The case of those who
reject essential attributes: objective theory of attributes, 149.

The

case of those

who admit

essential attributes: subjective theory

of attributes, 150.
attributes to one, 154.

Evidence for the subjective interpretation of

The reducibleness of all Spinoza's conception of attributes, 151. Explanation of Propositions XII-XIII, 156.

xiv

CONTENTS

CHAPTER
PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD
I.

VI
158

The

Ontological Proof
160.

158

Transition from "substance" to

of necessano

existit,

"God" What the

(Prop. XI), 158. Meaning proofs of the existence of


',

God

are

meant

to prove, 161.

reason, 161.

Classification of the traditional

Being: real\ fictitious verbal, and of methods of proving the

If God is known immediately, what need is Meaning of the ontological proof, and the stock objection against it, 167. Meaning of St. Anselm's answer to Gaunilon, 170. -- Meaning of the syllogism employed in ontoThe logical form of the syllogism underlying logical proofs, 174.

existence of God, 163.


there for proof? 165.

the ontological proofs, 176.

II.

Spinoza's Four Proofs


Evaluation of the ontological proof, 176. Analysis of the proofs of Descartes and Spinoza and their relation to each other, 178. Spinoza's first proof: its three types, and how the type used in the
Ethics
is

176

a modification of one of the two forms of the proof as given

Spinoza's second proof: its composite origin, 179. Distinction between internal, external, and impedimental Mediaeval proof for eternity of God, 186. Distinccauses, 186.

by Descartes,
184.

tion between necessary, impossible, possible, and contingent, 187. Analysis of the cosmological proof of the existence of God: its three Transformation of the third stage of the cosmological stages, 192. proof into an ontological proof in Spinoza's second proof 197.
',

Spinoza's third and fourth proofs:

how

related to Descartes' second


-

Analysis of Descartes' cosmological proof in Meditation III, 200. second cosmological proof: a modified form of the traditional proof from creation or conservation, 201. Why Spinoza calls it a proof Exfrom power, 204. Explanation of Spinoza's third proof 205.
',

planation of Spinoza's/0wrM/>r00/,207.- Explanation of Scholium to

Proposition XI, 208.

Concluding remarks on Spinoza's proofs, 212.

CHAPTER
EXTENSION AND THOUGHT
I.

VII
214

The Framework

of Spinoza's Universe

214

Recapitulation of Spinoza's arguments leading up to his conclusion that extension and thought are attributes of God (Prop. XIV), 214. The framework of Spinoza's universe and how he came by it, 216.

CONTENTS
The mediaeval framework of
fied

xv

the universe, 218.

How

a modi-

form of the mediaeval framework presented itself to the mind of Unfolding Spinoza's criticism of that framework Spinoza, 219. and his conclusion that God is material, 221. History of the conception of the materiality of God and how little it has to do with
Spinoza's similar conclusion, 222.
II.

Properties, Attributes,

and Modes

224

Origin of the doctrine of the infinite number of attributes, 225. Enumeration of attributes in mediaeval philosophy and Descartes,
226.

Mediaeval attributes called propria by Spinoza: the meaning


Spinoza's various
lists

of propria, 227.

of propria, 230.

Attri-

by which Spinoza has arrived at the two known attributes, and why he calls them extension and thought, 232. Modes: Forma corporeatatis as the origin of extension, 234. (a) Immediate infinite modes; how Spinoza came by them, 236. The names for the immediate infinite mode of thought, 238.
butes: the logical steps

The Meaning of idea Dei, 239. Meaning of intellect us, 238. names for the immediate infinite mode of extension, 242. Why the immediate infinite modes are called "Sons of God," 243. (b} Mediate infinite mode: only one; how Spinoza came by it, 243.
modes, 249.
(c) Finite or Meaning of fades totius universi, 244. Meaning of the resfxae aeternaeque, 249.

particular

Varieties

of possibility and necessity, 252. Natura naturans and natura naturata: influence of Thomas Aquinas, 253. How the attributes of extension and thought may be conceived as really distinct, one without the assistance of the other, and still not imply a plurality in
the nature of substance, 255. Attribute of extension not to be confused with the popular conception of the corporeality of God, 258.

CHAPTER
INFINITY OF EXTENSION

VIII
262
who

Spinoza's statement and refutation of the case of his opponents

deny

Spinoza seems to misrepresent his opponents and to commit the fallacy of equivocation, 265. Descartes not the one meant by his opponents, 268. Method to be
infinite extension, 262.

How

employed
Aristotle

in arriving at

an explanation of Spinoza's position, 270.

How Crescas estaband his followers on infinity, 271. lishes the existence of an infinite extension, 275. Explanation of Spinoza 'sfrst "example" and its corresponding first "distinction," 281. Explanation of Spinoza's second "example" and its corresponding second "distinction: the infinite and the indefinite," 286. Explanation of Spinoza's third "example" and its corresponding
third "distinction," 291.

xvi

CONTENTS

CHAPTER IX
THE CAUSALITY OF GOD
I.

296

Materiality and Causality of

God

-296

Traditional conception of omnipresence of God brought to its logical conclusion by Spinoza (Prop. XV), 296. -- Variety of characterizations of Spinoza's conception of God: Deism, Atheism, Acosmism,

Immateriality and causality two fundamental Pantheism, 298. characteristics of the traditional God, 301. Threefold causality of
the traditional God reduced by Spinoza to efficient causality, 302. Conventional classification of God's efficient causality adopted by

XVI), 304.
cause, 307.

God a universal cause (Prop. Spinoza and applied to his God, 303. God an efficient cause not in the restricted sense of
-

cmanatire cause, 306.

God an

essential cause, 307.

God

a first

II.

God
God

as Free

Cause

308

a principal and free cause (Prop. XVII), 308. Spinoza's definition of freedom, 309. - Mediaeval conception of will and intelli-

gence in divine causality and Spinoza's refutation thereof, 312. Spinoza's refutation of the view that God omitted to create things

He could create, 314. Spinoza's contention that the mediaeval conception of the homonymy of divine intelligence and will Denial of amounts to an assertion of necessary causality, 316.
which
-

chance and causelessness, 318.

III.

The Meaning

of

Immanent Cause

319

Two kinds Distinction between external and internal causes, 319. of internal or immanent causes, 321. Meaning of "transcendent,"
Meaning of Spinoza's conception of God as immanent cause The Immanent as whole or universal, 324. (Prop. XVIII), 323. Two differences mentioned by Spinoza two kinds of "whole," 325. between the "whole" and the conceptual universal; how they are
322.
traceable to Aristotle, 326.

Conjectural addition of a third differ-

ence: the concrete

and the abstract universal, 327.

IV.

God
God

as Conscious

Cause

}2tf

as a conscious but non-volitional cause, 328.

CONTENTS

xvii

CHAPTER X
DURATION, TIME, AND ETERNITY
I.

331
331

The Story

of Duration

Analysis of Plotinus' discussion of time: definite and indefinite time, How the term duration was given to indefinite time, 335. 332. Three forms of the Plotinian conception of duration in Arabic and

Hebrew

First form: in opposition to Aristotle's definitexts, 336. tion of time, 337. --Second form: supplementary to Aristotle's defiThird form: similar to Aristotle's definition nition of time, 338.

of time, 339.
tion, 340.

Etymology of Arabic and Hebrew terms

for dura-

Duration in Augustine: meaning o{distentio,34i.


in Descartes

Com-

mon

characteristics of duration in scholastic philosophy, 343.

Duration

and Locke, 345.

General characteristics

of duration, 346.

II.

Duration and Time

in

Spinoza
in Cogitata Metaphysica,

347
and Reason
its

Formal definition of duration

three

verbal differences from that of Descartes, 347. verbal difference: substitution of "attribute" for

for first

"mode," 348.

Reason
349.

for

Reason

second verbal difference: addition of term "actuality," for third verbal difference: addition of term "cre-

Relation of duration to existence, 351. Definiated," 350. tion of time in Cogttata Metaphyslca^ 353. Problem of the subjecDuration and time in letter to Meyer, 356. tivity of time, 355.

Duration and time in Ethics, 357.


III.

Eternity

358

Difference between Platonic and Aristotelian conceptions of eternity, and the reasons for that difference, 358. Platonic conception of

Platonic and Aristotelian conceptions of eternity in Plotinus, 361. Platonic eternity in Arabic and Hebrew philosophic texts, 361.

364.

and Aristotelian conceptions of eternity in Latin philosophic texts, Three common elements in mediaeval conceptions of eternity

when applied to God: (a) not infinite time, (b} immutability, (c) identity of essence and existence, 366. Only two of these three elements adopted by Spinoza as properties to be applied exclusively to God: (a) not infinite time or duration; examples of defective uses of the term "eternity," 366; (b) identity of essence and existence,

Meaning of Spinoza's comparison of the eternal existence of with "eternal truths," 368. Problem of the applicability of duration to God, 369.
367.
-

God

xviii

CONTENTS

CHAPTER XI
MODES
Structure of Propositions

370

X1X-XXXVI,

370.
Infinite

Spinoza's philos-

ophy

in its relation to

of "eternal

when applied to God (Props. XIX-XX), 375. Meaning of "eternal" and "infinite" when applied to immediate modes The mediate infinite and eternal mode (Prop. (Prop. XXI), 376.

"

emanation, 371.

modes: meaning

Introduction of the use of the term "mode" (Prop. The threefold sense in which God is said to be the 379. cause of the infinite and eternal modes: (a) as their efficient cause

XXII), 378.

XXI 1 1),
(Prop.

XXIV),
(c)

380;

(b) as their

383;

as their free cause (Prop.

dom and

Spinoza's denial of it or res singulares, 387. Where do they

immanent cause (Prop. XXV), XXVI), 385. Meaning of freeFinite modes (Prop. XXVII), 385.

come from?

388.

Spinoza's

An explanation which apparent explanation (Prop. XXVIII), 389. Certain historical explanations: (a) Finitude does not explain, 392.
an
(c]

illusion, 393.

(b}

Matter

as -Aprineipium individuationis, 393.


(d]

Cabalistic zimzum, 394.


in

"Emergent emanation,"
all

395.

Spinoza's real explanation, 397.

Conclusion of the discussion of


of them traceable to

modes: no contingency
their cause (Prop.

modes;
398.

God

as

XXIX),

CHAPTER
NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS
I.

XII
400 400

Intellect, Will,

and Power

Mediaeval belief in design in the causality of God and freedom in the action of man, 400. Design in God expressed in terms of attributes of life, intellect willy and power 401. How Spinoza denies design
, ,

by attacking these

attributes, 401.
(b}

(a)

Attribute of life
intellect

is

to be
will;

included under power, 402.


(1) first method of attack:

Attributes of

and

For God to act by intelligence and will as conceived by the mediaevals is the same as to act by necessity, 402; (2) second method of attack: Intellect and will do not pertain to the
essence of
402.

God and

Hence

there

belong to natura naturata (Props. XXX-XXX1), is no freedom of will in God (Prop. XXXII):

definition of will

and its freedom, 405. Hence, the world could not have been produced by God in another manner and in another order than that in which it has been produced (Prop. XXXIII): history of Continuation of the same problem in Scholia I the problem, 408. and
II

of Proposition XXIII: analysis of Scholium


will: (i) arbitrary

II, 410.

Two
sake of

mediaeval theories of divine

and

(2) for the

CONTENTS
some good, 416. Unfolding of Spinoza's criticism of the second (c) Attribute of view; explanation of his reference to "fate," 418. power: the identity of power with the essence of God makes for
necessity in God's causality (Props.

xix

XXXIV-XXXV),

421.

II.

Final Causes

422
final

How

problem of

causes

is

introduced by Spinoza, 422.

Spinoza's denial of final causes by his reducing them to efficient causes (Prop. XXXVI): historical background, 423. Appendix to Part I as a Scholium to Proposition XXXVI, continuing the discussion of final causes, 425.

Analysis of the Appendix: (a) Statement

of the case for

and its literary background, 425. Spinoza's explanation of the origin of the belief in final causes, 426. Problem of evil, 430. (b) Four arguments against final causes, 431. (c) Some erroneous views arising from the belief in final causes:
final causes,

relativity of

good and

evil, 436.

Problem of moral

evil or sin, 438.

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


VOLUME
I

CHAPTER

BEHIND THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD


IN DISCUSSING once with a group of friends the importance of philology and of bookish learning in general for the study of
the history of philosophy, I happened to remark that philosophers, after all, see the universe which they try to explain as already interpreted to them in books, with the only possible exception, perhaps, of the first recorded philosopher,
all

and

he could see was water.

"How
"Was

about Spinoza?" chal-

lenged one of the listeners.

he also a bookish philosopher?" Without stopping to think, I took up the challenge. "As for Spinoza," I said, "if we could cut up all the philo-

sophic literature available to him into slips of paper, toss them up into the air, and let them fall back to the ground,

then out of these scattered slips of paper


struct his Ethics."

we could

recon-

long after that I found myself reconstructing the out of scattered slips of paper figuratively cut out of Ethics
the philosophic literature available to Spinoza. The problem before us, as I discovered, was like that of a jig-saw puzzle.

Not

Suppose we have a box of pieces out of which we are to construct a certain picture. But the pieces contained in the box
are

more than can be used, and from among them we have


which are needed
for

to

select those

our purpose. Furthermore, do not fit together, and they have to be reshaped. the pieces Finally, many necessary pieces are missing, and we have to

supply them ourselves. But to offset all these difficulties, we have an outline of the picture which we are to construct.
picture which we have to construct in our own jig-saw puzzle is the Ethics as it was originally formed in the mind of

The

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


its

is

Spinoza, of which the present Ethics in only a bare outline. Since, however,
1

geometrical form

we do not know nor

read,

can we ascertain exactly what books Spinoza had actually what quotations he had come across in the course of
his readings, or

what casual information he had gathered from conversations with friends, we must take as our box of pieces the entire philosophic literature available at the time

make our necessary selections. Furthermore, since philosophic texts and ideas are the most
of Spinoza and out of this
plastic of material, capable of

assuming a variety of meanings

with different philosophers, pieces in the form which we have reason to believe they assumed in the mind of Spinoza. Finally, since the Ethics before us is not
the result of a syncretism of traditional philosophy but rather the result of criticism, and since this criticism, though implied,
is

we must reshape our

not explicitly expressed, we shall have to supply

it

ourselves.

In our study of the Ethics we must try to follow the same method that Spinoza followed in writing it. Spinoza did not
start out with classified lists of bibliographies, outlines, abstracts, quotations, and all the elaborate equipment with which methodical scholarship of today prepares itself for the writing of an informative work of reference. He started out

with a certain fund of knowledge acquired through miscellaneous reading which in his mind formed itself into a composite picture of the salient features of traditional philosophy. In this composite mental picture, we may assume, the prob-

lems of philosophy presented themselves in a certain order, each problem modelled after a certain pattern and expressed

Tagged on to this picture, underand deep down into the recesses of Spinoza's consciousness, we may further assume, there was an
in a certain terminology.

neath

its

surface,

Cf. below, p. 59.

BEHIND THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD

aggregation of notes swarming with references to sources of texts, to parentages of ideas, to conflicts of opinions, and to
diversities of interpretations, all of

them ready

to

come up

to

the surface, whenever the occasion arose, and take their place in the picture. In our endeavor to retrace the steps of Spi-

noza's reasoning, we must, therefore, first of all, equip ourselves with a similar fund of knowledge, or philosophical

mass of apperception,

as

it

may

be called.

With such an apperceptive mass as our equipment we begin to read the Ethics. Without forcing ourselves to understand the book, we let its propositions penetrate into our amassed fund of knowledge and by the natural process of association and attraction become encrusted with terms, phrases, and ideas out of the storehouse of our memory. At
first

these encrustations are indistinguishable

and shapeless

clumps, clinging to the propositions as bits of scrap-iron cling to a magnet. But then we let our mind play upon them

them and to study them. By the catalytic mind these indistinguishable and shapeless clumps begin to dissolve; they begin to group themselves, to solidify themselves into larger units, to become differento scrutinize

action of the

tiated

from each other, to assume form, and ultimately to

crystallize themselves into distinct topics of recognizable historical problems of philosophy. Thus at the very outset of the Ethics^ Proposition I, together with Definitions III and V and Axioms I and II upon which it is based, emerges as a dis-

tinct topic

by

itself,

which we label the definition of substance

The next five propositions, II- VI, crystallize themselves into a discussion of the unity of substance, made up of two historical problems, the unity of God and creation.
and mode. and XII-XIII shape themselves into a Propositions VIIof three closely related topics under the general discussion heading of the Simplicity of Substance, and wedged in be-

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


is

tween them

gives way discussion of the traditional proofs of the existence of God. Next follow two propositions, XIV and XV, which deal with

to the term

Proposition XI, where the term "substance" "God"; this is easily recognized as a

which deals with the

the attributes of extension and thought, and a Scholium, infinity of extension. The remaining

propositions of the First Part of the Ethics readily group themselves into discussions of the various meanings of the
causality of God, among which Spinoza dwells especially upon the immanence, freedom, necessity, and purposelessness of God's causality. In the Second Part of the Ethics the propositions fall into the traditional outline of the discussion of

the soul, dealing in the conventional order and manner with the definition of the soul, its relation to the body, and the
classification of its faculties.

The

last three parts of the

Ethics deal with

what

is

traditionally

known

as practical

philosophy as contrasted with the theoretical philosophy of


first two parts, dealing successively with the problems of the emotions, virtues, and the final happiness of man. As our

the

mind scrutinizes still further these groups of propositions it discovers that they follow one upon the other according to a certain order of sequence, which is at once intrinsically
logical
terns.

and
to

extrinsically in conformity with historical patthis,

With

the

first

stage in our study of the Ethics


to find a certain

comes

an end.
is

Then

the next stage in our investigation

coherence within each group of propositions.

The data upon

which we have to work are twofold.

On

the one hand, there

are the problems of philosophy as they unfold themselves before us in all their variety of forms in the vast literature that was available to Spinoza. On the other hand, there are the

utterances of Spinoza in the Ethics,


disjointed,

elliptical,

fragmentary,

and oftentimes,

if

we

are to admit the truth to

BEHIND THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD


ourselves, enigmatic and

unintelligible. Between these two extremes we expect to find the problems as they must have formulated themselves in the mind of Spinoza, the doubts which he must have raised against accepted views, and his own solutions of these doubts which he must have meant to

express in his uttered statements in the Ethics. The task before us, then, is to reconstruct the process of Spinoza's reasoning in all its dialectical niceties and in all its fulness of detail
it will lead us to a thorough understanding of the statements which confront us in the Ethics. By the method

so that

and error we experiment with one conjecture after another, until we finally arrive at a result which seems to us satisfactory. Thus, for instance, at the very outset of the Ethics, in Proposition I and its underlying Definitions III
of
trial

which we have already set apart with definition of substance and by itself, dealing mode, we reconstruct out of the material scattered in the literature of philosophy the problem as we assume it pre-

and

and Axioms

and

II,

as a topic

sented

itself to the mind of Spinoza the division of being, the definition of substance and accident, the classification of

substances, and so on.

Again, out of direct internal discus-

sions of these problems which occur in the philosophic literature of the past, or indirectly out of certain suggestions and hints, and sometimes even without these direct or indirect
aids,

as

we reconstruct a criticism of these traditional definitions we assume it formulated itself in the mind of Spinoza. As result we are enabled to integrate these Axioms, Defini1

and Proposition I into a coherent chapter, containing a logically formed argument. We follow the same method in
tions,

our study of the next group of propositions, Propositions IIVI, which we have found to reflect two historical problems, the unity of God and creation, and which we have subsumed
1

Cf. below, pp. 6 1

ff.

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

under the heading of the Unity of Substance. Here our task is somewhat more difficult, for we have to deal here not with

one single proposition, as


with
five propositions,

is

each of which

the case in Proposition I, but is followed by a demon-

stration,

transition.

and between which there seems to be no unity and Again, by the method of trial and error we ultiin reconstructing the

mately succeed

that in the light of it these five 1 And so we go through the entire Ethics, logical syllogism. and by the use of different devices we succeed in bringing
unity, coherence,
sitions.

thought of Spinoza so propositions form a connected

and harmony within each group of propothe second stage of our investigation

With

this,

comes

to an end.

the third and last stage of our investigathat of documenting our findings so that we may contion, vince others of the truth of our statements and reasoning.

Then we take up

Here, too,

we must follow the same method that Spinoza would have followed, had he documented his Ethics. We feel that it would not be enough to quote from books which we happen to know, or which happen to be generally known. We must ask ourselves what works Spinoza himself would have
used
if

this question

he had chosen to document his writings. To answer we must determine, even though only in a gen-

eral

way, the extent and variety of the philosophic literature


philosophic literatures were open to Spinoza, the and the Latin. His knowledge of Hebrew he had

available to Spinoza.

Two
Hebrew

acquired in a school where he had studied it systematically under the guidance of competent teachers probably from the

age of seven to the age of eighteen


'

(i

639-1 650)

2
.

Latin he
'

Cf. below, pp. 85

fT.

As

for the years of Spinoza's entering

Hayyim y
thal,

see Dunin-Borkowski,

and leaving the Hebrew School Ez Derjunge De Spinoza (1910), p. 103, and FreudenGebhardt, 1927),
I,

Spinoza Lebcn und Lehre

(ed.

p. 31.

BEHIND THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD


to

began His systematic study of that language under the tutorage of Francis van den Enden did not begin until 1652, when he was
already twenty years old. Though he had also a knowledge of several modern languages, Spanish, Portuguese, Dutch,
1 French, and possibly also Italian, German, and Flemish, the philosophic material in these languages was negligible. He-

study later, at first not in a school but privately.

to him not only the works of Jewish but also the works of Arabic philosophers, the philosophers works of Aristotle, mostly as incorporated in the commentaries of

brew made accessible

A verroes,

tators

on Aristotle, and

scholastic

some of the Greek commenworks of some of the Latin Latin similarly opened to him not philosophers.
the works of
also the

only the original Latin writings of the philosophers of the Roman period, of mediaeval scholasticism, and of the Renaissance, but also translations from the Greek, Arabic, and

Hebrew.

the most important works of Jewish whether those translated from the Arabic or philosophers, those written originally in Hebrew, were already accessible

In

Hebrew

to

him in printed form, some of them in several editions; but the translations from non-Jewish authors, with but a few
were accessible to him only in manuscript Manuscripts, however, at that time were not yet

slight exceptions,

form.

gathered up and stored away in a few closely guarded central libraries; they were still widely scattered among individual

owners and

Amsterdam, where and Hebrew printing presses flourished scholarship and where privately owned collections of Hebrew manuFurthermore, the student of scripts must have existed.
freely circulated, especially in

Hebrew

Hebrew

philosophic texts could gain a thorough knowledge

11.

1 As for Spinoza's knowledge of languages, see Epistola 19 (Opera, IV, p. 95, 12-15); Epistola 26 (p. 159, 1. 1 6); Lucas' La Vie de feu Monsieur de Spinoza in

A. Wolf, The Oldest Biography of Spinoza y pp. 51-52 and 104.

io

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

of the contents of the unpublished Hebrew translations of Arabic and Greek authors through the numerous and extensive quotations

from

their

works as well as through the

ela-

borate discussions of their views which were to be found in

Hebrew works

already published. In Latin the proportion of printed works in philosophy was greater than in Hebrew, even of works which were translated into Latin from the

Hebrew. Thus, for instance, the bulk of Averroes' commentaries on Aristotle, which were translated into Latin from the

Hebrew, existed

printed editions in Latin, whereas in Hebrew they existed only in manuscript form. To Spinoza these three literatures, Hebrew, Latin, and
in

many

Arabic, represented a common tradition. Whatever differences he noticed between them, they concerned only problems of a purely theological and dogmatic nature; the
philosophic basis of all such problems, and especially the discussion of problems of a purely philosophic nature, he could not fail to see, were all of a common origin. They were all

based upon Greek philosophy, at the centre of which stood Aristotle. The same Greek terminology lay behind the Arabic,

Hebrew, and Latin terminology, and the same scientific and philosophic conceptions formed the intellectual background
of
all

those

who

philosophized in Arabic, Hebrew, or Latin.

three philosophic literatures were in fact one philosophy expressed in different languages, translatable almost literally
into one another.

The

And

within each of these philosophic

liter-

atures

numerous works existed which were encyclopaedic

in

nature, covering as they did the entire range of philosophy, containing the same roster of problems, the same analyses of those problems, the same definitions of terms, the same metaclash of contrasting views, the same arguments in support or in refutation of each view, and, barring certain individual differences of emphasis or of inter-

physical brocards, the

same

BEHIND THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD

reader pretation, arriving also at the same conclusions. of these books in one of these three who had mastered any

languages found himself treading upon familiar ground when he came to read any book in the other languages. We do not know exactly in what language Spinoza would

books had the choice of language been determined by him on the basis of the ease with which he could express himself in it rather than on the basis of the linguistic

have written

his

equipment of the readers

whom

he wished to reach.

Had

Spinoza lived in the land of his forefathers, Spain or Portugal,


before the expulsion, or in any other European country where Jewish philosophy was cultivated, such as Southern France or Italy, he would have undoubtedly written in Hebrew, for Hebrew had been the exclusive medium of expression of Jewish philosophers

and

scientists

throughout Europe ever since

the disappearance of Jewish life in Southern Spain under Moslem rule with the coming of the Almohades in the twelfth

The particular attitude of an author toward the of religion was no deterrent to his use of Hebrew, problems for every shade of opinion, from extreme adherence to tradicentury.
tion to the

most daring adventures into freedom of thought,

found expression in Hebrew literature. In the intellectual autonomy which the Jews enjoyed during the Middle Ages, with the systematic pursuit of the study of philosophy and
the sciences in Jewish schools out of Hebrew books, Jewish thinkers were always assured of appreciative as well as criti-

people of whatever views they chose to express in Hebrew. But toward the end of the fifteenth century there appeared Jewish philosophers who,
cal readers

among

their

own

though brought up on Hebrew philosophic literature and themselves writing in Hebrew, wrote books in non-Jewish
languages for non-Jewish readers. Elijah Delmedigo, better known as Helias Hebraeus Cretensis (1460-1497), wrote his

12

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

Quaestiones Tres and his Adnotationes in Dictis Averrois super Libros Physicorum l in Latin, and Judah Abrabanel, better

known

as

Leo Hebraeus

(d. 1535),

wrote

his Dialoghi

d'Amore

in Italian. 2

In Spinoza's

which he was born, own teachers and schoolmates

own time and in Hebrew was still used

community in extensively by his

the

in their literary

was
in

also

made by some of them


Israel

works, but use of Spanish and Latin. His

teacher

Manasseh ben

wrote on theological problems

Hebrew, Latin, Spanish, and Portuguese. Under these circumstances, what language Spinoza would have used if he had chosen that in which self-expression was the easiest for him can be only conjectured. That it would not have been Latin or Dutch, in which his books happen to be written, is
quite evident by his own confession. At the time of the publication of his Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae and Cogltata Metaphysica (1663) he still felt the deficiency of his Latin, and before allowing his friends to publish these works he
stipulated that one of

them should,
3

in his presence,

"

clothe

In 1665, in one of his letters to he intimates that he could express his thoughts Blyenbergh/
in

them

more elegant

style."

was brought up/' better Whether Hebrew was with him, as it was with many Jewish authors of his time and place, a more
in

Spanish, "the language in which


in

than

Dutch.

natural vehicle of literary expression is uncertain. But it is quite certain that Hebrew literature was the

primary source of stock upon which


1

his
all

knowledge of philosophy and the main the other philosophic knowledge which

in Libros Physicorum^ 1501,


a

These two works are printed together with Joannes de Janduno's Quaestiones and other editions.
It is quite possible,

however, that the Dialoghi cC Amore was written originally Sonne, Lisheelat ha-T^ishon ha-Mefcorit shel Wikkuhe ha-Ahahab li-Yehudah Abarbanel^ in Ziyyunim (Berlin, 1929), pp. 142-148. For new evidence
in

Hebrew.
it

Cf.

I.

that
J

was

originally written in

Hebrew, see below,


11.

vol. II, p. 14.

Epistola 13 (Opera, IV, p. 63,

20-22).

Epistola 19 (p. 95,

11.

12-15).

BEHIND THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD


he later acquired was grafted.

13

He had become

familiar with

Hebrew

philosophic literature before he began to read philosophy in Latin. His nascent philosophic doubt arose as a reaction against the philosophy which he read in Hebrew.

With the exception of the new sciences, his readings in Latin supplied him merely with a new vocabulary for old ideas.
Throughout
his discussions of philosophical problems, especially those bordering

as the matrix in

upon theology, Hebrew sources appear which the general outline of ideas was formed.

Other sources appear as insets. It is Hebrew sources, too, upon which he draws for his casual illustrations. An outstanding example of this is to be found in his discussion in of the T*ractatus 'Theologico-Politicus of the two Chapter

XV

contrasting attitudes shown by philosophers towards the problem of the relation of faith to philosophy or of the-

ology to reason. been discussed in

The problem was an

old one, and

it

had

ism

alike.

Christianity, and JudaIn each of these three religions, the two contrast-

Mohammedanism,

had their exponents. In Mohammedanism, such exponents, to mention but two, were Algazali and Averroes. In Christianity, two typical exponents of these attitudes
ing attitudes
Spinoza, however, mentions none of these. He takes Alpakhar and Maimonides as his examples of typical representatives of these two contrasting views, and he does so simply because

could be found in Bernard of Clairvaux and Abelard.

men through whose works he first became with the nature of the problem. He did not even acquainted feel the need, writing as he did in Latin for non-Jewish readthese were the two
ers,

to substitute

two corresponding Christian authors

for

these two Jewish authors, for in Spinoza's time Jewish phi-

losophy had not yet been eliminated from European philosophy and relegated to the esoteric field of oriental wisdom.

From

the thirteenth century

down through

the seventeenth

4
it

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


was quite fashionable
for theologians

century

losophers to
authorities,

quote Hebrew authorities by and those who followed the


in

and phithe side of Greek


habit of quoting

the original Greek also quoted Hebrew sources in the original Hebrew. The only concession that

Greek sources

Spinoza seems to have made to his non-Jewish readers is that he referred to his Hebrew authorities with the aloofness of an
outsider.

literature for our

Following this principle, we go first to Hebrew philosophic documents. It is not any particular author

that

we go

to,

but the

field

of literature as a whole.

If one

particular author, Maimonides for instance, happens to be resorted to more often than others, it is not because he has

been especially selected for our purpose, but because Spinoza himself would have selected him, for his work is the most excellent depository of mediaeval philosophic lore, where one

can find the most incisive analyses of philosophic problems, the most complete summaries of philosophic opinions, the
clearest definitions of terms,

and all these couched in happy and

lels

quotable phrases. But we always try to give sufficient paralfrom other Hebrew authors so as not to create the errone-

ous impression that we are trying to draw parallels between

one single Hebrew author and Spinoza. In like manner, in order not to create the erroneous impression that the material

drawn upon

is unique in Hebrew philosophic literature, we or refer to, similar passages in the works of Arabic or quote, scholastic authors. When the occasion demands, scholastic

sources are resorted to in preference to the Hebrew. Furthermore, in order not to create the erroneous impression that
there
is

we quote from
a
list

something peculiarly "mediaeval" about the views the various mediaeval sources, we trace their

origin to Aristotle's works.

Frequently we string together of names from the various linguistic groups of philos-

BEHIND THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD


ophy
a
in order to indicate that the

15

views under discussion are

common

philosophic heritage.

from a certain book we

Before quoting a passage do not stop to ask ourselves whether

that book was known to Spinoza. In several instances we rather suspect that the book in question was unknown to him. But that makes no difference to us. Provided the
idea expressed in the passage under consideration is not uncommon, we assume that it was known to Spinoza, even

though for the time being we do not know exactly the immediate literary source of his knowledge. In such instances,
only one who would arrogate to himself divine omniscience could assert with certainty that the idea could not be found
to Spinoza. The burden of proof is the negative. always upon But very often certain passages are identified as being the direct and immediate sources of Spinoza. As a rule Spinoza
in

any source available

does not quote sources literally, even when he mentions them. In a letter to Meyer, for instance, he introduces his reproduction of Crescas' proof of the existence of God by the " "it reads as follows (sic sonat)* and yet the passage

words which

follows is not an exact quotation. But in many instances the evidence points to certain passages as directly underlying the utterances of Spinoza. In determining these direct sources it is not the similarity of single terms or even of single phrases

that guides us, for in the history of philosophy terms and phrases, no less than the ideas which they express, have a
certain

persistency about
their

them and they survive


It
is

intact

winding transmigrations. always a throughout a certain context, and that term or a phrase as imbedded in
context by
its

internal structure

and by a combination of

enveloping circumstances, that help us to determine direct literary relationships. When we feel that we are in a position,
1

Epistola 12 (Opera, IV, p. 61,

1.

18).

THK PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


it is

for instance, to affirm with reasonable certainty that

Thomas Aquinas from whom Spinoza has taken over

in the

Scholium to Proposition XXIX of Ethics, I, the distinction of natura naturans and natura naturata it is not because these
phrases happen to occur in his works, for as phrases they happen to occur also in the works of other authors; it is only because Spinoza's description of these two phrases seems
to be a modification of the description given

by Thomas

Aquinas, and

also because the reason for the modification of

the description by Spinoza can be adequately accounted for. 1 When, again, we are in a position to affirm with reasonable

over

certainty that it is Crescas from whom Spinoza has taken in the Scholium to Proposition of Ethics^ I, the " which his "opponents" prove the imthree "exam pies by

XV

possibility of an infinite extension

and

in refutation

of them

the three
to

"

distinctions

"

which he mentions

in Epistola

XII

not because these "examples" and "distincMeyer, tions" are to be found in Crescas, for as individual "examit is

ples" and "distinctions" they are to be found also in other authors; it is only because these three "distinctions" are

used by Crescas as refutations of three arguments which 2 correspond respectively to the three "examples" of Spinoza.
Finally, to take but one more example, when we are in a position to affirm with reasonable certainty that Spinoza's

discussion of the highest good, of human society, and of the virtues in Propositions XIX-LXXIII of Ethics^ IV, is based

upon

Aristotle's

Nicomachean Ethics

it is

not because we dis-

cover in them certain similarities in individual terms or


phrases;
it is

only because we discover

in

them

definite liter3

arguments. It is such methods that direct literary relationship has been by


ary
1

similarities in the construction of the

Cf. below, pp. 254 f. Cf. below, Vol. II, pp. 233

Cf. below, pp. 264


ff.

ff.

BEHIND THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD


established between Spinoza and
in this

17

many

of the authors quoted

work.

A list of passages quoted or referred to in this work from various authors will be found in the Index of References, and
an analysis of topics of each of these authors will be found in the Index of Subjects and Names. The works quoted or reit will be noticed, are drawn indiscriminately from the various linguistic groups of philosophic literature Greek, Latin, Hebrew, and Arabic. Conspicuously absent

ferred to,

the exception of a few references, mostly of ancillary importance, to Meir ibn Gabbai, Moses Cordovero, and Abraham Herrera, 1 is the Cabalistic literature, which

among them, with

from

earliest

time has been considered a source of Spinoza's

philosophy. This exclusion was unintentional; it merely happened that in our search for documentation we had no occasion to resort to the Cabalistic literature for source material.

Not

that the Cabalistic literature could not have furnished

us with apt illustrative material, but there is nothing in the Cabalistic literature which could be used for our purpose the
like

of which we did not find in philosophic literature, for, as has been said by one of the leading Cabalists, Moses Cordovero: "Know that in matters metaphysical oftentimes the

true masters of Cabala will be found to agree with the phil* "To follow" would perhaps have been a more osophers." accurate term than "to agree." The list of passages is by no means exhaustive. Had we

thought

it

necessary,

we could have added innumerable


but our purpose was not

parallels to every passage quoted;

to compile a complete catena of parallel passages.

com-

plete Index of mediaeval philosophy, Latin, Hebrew, and


1 Two of the references to Herrera, however, seem to point to a direct literary connection and are of special significance. Cf. below, pp. 245 and 314.

Elimah Rabbati,

I, 16.

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

Arabic, is indeed one of the desiderata of scholarship, but that will have to be done independently of any study of Spiare the passages quoted or referred to by us irreplaceable by similar passages from other works, though we have always tried to select passages which are most suitable

noza.

Nor

would be quite possible to rewrite conof this work by substituting other quotasiderable portions tions for those used by us, without necessarily changing our
for

our purpose.

It

present analysis and interpretation of the Ethics, for the passages quoted are only representative of common views
philosophic literature of the past. Had we thought it desirable, then instead of writing one single book on the Ethics, we could have written a series
in the

which were current

of papers bearing such

titles

as "Aristotle

and Spinoza,"

"Seneca and Spinoza," "Averroes and Spinoza," "Maimontdes and Spinoza," "Thomas Aquinas and Spinoza," "Leo

Hebraeus and Spinoza," "Descartes and Spinoza," and many other correlations of Spinoza with names of authors who are quoted in this work or who could have been quoted. But our
purpose was only to draw upon these authors for material in building up our interpretation of Spinoza and not to establish
analogies, and we were especially careful to avoid the extension of analogies beyond the limits of what the actual facts warranted, and also to avoid the suggestion of influences when

no direct literary relationship could be established. Had we thought it advisable we could have eliminated all the quota-

by omitting them altogether or by giving them in paraphrase form. But the interpretation of texts is an essential part of our work, and since texts had
tions
texts, either

from our

no paraphrase, however felicitous, could take the of an exact quotation. Probably the most logical literplace ary form for this work would have been that of a commento be used,

tary upon the Ethics preceded by a few general chapters of

BEHIND THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD


introduction.

19

But we chose our present method because our purpose was not to comment upon single and isolated passages of the Ethics, but to show the unity, continuity, and logical order that runs throughout the work, and withal
to present the philosophy of

Spinoza as a systematic whole.


it is

Of

all

the authors quoted or referred to in this work,

only Maimonides and Descartes, and indirectly through them, and quite as often directly through his own works,
also Aristotle,
1

that can be said to have

had a dominant

in-

upon the philosophic training of Spinoza and to have him in the formation of his own philosophy. It would guided indeed have been possible, within certain limits, to depict
fluence

the philosophy of Spinoza against the simple background of any one of these three philosophers, except for the fact that that would not have been a true presentation of the genesis of his thought, for it had a more complex origin. All

the other authors quoted in this work, however helpful they may have been in our reconstruction of the Ethics, can be
said to have

had a

direct influence only

upon

single passages

most upon certain groups of propositions. To go beyond that and to attempt to build up an extended analogy between the philosophic systems of any of these authors and Spinoza, on the mere basis of such isolated parallels of expressions or passages, even when a direct literary relationship between them could be established, would only mean the inflation of footnotes
in the Ethics, or

upon

single propositions, or at

into essays or
1

monographs.

whom Spinoza has been studied, see UeberwegFrischeisen-Kohler-Moog, Die Philosophic dcr Neuzeit bis zum Ende des XVIII. Jahrhunderts (i2th ed., 1924), pp. 668 ff.; R. McKeon, The Philosophy of Spinoza (1928), pp. 322 ff. Among all the studies listed, no less than five on Spinoza and
For
lists

of authors in relation to

Maimonides and no less than sixteen on Spinoza and Descartes, there is only the following one which deals with Spinoza's relation to Aristotle: Julius Guttmann,
"Spinozas Zusammenhang mit dem Aristotelismus," in Judaica, Festschrift zu Hermann Cohens siebzigstem Geburtstage (Berlin, 1912), pp. 515-534.

20

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

But whether direct or indirect, the sources of Spinoza are more important for us as a means of establishing the meaning of his text and philosophy than as a means of establishing an
analogy or priority of doctrine. The text of his Ethics is not a mosaic of quoted or paraphrased passages. Nor has his
philosophy developed as a rash out of the infection of certain heretical or mystical phrases. It has grown out of the very
philosophy which he discards, and this by his relentless driving of its own internal criticism of itself to its ultimate logical conclusion. In our endeavor to reconstruct the processes of
Spinoza's reasoning, therefore, it is not phrases that we are to deal with but the thought and the history that lie behind them and the use that he makes of them. When he says, for
instance, that

God

is

the

immanent cause of

all

things,

it is

not enough for us to find some one

who had

called

God an

immanent cause. We have to study the meaning of the term "immanent" in its complicated historical development and the particular use made of it by Spinoza throughout his writings. We shall then discover that he means by it something quite different from what we should ordinarily take it to mean. Not that we are to assume that Spinoza had actually gone through all the steps of the investigation which we are to
1

for that

trudge through in discovering the meaning of such terms was not necessary for him. He lived in an age when

the traditions of philosophy were still alive, and what we nowadays have to discover by the painstaking methods of

research
tradition.

came

to

him naturally

as the heritage of a living

most

Studied against the rich background of tradition, even the colorless of terms and expressions may become invested

with technical significance of the utmost importance. A case in point is the special significance which may be discovered in
1

Cf. below, pp. 323

ff.

BEHIND THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD

21

Spinoza's choice of the terms "attribute," "created things/' and "actuality" in his definition of duration, 1 and of the

terms "first thing," "actual," "human mind," "idea," "individual thing," and "actually existing" in his definition of

mind. 2

Even when Spinoza


is

is

well-known sources our task

obviously merely restating not completed by merely sup-

plying the perfunctory references. We must again study the meaning of the sources quoted and their implications and
all the shall possible uses he could have made of them. often find that what at first sight appears merely as a repetition of what others have said is in reality a criticism of what

We

they have said.

toward openly
cause of
it,

For despite Spinoza's expressed aversion 3 criticizing his opponents, and perhaps beis

primarily an implied criticism of his opponents. Thus, for instance, when he enumerates the various meanings of cause and asserts that God is a universal,
his Ethics
efficient, essential,

and

first

cause,

it is

not enough merely to

must identify the immediate source of his statement. study the implications of these terms, and we shall then find
that instead of merely repeating
said,
is

We

what

his predecessors

have

Spinoza they have said and of applying to their

really challenging their right of saying

what
"

God

the term "cause

And so throughout the Ethics, from his opening definition of substance to his concluding description of the religion of reason, we shall find that behind every posiin all these senses. 4
is lurking a negative criticism. With of his positive assertions we seem to hear Spinoza's every one challenge to his opponents: I accept your own definitions of

tive statement there

terms, but

am
1

not unwilling to use your


Cf. below, pp. 347
Cf. below, p. 58.
Cf. below, pp. 304
ff.

use them with greater consistency than you. I own descriptions of God, but
ff.
*

Cf. below, Vol. II, pp. 42

ff.

22

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

they are logically more applicable to my God than to yours. I see no reason why I should not use your own formulae, but

must give them an interpretation of my own. It is quite possible for me to adopt with some reservation one of your views, but I must reject all the others which you consider of
I

equal probability. That the Ethics in


is

its

literary

form

sist in

writing the obvious fact that

quite apparent. But


it is

its

a peculiar piece of peculiarity does not conis

divided into propositions and

demonstrations instead of chapters and sections. It consists in the fact, which becomes obvious only after a careful study
of the work, that the manner in which
is it

makes use of language

rather peculiar. It uses language not as a means of expression but as a system of mnemonic symbols. Words do not stand

complicated trains of thought. Arguments are not fully unfolded but are merely hinted at by suggestion. Statements are not significant for what they actufor simple ideas
for

but

ally affirm but for the denials which they imply. Now, the mere use of the geometrical method cannot explain that, for even within the geometrical method Spinoza could have been clearer and more expatiative. To some extent it may be ex-

plained, perhaps, by the cloistered atmosphere in which the Ethics was conceived and written. No challenging questions of inquiring students or friends guided Spinoza in the manner

of

its exposition or goaded him into a fuller expansion of its statements. Despite the fact that he allowed himself to enter into the discussion of problems which troubled the minds of

his correspondents, he

never communicated to them the

ful-

or discussed with them the philowhich troubled his own mind. The consophic problems genial group of merchants, booksellers, medical students, and
ness of his

own thought

holders of public office which formed the immediate circle of Spinoza's friends had a layman's interest in the general prob-

BEHIND THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD

23

lems of philosophy, but they could hardly serve as effective sounding-boards for his views during the experimental stages of his thinking. They seem to have had a more vigorous
grasp of the problems of theology, in which they were the liberals of their day, but with all the adventuresomeness of
their spirit they were just beginning to approach the liberalism of the mediaeval writings of Jewish rationalists read by

Spinoza

in

his early youth,

Spinoza was welcomed by them

which he had long outgrown. as an exotic genius to whose

occasional expression of shocking views they could listen indulgently because they could dismiss them from their minds
as a sort of outlandish heresy. In this strange environment, to which externally he seems to have fully adjusted himself,

Spinoza never felt himself quite free to speak his mind; and he who among his own people never hesitated to speak out with boldness became cautious, hesitant, and reserved. It

was a caution which sprang not from

fear but

from an inner

sense of decorum which inevitably enforces itself on one in the presence of strangers, especially strangers who are kind.

Quite early in his new career among his newly found friends he showed evidence of this cautious and guarded attitude,

and when on one occasion he became conscious of


was due
to the faults of the latter arising
1

it,

in the
it

case of Casearius, he deluded himself into the belief that

from
to

his

youth and

immaturity.

Little did he
little

understand the

real cause of his

own

behavior, and

did he

know
all

stamped

his general attitude

towards

the others

not the faults of youth and immaturity. thoughts of this book been simmering in his
nicative
essence,

what extent it who had So long had the

uncommuwe
is

mind that and it is

it

was boiled down

to a concentrated

this

concentrated essence that

are

served
1

in

the form of propositions.


11.

The

Ethics

not a

Epistola 9 (Opera, IV, p. 42,

19-26).

24

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


to the world;
it is

communication
with himself.
In
its

Spinoza's communication

allusiveness

concentrated form of exposition and in the baffling and ellipticalness of its style, the Ethics may be

compared to the Talmudic and rabbinic writings upon which Spinoza was brought up, and it is in that spirit in which the
old rabbinic scholars approach the study of their standard texts that we must approach the study of the Ethics.

We

must assume that the Ethics is a carefully written book, in which there is order and sequence and continuity, and in which every term and expression is chosen with care and used with precision. We must try to find out not only what is within it, but also what is behind it. We must try to understand not only what the author says, but also what he omits to say, and why he omits it. We must constantly ask ourselves, with regard to every statement he makes, what is the
reason?

What

does he intend to

let

us hear?

What

is

his

authority? Does he reproduce


If not,

his authority correctly or


it?

not?

why

does he depart from

What

are the differences

between certain statements, and can such differences be reduced to other differences, so as to discover in them a com-

mon

in full

underlying principle? In order to understand Spinoza and to understand him well, we must familiarize our-

must place selves with his entire literary background. ourselves in the position of students, who, having done the
reading assigned in advance, come to
to his
sit

We

at his feet

and

listen

comments thereon. Every nod and wink and allusion of his will then become intelligible. Words previously quite unimportant will become charged with meaning. Abrupt
transitions will receive an adequate explanation; repetitions
will

be accounted

for.

shall

thought than what is know what he wished to say and what he would have

of Spinoza's merely expressed in his utterances. We


shall

We

know more

BEHIND THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD


said

25

had we been able

to question

him and

elicit

further in-

formation.

But a question may now naturally come up.

How

do we

that our interpretation is correct? After all, what we have done is to construct an imaginary setting to fit the
Ethics.

know

do we know, then, that the setting is not a mere figment of the imagination? Even if it is admitted that the setting is constructed out of historical material and that the Ethics seems to fit snugly in it, still it may be argued that

How

the plot of a historical novel may be similarly constructed out of historical material, the individual incidents may be all
historically authenticated,

may
work

all

act in their true historical character,

and the personages of the novel and yet the

as a whole be nothing but an artificial

and

fictitious

production. In answer to this question we may say, in the first place, that the validity of our interpretation of the Ethics rests upon
its

workability and universal applicability. If there is anything arbitrary in our interpretation it is the initial assumption that Spinoza

thought out his philosophy

in a logical,

orderly, and coherent manner, and that he wrote it down in a work which is logical, orderly, and coherent, and in a language which is self-explanatory. But having started out with this assumption and finding that the Ethics is far from being a

book which
language
tory,
in

is

logical, orderly,
it is

which

written

is

and coherent, and that the far from being self-explana-

we have

a right to believe that

any interpretation,

his-

torically substantiated, that will help to explain the entire Ethics as a logically, orderly, coherently, and intelligibly

written book
It
is

is

more

like the plot of a

not fictitious like the plot of a historical novel. work of true historical research in
historical
is

which a meagre and sketchy account of certain

events preserved in a single fragmentary document

pre-

26

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

sented in a

new reconstructed form by the rilling in of gaps, the supplying of details, and by the explaining of causes by and motives, all on the basis of other authentic records. Historical research in philosophy,
is

no

less

than

in literature or

claiming the same test of certainty as politics, the hypotheses of the natural scientists, namely, the test of workability and of universal applicability as a description of
justified in

the phenomena that come under observation. The analogy of our study of the Ethics to the scientific in method of research holds true in still another respect the employment of a method which may be considered as a
all

modified form of what


Invariably

is

in the writings

called in science control-experiment. of Spinoza several texts are to be

found

in

which the same problems are dealt with.

In our

study of Spinoza we have always treated these parallel texts as the scientific experimenter would treat his guinea-pigs, performing our experimental interpretation on some of them

and using the others

as a control.

Thus

in

working on any

problem, instead of collecting at once all the parallel texts and ancillary material in the writings of Spinoza and working

on

all

of them at the same time,

we confined our

investiga-

tions to

some

particular texts,
texts.

and then tested our conclufor instance, in the

sions

by the other

Thus,
1

problem

of the unity of substance, for which Propositions II -VI of Ethics , I, Chapter II of Short Treatise, I, and Appendix I of
the Short "Treatise are parallel texts, or in the problem of the
relation of
II,

which Proposition X of Ethics^ Preface to Short Treatise II, and Appendix II of the

mind and body, 2

for

',

texts, the problem was worked out first in connection with one of these sets of and then tested and checked up by the others.

Short Treatise

are parallel

fully

texts

Cf. below, pp. 79

ff.
ff.

Cf. below, Vol. II, pp. 33

BEHIND THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD


Then
also, again in

27
in

analogy to the

method of research

the sciences, our investigation was not merely a matter of classifying data; it consisted mainly in discovering problems, stating them, and solving them; and the solution, as a rule,

was afterwards verified by a method which in scholarship may be said to correspond to the method of experiment and prediction in science. One probstarted with a conjecture which

lem with which


itself to us,

to start

our investigation always presented

and that was the problem of linking together ap-

parently disconnected propositions into a coherent argument. To solve this problem it was required to find the missing links

which
in the

in the original

form

in

mind of Spinoza and before

which the Ethics was conceived it was broken up into geo-

metric propositions supplied a logical transition between the disconnected statements which we now have before us. Now

sometimes these missing links could be forged out of material which we happened already to have at our disposal, but most often they had to be invented imaginatively out of material which we only assumed to exist and the corroborative evidence was to be discovered afterwards. And, as a rule, it was discovered.

But problems of still greater difficulty presented themselves to us on frequent occasions, such, for instance, as apparent misuse of terms on the part of Spinoza, or apparent

contradictions in his

own
set

statements, or apparent misrepreInvariably in the solution

sentations of the views of others.

up some distinction in the use of the term which Spinoza seemed to misuse, or we discerned some new aspect in the statement of the idea in which Spinoza seemed to contradict himself, or we assumed the possibility of some new interpretation of the view in which Spinoza seemed to misrepresent others. Here, again, most often these new distinctions, aspects, and interpretations were invented ad hoc, merely for the purpose of solving a certain
of such problems

we

28
difficulty,

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


and the evidence corroborating them was discovis the method which we have followed

ered afterwards. This

throughout our investigation, though it is not the method which we have adopted in the presentation of the results. In
the final form which this
clearness

work has assumed,

for the sake of

and brevity, the order of exposition has had to be the reverse of the order of discovery, and sources, which in

the actual process of investigation were evidence by which

a priori conjectures were corroborated, have had to be presented as data from which conclusions were drawn. The material dealt

with

in this

work did not seem

to us to possess

sufficient

elements of

human

interest to justify our attemptin the

ing to intrigue the reader form of a mystery story.

by presenting each problem

A typical illustration of this kind of proof by experiment or prediction may be found in Spinoza's discussion of the problem of infinite extension. This is one of the discussions
in

their views

which Spinoza makes reference and criticizing them.

to his

He

finds that

opponents, restating one of the


infinite

reasons

why

his

opponents denied the existence of an

extension was their belief in the divisibility of extension, and therefore concludes that inasmuch as matter is not divisible

an infinite extension does


cussion
it

exist.

From

the context of his dis-

appears that by divisibility he means divisibility into indivisible parts or atoms and that by indivisibility he

means

indivisibility in the

same sense

as a point

is

said to be

indivisible.

Having
them
is

identified his opponents,

we found

that

that kind of divisibility of extension which he seems to


ascribe to
explicitly denied

by them.

Furthermore,

we found

that Spinoza, in maintaining the existence of an infinite extension which is indivisible, uses the term "infinite"
in a sense

which

is

explicitly rejected

by

his opponents.

Spi-

BEHIND THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD

29

noza thus seems to misrepresent his opponents and to commit the fallacy of equivocation. This was the difficulty which
confronted
us.

Now,

of course,

we could have

dismissed this

difficulty by assuming either that Spinoza purposely misrepresented his opponents in order to be able to refute them,

or that out of sheer ignorance he attributed to them views of which they did not approve. But we preferred to believe that

Spinoza was both intellectually honest and accurately informed. We therefore tried to find whether it would not
be possible for us to interpret his utterances in such a way would remove our difficulty. We made several vain at-

as

tempts, until we finally hit upon a possible distinction in the use of the term "indivisible" and correspondingly in that of
the term "divisible."

By assuming

these terms according to this new vented ad hoC) we were able to explain his statements about his opponents in a fully satisfactory manner. We therefore

that Spinoza had used distinction which we in-

adopted this as a tentative hypothesis, for the truth of which we had no evidence except the internal criterion of its workability.

But

then, after

we had

satisfied ourselves as to the

workability of our hypothesis, we began to ask ourselves whether it would not be possible to find some external cor-

roboration of

it in

the form of a statement by

some author,

mediaeval or ancient, where that distinction in the use of the terms "indivisible" and "divisible" was made. After some
search,

"indivisible"

we found that this distinction in the use of the term is made by Aristotle and Thomas Aquinas.
1

Or, to take another illustration. In Spinoza's classification of the stages of knowledge, we traced the history of the classification itself as well as of the

terms used

in it to Aristotle.

Then when Spinoza evaluates


1

these orders of knowledge

and

Cf. below, pp. 270, 282

ff.

30

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

says that "knowledge of the first kind alone is the cause of is necesfalsity; knowledge of the second and third orders
sarily true" (Ethics, II, Prop.

evaluation to Aristotle.
culty.

XLI), we likewise traced this But here we were faced with a diffi-

Aristotle makes use of four terms, naturally in Greek. of these terms correspond exactly to the two terms which Spinoza describes elsewhere as the second and third

Two

kinds of knowledge, but the other two terms used by Aristotle usually mean in Greek just the opposite of the two Latin terms which are used by Spinoza in his first kind of
the evidence pointed to this Aristotelian origin of Spinoza's evaluation of knowledge, we assumed that somewhere in the history of the transmission of
all

knowledge. But inasmuch as

Aristotle's writings
in question

from the Greek into Latin the two terms

were somehow translated or interpreted in a sense corresponding to the two terms used by Spinoza. Then, after

we had completed

the chapter on the Stages of Knowledge, we began to ask ourselves whether it would not be possible for us to find some work accessible to Spinoza where that unusual
translation or interpretation of the

two Aristotelian terms

in

question actually occurred. After some search, we found that in two Latin translations made from the Hebrew of Averroes'

Arabic Long
these

Commentary on
1

Aristotle's Analytica Posteriora

two Aristotelian terms are translated exactly

as they

are found in Spinoza.

And

so in innumerable instances external corroborative

evidence was found for previously conceived conjectures. This gave us a sense of assurance that it was not merely an
structure that we were setting up for the Ethics, but some extent we had succeeded in penetrating into the mind of Spinoza and were able to see its workings, to sense its
artificial

that to

Cf. below, Vol. II, pp. 146, 151.

BEHIND THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD


direction, to anticipate its
its goal.

31

movements, and

to be guided to

In order to understand another

we must completely

identify ourselves with that other, living through imagi-

natively his experience and thinking through rationally his thoughts. There must be a union of minds, like the union of

our mind with the Active Intellect which the mediaevals


discuss as a possibility
certainty.

and of which Spinoza speaks as a

CHAPTER

II

THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD


OF THE
eleven works which bear the

name
(

of Spinoza as

author, two, the Ethics and the 'Tractatus Theologico~Politicus y present his entire philosophy in its definitive form. The of God as the Ethics treats of the philosophy of nature whole of nature, and of man as a part of nature. The of Tractatus Theologico-Politicus treats of human society
in Scripture,

organized religion with its beliefs and traditions as embodied and of organized government with its powers
as

and authority

embodied

in established institutions.

All

his other works, to the student of Spinoza's philosophy as

distinguished from

the student of Spinoza's writings, are only ancillary material, not to be studied by themselves but in connection with his two major works. The Short 'Treatise

Man, and His Well-Being (Korte Verhandeling van de Mensch en des zelfs Welstand) is nothing but a tentaGod, tive draft of that phase of Spinoza's philosophy which was
on Gody
later

completed and perfected


is

in the Ethics.

The

Cogitata

of certain philosophic views of scholastic origin, just as his Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae is, as described by Lodewijk Meyer and by Spinoza

Metaphysica

summary

himself, a

summary of "the
T

first

and second parts of Desfragment of

cartes' Principia Philosophiae , together with a

the third,"

and

disregarded by sidered only as introductory to


1

these two works are not to be altogether the student of the Ethics they may be conif
',

it.

The

Tractatus de Intellec-

13 (Opera, IV,

Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae, Praef. (Opera, I, p. 131, 1. 24). Cf. Epistola 11. 13-17). In his letter Spinoza does not mention the fragment of the

third part.

THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD


fus

33

Emendatione

in its present unfinished

form

may

be con-

sidered as supplementary to the discussion of the problems of knowledge and truth which occurs in Part II of the Ethics y

though from the outline of its plan which appears at the beginning of this treatise it may be assumed that it was originally intended to deal also with the problem of the highest of the good which is discussed at length in Parts IV and

The Compendium Grammatices Linguae Hebraeae was probably intended for the use of those who would undertake the study of the Hebrew Bible along the lines suggested
Ethics.

by Spinoza

in

his

Tractatus Politicus

is

fractatus Theologico-Politicus, and the nothing but an extension of the latter

part of the Tractatus 'Theologico-Politicus. His Epistolac^ of course, do not constitute an independent work; and as for his

on the Rainbow (Stelkonstige Reeckening van den Regenboog) and the calculation of chances (Reeckening van
treatises

Kanssen), they have as

much

or as

little to

philosophy as the woolens, linen, furniture,

do with his main and silver which

were

left

by him

at his death. 1

first

All these works of Spinoza, the writing of which, from the dated letter to the end of his life, cover a period of over

to bring to sixteen years/ are in pursuit of one purpose its logical conclusion the reasoning of philosophers through-

out history in their effort to reduce the universe to a unified and uniform whole governed by universal and unchangeable

That philosophers before him had fallen short of the attainment of this purpose-- that they had broken up the universe into discontinuous parts by positing a spiritual
laws. 3
For a list of these, sec "Invcntairc des bicns et des meublcs dclaisse"s par feu Seigneur Benedict de Spinoza," in A. J. Servaas van Rooijen, Inventaire des Livres format) t la Bibhotheque de Benedict Spinozti (La Haye, 1889), pp. in -i 16. 3 \f August, i 661-2 i February, 1677. His Short Treatise, however, may have
1

le

been written before that.


3

Cf. below, Vol. II,

Chapter XXI.

34

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


distinct

God as in man

from a material world, and correspondingly a spiritual soul as distinct from a material body,
beliefs of design in

with the resulting

nature and free will in

man

was

in his

opinion due
in his

to a logical inconsistency in

youth, when he first came out in opposition to traditional belief, he had revealed the main trends of his philosophic thinking. The heresies of which
their thinking.

Already

he was accused are said to have been three

that

God

is

corporeal, that angels do not exist, that the soul is identical with life. 1 Interpreted, these heresies meant a denial of the

existence of an immaterial

God

as distinct

from the material

world, of purely spiritual beings as distinct from material beings, and of a soul as distinct from body, which in maturer

years gave expression to the principles that extension and which thought are attributes of God, that infinite modes
in his

philosophy were the successors of the Intelligences or 2 are both of extension angels in mediaeval philosophy
soul
is

and of thought, and that the

inseparable from the

body. As corollaries to these views he denied also design in nature and freedom of will in man. These are the central
ideas which run through all his works and to establish which he fights against his opponents with their own weapons,

using their own arguments and their own terminology and confronting them with conclusions drawn from their own premises. Whatever differences may be found between his

various works, they are only in the use of terminology, or in the restatement of the views of others, or in the arguments

employed against those views. In his essential doctrines no change or even development is to be noticed in all these
works.
1 Cf. A. Wolf, I'hf Oldest Biography of Spinoza (Lucas* La Vie dejeu Monsieur df Spinoza), pp. 45-46 and 97-98.

Cf. below, pp. 2i8ff.

THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD


The
titles

35

of their

which Spinoza gives his works are all descriptive contents, and some of them are borrowed from, or
after, the titles of

modelled

well-known books.

Such terms
call

by which Spinoza refers to what we Short Treatise,* and ^ractatus, by which he refers
as Opusculum,
Politicus,

the

to

two

of his other books, and such a combination as fheologicowere in common use. Thus, for instance, the short
treatises of

Thomas Aquinas are each described as Opuscuand the younger Buxtorf calls two of his works Tractates lum, de Punctorum and Dissertationes PhiloOrigine
. .

logico-Theologicae.

His Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae 2 retains, of course, the title of Descartes' work upon which it is based. The Cogitata Metaphysica is modelled after such
titles

as

the

Dispi4tationes

Metaphysicae of Suarez

and

the Institutiones Metaphysicae of Burgersdijck.

The word

"compendium"
Hebraeae
in

the

in his Compendium Grammatices Linguae have been suggested by the word "epitome" may elder BuxtorFs Epitome Grammaticae Hebraeae^

though

in the latter case there

was an obvious

justification

term "epitome," for the book was an of his larger work entitled Thesaurus Grammaabridgement
for the use of the

Linguae Sanctae Hebraeae. The title of the Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione is evidently a paraphrase of Ibn
ticus

Gabirol's ethical

read Tractatus de

work which translated into Latin would Animae Virtutum Emendatione* The title

Ethics naturally goes back to Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics. Still, its use by Spinoza as the title of his chief work needs

some explanation.
According to
its

contents the Ethics

may

be divided into

three parts, corresponding to the three parts into which the


1

Epistola 6 (Opera, IV, p. 36, 1. 13). Or, more accurately, Renati DCS Cartes Principiorum Philosophiae Pars /, etll.
Sefer fikfan

Middot ha-Nefesh.

36

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


is

divided and which, according to a statement by Meyer, must have been described by Spinoza himself as De Deoy Anima rationali, summa hominis felicitate. 1 In
Short Treatise

which the present Parts

fact the original division of the Ethics into three parts, in are combined into III, IV, and

one, corresponded to this threefold division of the Short Treatise. Now, in this original division of the Ethics, the

term "ethics"

in its historical

usage describes only the Third

Part, or rather the present last three parts, dealing as they do with the emotions of the soul (Part III), virtue and vice

(Part IV), and human happiness (Part V). These are exactly the topics which are dealt with in the Aristotelian work called the Nicomachean Ethics. The Second Part of Spinoza's Ethics,
dealing with mind or the rational soul, is historically to be described as psychology, and the First Part, dealing with God, is historically to be described as theology, metaphysics, or first philosophy. Furthermore, these three disciplines
-

metaphysics, psychology, and

ethics

which form the sub-

ject-matter of Spinoza's Ethics fall, in the traditional classification of the sciences, under different headings. Kthics is
cal science

contrasted with both psychology and metaphysics as practiwith theoretical science. Again, psychology and

metaphysics, though belonging to the same type of science called theoretical, are contrasted with each other in that

psychology

is

a subdivision of physics which differs from


in
its

metaphysics
therefore,

would seem not

subject-matter/ The term "ethics," to be used quite accurately by

Spinoza as a description of the contents of his work called by that name.


Spinoza, however, had ample justification for the use of
Cf. quotation from the Epilogus to his Philosophta S. Scripturaf hiterprcs; c Exercitatio Paradoxa t in Spinoza Opera y I, Textgestaltungy p. 408. 3 Cf. Metaphysics, VI, i, 10263, 6-16. See below, Vol. II, p. 3.
1

THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD


the term "ethics" as the
title

37

of a book of which the greater

part consisted of metaphysics and psychology. The inclusion of psychology under ethics was recommended by Aristotle

himself in his statement that the student of politics and for that matter, we may say, also the student of ethics

must be

a psychologist. Furthermore, in mediaeval philosophy, psychology, or at least the treatment of the higher

functions of the soul, was removed from physics and placed under metaphysics. Thus the Ihwan al-Safa, 2 Bahya Ibn
5 Pakuda, 3 Judah ha-Levi, 4 Abraham Ibn Ezra, and Shem6 Tob Falaquera, in their enumeration of the topics of meta-

physics, include under


tellect.

it

the science of the soul and the inoriginally

Thus psychology, which

was a branch of

physics, could very well be treated either under ethics or

under metaphysics.

But then metaphysics,


changed
the
first

too, during the

Middle Ages, had

its

position in the classification of the sciences.

As

and the highest of the three branches of theoretical


it

stood, in the original Aristotelian classification, contrasted with ethics, which was the first of the three practiscience,
cal sciences, and, in

accordance with the Aristotelian con-

ception of the superiority of the contemplative life to the active life, it was superior to ethics. In the Middle Ages,

however, when the ethical writings of the pagan authors were supplemented, and sometimes supplanted, by the revealed
Cf.

Ntcomnchean Ethics^

I, 13, 1102:1,

i8-iy.

See below, Vol.


tier

II,

pp. 181-182.

Di

Cf. Kr. Dietcrici, Die Logik nnd Psychologic Abhandlmigen der Ichiean Es-Saf y p. 251. Cf. Ilobot ha-Lebabvt, Introduction.
Cf. CusariiV, 12.
Cf. Yesod

drabcr, p. 15;

Arabic text:

Mora,

I.

Cf.

M.

Steinschneider, Die hebraeischen


Classification of Sciences in

Uebersetzungen des Mittelalters,

2,

quoting from De'ot ha-Pilusofim.


Cf.

my "The

Mediaeval Jewish Philosophy,"


ff.

in

Hebrew Union

College Jubilee

Volume (1925), pp. 290

38

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

writings of religion, ethics sometimes becomes a part of theology or metaphysics. Ethics is thus treated as a part of
1 2 theology by the Ihwan al-afa, al-Mukammas, and Bahya 3 Ibn Pakuda. Furthermore, the relative importance of ethics

and metaphysics

is

sometimes also changed.

Instead of

ethics being a prelude to metaphysics, metaphysics becomes a prelude to ethics. Bahya Ibn Pakuda is especially explicit " All the divisions of philosophy as determined on this point: the difference of their subject-matter are gates which by

God

has opened to rational beings through which they


. .
.

may

The attain a knowledge of the Law and the world. science which is more particularly necessary for the Law is that which is regarded as the highest science, namely,
theology."
4

In his

own

ethical work,

"The

Duties of the

Heart" (Robot ha-Lebabof)^ Bahya gives a concrete example of this view by placing his treatment of theological problems
at the beginning of his book as a sort of preamble to his subsequent treatment of ethical problems.

not without precedent that Spinoza gives the book in which he treats of metaphysics, psychology, and
It is thus

ethics the general title of Ethics.


justified

By

precedent he was quite

subsuming under metaphysics, and

in

psychology either under ethics or to treat of metaphysics as merely a

prelude to ethics. That that was his purpose is quite evident from the structure of the Ethics^ the last part of which, he
says, "concerns the

leads to liberty" 5 "liberty" being one of the terms which Spinoza uses as

method

or

way which
6

synonymous with "blessedness."


1

* 3 < &

Cf. Fr. Dieterici, op. <:/'/., pp. 16-17; Arabic text, op. cit., pp. 252 253. Perush Sejcr Yezirah le-Rabbi Judah ben Barzilai (Berlin, 1885), p. 65. Hobotha-Lebaboty Introduction.
Ibid.

Ethics, V, Praef. (Opera, II, p. 277, Cf. below, Vol. II, p. 311.

11.

7-8).

THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD


As
in the titles of his

39

works, so also in the form in which

they are written Spinoza follows traditional patterns. With the notable exception of the poetical form, in which such
philosophers as Parmenides, Cleanthes, Lucretius, Solomon

Ibn Gabirol, Dante, and Bruno expounded their philosophy, Spinoza experimented with every literary form in which
philosophy throughout its history had been written. The gnomic saying with which the philosophy of the Greeks and the wisdom of Israel had made their beginning is represented in many of Spinoza's propositions, especially those which deal with human conduct, some of which read like verses from the Book of Proverbs or like sayings from the Seven Wise Men. The dialogue form used by Plato and the author of the Book of Job and favored by such authors as Erigena, Abelard, Solomon Ibn Gabirol, Judah ha-Levi, Leo Hebraeus, Galileo, and Bruno is represented in the two Dialogues which are inserted between the second and third chapters of Part I of the Short "Treatise. Philosophy in the form of exegeses of Scriptural passages which appears alike in the Agadic Midrashim of the rabbis and in the writings of Philo, from whom it passed on to the Christian Church Fathers,

and was used by Jews as well as by Christians throughout the Middle Ages, and even up to the very time of Spinoza, is the characteristic literary form of the theological part
of the Tractates Theologico-Pohticus. method of philosophic writing such as

The autobiographical we find in Descartes'

Discours de la Methode and in some of the works of other


philosophers before him is attempted by Spinoza at the beginning of his Tractates de Intellectus Emendatione. The dis-

such as we

cussion of problems of philosophy in letters to correspondents find, for instance, in the writings of Cicero, Seneca,

Maimonides, and Descartes


In addition to
all

is

these forms, Spinoza

represented in his Epistolae* makes use of the geo-

4o
metrical
in the

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


method
in the Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae,
',

Appendix to the Short Treatise and in the Ethics. This method, too, had its precedents. What the external form of this literary method is may be ascertained by a study of the form of Euclid's Elements^
all

which served as a model to method of demonstration

those

in

who used the geometrical philosophy. The geometrical

said to consist of the following parts: First, the primary truths which form the premises in the demonstrations are grouped together and placed apart from the

method may be

demonstrations as the first principles upon which the demonstrations rest, and are divided into definitions, postulates, and axioms or common notions. Second, that which is
sought to be demonstrated, that is, the conclusion which is to be established by the demonstration, is summarized apart from the demonstration in the form of a proposition. Third,
the the demonstration itself reasons from the known, that is, first principles, to the unknown, that is, the conclusion.

Fourth, supplementary deductions, explanations, and propositions are given in

theform of corollaries, scholia, and lemmas.


it is

is called geoEuclid in his work on employed by geometry, was also used in part or in whole in philosophy. An example of one kind of partial application of the geo-

Now

this

method of demonstration, which

metrical, because

method to philosophy is the reduction of philosophic views to the form of propositions, which may be either followed or not followed by demonstrations. This is to be
metrical

found

in

Porphyry's Sententiae ad
wpos
ret vorjra)

Intelligibjlia

Ducentes

('A</>opjuat

and

in Proclus' Imtitntio 'Theologica

(Sroix^oms #0X071/07). It is also to be found in almost every mediaeval compendium of philosophy. Duns Scotus in his fheoremata and Burgersdijck in his Institutiones Logicae even
designate these propositions by the Euclidian term "the-

THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD


orem."

41

An
is

method

imitation of this partial form of the geometrical also to be discerned in Bruno, when he summarizes

the conclusions of his doctrine of the unity and simplicity of God's being in a series of propositions. 1 In Jewish philosophy,
the twenty-six propositions at the beginning of Part II of

Maimonides' Moreh Nebukim y which summarize some of Aristotle's physical and metaphysical principles and to
later added demonstrations, belong to same type of literary composition. Outside of the field of philosophy and quite independently of Euclid's Elements^

which commentators
the

propositions which may be described as geometrical are to be found in various literatures. In Hebrew literature, this

form of proposition is characteristic of the Mishnah, which contains a digest of the teachings of the Tannaim, legal as
well as ethical. So impressed was an anonymous early Hebrew author with the similarity between the Mishnaic form and the form of geometrical propositions, with which he must

have become acquainted through Euclid, that his geometric work written not later than the tenth century and perhaps as
early as the second century, consisting of a series of definitions, constructions, tions,
is

called

and propositions without demonstrahim the Mishnah of Geometry (Mishnat by

ha-Middoi).

An example

geometrical method

of another kind of partial application of the to philosophy may be found in the

identification of the syllogistic

form of demonstration with

into the other.

the Euclidian geometrical form or the transformation of one Thus Aristotle's first argument against the

existence of a

2 vacuum, which is syllogistic in nature and is restated by Crescas in the form of a hypothetico-disjunctive

DC Immenso, I, Ch. i r (Of era Latina, Vol. Cf. J. L. Mclntyre, Giordano Bruno, pp. 192 f.
1

I,

Pars

I,

Neapoli, 1879, pp. 242

ff.).

Physics, IV, 8, 2i4b, 28-2 15a, 24.

42

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


2

1 syllogism, is concluded by both Averroes and Crescas with the equivalent of the phrase quod erat demonstrandum with

which Euclid concludes

The same

his geometrical demonstrations. Euclidian phrase is also used by Avicenna at the conclusion of some of his own syllogistic arguments. 3 Con-

versely, too, Aristotle's arguments against the existence of a circularly moving infinite body in De Caelo, I, 5-7, which

strations

are obviously written in the form of geometrical demonand are restated by Averroes in the form of geometrical demonstrations, are reduced by Crescas to the

4 syllogistic form.

The

identification of the syllogistic

method

of reasoning with the geometrical method is clearly indicated by Saadia, who in his plea for the validity of logical inference as a source of knowledge and for its application to matters
religious describes the conclusion arrived at

by demonstrative

reasoning as that
Finally, in
in philosophic

5 "geometrically demonstrated/' evident imitation of Euclid, we sometimes find

which

is

demonstrations that the

first

principles

upon

which the demonstration hinges are grouped together and put apart from the demonstration itself in the form of a
series of propositions

sometimes even called by the Euclidian terms, definitions, postulates, and axioms or common notions.

Thus Maimonides introduces

his

restatement of the

Aristotelian proofs of the existence of

God by

a series of

twenty-six propositions upon which the proofs


1

rest.

Though

Cf.

my

Crescas' Critique of Aristotle

',

pp. 141-143.

* 3

Cf. tf /V/., p. 339, n. 24.

Cf. Avicenna's treatise

on the soul published by


in Zeitschrift der
f

S.

Landauer under the

title

of

"Die Psychologic des Ibn Sina"


Gescllschajt,
4

Deutschen Morgenlandischen
9.

29 (1875), at tne enc^

Chs.

i, 2,

3,

and
ff.

Cf.

my

Crescas' Critique of Aristotle , pp. 175


y

Emunot we-Deot Introduction: ^v-U^iT


rON^D!}.
Cf. D.

U ^U

(p. 20),

1TT3JVP HD 'DJ

"TiytPTl

Philosophy, p. 183,
far as they are

Neumark, "Saadya's Philosophy," in Essays in Jewish where the phrase used by Saadia is aptly translated by "in so

deduced more geometrico"

THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD

43

these twenty-six propositions, unlike Euclid's "first principles," are themselves subject to demonstration, still they
are used in these proofs of the existence of God as the "first Prior to Maimonides, principles'" are used by Euclid.

Bahya Ibn Pakuda,


istence

in his un-Aristotelian

proof for the ex-

of God, similarly lays down three propositions, which are again subject to proof but are used by him as first principles, and then says: "And when these three propositions

have been established, the conclusion will follow, to him who knows how to use them and to join them together, To "join them together" 2 that the world has a creator/'
l

be taken here as a technical term meaning "to syllogize" (crv\\oyl$<yQai). A contemporary of Maimonides,

may

Alanus de Insulis or Nicolaus of Amiens, follows the same


still clearer indication that he is consciously the geometrical method. In his De Arte seu Artifollowing culis Catholicae Fidei, before starting upon his main work,

method and gives

which consists of a
demonstration
logue a

series of propositions,

each followed by a

in syllogistic form,

he lays

down

in the pro-

number of

definitions

(descriptiones}*

postulates

and axioms (communes animi conceptiones)^ so that the whole book assumes the geometrical form in its
(petitioned) y

completeness. A complete geometrical form is also used in Liber de TrinitatCy which is falsely ascribed to Alanus. 5

Boethius
nitely

in the preface to his

Liber de Hebdomadibus defi-

recommends

the mathematical

method

as the

method

to be followed also in other branches of learning. 6


*
'

Hobot ha-Lebabot,

I, 5.

U^" J

(p- 43),

Cf. below, p. 1 60, n. i. * Cf. Migne, Patrologia Latina, Vol. 210, Col. 597. s Cf. Cl. Bacumker, "Handschriften zu den Werken des Alanus," in Philosophise hes Jahrbuch, VI (1893), pp. 428-429.
6

Cf.

M. Baumgartner, Die

Philosophic des dlanus de Insulis (Miinster, 1896),

pp. 27-32;

Ueberweg-Baumgartner, Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophic der

44
It

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


1

was not without precedent, therefore, that one of Descartes objectors suggested to him to present his Meditationes in the geometrical form, that Descartes himself made an attempt at it, and that Spinoza attempted it in the Ap-

pendix to the Short Treatise, carried

it

out

in

full

in his

Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae and Ethics, and wanted 1 to use it in his Hebrew Grammar.
the geometrical method which with all his predeceswas only a casual attempt, and which Descartes himself, who attempted it, explicitly characterized as a method which "cannot so conveniently be applied to these meta2 is adopted by Spinoza and used conphysical matters/'
Still,

sors

sistently in his discussions of metaphysical matters throughout his chief philosophic work. Mere imitation of his predecessors cannot therefore explain his use of the geometrical method. Some other explanation will have to be found for it.

Many students of Spinoza regard his use of the geometrical


method
as a logical consequence of his mathematical

way

of

looking at things. One of his early biographers declares that " Spinoza had a geometrical mind" (I* esprit geometre)* Erd" mann says: For no other reason than because it is a necessary consequence of the mathematical way of looking at things, the geometrical form of proof is of great significance,

even where the proofs themselves are insipid and marred by inaccuracies.'' 4 Freudenthal maintains that "it was not
patristischen

und scholastischen Zeit (loth cd., 1915), pp. 326-327. For other examples of attempts at the application of the geometrical method to philosophy, mostly of the type described by us here as partial geometrical method, see S. Hahn, Thomas Bradwardinus (Miinster, 1905), pp. 13-14.
1

Cf. Preface to Opera

Posthuma quoted

in

Spinoza Opera,

I,

Textgestaltung^

p. 623.

Secundac Responsiones (Oeuvres, VII, p. 156, 11. 25-26). Pierre Bayle, Dictionaire Historique et Critique (ist ed., 1695-1697), under "Spinoza (Benoit de)"; A. Wolf, The Oldest Biography of Spinoza, p. 160.
*

Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophic^

II,

272.2 (English translation, II,

p. 58).

THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD

45

therefore a capricious notion, which might as well have been dispensed with, that made Spinoza style his system Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demons frafa ^ on the contrary, the method
called for in the title follows
1

thought/*
in a

from the inner necessity of his And Joachim concludes that "the form of
is

Spinoza's exposition

essential to its matter.

He

casts his

geometrical mould, because the subject-matter, system as he conceives it, demands such treatment." 2

But

let

us consider
is

all

the facts in the case


for the

and

see

whether

assumption that the nature of Spinoza's philosophy demanded that it should be written in the geometrical form. The points which we shall try to
there really

any ground

Both Descartes and Lodewijk Meyer make a distinction between the geometrical method of demonstration, which may be either synthetic or analytic, and the geometrical form of literary exposition, which,
establish are as follows:
(i)

whether synthetic or analytic, is to be modelled after the (2) The geometrical literary form of Euclid's Elements.

method of demonstration of the synthetic type


tory of philosophy.
(3)

is

nothing but

valid syllogistic reasoning as practised throughout the his-

The geometrical method of demon-

stration, whether synthetic or analytic, need not necessarily


in the geometrical literary form, and, conversely, the use of the geometrical literary form is not determined by the subject-matter of which it treats. (4) Spinoza's mathematical way of looking at things means only the denial of

be written

design in nature and freedom in man, and this need not necessarily be written in the geometrical literary form. The fullest discussion of the geometrical method is to be

found

in

the phrase "geometrical


1

Descartes Regulae ad Directionem Ingenii. method" in either two of


II, pp.

Though
its

forms

Spinoza Leben und Lthre (ed. Gebhardt, 1927),

iio-ui.

A Study

of'the Ethics of Spinoza, p. 13.

46

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


ordine geometrico and more geometrico

does not occur

there, Descartes openly advocates that "in our search for

the direct road towards truth we should busy ourselves with no object about which we cannot attain a certitude equal to that of the demonstrations of arithmetic and geometry." This method, which by implication may be called the geo1

contrasted by him with that method of philosophizing which others have already discovered and those weapons of the schoolmen, probable syllogisms, which
metrical method,
is

"

are so well suited for dialectical combats."

The

contrast

between the old

syllogistic

method of

the schoolmen

and the
as
*

new geometrical method which he proposes is described follows: The former deals with "probable knowledge"
"probable opinion"; attainment of truth;
4

or

its
it

object

is

"dialectics"

and not the

had no

utility

save the solution of

The geometrical method, on the other he says, deals with "true and evident cognition," ^ its hand, object is the discovery of truth, and it is to be employed to
empty problems.
6

This new geometrical method, he then continues, is based on intuition and deduction. It starts with premises which must be self-evidently true, and
solve useful problems.

by the method of inference, profrom the known to the unknown. 8 ceeding logically In analyzing these statements of Descartes about the geoit

arrives at conclusions

metrical method,

would

call

we find that it is nothing but what Aristotle a scientific demonstration. Descartes' insistence

that truth can be attained only by premises which are selfevidently true and by deduction is nothing but a repetition

of Aristotle's theory that demonstrative reasoning as ex1

Regulae ad Dircctionem Ingenii,


Ibid., II (p. 363, Ibid., II (p. 363,
11.
11.
11.

II (Oeuvres,
3 s
i

21-24).
14-15).

X, p. 366, Md., II (p.


IKd., II
(
.

11.

6-9).
11.
1.

362,

14-15).
23).
5).

P 363,

Ibid.,
8

IV

(p.

373,

26

ff.).

Ibid., II (p. 362,

1.

Ibid.,

IX and XI.

THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD


pressed in
"
true,

47

any syllogism must start with premises which are primary, immediate, more known than, prior to, and
"
l

the cause of, the conclusion.

Furthermore,

if

we study

carefully Descartes' language we shall notice that he does not really contrast his own method with syllogisms in general but with what he calls "probable syllogisms" or what

Aristotle

would call a "dialectical (5taXe/crtAc6s) syllogism" and a "contentious (epumfcAs) syllogism," 2 for Descartes' "probable syllogisms" are syllogisms which consist of what

Aristotle calls probabilities (ret c^oa), and "probabilities," according to Aristotle, yield a "dialectical syllogism" and a "contentious syllogism." 3 This is exactly what Descartes

means when, speaking of "probable

syllogisms," he says that 4 they are so well suited for "contentions" (bellis) or, as the French version translates it, "dialectical combats" (combats

de la dialectique). 3 His geometrical method, as described by him so far, is thus not contrasted by him with the syllogistic

method
method.

as such, but rather with the abuse of the syllogistic

on he adds a new point to his conof the geometrical method. Ancient geometricians ception were acquainted with two methods of proof, one by analysis

But

as Descartes goes

and the other by synthesis, though the proofs

in Euclid's

Elements are of the synthetic type. Descartes refers to the antiquity of the analytic method when he says: "Indeed I

seem
in

to recognize certain traces of this true


. .

mathematics
is

Pappus and Diophantus.


1

But

my

opinion

that

these writers then with a sort of low cunning, deplorable inAnalytic a Posteriora,
Topics,
* * 5

I, 2,

71 b, 21-22.

I, i,

looa, 29-30,

and loob, 23-24.


II (Oeuvres,

Ibid., looa, 29-1 oob, 24.

Regtilae

ad Directionem Ingenii,
la Direction de
I*

X,

p. 363,

1.

23).

Regies

pour

Esprit, II (Oeuvres de Descartes, ed. Cousin, XI,

p. 206).

48

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

l deed, suppressed this knowledge." These ancients, however, performed their analyses of geometrical problems by means

of construction; Descartes performs them by means of algebraic calculations, the process of which is known as analytical

change he extends the method of analysis to everything within the realm of mathematics, or, as he expresses himself, to any object in which "the question
geometry.

By

this

of measurement arises."
matics."
3

This he

calls

"universal mathe-

further, he applies the method of other sciences, thus making the knowledge of analysis to the 4 all things mathematical.
still

But going

From

this analysis of Descartes*

own conception

of the

geometrical or mathematical method, it is quite clear that he means by it only the method of demonstration itself and

not at

all

the literary form in which Euclid happens to couch


used, the synthetic or analytic, there anything Descartes says that it has to be
is

the demonstration. Whichever kind of demonstration of the

geometrical method
is

no indication

in

written in the form which Euclid employs in his Elements. That the application of the geometrical method of demonstration to philosophic problems does not necessarily require

the use of the external literary form of the Euclidian geometric propositions is still more evident from Descartes*

Secundae Responsiones. In a reply to one of his objectors who counselled him to propound the arguments of meditations in the geometrical
distinguishes in the "geometrical mode of writing" (modo scribendi geometrico) two things, namely, the order of proof and the method of proof
1

method (more geometrico}* he

Regulae ad Directionem Ingenii, IV (Oeuvres, X, p. 376,


Ibid.,

11.

21-26).

3 4 s

Ibid.,
/*/</.,

IV IV IV

(p. 378,
(p. 378, (p.

II. 11. 11.

3-4).
8-9).
5 ff.).

379,

Secundae Objections (Oeuvres, VII,

p. 128,

11.

13-17).

THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD


(ordinem
scilicet,

49
r
.

6? rationem demonstrandi)
it,

As

for

the

" merely in putting forward those Regulae, as consisting first that should be known without the aid of what things

"order of proof/' Descartes explains

as he does in his

comes subsequently, and arranging all other matters so that 2 their proof depends solely on what precedes them." This, as we have shown, is nothing but a repetition of what is
generally considered to be true of any good syllogistic argument. The "method of proof" is described by Descartes,

again as in his Regulae, as being twofold. One is analytic; the other is synthetic. The former reasons as it were a -priori, from cause to effect; the latter reasons as it were a posteriori,

from

effect

to

cause,

the latter

being, however,
in

the only
writings.
far as

method employed by ancient geometers

their

Now,

in his Meditationes,

says Descartes, in

so

he tried to put forward those things first that should be known without the aid of what comes subsequently, he
did certainly follow the geometrical order of proof. But he admits that, unlike the ancient geometers who had employed

only the synthetic method of proof, he employed in his Meditationes the analytic method, and he did so for the very good
reason that he did not believe that the synthetic method is applicable to the discussion of metaphysical matters. For
the synthetic

method of
"

proof, he says,

must

start with cer-

tain presuppositions or

primary notions" (primae notiones)

which are granted by all. Now, in geometry there are certain primary notions which "harmonize with the use of our
senses, and are readily granted by all"; in metaphysics, however, "nothing causes more trouble than the making
1

Sccundae Responsiones (Otuvres, VII,


Ibid. (p. 155,11. 11-14).
Ibid. (p. 155,
11.

p. 155,

11.

8-10).

J 3

23-24; p. 156,

11.

6-7).

Cf.

French version (Oeuvres, ed.

Adam

and Tannery, IX, pp. 121-122).

50

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


its

the perception of

primary notions clear and distinct

though in their own nature they are as intelligible as, or even more intelligible than, those the geometricians study." l

"This is the reason," concludes Descartes, "why I used the form of Meditations rather than that of Disputations [and Questions], as do philosophers, or that of Theorems and 2 Still, despite his explanation Problems, as do geometers."
of his preference for the analytic method over the synthetic method, he appends at the end of his reply to the second ob3 as he dejections "something in the synthetic style/'
scribes
sists

This "something in the synthetic style" conit. of his "arguments demonstrating the existence of God and the distinction between soul and body drawn up in geometrical fashion/' 4 in which he begins like Euclid with a

series of Definitions, Postulates,

and Axioms or

Common

Notions, and then follows with Propositions each of which 5 is proved by a demonstration.

Here, then, as in his Regulae ad Directionem Ingenii y Descartes makes it quite clear that by the geometrical method in its primary and general sense he means nothing

but what Aristotle would

call

a scientific demonstration con-

sisting of premises which are self-evidently true and of a conclusion deduced from those premises by logical inference. Again as in his Regulae the geometrical method is divided
>

by him into two types, the analytic and the synthetic. Now, the analytic type of the geometrical method, we know, is as1

Ibid. (p. 156, Ibid. (p. 157,


p. 123).

1.

2-p. 157,

I.

10).

11.

17-19).

Cf. French version (Oeuvres^ ed.

Adam and

Tannery,

IX,
3 <

Ibid. (p. 159,11. 13-14). Ibid. (p. 160, 11. i ff.).

It

is

the

first

principles

to be noted that, unlike Descartes, Spinoza includes no Postulates among which precede his propositions. Postulates are used by him,

however, between Props. 13 and 14 of Ethics, II (repeated in Ethics, III) and at the beginning of Part III ofPrincipia Philosophiae Cartesianae.

THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD

51

sociated historically with a certain external literary form, though Descartes makes no reference to it here. It is the

form

in

which the few

relics

of the analytic demonstrations

of the ancient geometricians and Descartes' own analytical geometry are written. But this external literary form was

not essential, according to Descartes' own admission, to the geometrical method of the analytic type. In Descartes' ap-

method to philosophical problems it took the form, as he himself says, of meditations. The external literary form of the synthetic type of the geometrical method
plication of this
is

likewise associated historically with certain external liter-

ary forms which are alluded to by Descartes himself. In the past, he seems to say, it had taken two literary forms:
that of "Disputations [and Questions]," by which he means the method used in the scholastic writings, and, secfirst,

ond, that of "Theorems and Problems," by which he means the method used in Euclid's Elements. The inference to be

drawn from
erary form

this statement, again,


is

is

that the Euclidian

lit-

not essential to the synthetic geometrical

to philosophical problems, inasmuch as the scholastic "Disputations and Questions" is another type of literary form mentioned by Descartes as one which can

method when applied

geometrical method of demonstrahe himself, as a concession to his correspondent, tion, though attempts to reduce a few of his philosophical arguments to the Euclidian literary form.

be used

in the synthetic

The same distinction within geometrical method between a method of demonstration and a method of literary exposiMeyer's Preface to Spinoza's Principia Philosophiae Carfesianae. He speaks there of the "wretched plight of philosophy" (niiserimam Philosophiae fortem) which finds itself without a proper method. The method in
tion
is

to be

found

in

Opera,

I,

p. 128,

11.

17-18.

52

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


in the scholastic literature,

vogue

which Descartes

refers to

as "Disputations and Questions," is described by him as "a method where the end is attained through definitions and
logical divisions

which are indirectly connected with each

other and interspersed with numerous questions and exI As against this he describes the new method planations.**

which was developed by those who were desirous to "leave to posterity some studies besides mathematics established
with absolute certainty.** He refers to this method as the "mathematical method** (methodo mathematicd)? At first
.

it

would seem that Meyer

refers here to the Euclidian

liter-

ary form. But as he proceeds and restates Descartes* words in the Secundae Responsiones it becomes clear that he deals
here not with the geometrical literary form but rather with the geometrical method of demonstration, which, following
Descartes, he divides into analytic and synthetic. Later, speaking of the Euclidian literary form of demonstration, he refers to it as "more Geometris" 3 But in the entire discus-

nothing to indicate that the application of the geometrical literary form by Spinoza to Descartes* Principia Philosophiae was the outgrowth of the mathematical method
sion there
is

of demonstration employed by Descartes. On the contrary, the indications are that it was considered to be something

imposed upon

it

externally.

In Spinoza, beyond the mention of the fact that he has reduced parts of Descartes' Principia Philosophiae to the 4 geometrical literary form and references to its use in the

work which

later
its
11.
1. 1.

came

to be

discussion of
Ibid.) p. 127, Ibid., p. 128,

nature as
ff.

known as the Ethics * there is no a method of demonstration. He

24
21.
27.

Ibid.^ p, 129,

Epistola 13 (Oeuvrts, IV, p. 63, Epistola 2 (p.


8,
1.

1.

13).
1.

15); cf. Epistola 3 (p. 10,

7).

THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD


makes

53

use, however, of certain mathematical analogies, such indeed as are also to be found in the works of Descartes.

these mathematical analogies Spinoza goes much In Descartes the mathematical further than Descartes.

But

in

analogies are used only as illustrations in his discussions of the method of demonstration. In no way do these analogies

imply that Descartes conceived the universe as a whole to be governed by laws of necessity like those which prevail in
mathematics.
In his universe, according to his own statements, there was still room for final causes, for a divine will, and for human freedom. In Spinoza, on the other hand, the
exist-

mathematical analogies are used as illustrations of the

ence of inexorable laws of necessity throughout nature.

Spinoza gives expression to this view when on several occasions he declares that all things follow from the infinite nature of God according to that same necessity by which it
follows from the essence of a triangle that its three angles are 1 equal to two right angles, and when he declares that the

human race would have been kept in darkness to all eternity with regard to final ends "if mathematics, which does not deal with ends, but with the essence and properties of forms,
had not placed before us another
2 rule of truth," or, finally,

when
sider

in

denying

human freedom he
3

declares, "I shall con-

human

actions

and appetites just

as

if I

were consider-

ing lines, planes, or bodies." It is these two principles the

the denial of final causes in


in

universe

and of freedom

human

actions

that

Spinoza wishes to illustrate by his use of mathematical analogies. It is only this, and nothing more, that his mathematical
1

way
I,

of looking at things means.


II,

Beyond

this, there

Ethics,

Prop. 17, Schol.;


II, 9.

Prop. 49, Schol.; IV, Prop. 57, Schol.; Cogitata


11.

Mttaphysica,
2

Ethics,
*

I,

Appendix (Opera,

II, p. 79,

32-34).

Ibid., Ill, Praef. (end).

54
is

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

nowhere any indication that he in any way connected his use of the geometrical literary form with this his mathe-

matical way of looking at things, nor can there be any such connection logically established on independent grounds. On the contrary, the fact that his Short ^Treatise^ where his

mathematical way of looking at things


oped,
is

is

already fully devel-

not

written in the geometrical literary

form would

seem

to indicate that the geometrical literary

form was not

a logical consequence of his mathematical way of looking at things. Furthermore, the fact that he had applied the

geometrical literary form to the philosophy of Descartes, which does not look at things mathematically in Spinoza's
sense,

would

also

seem

to indicate that there

is

no

logical

connection between the contents of a philosophy and the


particular literary form in which it is written. Finally, the fact that Spinoza had intended to apply it to the grammar of the Hebrew language would similarly seem to indicate that

there

is

no logical connection bteween the geometrical

liter-

ary form and the subject-matter to which it is applied. The thought that may occur to one that the planned application of the geometrical form to the Hebrew grammar may somehow be connected with a metaphysical conception of language which students of Spinoza maintain to have detected in his

theory of the priority of nouns to adjectives and verbs in the Hebrew language may be dismissed as a passing fancy.
'

Spinoza himself does not explicitly link his grammatical view as to the relation of adjectives and verbs to nouns with
metaphysical view as to the relation of modes to substance, and if he did ever link them at all in his mind,
his

in
J.

"Anhang"

Compendium Grammatices Linguae Hebraeae^ Chs. V and VIII; J. Bernays to C. Schaarschmidt, Des Cartes und Spinoza (Bonn, 1850), p. 197; Freudenthal, Spinoza Leben und Lehrc (ed. Gebhardt, 1927), I, p. 291; N.
1

Cf.

Forges,

"Spinozas Compendium der hebriiischen


p. 146.

Grammatik,"

in

Chronicon

Spinozanum y IV (1924-1926),

THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD


it

55

must have been

those

who

nature of a literary analogy. All have attached a metaphysical significance to this


in the

view of Spinoza have failed to notice the fact that an explicit analogy between the relation of adjectives and verbs to nouns

and the

relation of accidents to substance occurs also in the

1 philosophical grammar of Profiat Duran, and yet no implication of any metaphysical conception of language is to

be discerned there.
If, as we have been trying to show, there is no logical connection between the substance of Spinoza's philosophy and the form in which it is written, his choice of the Euclidian

geometrical form

is

to be explained

on other grounds. Pri-

marily, we may say, the reason for its choice was pedagogical, the clearness and distinctness with which the geometrical form was believed to delineate the main features of an argu-

ment and to bring them same reason that one

into high relief. It was used for the uses outlines and diagrams. This

pedagogical reason for the application of the geometrical form to philosophy is clearly stated by Descartes' objector,

when he suggested
"This
is

to

Descartes the use of this form.


if,

He says:

why

it

would be well worth the doing

hard upon

your solution of the difficulties, you advanced as premises certain definitions, postulates, and axioms, and thence drew
conclusions, conducting the whole proof by the geometrical method, in the use of which you are so highly expert. Thus

would you cause each reader


as
it

to

have everything

in his

mind,

were, at a single glance, and to be penetrated throughout with a sense of the Divine being." 2 Equally pedagogical is the reason given by Meyer for the reduction of Descartes'

philosophy to the Euclidian geometrical form by Spinoza. Conceiving the two types of geometrical method, the Euclid1

Maaseh

EJod, Ch. 9. Secundac Object! ones (Oeuvres y VII,

p. 128,

11.

13-19).

56

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

ian synthetic and the Cartesian analytic, as mutually complementary, the former as the method by which mathemati" cal truths are written down" (conscriptae) 1 and the latter

method by which they are disco vered" (inventae)? Meyer recommends the rewriting of Descartes* philosophy, which was discovered by the analytic method, in the Euclidas the

"

ian synthetic method, for the benefit of those who, having read Descartes' philosophy in the non-geometrical form in which it is written, "are not able to follow it for themselves,

nor can they teach


the

it

to others,"

and

also for the benefit of

many who have made Descartes' opinions and dogmas only a matter of memory and are unable to demonstrate
them and defend them against attacks. 4 It is thus always for the benefit of the reader, and because of the clearness with which it is supposed to state an argument, and not because the philosophic system itself demands it, that the geometrical form
is

made

use

of.

But there may have been another reason which had prompted philosophers at the time of Descartes and Spinoza
to turn to the use of the geometrical form. It may have been as a reaction against the new literary forms which since the

Renaissance, under the influence of the works of ancient writers, had been imported into philosophic writings, where

had taken the place of the syllogistic style. The Renaissance philosophers had an aversion toward the syllogistic method of the mediaevals, not so much on intellectual
it

grounds as on purely aesthetic grounds; not so much because the method itself could not be properly used in the

method could be abused and be made

discovery of truth or because of the ease with which the to lend itself to give a

semblance of proof to things which were not true as because


1

Opera,

I, p.

129,
1.

1.

16.

Ibid.
Ibid., p. 129,
11.
1

Ibid., p. 129,

8.

ff.

THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD


it

57
dissatis-

was bare and bleak and

skeleton-like.

They were

fied

satisfied

with syllogisms for the same reason that people are diswith food that is merely nourishment, with clothes that are merely warm, or with a house that is merely a shelter.
syllogistic

The

method may have been

practical

and

useful,

but it lacked form and was not pleasing to the eye and the ear. They therefore began to experiment with new literary forms, more polished, more refined, and more resonant
dialogues after the manner of Plato, poetry after the manner of Lucretius, and rhetorical prose after the manner of
Cicero.

ment.

But all these new literary forms proved a disappointInstead of merely garbing the logical nakedness of that logical syllogism which must inevitably the syllogism be implied in every sound argument they sometimes
and reasoning. Philosophy became metaphorical and efWhat was thus gained in grace was lost in accuracy and precision. A new method in presenting philosophical arguments was needed. To return to the old syllogistic

served as a cloak to cover up the lack of any kind of logic


fusive.

method openly and directly would have meant a return to scholasticism, for which the world was not yet ready. They
therefore returned to
cal form.
it indirectly by adopting the geometrithe philosophers of the seventeenth century the blessed word "mathematics" served as a veneer of

To

respectability for the discredited syllogism. In the case of Spinoza there may have been reason for his use of the geometrical form. It

still

another
in order

was

as

to avoid the need of arguing against opponents. The Ethics y we shall show, primarily consists of conclusions of an elabo-

rate criticism of traditional philosophy. Had Spinoza followed the old traditional method, the method used by rabbis and schoolmen alike, the comparatively small volume of the

Ethics would have run into

many bulky

tomes. That method

58

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

required that the various views held by opponents on each problem should be stated, that the pros and cons for each view should be reproduced, that refutations and rebuttals

should be marshalled, and that only then the author's own view should be given and its superiority to those of others
Spinoza, for reasons which can only be explained psychologically, did not want to go through all this elaborate formality. In a letter to Oldenburg he says, "It

pointed out.

custom to expose the errors of others," and in another place he expresses a reluctance "to seem to be deis

not

my

sirous of exposing the errors of others." place he declares himself not to be bound

In

still

another

"to discuss what

every one

may dream."

By

geometrical form he could avoid

resorting to the use of the all this, at least openly.

to imply that by his use of the form his philosophy, like the geometry of Euclid, geometrical is the unfoldment of certain a priori self-evident truths. For
his axioms, properly understood, are not necessarily selfevident truths, any more than his propositions are necessarily new truths discovered by demonstration. Most often

But Spinoza never meant

they are merely restatements of generally accepted mediaeval brocards. It will be noticed that the "Axioms" mentioned
in a letter

from Oldenburg

and

also in the geometric ap-

pendix to the Short treatise are called "Propositions" in


the Ethics for the terms "definitions," "axioms," "propositions," and their like are used by Spinoza more or less in',

discriminately as conventional labels to be pasted on here and there in order to give to his work the external appearance of a work of geometry. What the motives were that

prompted Spinoza
1

to depart

from the old form of exposition


11.

3
*

Epistola 2 (Oeuvres, IV, p. 8, 11. 18-19). Tractates de Intellects Emendatione, 95 (Opera, II, p. 34, Ethics, II, Prop. 49, Schol. (Opera, II, p. 133, 1. 20).

31-32).

Epistola 3.

THE GEOMETRICAL METHOD

59

can be only conjectured, but among them there may have been the desire to produce a book which externally would be different from
all

other books on philosophy.

He had

something new to say, and he wished to say it in a new way. And >erhaps, also, he chose the geometrical form in order to
;

avoid the temptation of citing Scripture.

But

still,

the form in which the Ethics

is

written,

we have

reason to believe, is not the form in which it formulated itself in the mind of Spinoza. He must at first have thought

out

all its

problems

in their full detail after the

manner of

the rabbis and scholastics, and only afterwards, when he came to write them down, did he break them up into geometric
propositions.

onstrated

in

thus behind our present Ethics, demgeometrical order, an Ethics demonstrated in

There

is

own fragmentary attempt


istence of
in

rabbinical and scholastic order, just as behind Descartes' to draw up his proofs of the ex-

God and

of the distinction between soul and body

geometrical fashion are the corresponding parts of the Meditationes, just as behind Spinoza's Principia Philosoph'tae Cartesianae
is

Descartes* Principia Philosophiae, and

just as behind the geometric Appendix to Spinoza's own Short Treatise is Chapter II of Part I of that book. Now,

Descartes himself admits that his geometric fragment does not give the full content of the arguments as they are unfolded in the Meditationes. "I should, however, like them kindly to notice," he says, "that I have not cared to include here so much as comes into my Meditations nor shall
.

explain in

such accurate detail that which

do include."

Spinoza similarly admits that the geometrical method might not convey easily to all the readers what he had in his mind, for in a Scholium, where he gives an outline of the topics
dealt with in a subsequent group of propositions, he says:
1

Sccundac Rf sponsions (Oeuvres, VII,

p. 159,

11.

15-19).

60

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

"Before, however, I begin to demonstrate these things by our full geometrical method, I should like briefly to set forth here these dictates of reason, in order that what I have
in

jny mind about them


l

may

be easily comprehended by
II of Spinoza's Short Treatise,

all."

Imagine now

that Descartes* Meditationes and Prin-

cipia Philosophiae
I,

and Chapter

were lost, and only Descartes*

own geometric

fragrient,

and Spinoza's Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae, and the geometric Appendix to the Short Treatise were left. In that
case, to understand fully these extant geometrically wr.tten

works we should have


Ethics
lies

to reconstruct the lost

works upon

which they are based. Similarly, to understand our prejent we must construct that hypothetical Ethics which
behind
it.

But how
Ethics?
in the

we to go about constructing that hypothetical The answer to this question has already been gr^en preceding chapter where we have discussed the method
are
in the reconstruction

employed by us
lies

behind the Ethics.

We may now

of the reasoning that proceed to the actual

task of reconstruction.
1

Ethics, IV, Prop. 18, Schol.

CHAPTER

III

DEFINITION OF SUBSTANCE AND


THERE

MODE

are certain types of literature which are inseparably associated in our minds with some sort of formal, conventional beginning. We thus all expect a fairy tale to begin with "Once upon a time," and a Christmas ballad with

"'Twas the night before Christmas/ A Biblical narrative always suggests to our mind the phrase "And it came to pass/' and epic poems, from the Iliad to the latest parody, begin with an invocation to the Muse. I suppose we should all be sorely disappointed if we woke up some fine morning
1

to find that Caesar's

Commentaries on (he Gallic Wars did not

begin with the familiar "Gallia est omnis divisa in partes


tres."

Now,

like

fairy tales,

and Christmas ballads, and

Caesar's Commentaries^ metaphysical treatises in the Middle Ages as a rule set out on their philosophical investigation by
a statement which might be reduced to the following formula:
All

Being

is

divided, etc.
the
All
o*>,
2

The term "Being" which I have used here represents Arabic maujud* the Hebrew nimza, and the Latin ens. these three terms are meant to reproduce the Greek TO
which
is

used by Aristotle as the main subject of his tenfold division of categories. But at this point the mediaevals depart from Aristotle's method of procedure. say outright at the very beginning that Being
ten categories,

They do not
is

divided into

very good reason that they do not seem to take the Aristotelian tenfold classification of catefor the

and

62
gories

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


as does

[ETHICS,

John Stuart Mill and others who have to be a primary, logical, and accriticized or ridiculed it curate classification of Being. In their opinion, it would
seem, when Aristotle wanted to be logical and accurate he simply divided Being into substance and accident; its subsequent subdivision into ten categories was meant to be merely tentative and was by no means fixed. It is with the
logical division of
fore, that the

Being into substance and accident, theremediaevals mean to begin their metaphysical

here, again, they do not exactly say that of beginning directly with the statement outright. Instead that all Being is divided into substance and accident, they

investigation.

But

begin with a rather broader and more general statement, and

by gradual paring,

whittling,

and edging

finally

narrow

it

down ment

to the Aristotelian phraseology.

usually reads that all Being is dwells within a dwelling and that which does not dwell
1

Their opening statedivided into that which

within a dwelling.
gated, and a

The term "dwelling" is then investi2 special kind of dwelling, named "subject," is
At
last the wished-for state-

differentiated from the others.

ment
which

is

is

arrived at, namely, that all Being is divided into that in itself and that which is in a subject, and the

former

is

given the

given the name of substance whereas the latter is name of accident. Thus the formula that everything

which exists is either in itself or in another thing occurs in the 4 3 writings of such philosophers as Joseph Ibn Zaddik, Albo
*.
2

Cf.

my

Crescas* Critique of Aristotle, p. 577.


Cf. ibid.

K2713,
3

fr

JJPJA.

viroKtlntvov.

'Qlam l^a\an^ I, ii (p. 8): "Every existing thing of the things which exist inevitably falls under one of the following four classes: [a] It exists in itself, \f\ it
exists in another thing, exists both in itself
*

[c] it

exists neither in itself nor in another thing, or [d]

it

and

in

another thing."

which

'Ibbarim, II, ii: "Things which exist are divided first into two classes, those exist in themselves and those which exist in other things."

PROP, i]

DEFINITION OF SUBSTANCE AND

MODE

63
is

and the formula that everything either a substance or an accident occurs still more widely

and Burgersdijck/

in

the writings of such philosophers as Alfarabi, 2 Algazali, 3 Abra-

ham Ibn Daud, Jacob


4

6 5 Anatolio, and Burgersdijck. A combination of these two formulae occurs in Eustachius a Sancto

divides ens into ens per se and ens per accident, 1 though he does not use the expressions ens per se and ens per accidens in the ordinary sense of substance and accident. 8

Paulo,

who

All these formulae

may

be traced to Aristotle's statement


it

that
is

things can exist apart and some cannot, and the former that are substances/' 9
is

"some

This

and

this is

chosen to

how mediaeval thinkers begin their philosophy; how Spinoza would have begun his Ethics had he write it more scholastico rabbinicoque. But as a

matter of

fact, even in its present artificial, geometrical form the Ethics begins with this statement, logically though not

spatially.

It

is

contained in Axiom

I,

which reads: "Every-

thing which

is, is

either in itself or in another/'

When we

come, however, to Spinoza's formal definition


is

of that thing which


1

in itself, labelled

by the good old name

Institutioncs Metaphysicae, Lib.

I,

Cap.

II,

dimus Entia quaedam per


per se subsistunt."
2

se subsistere, alia

non per

Thesis VIII: "Praetereadeprehense, sed in iis subsistere, quae

Mehut
exists

ha-Nefesh, in Kdelmann's

which
*

must inevitably be Ma%a$id al-Falasifah, II,


I,
i

Hemdah Genuzah, I (p. 46): either a substance or an accident."


(p. 79):

"Everything

"Existence

is

divided into substance and

accident."
4

Ernunah Rama/j,

(p. 4):

"Things which

exist are divided first into substance

and accident."
s

Ruah Hen, Ch.

10:

"All things which exist must inevitably be either subThesis III: "Itaque partiemur Ens

stance or accident."
6

primo
7

Institutiones Metaphysicae, Lib. II, Cap. in substantiam et accidens."

I,

Summa

Philosophiae, IV: Metaphysica, Pars

I:

"Prima
8

igitur divisio entis latissime

I, Posterior Disputatio, Quaestio sumti est in ens Rei, et ens Rationis: Secunda,

entis rei, in ens Per se et ens Per accidens."


Cf. ibid., Quaestio IV.
9

Metaphysics, XII,

5,

loyob, 36-10713,

i.

with the mediaeval definition, we find that while in part they read alike, Spinoza's definition contains a new additional element. The mediaeval
it

64 " substance/'

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


1

[ETH!CS,

and compare

definition simply reads, as has been said, that substance

is

that which
to "that

is

in itself,
is

which

2 But Spinoza adds i.e., not in a subject. not in itself" the statement "and is con-

ceived through itself" (Def. III). Again, the mediaeval definition of accident is that which is in another thing. 3 Here,
again, using the term "mode" (modus) which he identifies with the affections (ajjectiones) 4 of substance, Spinoza first
defines
it like

the traditional accident as "that which

is

in

another thing," but then adds the clause "through which " also it is conceived (Def. V) Furthermore, why did Spinoza
.

reject the term

"accident" (accidens)

in his definitions at the

beginning of the First Part of the Ethics , and replace it by the term "mode"? And why, too, did he not mention the

term "subject"
Shall

in his definitions
all

of substance and

mode?

we say

that

these are matters of mere accident or

This might pass as an explanathe Ethics to be an accidentally, carelessly, and indifferently written book. But we are now working on the assumption that the Ethics is as careful a piece of
carelessness or indifference?
tion if

we considered

In one of his letters he speaks, however, of "substantia sive ens."


1.

Epistola 9

(Opera, IV, p. 44,


2

17

and

1.

35).
i

Maka$id

al-Falasifah y II,

(p. 82):

"Substance

is

isting thing not in a subject";

Emunah Ramah,

I, i

a term applied to every ex(p. 4): "Substance is that

existing thing

which

is

not in need of a subject"; Burgersdijck, Institutiones Meta-

physicae. Lib. II, Cap. I, Thesis IV: "Substantia est Ens per se subsistens. Per se subsistens non excludit in hac defmitione dependentiam ab omnibus causis (nam
dici potest per se subsistere quam solus Deus) sed solummodo dependentiam a subjecto." * Emunah Ramah> I, (p. 4): "An accident is that which exists in [another] thing"; Thomas Aquinas, Quaestiones Quodlibetales Quodlibetum IX, Quaest. 3, Art. 5, Ad Secundum: "Substantia est quod per se est; vel, accidens est quod est
i
t

hoc sensu nullum Ens

in alio."

Cf. below, Vol. II, pp. 193-194.

PROP, i]

DEFINITION OF SUBSTANCE AND

MODE

65

writing even as the Elements of Euclid, where every term and phrase and statement has been carefully thought out and

chosen, where every variation from what we may with right consider his literary sources must be accounted for; and it
is

to prove the accuracy of this

assumption that

is

the main

burden of our present study. The solution that would naturally suggest itself to the reader, and one which is generally assumed by students of
the Ethics, is that Spinoza is following here not the mediaeval authorities but rather Descartes. It is sometimes argued that
the elements of Spinoza's conception of substance are to be found in Descartes, for Descartes, too, considered substance not only as something existing by itself but also as
all

something conceived by itself. However, the formal definition of substance given by Descartes in Principia Philosophiae^ I, 51, to which Spinoza makes reference in his Cogltata
Metaphysica,
isting
I,

by

itself, itself,

ceived by

i, describes substance only in terms of exwithout any mention of its being also conthough Erdmann, in his exposition of Des-

mode and substance, introduces from other sources the distinction between "per aliud concipiun2 tur" and "per se concipiuntur." " " Then also with regard to his use of the term mode instead of "accident," it may again be traced to Descartes. In fact
cartes' definition of

Spinoza himself ascribes his division of Being into _u_hs-taandjnade to Descartes. 3 Still, while it is true that the term
does occur in the passage of Descartes 4 referred to by Spinoza, Descartes himself uses the term "accident" as <l " s synonymous with mode" and the opposite of substance."
1

"mode"

Cf. A. Leon, Les ftttments Cartesiens de la Doctrine Spinoziste, p. 85.

2
3

Cf. Grundriss der Geschichtc der Philosophic, II, Cogitata Metaphysica, II, 5. Cf. also I, i.

267.4.

Principia Philosophiac,
s

I,

48 and 49. Cf. also


1.

I,

56.

Mcditationes, III (Ocuvres, VII, p. 40,

15):

"modos,

sive accidentia."

66

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

Why

then did Spinoza restrict himself in the Ethics to the use of the term "mode" after having used the term "accil

dent" as the equivalent of "mode" in some of his other writThat his subsequent rejection of the term "accident" ings?
is

not unpremeditated may be gathered from the following statement in the Cogitata Metaphysica, I, i: "In regard to this, however, and I say it deliberately,(l wish it to be noted

that Being is divided into substance and modes and not into substance and accident. 'V

The

solution of these difficulties, therefore, seems to

lie in

an entirely different direction. Spinoza, I think, was forced to introduce this additional element in his definition of substance not so

much because he

differed

from the mediaevals


substance

in the definition of that

term as because he differed from

them

in the

definition_of

mode. As

far as

itself is

concerned, Spinoza's definition, as we shall presently see, does not essentially differ from the mediaeval; he only re-

upon its rigid logical meaning. It is only in his conception of modes that Spinoza strikes out a line of his own;! his modes are entirely different from Aristotelian jacoSents^ and it is mainly for this reason
by firmly
insisting

stricts its application

that he discards the use of that term, and completely alters The thesis its definition by omitting the term "subject."

which
tional

am

going to sustain, therefore,


it

is

that Spinoza's
to the

definition of substance contains nothing new, that the addi-

element

contains was not

unknown

mediae-

vals, and that Spinoza introduced this additional element in order to round up his definition of substance so as to make
Fpistola 4. In Short Treatise, Appendix I, Axiom i, the reading is either "toevallen" (accidentia) or "wijzen" (modification es). See Opera, I, p. 114 and p. 603. Cf. G. T. Richter, Spinozas philosophi sche Terminologie (Leipzig, 1913), p. 85, n. 507.
1

Locke, too, substituted the term

"mode"
13,
19).

for

"accident"

(cf.

Essay concern-

ing

Human

Understanding,

II, 12,

3;

Leibniz, in his criticism of Locke,


(cf.

however,

tries to reinstate the

term "accident"

Nouvtaux Essais,

II, 13,

19).

PROP, i]
it

DEFINITION OF SUBSTANCE AND

MODE
new

67
defini-

read as the diametrical opposite of his entirely tion of mode.

In mediaeval philosophy the definition of substance mediately followed by the classification of substances.
the

is

imto

As

method by which

the different classes of substances are

deduced, something
fice it for

will

be said in another connection. Suf-

the present that the mediaevals speak invariably of four or five substances, including matter, form, concrete
object, soul,

and the separate Intelligences


will recognize as a

a classification

which the reader

composite view

made

up of several statements
sible of existence,'*

made by

Aristotle. 2

stances belong to a class of being which is 3 with which is contrasted a single, unique " " known as the Necessary of Existence 4 or God. The Being
relation

All these sub" termed the pos-

between these two kinds of Being

is

that of cause
the mediaeval

and

effect.

Now,

generally speaking,

it

is

view that thd Necessary of Existence or God cannot be called substancel even though He is in himself, for God cannot be

subsumed with other things under


acteristic
zali,
is
s

a general term.

Char-

statements on this point are to be found in AlgaAsher Crescas, 6 and Moses ha-Lavi. 7 But while this view
it is

generally admitted,
1

still

maintained by Augustine, 8
cf.

Cf.

Makavd al-Falasijah

II,

(p. 82);

Shahrastani, ed. Cureton, p. 365;


4123, 19.

my

Crescas' Critique of Aristotle^ p. 575.


3

Cf. Metaphysics, VII, 10, io35a,

i,

and De Anima,

II, i,

3"inD,
*

->^^1 V^J- C(
ii

Cogitata Metaphysica,

I, i.

t\talfa$id al-Falasifah, II,


it

of existence, just as

"Eleventh, that of Him who is necessary cannot be said that He is an accident so it cannot be said that
(p. 144):

He
6

is

a substance."
I,

Commentary on Moreh Nebukim^

57 (2):

"But He

is

neither a substance nor

an accident."
'

Maamar

Elohi:

sary of existence does not of the other categories."


8

"It has already been demonstrated that He who is necescome under the category of substance nor under any

De

Trinitate t VI, 5 (Migne, Patrologia Latina> Vol. 42, Col. 928).

68
1

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


2

[ETHICS,

that God can be called subGersonides, and Descartes stance provided only that He is understood to be a substance unlike any other substance. Burgersdijck says explicitly that substance is divided into God and created being. 3

In view of this application of the term "substance


crete objects, which

"

to con-

must necessarily exist in some place, and which must necessarily exist in matter, and to soul, to form, which must reside in a body, a certain question naturally
arises in

our mind.

If at least three of the so-called sub-

stances in the Aristotelian classification always exist in something else, what, then, did the mediaevals mean when they
itself

distinguished substance from accident as that which is in should the and that which is in something else?

Why

snub-nosedness of Socrates, for instance, be called accident, on account of the existance of the snubness in Socrates' nose,

any more than Socrates'


Or,

soul,

why

should the

"

which equally exists

in his

body ?

redness" of a "red table" be called an


its

accident, on account of

existence in a table, any


in

more than

the table
is

itself,

which must exist

some
this

definite place, that

to say, in

some other body? For

is

the implication of
1

space according to Aristotle's definition of the term.

The mediaevals were not unaware


difficulty,

of the first-mentioned

and they answered

it

as follows:

An

accident

is

said to exist in something else as in a "subject,"


in

and

to exist
in

a subject
1

means

to exist in

something without

any

Milhamot Adonai, III, 3 (p. 132]: "You must know that there are certain atwhich must inevitably be attributed to God, as, for instance, the predication that God is substance, not that the term 'substance' is predicated of God and other beings as a common genus but it is predicated of them stcundum prius tt
tributes

posterius." Ibid., V, iii, 12 (p. 280): "It can also be shown that fully to be called substance than is any other being."
* *

God

is

more

truth-

Principia Philosophiac y

I,

51.

Institutiones Metaphysicae, Lib. II,

Cap.

I,

Thesis II:

"

Et substantiam deindc

subdividas in
<

Deum
4.

et

creaturam," Cf. quotation above

p. 64, n. 2.

Physics, IV,

PROP, i]

DEFINITION OF SUBSTANCE AND

MODE

69

sense being the cause of the existence of that something. Incarnate soul, therefore, unlike snub-nosedness, is called

substance because, while existing in the body, it is the cause of the body's life, and for this very same reason is form called substance, since it confers upon matter, in which it is, actual
existence.
I
1

do not know whether the mediaevals have ever discussed


for

directly the second difficulty

answer
their
in

it

them from

their

we have raised, but we can easily own point of view and out of

own

statements.

To

say that a concrete object exists

something else, they would argue in the manner of Aristotle, may mean two things, either as a body exists in place or
Neither of these two kinds of

2 as a part exists in the whole.

existence in something else, however, makes a thing an accident, for in both these cases the thing might also exist without that something else. To exist in place, according to
Aristotle's definition of place,

means
is

to exist in

from which the occupant might be removed,


essential characteristics of place
3

for

another body, one of the

that

it

must be external

to the occupant. Then, again, in the case of existing in the whole as a part, the part can be removed from the whole, if it is a discrete quantity; and the part will have to be a sub-

stance like the whole,

only when
that
is,

a continuous quantity. It is a thing exists in something else as in a subject,


if it is
it

when

that

it is

called accident.

cannot exist by itself without its subject, The mediaevals could have found

support for this distinction in the following passage of Aristotle: "I mean by a thing being in a subject (vTroKel^pov) that which is in anything, not as a part, but so that it cannot exist separately from that
1

in

which

it

is."

The

red

Cf. my Crf seas' Critique of Aristotle, p. 573, n. 9. Physics, IV, 3, 2ioa, 16 and 24; Metaphysics, V, 23, 10233, 14-17.

Physics, IV, 4, 21

a,

ff.

<

Categories, 2, la, 24-25.

yo

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


is

[ETHICS,

table, therefore,

a substance, because

it

can exist without


to exist;

that particular place in


ness, however,
is

which

it

happens

the red-

redness,

it

an accident, because, as that particular cannot exist without that particular table.
it

This

is

how,

justified to their

appears to me, the mediaevals would have own satisfaction their formal distinction

between substance and accident and their application of the

term "substance" to concrete things. But I can see how Spinoza would have balked at such an explanation, and whoever has tried to approach the problems of philosophy by the same road as Spinoza, and to traverse the ground trod by
that ex-pupil of the Teshibat Ez llayyim of Amsterdam, cannot help feeling that these were the problems that passed
l

through his mind before he broke ground for the foundation of his new system. He would have argued against them somewhat as follows: It is true that concrete objects may be removed from the particular place in which they happen to be; still they cannot be removed from space in general.

Everything in the universe must exist in space, which, as has been said before, means in another body. This is an
Aristotelian
follow.

principle

which the mediaevals professed


all

to

Aristotle says something to the effect that

things

1 are in heaven (oupa^w),

logical

heaven to

by which he does not mean the theowhich martyrs and saints and others with

proper introductions are admitted to enjoy a life of eternal bliss and beatitude. What he means is that the universe,

which

is finite, is

all-surrounded by a sphere, which


if

is

the
all

outermost of a
the universe

series of concentric spheres, within

which

Consequently, everything within thus within something else, namely, within the outermost sphere, and if a substance must be in itself,
is

things exist as in space.

then nothing within the universe can be a substance.


1

Or,

Cf. Physics, IV, 2, 2cx)a, 33; IV, 4, 21 la, 24.

PROP, i]

DEFINITION OF SUBSTANCE AND

MODE

71

in

other words, the red table can no more be a substance than the redness.
It is reasoning like this, if

not exactly this very same


artificial

reasoning, that

must have

led Spinoza to reject the mediaeval

distinction between substance

and accident, and the

distinction of existing in something else and existing in a subject. Everything that is in something else in any sense or

manner, he seems to say, cannot be a substance. "That there is no such thing as a finite substance" is the starting point of his philosophy, and indeed it is the statement with which he
tise J

begins his investigation of "What God Is," in his Short Treawhich is a kind of Urethik. It is a challenge hurled at all

the mediaeval philosophers, ulemas, rabbis, and schoolmen alike, for they were all nursed by the same mother and fed

from the same source.

It denies the application of the

term

"substance" to

finite

things within the universe.

Thus in one

of his Dialogues, Reason, addressing Desire, says: "What you say, O Desire, that there are different substances, that, I
tell

you,
if

is false;

for I see clearly that there

is

exists

through

itself,

and

is

a support to

all

but One, which other attributes.


as sub-

And

you

will refer to the material

and the mental

stances, in relation to the

modes which are dependent upon must also call them modes in relation to them, why then, you the substance on which they depend." 2 Note that he does

not reject the generally accepted definition of substance; on the contrary, he insists upon its rigid application. Only that

which

is

really

stance, and

so only that

and absolutely in itself can be called subwhich is called the Necessary of

Existence or

be truly called substance. All the other things which belong to the so-called possible of existence are not substances; they are what the mediaevals would have
called accidents, but which Spinoza prefers to call
1

God can

by a new
9.

I, 2.

Short Treatise,

I,

First Dialogue,

72

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

name, modes, seeing that they are not exactly what is generally meant by accident. He confines the term "accident"
to

one of

its

more

specific usages,

and distinguishes
is

it

from

mode

as follows:

"For accident

real being].

thought and exists only in For example, when


is

nothing but a mode of to this [whereas mode is a regard

the motion

mode

I say that a triangle is moved, not of the triangle but of the body

moved. Therefore,
an accident, but
for

in respect to the triangle,

motion

is

only

in respect to the

body,

it is real

being or

motion cannot be conceived without a body, but mode; it may without a triangle."
'

is

If our account of the processes of Spinoza's mind thus far right, we can readily see how at this point, with his re-

jection of finite substances

and with

his restricting the

term

"substance"

to

God

alone,

Spinoza was confronted with a

perplexing problem. How should he define those discarded substances which he has renamed modes? As for his real
substance, he could very well retain the old definition, being But could he just in itself, for God indeed is in himself.

something else? Spinoza could have used that definition if he had retained Aristotle's conception of a finite universe, bounded from
it is

as well say of

mode

that

that which

is in

without by an all-surrounding sphere, for then indeed all modes would have been within something else. But believing as Spinoza did in an infinite universe he could not natu-

speak of modes as existing in something else, by this meaning Aristotle's space. Nor, again, could he say that they existed in a "subject," for the term "subject" to him
rally

has no meaning at all. And yet, if substance is to be defined as that which exists in itself, mode will, of course, have to
be defined as that which exists in something else. But what might that something else be if it is not space nor subject?
1

Cogitata Metaphysica t

I, i.

PROP, i]

DEFINITION OF SUBSTANCE AND

MODE

73

If

we were

justified in penetrating thus far

behind the

uttered statements of Spinoza in unfolding the hidden arguments that lie beneath them, we may be allowed to proceed
a little further with the same method and to go through the slow paces of this imaginary tentative reasoning of his until we arrive at a happy conclusion. We can clearly see how

Spinoza, in his groping for a new differentiation between substance and mode, would at first strike upon the other
sense in which, according to Aristotle, a thing is said to be in 1 something else, namely, as a part in the whole. Substance is thus the whole which exists in itself, whereas mode is the

part which exists in something arrived at a term with which

else.

Here

at last

we have
in

we

so often

meet
in

works

on Spinoza.

mind, steeped undoubtedly was and trained as it also was in its rigorous logical discipline, the term "whole'* would need further explanation. For there are several kinds
philosophic lore as
it

But

to Spinoza's

mediaeval

of wholes, 2 and which of these, he would ask himself, should he say is substance? The kind of whole that would probably
first

in

suggest itself to him as the most applicable in the case question would be that of a physical quantitative whole,

is simply the whole of the modes it is nothing but the universe, and the universe to Spinoza as to the mediaevals is something physical and quantitative. But such a

for if substance

conception of substance as merely the aggregate sum of the modes is contrary to all the uttered statements of Spinoza. To Spinoza's mediaeval mode of thinking the difficulty of

manner.

such a conception of substance would appear in the following A quantitative whole must be either discrete, conSubstance, however, could be neither
See also Short Treatise,
I,

sisting of heterogeneous parts, or continuous, consisting of

homogeneous
1

parts.

Cf. Physics, IV, 3, 2ioa, 16.

First Dialogue.

Metaphysics, V, 25.

74

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


It could

[ETHICS,

of these.

not be a discrete quantitative whole, because the modes, if their nature is to be judged by the two known modes, are each continuous. Even extension is continuous, for Spinoza

was an

Aristotelian, believing in the

continuity of matter. He was no atomist, and for this we have ample evidence in his discussion of infinity. 1 As for
the second alternative, there
self in
is

saying that substance

is

nothing contradictory in ita continuous quantitative

it is not impossible that Spinoza conceived a conbetween extension and thought. Still Spinoza would tinuity reject this conception. For if substance were only the aggregate sum of modes, how could one insist upon the unity

whole, for

and simplicity of substance without thereby declaring the between modes a mere illusion ? To such a view could by no means subscribe, for he was no mystic, Spinoza no idealist of the kind to whom everything that kicks and
differences

He was, many views to the a hard-headed, clear-minded emcontrary notwithstanding, piricist, like most of the mediaevals and like Aristotle.
knocks and
resists is unreal.

Spinoza will thus take a final step and declare that substance is a whole which exists over and above and beyond
the modes, and saying this he will rest his case. sound alarming and tantalizing, and it may also may appear as wholly inconsistent with what we have been accustomed to understand by Spinoza's repeated assertion that God is an immanent cause and not a transeunt cause.

the

sum of

This

But we shall see in a subsequent chapter that the term "immanence" as used by Spinoza in its application to substance
not contradictory to the term transcendence" in its original meaning of being more general. Quite the contrary, the
is

"

immanence of Spinoza's substance


manence. 2 Spinoza's substance
1

is

a transcendent im-

is

thus a whole transcending


2

See Epistola

12.

Cf. below,

Chapter VIII.

Cf. below, pp. 323

ff.

PROP, i]

DEFINITION OF SUBSTANCE AND

MODE

75

the universe, the latter being the sum of the modes, and the relation of substance to the universe is conceived by him
after the

manner of

whole

in this particular case

the relation of the whole to the part, the being a universal of a special

kind, a real universal, as distinguished from the attributes which are only nominal universals. 1 By the same token,

when Spinoza speaks of thing (in alio) he means

the modes as existing in another that the modes, individually or in their aggregate totality, exist in substance in the same sense " as when Aristotle says that the ringer is in the hand and
2

generally the part in the whole/*

and that "man

is

in

animal and generally species in genus/* 3 The term "universal," however, carries associations which

would be only confusing in its use in connection with Spinoza. Aristotle himself would have simply spoken of genus and species. In Arabic and Hebrew literature philosophers also
speak of genus and species rather than of universals, though the latter term is not altogether unknown. 4 It is also significant that the famous passage
versals, just as
in
s

Porphyry's Isagoge

to

which

legendary history assigns the origin of the problem of uni-

grammar-school readers assign to the falling the origin of Newton's laws of motion even that apple of genera and species rather than of univerpassage speaks sals. Spinoza himself, though he makes use of the term "universal** quite frequently, says in

one place:

"Hence

the

fixed

be like universals to us, or, so to speak, the genera of the definitions of individual mutable 6 We shall therefore use here the term "genus,** things.'*
.

and eternal things

will

and describe Spinoza's conception of the


1

relation

between

a 3

Cf. below, pp. 327-328. Physics, IV, 3, 21 oa, 15-16.


Ibid., 2ioa,
1

8.
I,

Moreh Nebukim,
6

51.

Ch.

I.

fractatus de Intellectus Emendatione,

101 (Opera,

I, p.

37,

11.

5-8).

76

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


its

[ETHICS,

mode and substance


and
genus.

as that between the individual essence

We

now come

to the last step in

totelian logic, universal terms like

perform certain functions

in

genus and "species" the formation of concepts. They

"

our argument. In Aris"

are the elements, or rather the causes, in the terms of which the individual essence of a thing, the "what" of it, can be

conceived.
his

They form

its definition.

Man

is

thus conceived

genus "animal" and his species "rational," and through he is thus also defined by the combination of these two terms.

And

so everything that

is

in

something

else, as

an individual

in its genus,

thing

else.

mode
it is

as

"

may be thus said to be conceived by that someThis is what Spinoza means by his definition of
is

that which

in

it, namely, as the individual Substance, on the contrary, "is in itself" absolutely, and "is conceived through itself," inasmuch as it is a summum genus. But to be conceived through itself is really

sense that

conceived"; that is it is conceived through

another thing through which also to say, it is in another thing in the

in its genus.

means
This

a negation. It does not mean anything positively. All it is that it cannot be conceived through anything else.

"That is the significance of Axiom II, which reads: which cannot be conceived through another must be conthrough
itself
itself." The emphasis is that to be conceived merely means not to be conceived through

ceived through

something
substance

else.
is

implication therefore is that Spinoza's inconceivable, and its essence undefinable and
1

The

hence unknowable.

Thus
cation

the mediaeval definition of the term "substance"


its

has not undergone any change in Spinoza, though

appli-

was
is

restricted only to

God.

It is still defined as that


its

which
1

in itself.

Even

the additional fact of

being a

Cf. below, p. 142.

PROP, i]

DEFINITION OF SUBSTANCE AND

MODE
is

77
it

summum genus,

undefinable and unknowable,

not new;

is a mediaeval commonplace. That unique substance, God, was thus conceived throughout the Middle Ages among

rational theologians.

stands alone in the views he


like

Says Maimonides, and he by no means is about to utter, for passages can be gathered at random from many a book: these
is

"There

sence of God.'*

no possibility of obtaining a knowledge of the esAgain he says: "The object is described


r

by

its definition, as, for

example,
.
.

man

is

described as a being

that lives and has reason.

All agree that this kind of

description cannot be given of God; for there are no previous causes to His existence, by which He could be defined: and

on that account
philosophers,

it is

a well-known principle, accepted

by

all

who

are precise in their statements, that no

definition can be given of

God."

That the something


stance and that
essence to
tion
I.

else in

which the modes are


in

is

sub-

mode
is

is

related to substance as the individual

Proposiproposition affirms the priority of substance to its 3 affections, i.e. modes, which is a truly Aristotelian principle, for the genus, according to him, is prior to, and better known

its

genus

clearly set forth

by Spinoza

The

4 than, the individual.

But of

particular interest

is

the ex-

pression "prior in nature" (prior est natura) used by Spinoza. In Aristotle, the expression "prior in nature" (irpbrepov rf;
<t>v(Ti) is

used

in

more

excellent,

two senses: and second,

first, in

the sense of better

and

in the sense of being the

cause

of something. 5 In the latter sense it is very often used in Arabic and Hebrew as well as in Latin philosophic literature. But we find that the expression has acquired in the Middle

Ages an additional meaning, namely, as the more universal


1

Moreh Nebukim,

I, 59.
4

Ibid., I, 52.

Cf. below, Vol. II, pp. 193-194.


Categories, 12, 14!), 4
ff.

Topics, VI, 4, i4ia, 26

ff.

78

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


is
1

[ETHICS,

to the less universal, as, for example, animality

prior in
legiti-

nature to humanity.

This seems to be nothing but a

mate extension of
genus
is
2 vidual essence.

use in the sense of "cause/* for the considered by Aristotle as the cause of the indiits

Or

it

may

also reflect Aristotle's statement

that the whole

is

3 prior in nature to the parts.

rightly says that "substance fections" (Prop. I).


1

is

prior in its

Spinoza thus nature to its af-

Maba$id al-Falasifah,

II,

(p. 119):
is

"With

regard to [prior] in nature, as


in nature, as, for instance,

when

we
is

say, for instance, animality

prior to humanity."

Millot ha-Higgayon, Ch. 12:


prior to

"Second, prior

animal

man."
prior in nature to

the

Ruah Jfen, Ch. 8: "In the same way you say that animals are human species." Duns Scotus, Qiiaestiones in Quatuor Libros Sententiarum^
2,

Lib. II, Dist.

1,

Quaest.

No.
.

3:
. .

"Hie

dicit

Primo
a
3

positive

sicut est

Doctor quod prius natura potest dupliciter accipi. de animali et rationali in homine, quia prius natura

positive animal praecedit rationale."

Analytica Posteriori, II, 2, 903, 31.


Politics, I, 2, 12533, 19-20.

CHAPTER

IV

UNITY OF SUBSTANCE
I

IN HIS definition of substance we have seen how Spinoza, reasoning from the mediaeval definition of the term, has arrived at the conclusion that conditional being can in no sense

whatever be called substance. The term is to be applied only to Necessary Being, or God. With this as a starting point, Spinoza now proceeds, in the First Part of the Ethics to de',

scribe the properties of substance, beginning in Propositions II-VI with a discussion of its unity, which in manner of

treatment, as we shall endeavor to show, runs along the line of the mediaeval discussions of the unity of God. It is philosophic dualism of which Spinoza's discussion of
the unity of substance is aimed to be a refutation, just as theological dualism was the target of mediaeval discussions of the unity of God. The philosophy against which Spinoza

took the field, starting with the Aristotelian distinction of matter and form, passed through a hierarchy of beings until
it

ultimately arrived, again like Aristotle, at a being, unique and absolute, who is pure form. In this philosophy, it may
is

be said, there
did
it

to be discerned a twofold dualism.

posit in the

world

itself a

or, as it

was better known

Not only of matter and form, duality in the fashionable philosophy of


and thought, but
it

Spinoza's

own

time, of extension

also

maintained the duality of a material, multifarious, changeable world and an immaterial, simple, immutable God, who is
pure form, whose essence
is

thinking. Matter and form,

thought, and whose activity is in the traditional terminology,

8o

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


all

[ETHICS,

concrete beings, which are also called substances; and by the extension of the 1 term "substance/' for which he had several precedents,

are two substances, which combined form

Spinoza speaks of the mediaeval contrast between God and the world again as a contrast between two substances. It
is

upon

this latter

phase of dualism, the existence of an imis

material

God

over against a material world, that Spinoza

warring whenever we find him contending against the existence of two substances, in the Ethics as well as in the Short
'Treatise.

The
is

object of Spinoza's criticism of this kind of dualism

not to abolish the materiality of the world, but rather to abolish the immateriality of God. He will endeavor to show
that

the assumption of an absolutely immaterial God is incompatible with the relation which the mediaevals as-

sumed

to obtain

between

God and

of cause and

effect.

He
it

will thus

the world, namely that introduce into his discus-

sion of the unity of substance the


first

problem of creation

the

might be said, which the mediaeval religious thinkers encountered when they attempted to
serious problem,

identify the Aristotelian pure form, a

mere

logical concept,

with the personal

God of tradition, and

to use it as a

working

hypothesis to explain the origin of a created world as well as its governance. The difficulties of the theory of creation, of which the mediaevals were not unaware, were many and varied, all arising out of the conception of God as an immaterial,

simple,

and immutable being, combined with the Neo-

platonic principle that "a simple element can produce only a simple thing." 2 Spinoza will hardly bring out new difficulties which have not already been thought of and fully discussed and answered by the mediaevals themselves, but he will insist that their answers are a kind of special pleading
1

See above, pp. 67-68.

Moreh Nebukim,

II, 22.

PROPS. 2-6]

UNITY OF SUBSTANCE

81

which really does not solve the problem. Had the Ethics been written more scholastico rabbinicoque^ Spinoza would have prefaced his argument in Propositions II-VI with
to the following effect: We shall now proceed to demonstrate that there is no God distinguished from the world

words

after the

manner of two substances, one


For
to posit such a

spiritual

and the

other material.

God would

involve us

which you have yourselves noticed in the problem of creation, and from which, despite all your efforts, you have not been able to extricate yourselves comshall see that, even in their present form, these pletely.
in all the difficulties

We

five

propositions contain

a clear-cut,

single,

consecutive

argument which in its external, logical outline is modelled after the mediaeval reasoning against the hypothesis of two deities and which substantially embodies the principal
mediaeval arguments against creation.

To

the

mind of Spinoza,

it

would seem, the widely scattered


l

mediaeval discussions of the problem of the unity of God presented themselves in the form of a hypothetico-disjunctive syllogism. If there were two gods, either they would have to be absolutely unrelated to each other or there would have to be some kind of relation between them. He could

clearly see why the mediaevals these alternatives as untenable.

would have rejected both Two unrelated gods would

imply the existence of two independent worlds, for in one world there could be no adequate division of labor between

and two unrelated gods would contradict the very conception of God as something absolutely unrelated. To
them;
Spinoza discusses the problem of the unity of God directly in Cogitata Metaphysica, II, 2. He reproduces there two arguments which he characterizes as futile. Both these arguments are taken directly from Burgerdijck's Institutiones Metaphysicae. Lib. I, Cap. VI, but are also found in Emunot we-De'ot y II, i and 2, and in
1

(lo&ot ha-Lebabot,

I, 7,

First and Third Arguments.

Cf. Freudenthal,
Zeller
. .

"Spinoza und

die Scholastik," in Philosophische Aujs&tze>

Eduard

gewidmet^ p. in.

82

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

assume such a formulation of the problem in the mind of Spinoza is nothing but to rearrange the mediaeval discussions and weld them into one composite argument. God to the mediaevals meant the God of a world. Their conception of God, which was the hybrid product of the
joining together of the Aristotelian logical principle of prime mover, or first cause, with the Biblical ethical teaching of sources

a creator and supreme ruler, has derived from both these its main characteristic feature as that of cause and

creator.

cause and creator, however these terms may have become attenuated, must of necessity be the cause and cre-

ator of something.
sole activity,
tify itself in

God's thinking, which constitutes His


either

by necessity or by design objeca world at a certain stage in the process of

must

An idle, quiescent, passive God, a God who no world to operate upon, would be an impotent God has and an object of commiseration and pity, as the hero of Chamisso's story who was without a shadow. It therefore
emanation.
follows that, granting two absolutely independent deities, there would have to be two absolutely independent worlds. But the existence of more than one world was generally

agreed to be impossible. For this there was the overwhelming authority of Aristotle, who with an impressive array of arguments had shown in the latter part of the First Book of De
Caelo (Chs. VIII-IX) that the existence of many worlds was impossible. It would thus be necessary first to establish the possibility of many worlds before it could be assumed that
there

was more than one God; and,


to

in fact,

Crescas, in his

expose the flimsiness of the philosophic proofs for the unity of God, attacks the problem from that very

attempt

angle, showing that the existence of

more than one world

is

not impossible.
1

Or Adonai,
ff.,

I, ii,

15

and

19.

Cf.

my

Crescas' Critique of Aristotle, p. 217

and

pp. 472

n. 127.

PROPS. 2-6]

UNITY OF SUBSTANCE

83

Since there must be only one world, within that only


world, the argument would proceed, two absolutely independent and absolutely unrelated deities could not be con-

ceived to exist and at the same time be active.

"A duality could only be imagined in this way, either that at one time the one deity is active, the other at another time, or that
both act simultaneously, nothing being done except by both But either of these arrangements would be together."
'

inconsistent with the absolute independence and omnipotence and self-sufficiency of the deities. To say that the two
deities act each independently in their

own

spheres

is

likewise

impossible, for "the whole existing world is one organic Hence body, all parts of which are connected together. it is to assume that one deity is engaged in formimpossible
. . .

ing one part, and another deity in forming another part, of that organic body of which all parts are closely connected 2 Here, again, Crescas tries to disprove the philotogether."

sophic proof for unity by suggesting a possibility, with what success does not concern us here, of an adequate division of
labor between two gods within this organic world. 3 If two absolutely mutually independent deities are impossible, the mediaevals would then consider the case of two deities

having something

in

common. Such
in

deities,

however,

could not properly be called two unless


possessing something in

addition to their

thing in

be
to

in

common they also possessed somewhich they differed. But what would that something which they differed? Usually in things which are said
in

have something
is

differ the identity implied is that of a

common and something in which they common genus and the

diversity that of a

common

that of a specific difference, or the identity is species and the diversity is that of an inIt is for

dividual difference, such as accidental qualities.


'

March Nfbukim, Or Adonai^ I, ii,

II, i.

Ibid.

19.

84

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

between which there no generic or specific or individual difference, cannot be is " Whatsoever is not a body does not admit of the counted.
this reason that bodiless spiritual beings,

idea of

number except

individual forces

may

it be a force in a body, for then the be numbered together with the mat-

ters or subjects in

which they

exist."

If

two

deities therein

>

fore existed,

having something in
differed, they

common and something


to possess the
still

which they

would have

metaworse,

physical distinction of genus and species, or, they would have to possess physical qualities.
are contrary to the very nature of
lutely simple follows:

Both these

and

indivisible.

God, who must be absoThe argument is stated as


believes that there
is

"We
God

say to him

who

more

that the essence of the two gods must inevibe one or more than one. If he says the essence is one, tably then the thing is one, and there is not more than one Crea-

than one

tor; and if he says that the essence of the one deity is unlike that of the other, then it would be necessary to posit a cer-

tain difference

between them/'

There is only one way, the mediaevals would conclude, in which purely immaterial beings can be counted, and that is when they are related to each other as cause and effect. Such
the case of the Intelligences which preside over the spheres. Though immaterial, still they are numbered, their number
is
3 corresponding to that of the spheres. The basis for their to the view held by Avicenna, is that in number, according the process of emanation they proceed in succession from one

another, thus being the cause of one another. "It follows, therefore, that separate beings, which are neither bodies nor
forces in bodies,
1

do not admit of any idea of number except


II,
I,

Moreh Nebukim y
and
I,

Introduction, Prop. 16.


7 (4).
Cf.

Hobot ha-Lebabot y
75
(2).

Emunot

we-De'ot, II, 2,

and Moreh Ncbukim,

II, i,
3

See Moreh Nebukim, II,

4.

PROPS. 2-6]

UNITY OF SUBSTANCE

85
x

when they

are related to each other as cause and effect."

Number
deities.

however, could not be applied to two If two deities were postulated to exist, they could
in this sense,
effect,

not bear to each other the relation of cause and


being produced by

one

the other, for that would run counter to

the very conception of God as an uncaused being. "The hypothesis that there exist two gods is inadmissible, be-

cause absolutely incorporeal beings cannot be counted, ex2 cept as cause and effect."

This then

is

the mediaeval argument against a duality of

gods as we assume it was formulated in Spinoza's mind. It begins with the alternative that two deities either would

have
to

to be absolutely different
in

from each other or would have

the impossibility of the first alternative, proceeds to reason against the second alternative by pointing out that if two gods were not absoit

have something

common. Showing

lutely different from each other they would have to be absolutely the same, inasmuch as their natures could not be

divided by being partly different and partly the same. Nor, having the same nature, could they be differentiated by their relation to each other as cause and effect. Within this

framework Spinoza's
in logical order,

five propositions

arrange themselves

forming the following consecutive argument: There are no two substances, that is to say, an immaterial
a material world, for
if

God and
A.

there were, the following

two alternatives would be inevitable:


be absolutely different from the world, and " hence have nothing in common with it, for two substances

God would

having different attributes have nothing one another" (Prop. II). But then,
(i)
1

in

common

with

There could be no causal relation between God and

Ibid., II, Introduction, Prop. 16.


Ibid., II, i, First Proof.

86

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


the world, for

[ETHICS,

If two things have nothing in common one another, one cannot be the cause of the with other" (Prop. III).

"

B. Or,

ferent, but then,

God and the world would not be absolutely God and the world would have to be

dif-

ab-

solutely the same, for the following reasons: (1) Things are said to be two only when they differ in essential or accidental qualities, for "two or more
distinct things are distinguished

either

by

the

difference

from one another, of the attributes of the

substances, or by the difference of their affections"


(Prop. IV).
(2)

Consequently,

if

God and

the world were of the

same nature and

differed neither in accidental nor in

essential qualities, they could not be called two, for

"in nature there cannot be two or more substances of


the
(3)

same nature or attribute (Prop. V). To say that God and the world would
one
is

"

differ in so

far as

"one

impossible, for substance cannot be produced by another subis

the cause of the other

stance" (Prop. VI).

The
form

logical order of these propositions

and

their syllogistic

thus quite apparent. But we must clothe this bare, skeleton-like outline with a body, in order to give to the propositions meaning and weight. Spinoza does not manipis

ulate his terms according to certain rules of the

game, as

if

they were pawns on the chess-board, for the mere pleasure of the play. There is always some concrete application in
his reasoning.

His propositions and their proofs, whenever are not an interpretation of facts of nature, are to be they taken as a criticism of the philosophy upon which he was
Proposition II contains Spinoza's restatement of the me-

nurtured.

PROPS. 2-6]

UNITY OF SUBSTANCE

87

diaeval view concerning the distinction between God and the world. The essence of God, according to this view, is so
different from the essence of the world that

no attribute can

be predicated of them in the same, or in any related, sense.


All terms used in describing the divine nature are to be taken as homonymous terms, none of them having the meaning

associated in our mind, and none of them conveying to our mind any direct knowledge of the divine nature,

with which

it is

which must always remain unknowable and ineffable. When the mediaevals speak of a knowing God or a living God they

do not mean to attribute to God a kind of knowledge or life which he shares in common with other beings, for knowledge and life in their application to God must have an absolutely different and unique meaning. "When they ascribe
to

God

essential attributes, these so-called essential attri-

butes should not have any similarity to the attributes of other things, and should according to their own opinion not

be included in one and the same definition, just as there is no similarity between the essence of God and that of other
beings/'

no way

a decisive proof that there is, in or sense, anything common to the attributes predi-

Again, "this

is

cated of God, and those used in reference to ourselves; they

have only the same names, and nothing else is common to them." 2 Referring to this view, Spinoza says: "Two substances having different attributes have nothing in common with one another" (Prop. II) that is to say, when the

same

attributes, predicated of

two substances, are homony-

mous

terms, used in absolutely different and unrelated senses, the predication of these attributes does not imply any real
relationship in the essence of the

two substances. The term

attributa in this proposition should be taken

sense of predicates, which, as will be


1

shown

simply in the in another

March Nebukim,

I,

56.

Ibid.

88

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


is
1

[ETHICS,
is

chapter,

one of the senses

in

which the term


is

used by

Spinoza.

The

refutation of this view

given in Proposition III.

Spinoza seems to be challenging the mediaevals in the following words: If you say that the divine nature is absolutely different from the nature of the world, how then can you interpret your traditional creation, as most of you do, in terms of emanation and call your creative God an emanative cause?

The theory of emanation maintains


verse with
all its

that the entire uni-

manifold

finite

infinite divine nature, the

the unfolding of the beings of its thinking. There is product


is

nothing in the universe which is not involved in the nature of God, and nothing happens in the universe which does not

emanate from Him. "Inasmuch as it has been demonstrated that God is incorporeal and has also been established that the universe is His work and that He is its efficient cause.
.

emanation and that God

say that the universe has been created by divine is the emanative cause of everythat comes into being within it/' 2 It is for this reason thing that God is said to know particulars by virtue of His knowl. .

We

3 edge of himself; it is also for this reason that it is said that by our contemplation upon the nature of the universe we may

arrive at the
relation

4 knowledge of the nature of God. This /kind of which God is said to bear to the world is a causal

relation of a particular kind, unlike the causal relation of corporeal agents to the objects upon which they operate. It
is

called

emanative causation. "Inasmuch as the actions of

the purely incorporeal Intelligence are clearly manifest in the world, and they are especially manifest in every case of
1

Cf. below, p. 228.

2 3

Morch Ncbukim, II, 12. See Milhamot Adona /, III, 4


See Robot ha-Lebabot,
II,

(p. 138),

and Or Adonai^

II,

i,

(p.

32b).

Cf. be-

low, Vol. II, p. 14.


<
I ff.

PROPS. 2-6]

UNITY OF SUBSTANCE

89

change that does not originate in the mere combination of elements, we cannot escape the conclusion that this agent,
definite distance.
is

not being corporeal, does not act by impact nor at a certain The action of the incorporeal Intelligence

always termed emanation, on account of its similarity to a


*

water-spring."

duced
even

This principle of emanation, which was primarily introto obviate the difficulty of how an incorporeal agent could act upon a corporeal object, was found to be insufficient
in the eyes of the

mediaevals, whose strictures upon this point will be quoted later. Even after interposing a series of immaterial intermediaries between God and the
world, they were
still

harassed by the question

how

could

matter ultimately arise if it were not to be found originally in the nature of God. One of the solutions offered is that God as
the emanative cause of the universe does not act by necessity but

by

volition,

and consequently

all

variety in nature,

due

to the existence of matter, as well as

matter

itself, is
2

to

be attributed to the design and determination of God. The principal points in this mediaeval view, so far as
are here concerned, are three.

we

God

is

the emanative cause

of the world, with all that it implies. But God is immaterial, and how could a material world emanate from Him ? The

answer

is

that

God

acts
this,

In opposition to

and design. denies the immateriality of Spinoza


by
volition
in

God

as well as will

and design

His action.

He

does not

hesitate to speak of

God

as the cause of the world, but he

insists that the causality

must be mechanical and not intenthink that

tional.

As against

those

"who

God is a free cause,"

and that He creates "by a certain absolute will," he argues that "I think that I have shown with sufficient clearness
1

Moreh Nebukim y
Ibid., II, 22.

II, 12.

90
(Prop.

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


XVI)
infinite nature, infinite things in infinite
all

[ETHICS,

His
say

that from the supreme power of God, or from ways, that is to

things,

by

the

same

necessity, in the

have necessarily flowed, or continually follow same way as it follows from the
*

nature of a triangle, from eternity and to eternity, that its three angles are equal to two right angles." This conception of God as a necessary cause is laid down by Spinoza
in

Axioms III, IV, and V, at the beginning of Ethics, I. The term "cause'* which occurs in these axioms is to be taken as
God, or substance,
he affirms that
in its relation to

referring specifically to

the world. In
sity:

Axiom

III,

God

acts

by neces-

a given determinate cause an effect necessarily " Since God acts by necessity and not by volition, follows. there is nothing in the nature of the world that is not in
the nature of

"From

God; the two must be mutually implicative. "The knowledge of an effect depends upon and involves
(Axiom IV), for "those things which have nothing mutually in common with one another cannot through one another be mutually understood, that is to say, the conception of the one does not involve the conthe knowledge of the cause

"

ception of the other his own premise that


the mediaevals that

"

(Axiom V). Starting,

therefore, with

God
if

by necessity, he argues against God's nature be essentially different


acts

from the nature of the world, He could not be the cause of the world, for "if two things have nothing in common with
one another, one cannot be the cause of the other" (Prop. III). In an earlier version of the same Proposition, the argument is stated more directly: "That which has not in itself

something of another thing, can also not be a cause of the


existence of such another thing" a that is to say, if God is immaterial, He cannot be the cause of a material world.
-

Ethics, I, Prop. 17, Schol.

Short Trfatisf, Appendix

I,

Axiom

5.

PROPS. 2-6]

UNITY OF SUBSTANCE
that

91

Spinoza, however, knew

by

this

he had not yet fully

succeeded in reducing his opponents to silence. To tell them that God could not be the cause of the material world, if He

were assumed to be immaterial, would only evoke the reply that it was just to meet this difficulty that emanation was
introduced to take the place of direct creation. God as the direct cause of matter would indeed be impossible. But emanation claims only that

God

is

the cause of a single Intelli-

gence, a purely spiritual being, as devoid of matter as God himself. It is this pure spirit of which God is the cause;

and matter proceeds not directly from God but from the Intelligences. "In accordance with this axiom, Aristotle holds that the direct emanation from God must be one simple Again, "from the NecesIntelligence, and nothing else/'
1

sary Existent only one thing can proceed without an intermediary, but many things can proceed from Him by order of succession and through intermediaries." 2 Reduced to Spinoza's terminology, it may be said that there are two substances, namely, God and the first Intelligence, who are reshould that be lated to each other as cause and effect.

Why

impossible?

The answer
and VI,
in

to this

is

to be found in Propositions IV, V,


will

which Spinoza

endeavor to show that the

in-

terposition of incorporeal intermediaries was merely a makeshift and did not really solve the problem how a purely
spiritual

God

could produce a material world.

begin with, Spinoza repeats the question raised with respect to the hypothesis of two deities, namely, by virtue

To

of what could

God and

the

first

Intelligence be called two? In

order to be susceptive of number, things must be distinguished either as separate substances or as separate modes;
1

Moreh Nfbukim^ II, 22. Makajid al-Falasifah II,


y

ii,

10 (p. 143).

92
or, to

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

put it in the words used by Spinoza elsewhere, the distinction between them must be either realis or modalis y for
l

extramental being, that is, real being (ens reale), as distinguished from fictitious being (ens ficturri) and being of reason (ens rationis)? must be either substance or mode.

Hence Proposition IV: "Two or more distinct things are distinguished from one another, either by the difference of the attributes of the substances, or by the difference of their
affections.

"

he endeavors to prove that the first Intelligence, in the mediaeval theory, could not be distinguished from God and still have something in com-

Continuing

this line of reasoning,

mon

with Him, but that the two would have to be either

absolutely different or absolutely identical. God and the first Intelligence, he argues, could not be said
to be distinguished

from each other

in part of their nature, that is to say,

common and something in since God is the highest genus, He could not share anything in common with any other being, as that would constitute His genus. If God is therefore to be distinguished from the first Intelligence realiter^ He will have to differ from the latter in His entire nature, having no attribute in common
thing in

by differing only by their having somewhich they differed. For

realiter

with

by

it. Spinoza thus says: "If they are distinguished only difference of attributes, it will be granted that there is

but one substance of the same attribute (Prop. V, Demonst.). God and the first Intelligence would therefore have to be
absolutely different from each other. Still less could it be said that God and the
differed in accidental qualities.
first

Intelligence

Spinoza does not attempt to refute this on the ground that the mediaeval immaterial God
1

Short Treatise , Appendix


Cf. Cogitata Mttaphysica y

I,

Prop.

I,

Demonst.

I, I.

Cf. below, p. 161.

PROPS. 2-6]

UNITY OF SUBSTANCE

93

qualities which are He knew quite well that for the mediaeaccidental to matter. vals that would form no obstacle. They could interpret

and pure Intelligences could not possess

these qualities atrributed to God and the Intelligences in the same way as they interpreted the divine attributes, namely, either as external relations/ or as actions and nega-

He attacks it, however, from another angle. He seems to say to his imaginary opponents: However you would take these qualities, as relations, actions, or negations, you would
tions.
2

have to admit that they are something external; that they are distinctions existing only in relation to our own mind, and
in

their

no way affecting the nature of God and the Intelligence. In own nature and essence, therefore, God and the Intel-

ligence

would be identical and hence one.

To quote him:

"But

if

since substance

they are distinguished by difference of affections, is prior by nature to its affections (Prop. I),

the affections therefore being placed on one side, and the substance being considered in itself, or, in other words (Def. 3 and Ax. 6), truly considered, it cannot be conceived as dis-

tinguished from another substance'' (Prop. V, Demonst.). The upshot of this is that God and the first Intelligence

would have to be either absolutely different or absolutely identical, inasmuch as "in nature there cannot be two or more substances of the same nature or attribute" (Prop. V).
Spinoza would have been quite
in

satisfied,

on mere

logical

grounds, assuming that God and the first Intelligence are of absolutely the same nature and are to be distinguished

only

in so far as the

former

is

related to the latter as cause

But he would insist that this identity would mean that both God and the Intelligence must be material; that is to say, they must have extension as one of their attributes.
to effect.
1

Cf. Cuzariy II, I, and Emunah Ramah t II, iii. Cf. Moreh Nebukim, I, 52 and 58. Cf. below, pp. 143-144.

94

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


shall see, is
1

[ETHICS,

His own view, as we


a doctrine.

only a modified form of such


far

But the mediaeval thinkers were


all

from ac-

knowledging such an identity. They were

agreed on the

absolute immateriality of God, though there was some difference of opinion as to the immateriality of the Intelligences.

Matter makes

its first

appearance

in

the Intelligences them-

selves, according to those

who

like
it

Ibn Gabirol held the In-

telligences to be material, or

arises

from the particular

nature of the Intelligences, according to those who believed that while the Intelligences are immaterial they possess in
their nature a certain possibility

which ultimately gives

rise

consider God to matter. In either case, they ent from the Intelligences; and still they all agree that God is the cause of the Intelligences. The difficulty raised by
all

to be differ-

in Proposition III thus occurs again, and is restated him in Proposition VI: "One substance cannot be proby duced by another." Proposition VI, as will have been noticed, is a repetition

Spinoza

of Proposition III, and in fact its demonstration is based upon the latter proposition. Likewise the second demonstration of the Corollary of Proposition VI is a reproduction of the demonstration of Proposition III. Furthermore, in

dix

a letter from Oldenburg (Epistola III), as well as in AppenI to the Short 'Treatise^ the equivalents of Proposition III are given as axioms upon which the equivalents of Proposition

VI are based
in

occur

some

as propositions. That both these should the Ethics as propositions would seem to need explanation. However, in the light of the logical out-

line in

which we have shown these propositions to be conis

nected, there
repetition.

ample justification

for this

seemingly useless

Our
1

discussion of these five propositions

may

be brought

Cf. below, pp. 2i8ff.

PROPS. 2-6]

UNITY OF SUBSTANCE

95

by the following remark on the Corollary in VI. The Corollary begins with the statement, Proposition "Hence it follows that there is nothing by which substance
to a conclusion

("Hinc sequitur substantiam ab alio non posse "), and ends with a similar statement, produci "Therefore absolutely there is nothing by which substance can be produced" ("Ergo substantia absolute ab alio produci
can be produced"

non potest"). In Short Treatise^ I, 2, the proof of the third " that one substance cannot produce another/' proposition,

same as Proposition VI in Ethics I, is given as follows: "Should any one again maintain the opposite, we ask whether the cause, which is supposed to produce this substance, has or has not the same attributes as the produced [substance]. The latter is impossible, because something cannot come from nothing/' Similarly in the proof of the first proposition given in the foot-note in the same chapwhich
is

the

',

ter of the Short 'Treatise it is said that, if there

were a

finite

would necessarily have something which it would have from nothing." Likewise in Epistola IV to
substance, "it

Oldenburg Spinoza produces Proposition


as follows:

III,

which he proves

"Nam quum

nihil sit in effectu

commune cum

In the light causa, totum, quod of all these passages, the conclusion of the Corollary here may be interpreted to mean as follows: Therefore, if substance

haberet, haberet a nihilo."

could be absolutely produced, it would have to be produced from nothing (Ergo, si substantia absolute produci posset, a
nihilo deberet produci).

The main point


if

of the Corollary

would thus be

to

show that

the material world were pro-

duced by an immaterial God, something would be produced from nothing. The force of this argument as well as its historical background will be dealt with in the second part
of this chapter, in the discussion of the Short Treatise, to

which we now turn.

96

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


II

[ETHICS,

The second chapter of


which bears the
tions

the First Part of the Short Treatise,


Is," is again, like Proposia criticism of mediaeval dualism.
will therefore occasionally

"
title

What God
I,

II-VI of the Ethics,


this

Our comments upon


have
to dwell

chapter

upon matters which have already been dealt

with in our discussion of the Ethics. Whenever such a repetition occurs, it is to be excused on the ground that it could not be avoided, unless we preferred to be economical at the ex-

pense of clearness and completeness. Mediaeval dualism considers God as something essentially different from the world. God is pure form; the world is material.
all

As a corollary of this, the world is conceived to have the imperfections of which God as pure spirit is free. The
is

world

furthermore the creation of God; the world

is

thus

called conditional being whereas God is absolute being. Since creation is assumed to be in time, the world is still further

contrasted with

God
l

as the created substance with the un-

created substance

or as the temporal with the eternal. The creation of the world was not by a single act but rather by a of emanation. Matter did not come directly from process

God;

it

has

made

its

appearance at a certain stage

in

the

devolution of the issue of divine thought. thought, and His only activity is thinking.
thinking
is

God
But

is

pure

as His

thought, known

a creative power, it becomes objectified in a as Intelligence, which, while immaterial like


is

himself, according to one of the prevailing views, 2 of a less perfect order, inasmuch as by its nature it is

God

only

possible being,
this

thought of
1

having a cause Intelligence, which


Deo"

for
is

its

existence.

The

said to possess a dual


Mctaphysica,
I, 2.

"de substantia increata, sive de Cf. above, p. 91, and below, p. 223.
Cf.

in Cogitata

PROPS. 2-6]

UNITY OF SUBSTANCE

97

another Intelligence and a sphere. nature, So the process goes on until at a certain stage crass matter appears which is the basis of the sublunar world. The world thus possesses imperfections which are not found in
objectifies itself in

the original thinking essence of God. In the language of Spinoza these mediaeval contrasts befinite

God and the world are expressed in the phrases "insubstance*' and "finite substance." It is Spinoza's purpose in his discussion of "What God Is" to abolish this
tween

dualism between the thinking essence of

God and

the

ma-

terial, or extended, essence of the world, to identify God " with the wholeness of nature, and to conclude that we posit He begins in the first extension as an attribute of God."
I

proposition by denying the old conception of a hierarchy of substances falling into a general division of spiritual and material substances, or infinite and finite, asserting "that there

substance; but that every substance must be in2 If the mediaevals therefore finitely perfect in its kind." to speak of the world as an emanation of the are pleased
is

no

finite

divine thinking essence, that divine thinking essence must contain the material element of which the world is made,

"that

is

to say, that in the infinite

understanding no sub-

stance can be more perfect than that which already exists in nature." 3
this proposition by the method employed him elsewhere, 4 ex absurdo contradictor 10^ for "should any by one want to maintain the opposite, we would ask the follow-

Spinoza proves

ing question." Suppose, he says, God is a purely immaterial being and beside Him there is a material created substance.

The
1

question would then be raised:


I, 2,
11. 1

how

did this material

Short Treatise y
Ibid.,

8 (Opera, I, p. 24,

1.

n).
Ibid. (p. 20,
11.

>

2 (p. 19,

ff.).

6-7).

<

Cf. below, pp. 183,378.

98

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


You would have

[ETHICS,

world come into being?

to resort to the

various theories of creation offered by the mediaevals.

But

none of these

is

free

from insurmountable

difficulties.

And

hereupon Spinoza proceeds to discuss some of the difficulties of creation and their attempted solutions by the mediaevals.
In the classic writings of Jewish philosophers the discussion of the problem of creation opens with a consideration of
the Epicurean theory of a world having a beginning in time but without necessarily having come into existence through " a God. Says Saadia: After it had become perfectly clear

that all things are created, I began to inquire whether could have been produced by themselves or whether they they could not have been produced except by some agent not themselves/' x Says also Bahya: "The propositions by which
to

me

may

be proved that the world has a creator by whom it has been created from nothing are three: First, a thing cannot
it

produce
after

For anything coming into existence itself. has been without existence must inevitably satisfy
.

either one of these conditions

either

it

has come into ex-

istence through itself or

a cause not itself/' 2

has come into existence through Similar allusions to a theory of creait

tion through itself, or what is better known as creation by 3 4 chance, abound also in the writings of Maimonides, Ger-

sonides,

and Crescas. 6 Descartes,


in the

too, formulates the prob-

lem of creation
it

form of a disjunctive proposition: "But


itself

seems to

me

to be self-evident that everything that exists

springs from a cause or from

considered as a cause/'

Following his masters, Spinoza similarly begins his


1

in-

Em tin of we-De' of
y

I, 2.

Ifobot ha-Lebabot^

I, 5.

Cf. below, p. 318.

4 *

6
7

Moreh Nebukim II, 13 and 20. Milhamot Adonai y VI, i, 6. Or Adonai, III, i, 3 (p. 635). Primae Rcsponsiones (Oeuvres, VII,

p. 112,

11.

3-5).

PROPS. 2-6]

UNITY OF SUBSTANCE
1 *

99

quiry by asking "whether this substance is finite through or whether it is thus finite through its cause. itself.
1
.
.

Spinoza's refutation of this

first

alternative

is

found

in

two

versions, one given in the text and the other in the footnote. The latter is not much unlike the refutation given by

Saadia.
self,

It

reads as follows: "It could not have done so

it-

its

because having been infinite it would have had to change whole essence/' 2 The following is Saadia's answer: "If

we take any of the existent things and assume it to have made itself, we know that after its coming into existence it must possess a still greater power and ability to create something like itself. If it could therefore produce itself when it was weak and in a state of non-existence, it should be able
to

produce something

like itself after it

has become powerful

and attained a state of existence. Seeing, however, that it cannot produce something like itself when it is powerful, certainly it could not have produced itself when it was
weak/'
tions
is
3

The underlying assumption in both these refutathat the substance, having made itself, could not so

change its nature as to become less powerful or less infinite than before it has made itself. It is somewhat like the following argument quoted from Suarez by those who objected " If anything is self-derived and does not against Descartes:
issue

from a cause,

it is

necessarily unlimited

and

infinite."

Thus disposing of creation through itself, Spinoza takes up the second alternative suggested by the mediaevals, namely, that "it is made finite by its cause, which is necessarily

God."

Against

this alternative
is

Spinoza raises three

objections, one of which


1

found both
11.

in the text

and

in the

Ibid.,

3
< s

Short Treatise, I, 2, 3 (Opera, I, p. 20, 2, note 2 (p. 19, 11. 20-21). Emu not we-De'ot, I, 2.
p. 95,

11-13).

Primae Objectiones (Oeuvres, VII,


Short Treatise,
I, 2,

11. 11.

16-18). 17-18).

4 (Opera,

I, p.

20,

loo
foot-notes;
It
is

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

my

the other two are given only in the foot-notes. purpose to show that these arguments are directed

against mediaeval attempts to remove two great difficulties with regard to the theory of creation, and furthermore to show that Spinoza's arguments themselves are taken from
the mediaeval discussions.

One of

the difficulties about creation in time which the


is its

mediaevals grappled with


the omnipotence

obvious inconsistency with


or,

Maiwants, changes, and it, An omnipoobstacles are absent from the essence of God." tent and immutable God could not be conceived as being active at one time and inactive at another. And then, too,
as

and immutability of God,


"

monides puts

with the belief

that

all

why
tion?
is

did

God

choose one time rather than another for creathe argument from Maimonides: "An agent and inactive at another, according
.

To quote

active at one time

As, not subject to accidents which could bring about a change in His will, and is not affected by obstacles and hindrances that might appear or disappear, it is im. .

as favorable or unfavorable circumstances arise.


is

however, God

possible, they argue, to imagine that

God

is

active at one

time and inactive at another/'

In answer to this difficulty, Maimonides draws a distinction between the actions of God and the actions of created
beings.

Human
is

action

is

an exercise of power, or free

will,

which

dependent upon external conditions; God's action an exercise of pure or absolute will and is entirely selfis sufficient. "Every being that is endowed with free will and
performs certain acts in reference to another being, necessarily interrupts those acts at one time or another, in con1

Morth Ncbukim,
III,
i,

II, 18.

Ibid.y II, 14, Sixth


i.

Method.

Cf.

Milhamot Adonai, VI,

i,

3 (p. 299), and

Or

Adonai)

PROPS. 2-6]

UNITY OF SUBSTANCE
.

101
.
.

sequence of some obstacles or changes. circumstances change his will, and the
with obstacles,
is

will,

Thus changed when it meets


is

not carried into

effect.

This, however,

only the case when the causes of the actions are external; but when the action has no other purpose whatever but to fulfil
the will, then the will does not depend on the existence of

favorable circumstances.

The being endowed with

this will

need not act continually even in the absence of all obstacles, because there does not exist anything for the sake of which
it

acts,

and which, the absence of

all

obstacles,

would neces-

sitate the action:

is given somewhat Gersonides. Creation, he says, is an exercise not only of by the divine absolute will but of the divine disinterested good-

the act simply follows the will/* x different turn to this same argument

will.

"If

God

created the world for His

own

benefit, there

would be some ground


been
tion

for this difficulty.

But

since

it

has

made

clear that

God

derives no benefit from His crea-

and that creation is only an act of goodness and kindness, the time and manner of creation must be attributed to His
2

will."

The argument that any sort of finitude in the world, whether that of creation in time or that of magnitude, implies either a lack of power or a lack of good-will on the part

God is repeated by many other philosophers. Thus Leo Hebraeus asks: "Furthermore, the purpose of the Creator in creating the world was nothing but His will to do good.
of

should not the good have been made from eternity, seeing that no obstacle could have hindered the 3 Bruno similarly powerful God who is most perfect ?" that if the world were finite God would have to be argues
Since
it is so,

why

Morth Nebukim, II, 18, Second Method. Milhamot Adonai, VI, i, 18, Ninth Doubt.
Dialoghi d'Amore^ III, pp. 238-239 (Bari, 1929).

102

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

considered either as unable or as unwilling to make it infinite; in either case God would be evil, for "not to be
able is privatively evil, to be able and to be unwilling would be positively and affirmatively evil." Suarez, too, those who objected against Descartes as saying is quoted by that "all limitations proceed from a cause, and the reason
l

why anything
fection/'
2

is finite it

could not, or that

and limited is, either that its cause would not, give it more being and perHerrera, in his tentative argu-

Finally,

Abraham

ment against the finite number of emanations, says that if their number were finite, it would have to be "either because God was unwilling to make them infinite and thus His is not or because He was unable, and thus goodness perfect,
.

3 lacking in power/' Drawing upon these passages, without necessarily following them, Spinoza similarly argues that the creation of a

He

is

finite

world by an

infinite

God would

be incompatible with

divine power and with divine will or good-will. "Further, if it is finite through its cause, this must be so either because

cause could not give more, or because it would not give more. That He should not have been able to give more would
its

contradict His omnipotence; that He should not have been willing to give more, when He could well do so, savors of
ill-will,

which
4

is

nowise

in

God, who

is

all

goodness and
felt

perfection."

Both Maimonides and Gersonides, however,


ness of their solution.
will,

the

weak-

To

attribute creation in time to divine

or good-will,

immutability, but
1

would indeed save divine omnipotence and it would still allow for change in divine
I,

De Immensoct Innumerabilibus^

10 (Opera latina,

I, I,

Neapoli, 1879,

P- 2 3^)

Cf. J. L. Mclntyre, Giordano Bruno, p. 191.


2

Primae Objectiones (Oeuvres, VII,

p. 95,

11.

14-16).

Shaar ha-Shamayim,
Short Treatise,
I, 2,

II, 4.
5

(Opera,

I, p.

20,

11.

18

ff.).

PROPS. 2-6]
will.

UNITY OF SUBSTANCE
ask, even
if

103

"But, some might


all this, is

we admit

the correct-

not change imputed in the fact that the x will of the being exists at one time and not at another ?" While in one place Maimonides attempts to answer it by
ness of

drawing a rather arbitrary line of distinction between human will and divine will, the latter of which he declares to be a 1 homonymous term, in another place he answers it in the
following words:

"The

question remains,

Why

has this

thing been produced now and not long before, since the cause has always been in existence? The answer is that a certain
relation

cause be corporeal;
In a like

between cause and product has been absent, if the or, that the substance has not been
3

sufficiently prepared, if the cause be incorporeal/'

same answer to his own theory of creation. Unlike Maimonides he does not believe in absolute ex nihilo. The world according to him was created from a primordial, formless matter which co-

manner Gersonides

applies the

existed with

God from

eternity, the act of creation being

The

nothing but the investiture of the formless matter with form. choice of a particular time for creation was determined

not by a change in the will of God but by the nature of the matter out of which the world was created. This, according

would militate neither against the immutability of the divine will nor against divine omnipotence: "One might say that inasmuch as God exists always in the same manner,
to him,

His

will

must
it

also remain always the same;

therefore that

God

wills to

by assuming do a thing at one time and does

not will to do

at another, there

must inevitably be a change


that the nature of
it

in the divine nature.

To him we answer
is

the material, primordial element


1

such that

requires that
t

Moreh Nebukim

II, 18,

Second Method, and


a

Ninth Doubt.
i

cf. Milhamot Adonai VI, Moreh Nebnkim, he. cit.

i,

18,

Moreh Ncbukim,

II, 12.

104

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

the existence of the good in it should have a beginning ii time, inasmuch as that good must come to it from somethinj without itself, as has been shown before, whence it has als(

case,

been proved that the world must be created. This being th< it is clear that the existence of the good in this material

primordial element is due to God, whereas the fact that tha good did not exist in it from eternity is due to the imperfec nature of that primordial element, which imperfection ha:

were

served us as a proof that the good in it must be created, fo] it not for this, we have shown, the good in it woulc

have come into being without an efficient cause, which woulc be absurd, as has already been pointed out. This being the case, the coming of the world into existence necessarily hac
to be at a certain time.

There

is

no reason therefore
created

for tru

question,
the

why God

did not create the world at an earliei

time, because whatever time

God

it

before this time

same question could

still

be asked.

And

just as

Goc

cannot be described as possessing the power to create in a thing two opposites at the same time, inasmuch as He h
prevented from doing so by the nature of the object receiving the action, so also cannot God be described as having the

power of making the good exist from eternity in the material element out of which the world was created, for the imperfection in the nature of that element requires that the good
in it

should be created

in

time."

Against both these passages Crescas argues that absolute nothingness and formless matter cannot be said to possess

any nature which would require that

its

creation should take

place at a certain particular time. His argument against Maimonides reads as follows: "The question still remains,

What
1

has

made God
it

create at one time rather than at anit

other? For

would seem that


i,

could not be explained by

Milhamot Adonai, VI,

18,

Ninth Doubt.

PROPS. 2-6]

UNITY OF SUBSTANCE

105

any other reason except that it was the will of God. For if it were for some other reason, that reason would inevitably Agent who performed the action, or in the object upon which the action was performed, or in something outside both the Agent and the object, as, e.g., the organs through which the action was performed.
have
to be

found either

in

the

It could

not be

in the
it

Agent, for His relation to

all

times

is

the same; nor could

non-existence; nor a fortiori could nal, for there is nothing external."

be in the object, for it is nothing but it be in something exterl Against Gersonides he

argues in this wise: "That the change would have taken place without a cause can be easily shown by what has al-

ready been

said.

For

if

the change of God's will

had a cause,
or in the

that cause would have to be found either in


eternal, formless matter, inasmuch as there

God
is

nothing else

besides these two.


times,

But the

relation of

God

is

the

same

to all

and so also is the relation of that eternal, formless matter, and of all that arises from it, the same to all times. Thus there could be no cause for the change of will implied
choosing a particular time for creation." This tilt of Crescas against Maimonides and Gersonides is unquestionably the source of Spinoza's argument given in
in
2

say to this that the nature of the thing required such [limitation] and that it could not therefore be otherwise, that is no reply: for the nature of a thing can rethe foot-note:

"To

quire nothing while

it

does not exist/'

great difficulty of creation which the mediaevals grappled with is the explanation as to how this material, multifarious world could have arisen from the simple, im-

The second

material divine thinking essence.


1

"Ex

nihilo nihil fit/'

This

Or Adonai,

III,

i,

(p.

66b).

Ibid. (p. 68b).

Short frtatise,

I, 2,

5,

note 3 (Opera,

I,

p. 20,

11.

23-25).

io6

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

Aristotelian principle is repeated in Jewish philosophic literature from the earliest time. 1 Matter could not have
origi-

nated
did
it

in

God,

for it

is

excluded from His nature.

Whence

is stated by Jewish philoso" formula that a simple element can phers Neoplatonic 2 Crescas expresses the imonly produce a simple thing/' of matter arising directly from God in the followpossibility

come then? The problem

in the

ing words:
is

"Inasmuch
is

as this matter [in Gersonides' theory]


it

extremely imperfect,

could not have


3

come by

necessity

from God who

infinitely perfect."

The theory of emanation which purported to be a solution of this difficulty was found to be unsatisfactory by both Maimonides and Gersonides. If everything must emanate
from God and if in God there is nothing material, how could matter appear at all at any stage of emanation unless you say it sprang up out of nothing and is in no way traceable to God? It was this reasoning that forced Maimonides to make emanation a volitional process and Gersonides to accept the
Platonic theory of the pre-existence of an eternal, formless matter. Their solutions, however, do not interest us now.

We

are interested only in their statement of the problem. Says Maimonides: "I ask the following question: Aristotle

first Intelligence is the cause of the second, the second of the third, and so on, till the thousandth, if we assume a series of that number. Now the first Intelligence
is

holds that the

undoubtedly simple.

How

then can the

compound form

of existing things come from such an Intelligence by fixed laws of nature, as Aristotle assumes? ... By what law of

nature did the spheres emanate from the Intelligences? What 4 relation is there between material and immaterial beings ?"

Says Gersonides:
1

"This analogy, when


2,

closely examined,
5

Emunot ve-De'ot, 1, Morth Nebukim, II, 22. Morch Ntbukim> II, 22.
Cf.

and Ifobot ha-Lebabot> I, J Or Adonai,

III,

i,

(p. 68a).

PROPS. 2-6]

UNITY OF SUBSTANCE
fall

107

will

be found to

short of proving that matter can be

created from absolute nothing. Only forms can arise in this manner, but not matter. In general, form can produce something of its own kind; hence it produces forms, for all forms are things of reason; but how could it produce materiality?"
'

These discussions as

to the rise of

matter are reflected

in

the following argument of Spinoza, also given in a foot-note. "That there can be no finite substance is clear from this,

namely, that, if so, it would necessarily have something which it would have from nothing, which is impossible. For

whence can

it

derive that wherein

it

differs

from God?

Certainly not from God, for He has nothing imperfect or 2 We have finite, etc. So, whence then but from nothing?**

already called attention to other passages where the same

argument
This

is

first

advanced by Spinoza. proposition of Short Treatise^

I, 2,

as will have

been noticed, corresponds to Propositions II and III of Ethics I. The second proposition, "that there are not two
',

like substances,"

corresponds to Propositions

IV and

of

that "if there were two alike they would necessarily limit one another" 4 is reminiscent of the argument after which it is modelled, namely, that if there
the Ethics.

The argument

were two deities they would limit each other by having a

common genus and

a specific difference. 5
I, 2,
6

The

third proposi-

tion of the Short Treatise,

namely, "that one substance


7

cannot produce another,"


the Ethics > and
is

corresponds to Proposition VI of

proved by three arguments. The first is the argument based upon the impossibility of something arising from nothing which we have already discussed. The
1

Schol.,
a

Milhamot Adonai, VI, i, 17 (p. 364). A parallel statement in is cited by Joel in Lewi ben Gerson als Religionsphilosoph,
I, p. 19,
11.

Ethics, I, Prop. 15,


p. 78, n. I.

3
s

Short Treatise, I, 2, 2, note 2 (Opera, 2 (p. 20, 1. 4). Ibid.,


Cf. above, p. 83.

26-30).
I, 2,

Short Treatise,
'

6.

Short Treatise,

I, 2,

and

7.

Ibid.,

8.

io8
1

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

second, however, is new and somewhat puzzling. It is my purpose to show that it can be rendered clear and intelligible

by interpreting it as a criticism of Gersonides' theory that the world was created from an eternal formless element.
In Cogltata Metaphysica, II, 10, in a passage which is an undoubted allusion to Gersonides* theory of creation, 2 Spinoza says as follows: "We will not pause to refute the

opinion of those who think that the world as chaos, or as matter devoid of form, is co-eternal with God, and so far

independent of Him."
to refute Gersonides,

Here, however, Spinoza does pause

and with an argument raised by Ger-

sonides himself.

Gersonides begins to argue against his

own

theory by saying that "it is inevitable that either some part of this formless element remained after the world had been
created from
to
it or no part of it remained." He then proceeds that neither of these alternatives is possible, adding prove that "it is also past comprehension that the size of this pri-

mordial element should exactly agree with the size of which the world must be, for it is evident that the size of the world
less than what it is." 3 This is exactly what Spinoza means by the following argument: "Further, that which is created is by no means produced from nothing, but must necessarily have been produced from that which is existent (die wezentlyk /V). 4 But that something should come forth from that which is existent and that this latter should not have that something less even after it had been produced from it that we cannot grasp with our understanding." 5 If we take the last part of the passage to mean that the thing "which is created," i.e., the world, after it was produced "from

can be neither more nor

that which
1

is

existent,"
a

i.e.,

the eternal formless matter,

Ibid.,
*
4

9.

Cf. Joel,

Z#r

Genesis der Lehre Spinoza's, p. 48.


141, n. 4,

Milhamot Adonai, VI, i, 18, First Doubt. On the meaning of wezentlyk, cf. below, p.
Short Treatise,
I, 2,

and

p. 382, n. 7.

9 (Opera,

I, p.

21,

11.

21-26).

PROPS. 2-6]

UNITY OF SUBSTANCE
less

109

could not be

than the latter had been before the world was


the

produced from

it,

meaning of the

entire passage

may

be

restated, in the light of Gersonides' argument, in the following manner: Further, since creation ex nihilo has been shown
to be impossible, let us

now

consider creation from an eternal

pre-existent formless element.

This

is,

however, likewise

inconceivable, for

how
by

the created

we cannot grasp with our understanding world, the size of which must be determined

its

own

size of the eternal pre-existent element,


size, so

nature, should happen to agree exactly with the and not be of a lesser

that no part of that element would remain unused after the world had been created from it. This unaccounted
for

agreement in size is characterized by Spinoza as something which "we cannot grasp with our understanding/'
1

Gersonides similarly characterizes

"past comprehension" " comprehend or "conceive


If
is

it as something which is and as something which "I cannot

"

of.

last passage quoted from then the argument contained therein as correct, Spinoza well as the argument contained in the parallel passage

our interpretation of the

quoted from Gersonides is based upon an assumption which is found in Plato and repeated by Philo, namely, the assumption that the matter out of which the world was created was
completely used up
ing
in the creation

of the world so that nothin the following passage:

was

left

of

it.

Plato states

it

"Now

the creation took

up the whole of each of the four

elements; for the Creator compounded the world out of all the fire and all the water and all the air and all the earth,
leaving no part of any of them nor any power of them outside. He intended, in the first place, that the whole animal should

was formed should be

be perfect, as far as possible, and that the parts of which he perfect; and that he should be one,

no

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

leaving no remnants out of which another such world might be created/' 1 Philo restates this view in the following passage:

"It

is

unlikely that

any material body has been

left

over and was moving about at random outside, seeing that

God had wrought up and


matter wherever found."
2

placed in orderly position all Eusebius quotes another passage

from Philo's

lost

De

Providentia as follows:

"With

a view to

estimated an exactly sufficient of matter, so that there might be neither deficiency quantity nor excess. ... I shall therefore confidently assert that the
the creation of the world

God

world needed neither


its
3

less

nor more material substance for


is

in

This passage from Eusebius furnishing." Hebrew by Azariah dei Rossi. 4


third

reproduced

The

argument reads as

follows: "Lastly, if
is

we would

seek the cause of the substance which

things which issue from its seek also the cause of that cause, and then again the cause of that cause, et sic in hifinitum; so that if we must necessarily stop

the origin of the attributes, then it behoves us to

and halt somewhere,

as indeed
5

we must,

it

is

In this passage would seem to admit the impossibility of an infinite Spinoza causal regression, and he would therefore contradict himself, 6

necessary to stop at this only substance/'

for elsewhere

he denies

this impossibility. 7

It

seems

to

me,

however, that the argument contained in this passage has


an entirely different meaning. It must be borne in mind that Spinoza advances it as a proof "that one substance cannot produce another," by
1

* 3

De

Timaeus, 32C-33A. Translation by Jowett. Palantationc Noe, II, 5. Translation by G. H. Whitaker.

Praeparatio Evangelica, VII, 21. Translation by E. H. Gifford.

Mf'or 'Enayim, Imre Binah, Ch. 6

s 6
7

(ed. Cassel, p. 125). Short Treatise, I, 2, 10 (Opera, I, p. 21, 11. 26-32). Cf. A. Wolf, Spinoza's Short Treatise p. 174.
',

Epistola 12.

Cf. below, pp. 195

ff.

PROPS. 2-6]

UNITY OF SUBSTANCE
to refute the theory that a material
in so far as

1 1 1

which he means

world
is

was created
material
is

by an immaterial God who


a

He

im-

transeunt cause.

Like most of his other

arguments
premises.

it

The passage

reasons against his opponents from their own therefore is to be divided into two

parts, in the first of which he reproduces the premise of his opponents and in the latter of which he draws his own con-

clusions from the self-same premise. Spinoza seems to say to them as follows: do you assume the existence of

Why

two substances, God and the world, considering God as the prime cause and rejecting the existence of any other cause
prior to

Him?

It is

things in

change must have

because you believe with Aristotle that a cause and that the series of

causes cannot be infinite, and so you argue that "if we would seek the cause of the substance [i.e., God] which is the origin

of the things which issue from its attribute, then it behoves us to seek also the cause of that cause, and then again the cause of that cause, and so on in infinitum" Your postulating of a prime cause outside the world is therefore dictated by nothing but the alleged need of arbitrarily terminating the series of cause and effect. This being the case, why

not stop the series with the world as a whole and postulate the prime cause as something immanent in the world, "so
that
if

we must

necessarily stop

and halt somewhere, as

in-

deed we must,

it is

necessary to stop at this only substance

[i.e., the world]." The full force of this reasoning will be discussed in our comments on Proposition XVIII of Ethics^ I.

The

fourth and last proposition in this chapter of the Short

its proof many elements taken from the proofs of the preceding propositions, does not properly belong in our present discussion of the unity of substance. It will be treated subsequently in our discussion

Treatise ^ though containing in

of the simplicity of substance.

CHAPTER V
SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE
I.

SIMPLICITY AND ATTRIBUTES

IN THE Appendix at the end of the First Part of the Ethics, Spinoza furnishes us with the unused titles for the unmarked
chapters into which the book would have undoubtedly been divided had he chosen to write it after the manner of the
scholastics "

and the

rabbis.
in

Using the terms


their

"

nature'* and

technical sense, he says: properties" advisedly "In these chapters I have explained the nature of God and

His properties/'
erties:

He

then proceeds to enumerate these prop-

(i) necessarily exists; (2) that He is one; that from the necessity alone of His own nature He is (3) and acts; (4) that He is, and in what way He is, the free

"That He

cause of

all

things;

(5) that all things are in

Him, and

so

depend upon Him

that without

Him

nor be conceived; and,

finally, (6)

they can neither be that all things have been

predetermined by Him, not indeed from freedom of will or from absolute good pleasure, but from His absolute nature
or infinite power." The "nature of God," as we have already seen, is treated in Proposition I, which supplements the definition of substance. Of the six "properties" enumerated by
1

Spinoza the

last four will

be found to cover Propositions

may serve as a heading for There remains therefore only the second " property, that He is one," which is to describe the contents of Propositions II-X and Propositions XII and XIII. We
while the
first

XIV-XXXVI,

Proposition XI.

have already shown


1

in the

preceding chapter
3

that Proposiff.

Cf. above, pp. 61

ff.

Cf. above, pp. 79

PROPS. 7-io, 12-ij]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE

113

tions II-VI deal with the traditional

of God.

We

shall

now

problem of the unity endeavor to show that in Proposi-

tions VII-X and XII-XIII Spinoza similarly deals with another traditional aspect of the same problem. " The expression unity of God*' was used by mediaeval phi-

losophers in two senses. In the first place, it was used in the sense of numerical unity, as an assertion of monotheism and
a denial of the existence of more than one
it

God. In the second


1

of essential unity, or simplicity, place, as a denial of any kind of inner plurality in the divine nature. This distinction in the use of the term "unity" may be traced
in the sense

was used

to Aristotle's discussion of the various meanings of the term "one,"^ which is repeatedly reproduced with the usual modifications and elaborations in mediaeval literature. 3

Unity in the first sense is the subject of the mediaeval proofs of the unity of God; unity in the second sense is the principle underlying the mediaeval discussions of the nature of the
divine essence, or what
divine attributes.
4

generally known as the problem of Spinoza follows the traditional method


is

of treatment. Having discussed the numerical unity of God in Propositions II VI, he now enters upon the discussion of
the essential unity, or simplicity, of God in Propositions VII-X and XII-XIII. The simplicity of God upon which the mediaevals so

strongly insisted was meant to emphasize the impropriety of the assertion, or even of the implication, of any kind of inner plurality in the divine essence. They especially mention
three of such inner pluralities which the idea of absolute simplicity was meant to deny. First of all, it denies the ex1

Or Adonaiy

I, iii, 4.

3 3

Metaphysics, V,

6.
i

Maka$id al-Falasijah, II, (p. Emunah Ramah, II, ii, i; 'Ikkarim,


<

114);
II, 10.

Hobot ha-Lebabot^

I,

8;

Citzari, II, 2;

Cf. 'Ibfrrim, II, 7.

14

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


God
of accidental qualities.

[ETHICS,

istence in

These had

to be re-

jected on account of the belief in the absolute incorporeality of God which tradition, if not the actual asseverations of
the Bible,
intensified

which belief was further had taken for granted when the traditional God was identified with the

Aristotelian pure form.

"He

is

not a magnitude that any

quality resulting from quantity as such could be possessed by Him; He is not affected by external influences, and there-

any quality resulting from emotion; not subject to physical conditions, and therefore does not possess strength or similar qualities; He is not an animate
fore does not possess

He

is

being, that He should have a certain disposition of the soul, or acquire certain properties, as meekness, modesty, etc., or be in a state to which animate beings as such are subject, as, e.g., in that of health or of illness. Hence it follows that

no attribute coming under the category of quality can be predicated of God." But the simplicity of God denies more than that. It also
l

denies the metaphysical or logical distinction of genus and species in the divine nature, or what are known as essential

attributes as distinguished from accidental attributes.

Arabic as well as Jewish philosophers are explicit in their denial of the distinction of genus and species in God. 2 It is
this principle that underlies the following

passage of Mai-

monides: "The object

is

described by

its definition, as, e.g.,


.

described as a being that lives and has reason. All agree that this kind of description cannot be given of God;
is
. .

man

for there

is

no previous cause
. .

to

His essence, by which

He

could be defined.
definition, as

when,

e.g.,
. .

An object is described by part of its man is described as a living being or


.

as a rational being.
1

All agree that this kind of descrip-

Moreh Ncbukim
Ma%a$id

I,

52.
ii,

al-Falasifah, II,

(p. 145);

'Ibfyarim, II, 6

and

7.

PROPS. 7-10,12-13]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE
in reference to

115

inappropriate speak of a portion of His essence, essence to be a compound." *

tion

is

to God; we should consider His

for if

we were

There

is

nature which

a third possible kind of distinction in the divine is specifically rejected by the mediaevals in

their discussion of the simplicity of

tinction of essence
torical reasons, to

God, namely, the disThere are certain hisbe dealt with subsequently, which induced

and

existence.

the mediaevals to single out the predicate of existence for special discussion. Suffice it to say for the present that both Arabic and Jewish philosophers deal with this problem
specifically in their general discussion of the nature of the

We may quote here the following typical from Maimonides, which occurs in the course of his passage discussion of attributes: "It is known that existence is an
divine essence.

and therefore an element superadded to their essence. This must evidently be the case as regards everything the existence of which is due to some cause; its existence is an element superadded to its essence. But as regards a being whose existence is not due to any cause God alone is that being, for His existence, as
accident appertaining to
all

things,

we have

said,

is

absolute

existence

and essence are peris


2

fectly identical.

He

is

not a substance to which existence

joined as an accident, as an additional element."


plurality, physical as well as metaphysical

Simplicity in this sense, as a denial of any kind of internal

and

logical, is

maintained by Spinoza with regard to substance.

Of

the

three kinds of internal plurality especially rejected by the the plurality of subject and accidental qualmediaevals,

genus and species, and of essence and existence, Spinoza mentions the last one specifically in Proposition
ity*
f

VII. As for the second kind of internal plurality, he quotes


1

Moreh Nebukim,

I,

52.

March Nctukim,

I, 57.

n6
x

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


"God
is

[ETHICS,

the mediaevals to the effect that

not a species of any

genus,"
is

which means the same as to say that in God there no distinction of genus and species. This, as we have alis

ready seen/

the implication of his definition of substance

and of Proposition I, which is based upon it. It is this, too, which is meant when he says in one of his letters to Jellis that "of His [i.e., God's] essence we can form no general
idea (universalem
3 ideam)." Finally, as for the first of internal plurality, in Scholium 2 to Proposition VIII, kind which really belongs to Proposition VII, he dismisses, in un.

mistakable terms, the inherence in substance of accidental qualities, and almost in the words of Maimonides he says
that those
so because

who
"

attribute accidental qualities to substance do they do not distinguish between the modifica-

tions of substances

and substances themselves," and

also

because they "confound

"readily attribute to thus to Spinoza, like simple, free from accidental as well as from essential attributes,

human nature with divine" and God human affects." Substance is God to the mediaevals, absolutely
to the distinction of essence

and likewise impervious

and

existence.

The mediaeval insistence upon the absolute simplicity of God did not, however, mean to divest Him of all traits of personality. A God who has been conceived as creator and
governor of the world, as lawgiver to man, and judge of human actions, could not possibly be conceived as impassive
as a mathematical point

and

as indifferent as a metaphysical

absolute. This belief in the personality of God is summed up by the mediaevals in the statement that "God, blessed be

He, must be
1

free

of imperfections,"
a

by which

is

meant that

Short Treatise,

I, 7,

3.
II.

Cf. above, p. 77.

Epistola 50 (Opera, IV, p. 240,


,

2-3).

I,

15;

cf. II, 7.

PROPS. 7-10, 12-13]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE

117

possess power and will and the other attributes without which He could not be thought of as perfect."
*

"He must

Spinoza restates this view in a letter addressed to Hudde in the following words: "That everything, which includes necessary existence, can have in itself no imperfection, but must 2 Thus while on the one hand God express pure perfection."

must be absolutely simple and unqualifiable, on the other hand He must possess all those qualities which make for personality. How these two can be reconciled is the problem
of attributes, which does not concern us for the present. The following brief statement from Albo will suffice as an indication of the mediaeval point of view: "All the attributes of perfection that are predicated of God or are conceived to
exist in exist in

Him are Him only


3

predicated of
in the sense in
in

Him and

are conceived to

but

in

none of the senses

which they imply perfection which they would imply imper-

fection."

made by

particular importance for us here is the use the mediaevals of the term "infinite" with regard

Of

to these attributes of perfection.

In the

first

place, these

attributes of

God

are to be infinite in

number: "It must be

understood that the perfections which exist in God are infinite in number." 4 In the second place, each of these attributes must be infinite in two senses: infinite in time, that eternal, and infinite in the degree of importance, that is,
its
is,

in

essential nature.

attributes

by which

"When we ascribe to God any of the He may be described, whether negative

or positive, that attribute must be taken to be infinite in two s and infinite in perfection or imrespects, infinite in time
6

portance."
1

The term

"infinite" applied to
2

God

thus means

Ibid., I, 15.
3
s

Epistola 35.
Ibid., II, 25.

'Ikkarim,

II, 21.

The term "time" has two meanings according


passage
is

to Albo,

and

infinite

time in

this
6

the equivalent of eternity.

Cf. below, pp. 339, 363.

'Ifckarim, II, 25.

Il8

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

to designate that He possesses an infinite number of attributes each of which is eternal and absolutely perfect. To

with reference to this that the Cabalists designated God by the term Infinite (En Sof), to indicate that the perfections which are to be found in Him are infinite in the
quote: "It
is

three senses which


infinite in the
finite in

we have mentioned that is to say, number of attributes and each attribute in'

"

time and in perfection. Similarly to Spinoza, while God is absolutely simple and unqualifiable, He may still be described as possessing attributes, infinite in number,

the mediaevals called time

and each of them infinite in what and perfection. His definition


is

of God at the beginning of the First Part of the Ethics


ing but a restatement of the passages from Albo in the preceding paragraph.

noth-

we have reproduced

"By God,

under-

stand Being absolutely infinite, that is to say, substance consisting of infinite attributes, each one of which expresses

Note the expression "eternal and infinite essence." By "eternal" 3 he means here what Albo calls "infinite in time," and by "infinite" he means again what Albo calls "infinite in perfection or importance."
eternal

and

infinite essence."

In his definition of God given in a letter to Oldenburg, 4 where incidentally the term "eternal" does not occur, Spinoza

himself explains the term "infinite," by which each of the infinite attributes of God is described, as meaning "in the
highest degree perfect of its kind." And what he has laid down of God in his definitions, he now tries to prove of sub-

stance in his propositions. First he shows that "every substance is necessarily infinite" (Prop. VIII), just as God is

"absolutely infinite." Then, just as


1

God
I,

is

"substance conand

Ibid.

Ethics,

Def. 6.
ff.

For Spinoza's various uses of the term "eternal," see below, pp. 366
ff-

375

Epistola 2 (Opera, IV, p. 7,

11.

25-26).

PROPS. 7-10, 12-13]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE

119

sisting of infinite attributes," so substance possesses infinite " the more reality or being a thing possesses, attributes, for

the

more

attributes belong to it" (Prop. IX),

and inasmuch

as substance has infinite reality or being, it must have infinite attributes. Finally, each attribute of substance must "ex-

press eternal
for

and

infinite essence," just as the attributes

of

"each attribute of a substance must be conceived God, through itself" (Prop. X), and must therefore be identical with substance, and inasmuch as substance is infinite, each of its attributes must be infinite. In Jewish philosophy, too,
the infinite nature of each attribute
finite
is

deduced from the

inis

nature of God.

"For

just as God, blessed be He,

infinite

time and in importance, so is each of His 1 attributes infinite both in time and in importance."

both

in

of the mediaevals to preserve God's personality by endowing Him with infinite attributes while at the same time insisting upon His absolute simplicity has landed

The attempt

them, as we have already pointed out, in a self-contradiction. Attributes are either accidental or essential; they must be

and weight and suchlike, or as genera and species, as, e.g., life and rationality are related to man. In either case they must imply a distinction of essence and attribute in the subject, though
related to the subject either as color

and

size

only metaphysical or Furthermore, attributes differ among themselves logical. from each other, and therefore the assertion of an infinite
in the latter instance the distinction
is

number of number of

attributes

must imply a corresponding

infinite

differences in the nature of the subject.

If the

divine nature is to be free from any kind of plurality, how then can it have attributes? This difficulty constitutes the

problem of divine attributes in mediaeval philosophy. The solutions offered will be touched upon in the sequel. In a
1

'Ifckarim, II, 25.

120

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

general way, it may be said that in the attempted solutions two facts are sought to be established: first, all the attri-

butes of

God

are in reality one attribute, and, whatever

differences there

do not

appear to exist between them, they nature of God; second, whatever may be the relation between essence and attribute, the assertion of

may

affect the

divine attributes does not contravene the simplicity of God's


essence.

Similarly Spinoza, after having stated in Propositions that substance has an infinite number of VIII, IX, and

attributes, proceeds to

show that though assuming an

infinite

number of

attributes of which two

"may

be conceived as

really distinct,

that

is

to say,

one without the assistance

we cannot nevertheless thence conclude that of the other, " they constitute two beings or two different substances
(Prop. X, Schol.), and that "no attribute of substance can be truly conceived from which it follows that substance can

be divided" (Prop. XII), concluding that "substance abso" lutely infinite


is

indivisible

(Prop. XIII).

This then

is

the logical

VII

and XII-XIII.

argument underlying Propositions Had the Ethics been written more

Spinoza would have prefaced these with the following words: We shall now propropositions ceed to show that just as substance is like God in its numerischolastico rabbinicoque
cal unity (Props. II VI), so
it is

also like

God

in its

absolute

simplicity.

That

it

has no distinction of genus and species

has already been stated (Def. Ill and Prop. I); that it should have accidental qualities must be dismissed as something incomprehensible to a philosopher (Prop. VIII, Schol. What is therefore left us to show is that like the philo-

2).

sophic God of the mediaevals substance has no distinction of essence and existence (Prop. VII). Furthermore, though like

God "every

substance

is

necessarily infinite*' (Prop. VIII),

PROPS. 7-io, 12-ij]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE

121

that is to say, consisting of infinite attributes (Prop. IX), each one of which expresses eternal and infinite essence (Prop. X), still this infinity of attributes does not imply that sub-

stance

is

in

any sense

divisible (Prop.

X,

Schol.;

Props.

XII-XIII).

With these general remarks we are now ready to discuss more fully the following three topics and the propositions in which they are treated: (i) the problem of essence and
existence (Prop. VIII; Def. I); (2) the definition of the term "infinite" (Def. II; Def. VI; Props. VIII-X); (3) the relation of attribute to substance (Def. IV;

Prop. X, Schol.;

Props. XII-XIII).

II.

ESSENCE AND EXISTENCE


existence which
is

The problem of essence and

dwelt upon

by Spinoza not only in his Ethics but also in his other writings, the terms in which the problem is couched, and the

manner

in

which

it is

treated, are

all

part of the great philo-

Two

sophic heritage which had fallen to him from his predecessors. distinct traditions served him as sources of supply.
the philosophic writings in Hebrew which have preserved the traditions of Arabic philosophy; the other was

One was

Descartes,
scholastics.

who has preserved


It

the traditions of the Latin

can be shown that the two traditions had

crossed at one time, and that the scholastic tradition of a


later period

influence.

was greatly indebted to the Arabico-Hebrew But in Descartes, in whom the scholastic tra-

dition reached

its culminating point, owing to the influence of Anselm's ontological proof of the existence of God, the assertion of the identity of essence and existence in God as-

sumed
which

it

a meaning which was entirely different from that had in Jewish philosophy. In Jewish philosophy the

122

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


God
else it is phrased,
is

[ETHICS,

assertion that in

however
that

essence and existence are identical, or 1 was merely another way of saying

necessary existence out of which arises the eternity, unity, simplicity, immutability, and unknowability of God, and in fact all those negations which tend to make God

God

an absolute and

infinite being. It

does not however

mean

that

thereby God becomes a "real" being (ens reale) as opposed to a being of reason and a fictitious being (ens rationis, ens
fictum).

God

Or, in other words, the fact that in the idea of essence involved existence was not used to prove the

actual existence of God, for in Jewish as well as in Arabic


2 In philosophy that mode of reasoning was not followed. Descartes the identity of essence and existence means all

it also means something else in addition. means also that this very idea of the identity of essence and existence in God proves that He is a "real" being. In Spinoza, as we shall endeavor to show, these two trends of

that, to be sure, but

It

inherited from the

thought meet, and upon the groundwork of philosophic lore Hebrew books of his youth he raised the

superstructure of Descartes* ontological proofs of the existence of God.

However complicated and important the problem of sence and existence may have become in the course of
sumed
had
in the

esits

development, and however great the significance it has asin its later history, the problem seems to me to have
it originated of propositions in which meaning the term "existent" forms the predicate, as, for instance, "A

a simple

and humble

origin.

To my mind,

question as to the

is

existent."
1

In order to appreciate the significance of this


of phrasing it is that God is existence without essence added "Crescas on the Problem of Divine Attributes," Jewish Quarterly

The

other

way

thereto.

See
n.s.,

my

Review,
3

Cf.

my
I

"Notes on

Vol. VII, p. 189, n. 85. the proofs of the Existence of


f.

God," Hebrew Union

College

Annual\

(1924), pp. 583

PROPS. 7-10,

2-13]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE
in

123

question,

we must bear

mind that

Aristotle,

and following

him Arabic and Jewish logicians, held that every logical judgment must be synthetic, so that in every proposition the predicate must be a universal term belonging to one of the four or five predicables enumerated by Aristotle and Porphyry. It must be the genus of the subject, its species, a
specific difference, a

property or an accident.

In mediaeval

terminology the

first

sential attributes," the last

three predicables are known as "estwo as "accidental attributes."

characteristic of all these predicables is that are all universal terms and are not identical with the they essence of the subject. Essential attributes state the ele-

The common

ments of which the essence of the subject is constituted or to which it belongs, and though not different from the essence of the subject they are either more extensive or less extensive than it, as, for instance, when the combination of

animality and rationality, or either one of these, is predicated of man. Accidental attributes are something different from,
the essence of the subject, adding some adventitious quality to it, as, for instance, when color and

and external
size

to,

and age are predicated of man. Nothing that is perfectly identical with the subject and co-extensive with it and is a mere verbal repetition of its essence can be affirmed
tle laid it

in the predicate, for identity

not a logical relation. Aristodown as a rule when he stated that "individuals,


is

and whatever is one in number, are predicated of no suband the mediaevals condemned as tautological any ject," proposition like "A is A." In view of this the question may be justly raised as to what kind of predicate is the term
l

"existent"

in the proposition

"A

is

existent."

It

cannot be

identical with the essence of the subject, for then the proposiis A. It is theretion would be tantamount to saying that

Categories, 2, ib, 6-7.

124

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


is
1

[ETHICS,!

fore concluded that existence

always an accident super-

added to the essence of a thing. That existence is an element adventitious to the essence of things would seem to be on the whole in accord with what

we know of Aristotle's views on the subject. According to him the existence of things is not implied in the knowledge of their essence which we may attain from their definition, and thus while we may have an idea of man and knowledge of his essence, and while we are even capable of defining him, none of these can prove the actual existence of man. For all definitions are answers to the question what a thing is but
not to the question whether a thing
is.

"But 'what man


3

is*

and 'that man

exists' are

two

different questions."

Again:

'Evidently those who define according to the present methods of definition do not demonstrate that a thing exists." 3

To form

conceptions of certain essences, to define them, to describe them in formal propositions, does not imply that

nominal

they exist, for definitions and propositions may be purely in which words rather than things are the subject of
If a thing does actually exist,
it

discourse.

it

only happens to

exist, just as

only happens

to be white or black, large or

assert therefore of such a thing that it is existent is simply to attribute to it an accidental quality, just as to say of a black or white thing that it is black or white. This

small.

To

interpretation of Aristotle, to be sure, might be doubted. It might be argued that while indeed there are nominal definitions in which existence is not implied, it may be still possible that in real definitions existence is implied, and that to attribute existence to things that do actually exist is not to

attribute an accidental quality but rather to affirm some1

This argument
I, iii, i.

is

reproduced by Crescas in the name of Avicenna in his Or


92!^ 10-11.

Adonai,
2

Analytica Posteriora,
Ibid.) 92b, 19-20.

II, 7,

PROPS. 7-10,

2-13]
is

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE

125

thing that

involved in their essence.

This indeed would

seem

to be Averroes' interpretation of Aristotle, for he


is

mainan

tains that existence

always involved

in the essence of

1 actually existent subject. Avicenna, however, and his Jewish followers, as Maimonides, for instance, by maintaining

that existence

seem

to

is an accident superadded to the essence would have understood Aristotle as explained above.

But even according


exception. to His essence any

to

Avicenna and

his school,

God

is

an

In

Him

existence cannot be assumed to be added

more than any of the other

attributes

could be considered as accidental qualities. This is impossible by reason of the simplicity of the divine nature. It is

because of this general principle that existence is accidental to the essence of created beings that the theologians of the Avicennian school have included in their discussion of the
divine attributes the statement that

superadded to His existence, or that


istence are identical. 2
It

God in God

has no essence
essence and ex-

would seem that

it

was

this traditional

method of

in-

sion of attributes or the simplicity of

cluding the problem of essence and existence in the discusGod that led Spito lay

noza

down

his

seventh proposition.

All of Spinoza's

statements with regard to the nature of existence in relation to essence reflect the Avicennian and Maimonidean point of
view.

Repeating almost verbatim the words of Aristotle, he

says that "the true definition of any one thing neither involves nor expresses anything except the nature of the thing involved." 3 Again, corresponding to the Avicennian formula
that in created beings existence
their essence, Spinoza says:
1

is

an accident superadded to
essence of things produced
I,

"The

Cf. quotation in

Munk, Guide
cf.

des

gars, Vol.

p. 231, n. I.

3
J

Cf. above, p. 122, n. i. Ethics y I, Prop. 8, Schol. 2;

Epistola 34.

126

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


r

[ETHICS,

by God does not involve existence."


ferent, for

"I define
2

God

as a being to
is

God is however difwhose essence belongs


is

existence."

And what

true of

God

true also of sub-

"It pertains to the nature of substance to exist." 3 The contrast between God and created beings is clearly
stance:

brought out in the following passage: "Essence in God is not different from existence; indeed the one cannot be conceived without the other. In other things essence differs from 4 existence, for the one may be conceived without the other."

In his proof of Proposition VII, no less than in the proposition itself, Spinoza follows his predecessors. In Jewish philosophy, the negation of the distinction of essence and ex-

God, as well as that of any other distinction, is based upon the view that any form of composition requires a cause to bring about that composition and that God can have no cause. "Everything that is composed of two eleistence in

ments has necessarily

their composition as the cause of its

existence as a composite being, and consequently in respect to its own essence it is not necessary of existence, for its

upon the existence of its component parts 5 Again: "Everything which is of existence in respect to its own essence has no necessary cause for its existence in any manner whatsoever or under 6 any conditions whatsoever." With this in mind Maimonides
existence depends

and

their

combination."

argues for the identity of essence and existence in God as follows: "It is known that existence is an accident apper-

and therefore an element superadded to This must evidently be the case as regards everything the existence of which is due to some cause; its
taining to
all

things,

their essence.

Jbid.,\, Prop. 24.

2 4

Epistola 83 (Opera,

I, p.

335,

1.

5).

Ethics,
7.

I,

Prop.

7.

Cogitata Metaphysica,

I, 2.

Cf. Ethics, I,

Axiom

Moreh Ncbukim,
Ibid., Prop. 20.

II,

Introduction, Prop. 21.

PROPS. 7-10, 12-13]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE

127

an element superadded to its essence. But as a being whose existence is not due to any cause regards God alone is that being, for His existence, as we have said,
existence
is is

absolute
is

existence

and essence are perfectly


is

identical;

He

joined as an accix so as to constitute an additional element." dent, The short proof of Proposition VII given by Spinoza fol-

not a substance to which existence

line of reasoning. The essence of substance must involve existence, he argues, because substance has no cause, for " there is nothing by which substance can be produced/' Were existence superadded to its essence, substance would require a cause to produce it. This state of

lows the same

being causeless, which the mediaevals as well as Spinoza himself usually designate by the expression "necessary existence," Spinoza also designates by the expression "cause of itself" (causa sui\ a phrase which had already been in current use in philosophic literature. 2 Causa sui y like the

mediaeval "necessary existence,"

is primarily nothing but a negation, meaning causelessness, and to Spinoza it is only a shorter way of saying that the essence of substance in-

volves existence.
tion of causa sui y

He

thus says in his first part of the defini"By cause of itself, I understand that,

whosef*essence involves existence/' 3 though the latter part of'the definition, as we shall presently show, introduces a

new

idea into the phrase.

We thus have in Spinoza the following equation


existence

causa sui

necessary that whose essence involves exist:

All of these expressions, as marily nothing but causelessness.


this effect
*

ence

we have

seen,

mean

pri-

is

to be

found

in

explicit statement to the following passage of Spinoza:

An

Ibid., 1, 57.
2

Cf. J. Freudenthal,
. .
.

"Spinoza und die Scholastik"

in

Philosophised Aufsdtze.
of Spinoza , p. 118, n.
i.

Eduard Zeller
a

gcwidmet, p. 119; Martineau,


i.

A Study

Ethics,

I,

Def.

128

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


thing must be conceived either through
its

[ETHICS,

"A

essence alone

or through its proximate cause. Namely, if a thing be in itself, or, as it is commonly termed, its own cause (causa sui) y

then
if

it

must be understood through

its

essence alone; but


it
r

a thing be not in itself, but requires a cause to exist, then

must be understood through its proximate cause." Now, Arabic and Jewish philosophy the concept of necessary existence as applied to God is the main principle out of which arise all the negations and affirmations about the divine nature. It is from this that it is deduced that God is immain

not an accident existing in a subject or a matter, that His essence and existence are identical, that He is not conditioned by any other cause nor
terial,

that

He

is

form existing

in

being, that He is one, that He has no accidental qualities, that He is immutable, that He is the emanative cause of every thing, that He
in

any other way dependent upon another

is

indefinable,

and that
2

He

is

the source of the existence of

to By everything deduce from the concept of necessary existence, or its equivalents, a similar list of negations and affirmations about God.
else.

the

same token Spinoza undertakes

in one of his letters to Hudde: "I will briefly show what properties must be possessed by a Being that includes necessary existence. To wit: I. It must be eternal. ... II. It must be simple, not made up of parts. III.

Says he
.

It
. .

cannot be conceived as determinate, but only as infinite. IV. It must be indivisible. ... V. [It] can have in itself
.

no imperfection, but must express pure perfection. there can only be a single Being, of which existLastly
.

ence belongs to
that
1

its

nature."

Again:

"From

the fact alone,


exist-

define

God

as a Being to

whose essence belongs


92 (Opera,
II, p. 34,
11.

Tractates de Intelltetus Emendationc,

9-13).

2 3

Mafya$id al-Falasifah,
Epistola 35.

II,

ii

(pp. 137

if.).

PROPS. 7- 10, 12-13]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE

129

ence,
*

infer several of

necessarily exists,
etc."

His properties; namely, that He that He is one, unchangeable, infinite,

Not only from the mediaevals but also from Descartes has Spinoza derived the method of deducing the properties of God from the concept of necessary existence. "Indeed upon this truth alone, namely, that existence belongs to the nature
of God, or that the concept of God involves a necessary existence as that of a triangle that the sum of its angles is equal to two right angles, or again that His existence and His of God's attributes by which
essence are eternal truth, depends almost all our knowledge we are led to a love of God (or
to the highest blessedness)."
2

But from Descartes Spinoza has borrowed also the ontological proof. A being whose conception involves existence, according to this reasoning, must necessarily exist, and this
existence of
sort of reasoning forms the basis of Spinoza's proofs of the God in Proposition XI, to be discussed in a sub-

sequent chapter. Now, according to Descartes, the term a se, which he applies to God in the same sense as sui causa, 3
has both a negative sense and a positive sense. In its negative sense it means that God has no cause; 4 in its positive
sense
it

means that God stands

to himself in the

as an efficient cause does to its effect. 5

same way The term causa sui


meaning causeit is

similarly in Spinoza is not a mere negation, lessness; it means also something positive:

an asser-

tion of self-sufficency and hence actual existence. He thus says in the second part of his definition of causa sui: "or that, whose nature cannot be conceived unless exist1

Kpistola 83.

Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae,

I,

Prop.

5,

Schol.
16

J
*

Primae Responsiones (Ofuvres, VII, Ibid. (p. no, 1. 24). Ibid. (p. in, 11. 6-7).

p. 109,

11.

and

21).

130
*

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

Likewise Proposition VII of the First Part of the Ethics, while on the whole it is a reproduction of mediaeval Jewish discussions, contains also the additional Cartesian
ing."
is indicated in its phrasing. Spinoza does not there as he says in Cogitata A4etaphysica, I, 2, that say essence in substance is not different from existence, but he

element, as

says, "It pertains to the nature of substance to exist."

The identity of essence and existence is also the burden of the fourth proposition in the second chapter of the First Part of the Short 'Treatise. The wording of the proposition somewhat obscures
infinite

meaning. It reads as follows: "That in the understanding of God there is no other substance than
its
is

that which

formaliter in nature/'

proposition, however, becomes clear with its restatement at the end of the Short Treatise,

The purpose of this when it is compared


Appen-

"To such an extent does existence I, Proposition IV: nature to the essence of every substance, that it pertain by
dix

impossible to posit in an infinite understanding the idea of the essence of a substance that does not exist in nature/'
is

It

is

clear that this fourth proposition, both in the


in

main

text

Appendix of the Short Treatise, is parallel to Proposition VII in Ethics, I, namely, that existence pertains to the nature of substance. In the Short Treatise, howthe

and

and existence

ever, Spinoza utilizes the principle of the identity of essence in substance as an argument for what is the

main contention of Chapter 2 of the Short Treatise, I. The main contention of that chapter, as we have already shown, is to refute the mediaeval view that there are two substances,

God and
volved in
1

the world, the latter of which has no existence inits

essence,
i.

inasmuch as

it

must acquire existence


But
is

Ethics, I, Def.

Short Treatise,
is

I, 2,

2 (Opera,

I, p.

20,

11.

6-7).

"there

no substance or attribute" instead of "there

II (p. 21, 11. 33-34): in no oth^r substance."

PROPS. 7-10,

2-13]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE

131

through an act of creation or emanation. Spinoza seems to say to his mediaeval opponents, in Proposition IV of the
Short Treatise ,
[i.e.,

I, 2,

as follows:

You maintain

that the world

conditional substance] had existed prior to its creation as an "idea" in the "infinite understanding [i.e., intelonly lect] of God," and that only through an act of creation has

But any form of creation, however have already shown to you to be impossible. 1 Existence therefore must pertain to the essence of the world just as you say it pertains to the essence of God, and there is
it

acquired existence.
I

explained,

thus no such distinction between

God and

the world as that

of creator and created, or absolute substance and conditional substance. He thus concludes, in the Corollary to Proposition IV in Appendix I at the end of the Short Treatise, that:

"Nature
thing.
infinite

is

known through

itself,

It consists of infinite

and not through any other attributes, every one of them

and perfect in its kind; to its essence pertains existence, so that outside it there is no other essence or existence,
thus coincides exactly with the essence of God, who alone is glorious and blessed." By "nature" here Spinoza

and

it

means

the universe;

God

is

not outside of

it,

that

is

to say,

pure form as opposed to matter, but the two are essentially the same, for, as he sums up his conclusions at the end of the
four propositions in the same chapter of the Short Treatise, "we posit extension [i.e., matter] as an attribute of God." 2

The proofs of the fourth proposition given in Chapter 2 of the Short Treatise, I, are not altogether new. They are only restatements of the arguments already used by Spinoza in his
first three propositions. We have already out the literary origins of these arguments in our pointed discussion of the unity of substance in the preceding chapter.

discussion of the

Cf. above,

Chapter IV.
1, 2,
1

Short Treatise >

8 (Opera, I, p. 24,

1.

H ).

But see below, pp. 299, 3 19

ff.

132

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

The

sources quoted there will throw light upon Spinoza's reference here to an argument "from the infinite power of

God, since in Him there can be no cause by which He might have been induced to create one sooner or more than another"
x

date his

Argument). They will likewise help to elucireference to an argument that God "cannot omit to
(First
is

do what

good"

ment based upon

(Third Argument), as well as his arguthe principle "that one substance cannot

3 produce another" (Fourth Argument). There is only left for us to account for his allusion to an argument "from the 4 simplicity of His will" (Second Argument). This I believe to reflect a passage in which Crescas attempts to refute Maimonides* solution of the problem of creation. It will be

recalled that as to

Maimonides endeavors

why God

answer the question created the world at one time rather than at
to

another, as well as to explain the other difficulties of creation, by the general statement that creation was an act of divine
will.

To

this

Crescas retorts somewhat as follows:

If the

is

world was created by divine will, then inasmuch as the world composite, the will that has created it will have to be com-

posite, for the creative will

must be

diffused throughout the

parts of the object created. But this is impossible, since God's will, not being distinct from His essence, must be as simple
as the essence
itself. 5

Hence Spinoza's cryptic statement,


will."
6

"from the simplicity of His


1
3

Short treatise,
Ibid. (p. 22, Ibid. (p. 22,
11.
1.

I,

2,

1 1

(Opera,

I, p.
3

21,

1.

35~p. 22,
(p. 22,
11.

1.

3).

3-4).
3).

I^d.

5-7).

Cf.

Or Adonai)

III,

i,

(p.

66b,

11.

42-45): "Granted that the proposition leads

to the conclusion that there

must be
will

the will of an agent, this very

same proposition

would

also

have to make that


itself

composite object would


6

produce one simple object, for a will producing a have to be composite, inasmuch as the will must be
it

diffused throughout the composite object which

produces."

Cf. also Descartes' statement that "the will consists only of one single element,
is

and

so to speak indivisible" (Mcditationes^ IV, Oeuvres, VII, p. 60,

II.

22-23).

PROPS. 7-10, 12-13]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE

133

III.

DEFINITION OF THE

TERM "INFINITE"
"every substance endeavor to explain in

Coming now
is

to Proposition VIII, that

necessarily infinite,"

we

shall first

what sense Spinoza uses the term "infinite." Here, too, it is to his predecessors that we must turn for help and information. Spinoza speaks of two kinds of infinite. There is,
first,

With
(in

the "absolutely infinite" (absolute infinitum) (Def. VI). this is contrasted, second, the "infinite in its own kind"

suo genere infinitum) (Def. VI, Expl.).

Corresponding
its

to the "infinite in its

own kind"

there

is

the "finite in

own kind"
will

(in suo genere fin itum) (Def. II). These phrases to be sure, all defined by Spinoza, but his definitions, as are,

have been gathered, are in most cases brief restatements of generally accepted and well-known mediaeval concepts.

What then is the origin and background of these phrases as well as of the ideas behind them ?
In mediaeval discussions of infinity the term "infinite" is said to have two meanings. It may be an accident either of

magnitude or of number, or
lect.
1

it

may

be an essence, that

is

to

say, a self-existent substance, immaterial like soul

and

intel-

As an accident of magnitude

it

means an unlimited

distance or length, something that has no end or boundary. As an accident of number, it means something that is endlessly addible or divisible. "Finite" as the antithesis of this

kind of infinite means just the opposite, a distance that is bounded and a number that is limited, or, in other words, something comparable with others of its kind and exceeded

by them. But an

essentially infinite

substance means something

1 See Or Adonai, I, i, i (p. 4a-b), based upon Averroes' Middle Commentaries on Physics , III, 4, 2043, 2-5, 2043, 32, and Metaphysics XI, 10, io66a, 35~io66b, 21. Cf. my Crescas' Critique of Aristotle, p. 137 and notes on pp. 329-335.
,

134

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

It means a substance whose essence is entirely different. unique and so incomparable that it cannot suffer any form

of limitation and hence cannot have any form of positive


description, for every description necessarily implies a limita1 tion, or as Spinoza puts it: "determination is negation."

To

call

a substance infinite in this sense

is

like calling voice


it

colorless.

When

voice

is

described as colorless

does not

mean

the negation of a property which we should expect it to have and which it may have, but rather the absolute ex-

clusion of voice from the universe of color.

By

the

same

" trasted with "particular negation expressed in the distinction between


is

when substance means its absolute exclusion from any form of finitude, limitation, and description. The negation of finitude implied " " infinite is what the mediaeval in this sense of the term would call "absolute negation" as conJewish logicians
token,
is described as infinite in this sense,

it

a contrast which

is

"A

is

not-B" and

"A

There is a suggestion of this distinction in Arisand Spinoza himself uses for these two kinds of netotle, gation the terms "negation" (negatio) and "privation"
not B."
2

"Thus privation is nothing else than denying of (privatio). a thing something which we think belongs to its nature; negation is nothing else than denying of a thing something because 3 Of the parallel passages it does not belong to its nature."
in Jewish philosophy the following

may

be quoted:

"You
is

already know from your reading in logic two kinds. One is particular negation, 4
*

that negation
as, e.g.,

of

when we

say

Balaam does not see/ which

sense of the term.


to say, the
1

The

other

is

negation in the true absolute negation, 5 that is


is

denying of the subject that which does not natu11.

Epistola 50 (Opera,YV, p. 240,


I,

13-14): "determinatio negatio est."


Interpretations
5-7).
',

Cf.

Ethics,
*
<

Prop.

8, Schol. i.

De
11.

Ch.

10; Metaphysics,

V, 22.

Epistola 21 (Opera , IV, p. 129,

rnnvon

n^pn.

nrfrwon n

PROPS. 7-10, 12-13]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE
it,

135
is

rally belong to

as, e.g.,

"The wall does not see/ which


l

negation in a general sense/'


cidental infinite
totle:
is

This mediaeval distinction between an essential and an ac-

"The

infinite is either that


it is

based upon the following passage in Ariswhich is incapable of being


not
its

traversed because

nature to be traversed
'

this
,

corresponds to the sense in

which the voice

is

in visible*

or that which admits only of incomplete traverse or scarcely admits of traverse, or that which, though it naturally admits of traverse, is not traversed or limited; further, a thing may

be infinite

in respect

of addition or of subtraction or of both." 2


is this.

The

implication of the passage


limit.

The

infinite is that

which has no

The term

is

derived from magnitude and

other thing which

number, and must thus primarily apply to them or to any may be measured either quantitatively or

may therefore speak of infinite beauty as qualitatively. well as of infinite length and number. All such forms of
measurement, however, imply a common standard and a comparison of the thing measured with other things of its kind.

We

But the term "infinite" may be used

also in a derivative

sense as applied to ured on account of their uniqueness and incomprehensibility in a class in which they can be compared with others of their
kind. "Infinite" in this sense is an absolute negation, the denial of a thing of any kind of determination and description, as something not belonging to its nature.

things which are incapable of being meas-

In view of this discussion, we may now explain the meaning of the different kinds of finite and infinite in Spinoza.

and since only like things can be compared, to be finite means to be " If between two things included within a class of like things.
be
finite or limited

To

means

to be comparable,

Narboni's commentary on Moreh Nebukim, Metaphysics y XI, 10, io66a, 35-10666,


i;
cf.

I,

58.

Physics , III, 4, 2O4a, 2-7.

136

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

no relation can be found, there can be no similarity [and hence no comparison] between them, and there is no relation
between two things that have no similarity to each other; as, e.g., we do not say that this heat is similar to that color,
or this voice
is

similar to that sweetness.

You must

that two things of the same kind i.e., whose essential properties are the same, distinguished from each other by
are greatness and smallness, strength and weakness, etc. I similar/' that suffers description necessarily Everything

know

may

therefore be called finite in

its

own

kind, for

it

cannot be

described except in terms that properly belong to it and limit A thing finite is thus something that is similar in some it.
respect to something else of
its

own kind with which

it

may

be compared and be found greater or smaller, longer or

more important or less important. Hence Spinoza's definition: "That thing is called finite in its own kind which can be limited by another thing of the same nature. For exshorter,

ample, a body is called finite, because we always conceive another body which is greater. So a thought is limited by another thought; but a body is not limited by a thought,

nor a thought by a body" (Def.


"Infinite in its

II).

the superlative of comparison, its surpassing of all others of the same degree kind. It does not mean that the thing so described as infinite
is

own kind" means simply

unique and incomparable by possessing an


it

infinite

number

of qualities, nor does

mean

and incomparable. What it qualities upon being compared with others of their kind will be found to surpass them all. Hence Spinoza's statement:

that any of its qualities is unique means is that certain ones of its

"For of whatever

is

infinite

only in

its

own

kind,

we can

deny infinite attributes" (Def. VI, Expl.). But "absolutely infinite" means an absolute exclusion
1

Moreh Nebukim,

I,

56.

PROPS. 7-10, 12-13]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE

137

from the universe of finitude, determination, and description. It implies uniqueness and incomparability; there is no kind
to

which

it

may

be said to belong.
its

It

is

sui generis.

It

is

an

individual essence of

own

kind.

The number

of

its attri-

butes

is infinite,

reason

it

suffers

and so is each of its attributes, and for this no description or determination. Spinoza
to the essence of that

thus says:

"But

which

is

absolutely

infinite pertains

whatever expresses essence and involves no


this

negation" (Def. VI, Expl.). It is as an "absolutely infinite" of

kind that

God

is

described by the mediaevals, a description which denies the existence of any relation between the essence of God and that

of other beings.

"Since the existence of a relation between

God and man,

or between

denied, similarity who like Crescas contended for the existence of essential
attributes likewise denied that there

must

Him and other beings, has been likewise be denied/' r Even those

is any similarity between divine and human attributes, "for they widely differ the one being finite and the other infinite," and "there
. .

can be no relation and comparison between the infinite and the finite." 2 In almost exactly the same words Spinoza says:
is

"This I know, that between the no comparison (proportion em)

finite
;

and the

infinite there

so that the difference be-

tween the greatest and most excellent creature and God is the same as the difference between God and the least creature."
3

The

absolute infinity of God in this sense

is

described

by Maimonides as follows: "Even these negative attributes must not be formed and applied to God, except in the way
which, as you know, sometimes an attribute is negatived in reference to a thing, although that attribute can naturally
in

never be applied to
'

it in

the

same

sense, as, e.g.,

we

say,

Ibid., I, 56.
2

Or Adonai,

I, iii,

3 (pp. rjb-^a).

Epistola 54.

138

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


x

[ETHICS,

Says also Judah ha-Levi: "As regards the negative attributes, such as Living, Only, First
'This wall does not see/"

and Last, they are given


stand them.

to

Him

in

contrasts, but not to establish

them

order to negative their in the sense we underlife

For we cannot understand

except accom-

God, however, is panied by sensibility above them. One cannot, for instance, speak of time as being endowed with life, yet it does not follow that it is
. . .

and movement.

dead, since its nature has nothing to do with either life or death. In the same way one cannot call a stone ignorant,
is

although we may say that it is not learned. Just as a stone too low to be brought into connection with learning or

ignorance, thus the essence of God is too exalted to have " 2 Exactly the same anything to do with life or death.
reasoning, though for a different purpose, Spinoza: "I say then, first, that privation
is

employed by
not the act of
.

is

depriving, but simply and merely a state of want. say, for example, that a blind man is deprived of sight, because we readily imagine him as seeing. This imagination
. .

We

we compare him with others who we compare his present condition with his But when the decree past condition when he did see. of God and His nature are considered, we cannot say of that
comes about
see, or

either because

because

man any more

than of a stone, that he

is

deprived of sight,
less inconsist-

for at that time sight pertains to that


3 ently than to a stone/' Hence the term "infinite" stands

man no

in

as

"

"

"

Spinoza for such terms


"
indeter-

unique,"

incomparable,"

"

homonymous,"
"

ineffable," minate," "incomprehensible," indefinable," "unknowable," and many other similar terms. "Unknow-

able" and "indefinable," however,


1

will

be found
2.

its

most

March Nebukim,
Epistola 21.

I,

58.

Cuzari, II,

PROPS. 7-10, 12-13]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE
It is in

139

convenient equivalents.

accordance with Aristotle's


is

dictum that

"

the infinite so far as infinite

unknown,"

'

which Spinoza himself repeats in connection with his argument that by an infinite number of methods "we can never
arrive

...

at

any knowledge whatever/'

In the three propositions from VIII to


to prove, as

we have already

trying indicated, that substance is


in his defini-

X Spinoza
like

is

everything that
tion.

God

has been laid down to be

absolutely infinite," substance is also "necessarily infinite." Formally the proof of this proposition is based upon
is

"

Proposition VIII begins by showing that

God, who

in Proposition

the identity of essence and existence in substance, as stated VII, and upon the impossibility of two or more

substances having the same nature or attributes, as stated in Proposition V. Materially, however, the proposition rests upon the very definition of substance. For Proposition VII,

we may recall, is based upon the principle that substance has no prior cause, and Proposition V is likewise based upon the principle that substance can have no higher genus, both of
which principles are implied in the definition of substance. So this proposition, too, is derived from the very nature and
definition of substance as

"something which

is in itself

and

is conceived through itself." In fact, Propositions VII, VIII, are all unfoldings of the implications of the definiIX, and

tion of substance.

The next
is

to

show that by

step in the analogy between substance and God infinity in both cases is meant the possesis

sion of infinite attributes. This

IX.

The

proposition as

it

stands

the purpose of Proposition is incomplete. Only the

major premise is given. Its full significance, however, can be brought out by supplying the minor premise and conclusion.
,4,

187^7.
Emcndatione^
13 (Opera, II, p. 13,
11.

'Tractatus de Intellectus

17-23).

140

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

"The more
tributes

reality or being a thing possesses, the more atbelong to it." But substance possesses infinite

reality or being. Hence, to substance belong infinite attri1 butes. In one of his letters to de Vries, as well as in the

Scholium to Proposition X,
tion

IX

is

both of which places Proposireproduced, Spinoza actually adds the needed


in
I

conclusion.

There

is

one incidental comment which

should like to

make here with regard to the source of Proposition IX. It seems to me that this proposition reflects Aristotle's discussion with regard to the character of a true proprium predicated of a subject. If it can be shown, says Aristotle, that A

can also be shown that what is more A is what is more B. To quote him in full: "The confirmer however [must consider], whether what is simply is the property of what is simply; for the more will be
is

a proprium of B,

it

also a proprium of

the property of the more, the less also of the less, the least of the least, and the most of the most; thus, since it is the

property of

fire

naturally to tend upwards,


fire

it

would

also be

the property of what is more naturally to tend more upwards, and in the same manner we must direct attention

from other things also, to all these." 2 That Aristotle speaks of proprium ('idiov) whereas Spinoza here speaks of "attributes" is a matter of indifference. In mediaeval Hebrew literature the term proprium in a similar passage of Aristotle is translated by the word which usually means "attribute." 3
1

Epistola 9 (Opera, IV, p. 45,

11.

2-4 and 20-22).

Topics, V, 8, I3yb, 33~i38a, 3. 3 Cf. Emunah Ramah, II, iv, 3 (p. 65): "These are some of the propositions which are derived from the more (iniYI) and less (ninDHl). Aristotle mentions

them

in the

Book on

Dialectic (fTOJ

rabi as the

Book on Topics (JTIDIpDn

= J-*-), the title of which is translated by Alfa= JjJ-l ^J^; cf. Steinschneider, Al-

Farabi y p. 53, n. 74). The proposition in question is as follows: If a certain thing has a certain attribute ("JNin), and if also the more that thing is the more it has of that attribute, then the attribute belongs to the thing truly by necessity." This

PROPS. 7-10, 12-13]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE

141

Spinoza himself occasionally uses the term "attribute" in the sense of property. Starting therefore with the definition
1

of attribute as "that which the intellect perceives of substance, as if constituting the essence of substance" (Demonst. of Prop.

IX) and assuming

it

to be thus a true proprium

of substance, Spinoza concludes that

"

the

more

reality (reali-

tas) or being (esse) a thing possesses the

more attributes be-

long to it" (Prop. IX). Incidentally it may be remarked that 2 since here as well as in his correspondence Spinoza uses realitas as the equivalent of esse or of entitasj* the term wezentheid (or wezeendhijd),

which
4

Short

'Treatise^ I, 2,

ly, is

translated by esse

(i.e.,

corresponding passage in used in place of realitas , should be being, Sein) rather than essentia (i.e.,
realitas
is

in a

essence, Wesenheii).

Spinoza further uses

as the

equivalent of perfection for which use there Descartes. 6


Proposition

a parallel in

concludes the analogy between substance


is

and God by showing that each attribute of substance


finite in all the

in-

various senses of infinity, "Each attribute of substance must be conceived through itself." To be con-

ceived through

has already been shown, means to "indefinable" and "infinite," it has also be indefinable, and
itself, it

been shown, are interchangeable terms. 7


passage
is

based on Topics, V,

8,

ijyb, 14

ff.,

where the locus of more


the

(juaXXop)
for

and

less (JITTOV) Is discussed.

The Greek term underlying

Hebrew term

"
attri-

bute
1

"
is

proprium

(tSiw).

Cf. below, p. 230.

Epistola 9 (Optra, IV, p. 45,

11.

2-3 and 20).


1.

Ethics, IV, Praef. (Optra, II, p. 207,

27).

Optra,
n. 7.
*
6
7

I, p.

23,

II.

22-24; p. 534.

Cf. above, p. 108, n. 4,

and below,

p. 382,

Ethics, II, Def. 6, et passim.

Medttationes, III (Otuvrts, VII, p. 40,

1.

28).

See above, p. 76.

42

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


IV.

[ETHICS,

RELATION OF ATTRIBUTE TO SUBSTANCE


the

The God or substance of Spinoza, like


rationalists,
is

God of mediaeval

unknowable in His essence.

He may indeed, in

Spinoza's view, be immediately perceived by intuition as a


clear

and

distinct idea, but


its

He

is

not subject to knowledge

terms broader and more general. When Spinoza argues against the mediaeval conception of an unknowable God, 1 he simply argues for the view that God
that defines

object in

can be known, after a manner, even though He cannot be defined in terms of genus and species. "Of His [i.e., God's]
2 general idea." Spinoza indeed will endeavor to prove the existence of God, but in this he will be merely carrying out the mediaeval tra-

essence," says Spinoza,

"we can form no

dition that while we can have no knowledge of God's essence we can prove His existence. "There is no possibility of obthe only taining a knowledge of the essence of God
.

thing that
exists."
3

man

can apprehend of

Him
is

is

the fact that

He

Or again: "If knowledge

sought concerning a

thing whose very existence is in doubt, the first question to be asked is whether it exists or not. When the question of
its

existence has been answered positively, the thing then to


it is,

What is it? How is it? Wherefore is it? Concerning God, however, man has no right to ask except the question as to whether He exists." 4 But while the real nature of God must remain beyond comprehension, still God as a living and dynamic force in
be asked about
the world, conceived as creator, lawgiver, caretaker, guide,

and guardian, makes himself known


1

to

mankind through His

Short 'Treatise ,

I, 7,

ff.
11.

Epistola 50 (Opera, IV, p. 240,

2-3).

Morch Nebukim>
Hobot ha-Lfbabot,

I, 59. I, 4.

PROPS. 7-10, 12-13]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE
assumes

143

and works, and acter and personality. God was determined, in tive terms drawn from
actions

in their eyes a certain char-

This character and personality of

the Middle Ages, by a set of descripthe literature of religious tradition. In the philosophic terminology of the time, these descriptive terms were known by the name of divine attributes.

There were many kinds of attributes which, when taken in their literal sense, would express the various relations that

may

exist

between attribute and subject.

Some

of these

divine attributes would constitute in their ordinary meaning accidental qualities. Others would designate actions. Still

others would only express some external relations. It was, however, generally agreed that attributes could not be taken
in a sense

which would imply plurality

in the divine essence

or a similarity between God and His creatures. 1 It was therefore commonly recognized that attributes are not to be

taken in their literal sense. The Talmudic saying that "the " Torah speaks according to the language of men 2 is quoted in this connection by the mediaeval Jewish philosophers. 3 Spinoza repeats it in his statement that "the Scripture 4 How these continually speaks after the fashion of men."
.
.

attributes could be interpreted so as not to contravene the absolute simplicity and uniqueness of God constituted the problem of divine attributes with which all the mediaeval Jewish

philosophers had to grapple. That attributes could not be taken as accidental qualities was generally admitted.

Whether they should be interpreted as external would seem to be a question upon which opinions
1

relations
differed,
5

See

my

"Crescas on the Problem of Divine Attributes," Jewish Quarterly Re-

view, n.s., Vol. VII, p. 9, n.


2

u.
3

Berakot jib, and parallels.


Epistola 19 (Opera, IV, p. 92,
11.

Moreh Nebukim,

I,

26.
11.

Cuzari, II, 2;

Emunah Ramah,

12-13); Epistola 21 (p. 132, II, iii; Ilobot ha-Lcbabot y I, 10;

34

f.).

Moreh Nebukim,

I,

52 and 58.

144

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


I

[ETHICS,

though,

believe, it

can be shown that the difference was


It was agreed by all, however, be taken in the sense of actions. There

merely

in the use of terms.

that attributes

may

was equally a general agreement that no attribute, in its literal and obvious sense, expresses the real essence of God, inasmuch as the essence of God must forever remain unknowable.

The mediaeval

discussion about attributes

is

sometimes

drawn between the name Jehovah and the other names of God. Says Judah ha-Levi: "All names of God, save the Tetragrammaton, are predicates and
in a distinction

summed up

attributive descriptions, derived from the way His creatures * are affected by His decrees and measures." Says also Mai-

monides: "It

is

well

known

that

all

the

names of God

oc-

from His actions, except the Tetragrammaton, which consists of the one, namely, 2 letters yod^ he waw> he. This name is the nomen proprium
curring in Scripture are derived
y

of
is

God and

is

to say, the

on that account called Shew ha-Meforash that name which indicates the essence of God in a
y

the implication of its having anything in common with the essence of other beings. All the other glorious names are common appellatives, 3 inasmuch as
similar/'

manner which excludes

they are derived from actions to which some of our own are 4 In connection with these divine names Judah

ha-Levi quotes Exodus 6, 3, where God says to Moses: "And I appeared unto Abraham, unto Isaac, and unto Jacob, by the name of God Almighty (El Shaddai\ but by my name

Jehovah was
in

not known to them."

In Spinoza we find this view of the mediaevals restated almost their own words. Quoting the same verse from
1

Cuzari, II, a.

1ITPO DP.

3
5

fpnBQ
Cuzari y

omo.
II, 2.

March Nebukim,

I,

61.

PROPS. 7-10, 12-13]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE

145

6, 3, he comments upon it as follows: "We must note that in Scripture no other name but Jehovah is ever found which indicates the absolute essence of God,

Exodus

without reference
that the other
in truth, the

to created things.
is

for this reason, that this

the only

The Jews maintain, nomen propriitm of God;

names are mere appellatives (cippellativa); and, other names of God, whether they be substanis

tives or adjectives, are


in so far as

or
as

is

mere attributes, which belong to God conceived of in relation to created things manifested through them." He then concludes: "Now,

He

tells Moses that He was not known to the patriarchs the name of Jehovah, it follows that they were not cogniby zant of any attribute of God which expresses His absolute

God

essence, but only of His deeds and promises 2 power, as manifested in visible things."

that

is,

of His

Now, Spinoza

has adopted the traditional term "attribute," and makes use of it as a description of the manner in which substance,

unknowable

in itself,

manifests itself to the

human mind.

But how would Spinoza characterize his attributes if he were to classify them according to the mediaeval fashion? They
are not accidents, nor relations, nor actions.
ever, what, as

They

are,

how-

we

shall presently see, the


is

mediaevals called

essential attributes, that


stitute the essence.
1

to say, attributes

which conI

He

thus says:

"By

attribute,

under-

In his

comment on

the divine

name El Shaddai which

occurs in this verse,

Spinoza remarks that "El Shaddai, in Hebrew, signifies the God who suffices, in " that He gives to every man that which suffices for him (Opera, III, p. 169, 11. 3-5).

Judah ha-Levi, in the corresponding passage quoted in the preceding paragraph, explains El Shaddai as meaning "power and dominion." Spinoza's explanation, however, is found in Rashi's commentary on the Bible (cf. Genesis 17, i; 28, 3; 35, 1 1). Maimonides, though he like Rashi derives El Shaddai from a word meaning "sufficient," explains it to mean that "His existence is self-sufficient" (Moreh Nebukim^ I, 63). These two etymologies of El Shaddai go back to still earlier
sources.
a

fracfatus fhcologico-PohticuSy Ch. 13 (Opera, III, p. 169,

11.

7-24).

146

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

stand that which the intellect perceives of substance, as constituting its essence" (Ethics, I, Def. IV).

if

But here we
too,

are

met with

a difficulty, a natural difficulty,

which has divided Spinoza scholars into two camps. The definition may have two meanings, depending upon
its

which of
"

elements

is

emphasized.
is

If the

expression
it

which the

intellect perceives"

laid stress

upon,

would

seem that attributes are only


thus be only a subjective

in intellectu.

Attributes would

of thinking, expressing a relation to a perceiving subject and having no real existence in the essence. On the other hand, if only the latter part of the
definition is taken notice of, namely, "constituting the essence of a substance," it would seem that the attributes are extra intellectum^ real elements out of which the essence of the

mode

substance
be sure,
there
is it

is

is

composed. According to both interpretations, to the mind which perceives the attributes, but
According to the former
to be in-

the following difference.

interpretation, to be perceived
vented

by the mind means

by

the mind, for of themselves the attributes have

no

independent existence at all but are identical with the essence of the substance. According to the latter interpretation, to
be perceived by the mind means only to be discovered by the mind, for even of themselves the attributes have independent
existence in the essence of the substance.
1

been adduced by scholars

In the discussion of the subject two kinds of evidence have in support of their respective inand material. It is not my purpose terpretations: literary

here, however, to assemble

and

assess

what has been

said

by either side in support of its own view and in objection to the other. On the whole, the abundance of both literary and
material evidence
is in is

This interpretation
1

in

favor of the subjective interpretation. harmony both with the variety of


Gcschichte der Philosophic
',

Cf.

Erdmann, Grundriss der

II,

272.6.

PROPS. 7-10, 12-13]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE
attributes

147

statements

made by Spinoza about

and with the

place which the attributes occupy in his system. Of the latter we shall have occasion to speak in other chapters. The

main objection
in the

to this interpretation has

been

summed up
l

statement that "no prae-Kantian reader would have We shall such a construction on Spinoza's language/' put therefore address ourselves to this particular objection and

try to show that this very controversy between the upholders of the subjective and the objective interpretations of Spinoza's attributes is the question upon which mediaeval Jewish philosophers were divided in their theories of divine
attributes, and also to point to certain facts which indicate that

Spinoza has consciously and advisedly aligned himself with


that group of Jewish philosophers theory of attributes.

who

held a subjective

The gravamen of the mediaeval discussion of divine attributes is what is known as the problem of essential attributes. By essential attributes are meant those elements which constitute the essence of a subject, or

which are related to the

essence of the subject as the genus and species are related to the essence of the object defined. It appears primarily as a problem in the exegesis of those adjectives which in the Bible
or in the other traditional literature are ascribed to God.

Admitting, as we have already pointed out, that attributes are not to be taken literally, that they cannot be interpreted
as accidental qualities but

may

be interpreted as actions, the

mediaevals raised the question as to whether any of these adjectives may be taken as being related to God in the same
sense as the elements of a definition to the object defined, that is to say, as if constituting the divine essence. The prob-

lem, it must be remarked, was not whether the divine essence could be conceived as consisting of a genus and species. The
1

Martineau,

Study of Spinoza

p. 184.

Cf.

Krdmann, he.

cit.

148

absolute

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA [ETHICS, simplicity of God is a principle established beyond


i

any question, a simplicity which is to exclude metaphysical and logical plurality no less than physical composition. It is thus generally admitted that God is not a species and can have no genus. The question was merely as to whether the
1

assumption of essential attributes contravened that simplicity of essence.

To put the question more bluntly: Assuming that the relation of God's attributes to His essence is analo-

gous to that of the parts of a definition, genus and species, to the essence of the object defined, does that mean that the
essence
is simple or not? Those who reject essential attributes answer it in the negative; those who admit them anit

swer

in the positive.

The

basis of the problem,

it

seems to me,

is

to be found in

the question as to the nature of the reality of genus and species, or, in other words, of universals. If universals have

genus and species have some kind of real existence, and a subject to which are attributed terms related to it after the analogy of genus and species cannot be
reality, then

some kind of

said to be absolutely simple. On the other hand, if universals have no reality at all, then genus and species are mere

names, and definitions are purely nominal, and the essence


is in reality simple. The problem of thus a problem of universals, the controversy between realism and nominalism. It is, however, not a conflict between Platonism and Aristotelianism. Pla-

of the subject defined


is

essential attributes

tonic realism

had no

followers

among

the classical Jewish

philosophers.

It is as Aristotelians,

and as interpreters of
which are hid away
in

Aristotle's view, that Jewish philosophers latently formulated

their respective theories of universals their discussions of divine attributes.

universals,
,

it

may
6 and
7.

problem of be said, began with the rejection of Plareal


Cf. Short 'Treatise,
I,

For the

II,

7,

3.

PROPS. 7-10, 12-13]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE
speculation became
those
1

149

tonic realism,

when

universals which were

As spokesman of

now who

concerning those said to exist only in the mind.


rife

reject essential attributes

we

may

While essential attributes, says take Maimonides. Maimonides, denote the essence of the object and do not

imply anything extraneous superadded to

it, still they are to be rejected, for they imply that the essence itself is composed, as it were, of genus and species, which as universal terms are

considered as previous causes to the existence of the individual essence. 2 It is here that the theory of universals comes
into play. Like all Arabic and Jewish philosophers, Maimonides rejects Platonic realism, affirming that "species have no existence except in our own mind." 3 Still this assertion

makes him neither a nominalist nor a conceptualist. Nominalism must be rejected as inconsistent with the entire trend of his argument, for if universals were mere words, definitions would be purely nominal, and Maimonides could not reject essential attributes on the ground that "there are no
previous causes to His existence, by which He could be defined/* and quote with approval those who maintain that

God." 4 Conceptualism, or the theory that universals have ideal without real existence, is explicitly rejected by Maimonides in his repudia" tion of the assertion of some thinkers, that ideas, i.e., the
definition can be given of

"no

universals, are neither existent nor non-existent."

Maimonides, as follower of Avicenna and


all his

in

What common with


s

contemporaries, conceived of universals is that they have both ideal and real existence. Universals, to be sure,

exist in the
1

mind, but the human mind does not invent them

The historical survey which follows is based upon my essay "Crescas on the Problem of Divine Attributes/' Jewish Quarterly AV:7>:r, n.s., Vol. VII (1916), pp.
1-44, 175' 221
* *
-

Morfh Nfbukim,
Ibid., Ill, 18.

I, 51 "

and

52.

Ibid., I, 52.

Ibid., I, 51.

150

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


What
the

[ETHICS,

out of nothing.
in

mind does

is

the multifarious individuals. For prior

only to discover them to the rise of in-

dividual beings the universals exist in the


entities,

mind of God

as

and they remain as such even when independent enter upon plurality in material form, though their they presence in the individuals is not discernible except by mental
activity.

lated to the subject as genus

Consequently essential attributes, which are reand species are related to the

object defined, must necessarily imply some kind of plurality in the essence of the subject. This plurality, to be sure, would be only mentally discernible, but still it would be inconsistent with the conception of absolute simplicity. As against this view there are those who maintain that
essential attributes are admissible.

They

insist that uni-

versals have no reality at all; their existence in the mind means that they are invented by the mind. Genus and

species are thus only generalizations, and definitions consisting of genus and species are only nominal. Averroes, whose

view
this

quoted in Hebrew literature, is clearly outspoken on point. "It is of the nature of essential attributes that
is

they do not introduce any plurality into the subject which


supports them actually. If they do import into them some kind of plurality, it is only in the same sense that the parts of a definition

may

be said to import some kind of plurality

into the object defined, and that is what is called by philosophers an intellectual plurality in contradistinction to an actual
l

plurality/'

No

less

outspoken

is

Moses ha-Lavi

in his ad-

mission of essential attributes.

"Some

attributes," he says,
as,

"are identical with the essence of the object described,


for instance,
. . .

when we

describe

man by

the attribute 'animal.'

With

reference to such attributes as are identical with


p. 300,
11.

Averroes, ^ahajut a/-Tahafut, V (ed. M. Bouyges, phrased also by Narboni on Moreh Nebukim> I, 58.
1

12-15); para-

PROPS. 7-10, 12-13]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE

151

the essence of the object described, it is evident that God can be described by them, inasmuch as they do not imply

any addition
again
is

The implication here that essential attributes, related to God after the
to the essence at all."
z

analogy of the genus animal to man, are purely subjective terms, in reality being absolutely identical with the essence of

argument against Maimonof attributes, justifies his own negative interpretation positive interpretation by pointing to their subjective charGod. Likewise Gersonides,
in his
ides'

acter.

a distinction between two kinds of propositions, one in which the relation of subject and predicate is

He draws

that of discourse, the other in which


a distinction reminiscent of that

it is

that of existence
Aristotle

made by

between

nominal and real


lated to

definitions. 3

Divine attributes are thus to

him purely subjective and nominal predications of God, reHim only in discourse, and implying no plurality in His essence, and may therefore be taken as positive terms. It can also be shown that Crescas* insistence upon the admissibility of positive essential attributes
is

based upon the

view that attributes are purely subjective terms. The eclectic Albo, vacillating between the positive and negative interpreof attributes by calling them intellectual conceptions" 4 of " divine perfection. When I awaken from my reflections upon
the plurality of attributes I begin to realize that all the attributes are nothing but intellectual conceptions of those perfections which must needs exist in Thy essence but which in
reality are nothing but

tations of attributes, endeavors to justify the positive form "

Thy

essence."

In view of this controversy over essential attributes in the


Md'amar
Elohi.
III, 3:
y

Milhamot Adonai,

DIN'SDH
pjb, 29

Analytica Postfriora

II, 10,

ff.

nv^iw mrna.
'Jkkarim, II, 25.

152

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

philosophic literature with which Spinoza had an intimate acquaintance, and in view of this insistence upon the subjective nature of essential attributes on the part of many of his Jewish predecessors, it is not unreasonable to assume that
it is

not as a mere turn of speech that Spinoza always refers

to
it,

attribute in subjective terms, as when he describes for instance, as that which the intellect perceives (perl

cipif)

concerning the substance, or as that which expresses 2 3 (exprimii) or explains (explicat) the essence of substance,

or as that under which


is

God

is

considered (consideratur)

or

conceived (concipi)^ or as that which is the every entity same as substance but is called attribute with respect to the
intellect (respectu intellectus}? There is, furthermore, evidence that Spinoza was acquainted with the moderately realistic Avicennian and Maimonidean theory of universals

and that he disagreed with


set

it

and
. . .

up general

ideas," he says,

criticized "

it.

"They have

These

ideas, they state,

have

are in the understanding of God, as many of Plato's followers said, namely, that these general ideas (such as rational,

animal, and the like) have been created by God; and although those who follow Aristotle say, indeed, that these
things are not real things, only things of reason, they never-

The theless regard them frequently as [real] things/' reference in this passage to the objective interpretation of Aristotle's universals is clear. He finds it to differ only little
7

from Platonic realism.

It

would seem that Spinoza himself

considered universals, with the exception of only one uni1

Ethics,
2

I,

Def. 4.

Ibid.) I, Prop. 10, Schol.; Prop. 32,

Demonst.
1.

Tractatus Theologico-Politicus, Ch. 13 (Opera, III, p. 169,

23).
11.

Ethics, II, Prop. 6; Prop. 7, Schol.; Epistola 64 (Opera, IV, p. 277,

23-24

and 28-29).
5
6
7

Ethics,

I,

Prop. 10, Schol.;

cf.
1.

Epistola 9 (Opera, IV, p. 45,


4).

1.

2).

Epistola 9 (Optra, IV, p. 46, Short Treatise, I, 6, 7.

PROPS. 7-10, 12-13]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE
1

153

versal, namely, substance, as purely subjective concepts; and what is true of universals is also true of attributes. It is thus

not in vain that in his formal definition of attribute Spinoza 2 says that he understands by it "that which the intellect
perceives of substance, as if constituting its esssence," instead of merely saying, as does Descartes, that attributes
constitute

Elsewhere, too, in the Ethics as well as in his other writings attributes are always spoken of in terms which suggest their subjective
character. 4

the essence of substance. 3

In one place he says explicitly that attributes are distinguished only by reason. 5 This subjective interpretation of attributes disposes of
the difficulty which
is

raised

tive interpretation.

"How

by those who follow the objecthat essence can be one and

self-identical, while its constituents are

many, heterogeneous
6

and unrelated,
1

is

a question which

is

hopeless of solution/'

Cf. below, pp. 327-328.

By

the term "intellect" in this definition Spinoza

means

the finite

human

in-

Prop. VII, Schol., that "we have already demonstrated, that everything which can be perceived by the infinite intellect as constituting the essence of substance pertains entirely to one substance, and consetellect.

When

he says in Ethics

II,

quently that substance thinking and substance extended are one and the same substance, which is now comprehended under this attribute and now under that," it
is

not to be inferred that an attribute of substance

is

that which can be conceived

only by the "infinite intellect." What the passage means to say is that "everything which can be conceived of by the infinite intellect as constituting the essence of sub-

and the infinite intellect can conceive of an infinite number of things as stance" is only an attribute of substance and not a constituting the essence of substance substance itself, and consequently extension and thought, which alone can be conceived by the finite human intellect as constituting the essence of substance, are only attributes of substance and not substances themselves. J Principia Philosophiae, I, 53: "Substantiae praecipua proprietas [= attributum], quac ipsius naturam cssetiamque constituit"; Notae in Programma
((EitvreSy

VIII,

2, p.

349,

11.

naturamque
II,
4

constituit."

1-2): Attributum, quod ejus [substantiae] essentiam See Erdmann, Grundriss dcr Geschichte der Philosophic^

"

272,6.

See references above, p. 152.

Cf. Busolt, Die Gi undzuge der Erkenntnisztheorie


s

und Metaphysik Spinozns, pp. 107-111.


6

Cogitata Metaphysica,

I, 3.

Martineau,

A Study

of Spinoza, p. 185.

154

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

The

question had already been raised by Simon de Vries in a letter to Spinoza: "If I may say that each substance has

only one attribute and if I had the idea of two attributes, then I could rightly conclude that where there are two different attributes there are also

two

different substances/'

Spinoza's answer is like that given in Jewish literature by those who admitted essential attributes, namely, that attributes are merely different sence.

"You

desire,

though there

words expressing the same esis no need, that I should

by an example, how one and the same thing can be stamped with two names. In order not to seem miserly, I 2 That essential attributes, as suggested will give you two/' in this quotation, are only names by which the essence is
illustrate

denoted

is

the view held by both those

who admit

the use of

positive attributes and those who reject it. Even Maimonides speaks of essential attributes as being merely "the 3 If he does reject their positive use, explanation of a name/'

only because he endows essential attributes with some kind of objective reality. Were they all names only and
it is

Maimonides would permit their positive use. Albo well restates Maimonides' view in the following passage: "You must know that God cannot be described by two things which would constitute His essence after the He can, analogy of animality and rationality in Man.
nothing
else,
. .

however, be described by any attribute which explanation of the name by which He is called."

is
4

only the

In the mediaeval enH^avor to reconcile the apparent contradiction between the plurality of attributes and the simplicity of essence an attempt is often made to reduce all the
different attributes to one.
1

It

is

shown that the variety of

Epistola 8 (Opera, IV, p. 41,

11. 11.

10-13).
7-9). Cf. below, pp. 229-230.

a
*

Epistola 9 (Opera, IV, p. 46,

Moreh Nebukim,
'Ibfcarim, II, 9.

I,

51

and

'

52.

PROPS. 7-10, 12-13]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE
different they

155
us, are in

attributes,

however

may

appear to

reality one, for they are all involved in our conception of God,

they are conceived by us simultaneously, and they are always


together in God. "These three attributes [life, power, wisdom] are conceived by our mind immediately and simultaneously without the aid of intermediate reasoning, for conceiving God as we do in the nature of a creator we at once think of Him as living, powerful, and wise. But though these three attributes occur to our mind at once, it is impossible
.

for our

tongue to utter them at once, for we do not find

in

human

speech a single word comprehending all the three attributes and we are compelled to resort to the use of three
1

words/'

Again:

ascribed to God,

therefore say that the attributes though different from each other when
all

"We

used with reference to us, are

erence to ourselves, inasmuch as

one in Him. For with refwe conceive them or acquire

them one after the other, we consider them as being different from each other; similarly, inasmuch as we acquire them after we have been without them, we naturally consider
superadded to the essence. With reference to God, however, we must consider them as unified and unacquired in such a manner as not to imply any plurality in His es-

them

as

sence."'

It

is

the

same reasoning that underlies the

follow-

ing passage of Spinoza: "From this it is apparent that although two attributes may be conceived as really distinct

that

is

to say,

one without the assistance of the other

we

cannot nevertheless thence conclude that they constitute two things or two different substances; for this is the nature
of substance, that each of
itself,

its

attributes

is

conceived through

since

all

the attributes which substance possesses were

always
1

in it together,
we-De'ot, II, 4.
,

nor could one be produced by another;

Emunot

II, 21.

156

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


Schol.).

[ETHICS,

but each expresses the reality or being of substance" (Prop.

X,

The two

The implications of this passage are these: attributes appear to the mind as being distinct
reality,

from each other. In


Proposition X,

however, they are one. For by

attributes, like substance, are

summa

genera

("conceived through itself"). The two attributes must therefore be one and identical with substance. Furthermore,
after

the two attributes have not been acquired by substance it had been without them, nor are they conceived by the mind one after the other or deduced one from the other.

They have always been in substance together, and are conceived by our mind simultaneously. Hence, the attributes
are only different words expressing the being of substance.

same

reality

and

Proposition XII is complementary to the definitions of substance and attribute. While the definition of attribute
states affirmatively the subjective nature of attributes by declaring that they are only perceived by the mind, the pro-

position denies any independent reality to attributes by which the simplicity of the substance would be endangered.

"No
which

attribute of substance can be truly conceived from it follows that substance can be divided." The conis

clusion

then reached in Proposition XIII, namely, that "substance absolutely infinite is indivisible."

Spinoza's demonstrations for both these propositions are practically the same. In both cases he begins with the same
hypothetico-disjunctive proposition and proceeds to show in an identical manner that substance, because it is absolutely infinite,

cannot be divided.

It will

be recalled that

Spinoza's "absolutely infinite" has been shown to correspond to what the mediaevals called "essentially infinite."
It is singularly worthy of notice that Spinoza's argument here against the divisibility of an absolutely infinite substance is

PROPS. 7-10, 12-13]

SIMPLICITY OF SUBSTANCE

157

argument against the divisibility of an essentially infinite substance.


the

same

as the mediaeval

Spinoza's argument runs as follows: I. If an absolutely infinite substance were divisible, the parts would either retain the nature of the whole or not.
II.

If the parts retained the nature of the whole, there


infinite substances,

would then be many


III.

which

is

absurd.

If they did not retain the nature of the whole, then

the whole would lose the nature of substance and cease to be.

against the divisibility of an essentially infinite substance, as given by Averroes, runs in a similar vein:
I.

The mediaeval argument

If an essentially infinite substance were divisible, the

parts would either have the same nature as the whole or not. II. If the parts had the same nature as the whole, then the parts of an infinite would be infinite, which is absurd.
III. If they did not have the same nature as the whole, then the whole would consist of heterogeneous parts and would thus lose its homogeneous and simple character.
1

The

fined to those phases of the problem

discussion of attributes in this chapter has been conwhich the exigencies

of the interpretation of Propositions VII -X and XII -XIII required. Other phases of the problem will be discussed in
the chapter on Extension and Thought.
r

See Averroes' Middle Commentaries on Physics, III,


1

5,

2O4a, 20-32, and Meta-

physics, XI, 10, io66b,


(dj

1-21.

Cf.

my

Crescas* Critique of Aristotle, p. 137,

and note

on pp. 331-332.

CHAPTER

VI

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD


I.

THE ONTOLOGICAL PROOF

THE

first ten propositions of the Ethics^ which precede Spinoza's proofs of the existence of God, are a challenge to mediaeval philosophers. The starting point is the definition

of God, placed by Spinoza near the beginning of his work, which, as we have already shown, is an exact reproduction

of a definition found in a standard work of a popular mediaeval Jewish philosopher. 1 Spinoza seems to address his imaginary opponents as follows:

you mediaevals, to whatever school of thought you may belong, have builded your philosophies on the conception of a God epitomized by you in a formal definition which
All

contains four characteristic expressions. You say that God is (i) an ens in the highest sense of the term, by which you mean that He is a being who exists necessarily. You also say

that

He
is

is (2)

He
(4)

(3)

"a substance

"absolutely infinite," by which you mean that consisting of infinite attributes,"

"each of which expresses eternal and infinite essence" (Def. VI). God so defined you call absolute substance^ you differentiate Him from the world which you call conditionaj^
substance, and then you declare that the relation between the ^ absolute and the conditional substance is like that of
to you, I deny at the very createdTjIn opposition outset the existence of a God outside the world and of His

creator to

relation to the world as creator.


1

Still,

unaccustomed as

am

'Iklfarim, II, 25.

Cf. above, p. 118.

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

159

1 to dispute about mere names, I shall retain your own term substance as a philosophic surrogate to the pious name God,

and

in

your own terms

of the nature of

I am going to unfold a new conception God and of His relation to the world.

To begin with, I shall abandon your distinction between absolute substance and conditional substance, but shall use
the term WEstance in that restrictive sense in which you use the expression absolute substance. Then, what you call
conditional substance, or the world,
I

shall call

mode. Fur-

thermore, unlike you, I shall not describe the relation of substance to mode as that of creator to created, but rather as
that of whole to part, or, to be
to particular (Defs. II

The reason

for

my

more exact, as that of universal and V; Axioms I and II; Prop. I). 2 disagreeing with you on the question of the

causal relation between

God and

the world

is

that

I find

your

doctrine of creation, however you

may

untenable hypothesis (Props. II-VI). 3 between us, a difference which, I must confess, is fundamental and far-reaching in its effect, I am going to describe

try to explain it, an Barring this difference

my

substance in

all

those terms which you

make

use of in

describing your God. Like your God, my substance is (i) the highest kind of ens, for existence appertains to its nature
(Prop. VII).
(3)

(2) It is also absolutely infinite (Prop. VIII).

(4) Finally,

Furthermore, it consists of infinite attributes (Prop. IX). each of its attributes expresses eternal and inX). 4 I have thus described my substance terms which you use in your formal definition of
I

finite essence (Prop. in all those

God. Consequently, as
the existence of
I

am now

to reproduce

your proofs of

God

to prove the existence of

shall bracket together the


1

terms

God and

my substance, substance and


n. 3.

* <

Cf. Cogitata Mctaphysica, Cf. above, Chapter III.

I,

3,

quoted below. Cf. below, p. 190, Cf. above, Chapter IV.

Cf. above, Chapter V.

160

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

say: "God, or substance consisting of infinite attributes, each of which expresses eternal and infinite essence, necessarily
exists" (Prop. XI). Having made it clear by this time what I mean by the term God, I am no longer afraid of being mis-

understood.
use in
its

Hereafter

shall

stead the term God.

drop the term substance and And so he does.

expression necessario existit y which Spinoza uses in the eleventh proposition, is to be understood to have two

The

meanings.

In the

first

place,

it

means that

it

can be shown

apodictically, by necessary, logical reasoning, that God must exist. In the second place, it means that the existence which
is

proved of God belongs to that class known as necessary existence as opposed to possible existence. In a passage in the Cogitata Metaphysica^ I, i, Spinoza points out the distinction

between these two classes of existence: "From the


or, if

defi-

description, it is now easily seen that Being should be divided into Being which because of its own nature necessarily exists, or Being

nition of Being,

you

prefer,

from

its

whose essence involves existence, and Being whose essence


involves only possible existence." In the course of our subsequent discussion of the proofs, especially of the second
proof, it will become clear that the purpose of this proposition is to state not only that God exists but also that His
as necessary existence. This double purpose of the proofs of the existence of God is clearly

existence

is

of the kind

known

brought out by Spinoza in his Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae^ I, Proposition V, Demonstration: "The concept of God includes necessary existence. Therefore it is true to say
'

Definition (6pio>i6s,

-*>-,

TT3)

is

to be distinguished

from description (viroypa^y


Spinoza's hesitancy as to

j,

QCn). Cf. Maimonides, Millot ha-Higgayon, Ch.

10.

whether Being (ens) has a definition or only a description reflects the question raised by Hillel of Verona in his Commentary on Maimonides' Twenty-five Propositions (Prop. 25) as to whether substance has a definition in view of the fact that it is a

summum genus.

Cf.

my

Crescas' Critique of Aristotle , p. 575.

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

161

that He has a necessary existence in himself, or that He exists." Similarly Crescas in conclusion of his summary of Maimonides' proofs of the existence of

God seems

to emphasize that

the proofs demonstrate not only that God exists but that exists with an existence which is necessary per se.
1

He

what what he is trying to establish thereby. Spinoza himself would have said that he was trying to determine by these proofs or rather the what kind of being (ens) God is. For being
he
ideas

It will be well for us to state in Spinoza's own terms is driving at in his proofs of the existence of God and

according to Spinoza, of fourjdnds ^classification which seems to be derived from a Hebrew


is,

we have of being

source.

Some

ideas are reaJ,

and these are ideas which have

an extra-mental object as their source; others are unreal^

mere figments of the imagiof things perceived and experination, composite pictures enced; others are rational, mere modes of thought, such as the universals known as genera and species; and still others
fictitious,

and of these some are

nor

are merely verjxil, because they exist neither in the intellect in the imagination, such as chimeras and ideas conveyed " 2 by expressions like a square circle." None of these unreal

ideas are ideas of things, for they have


1

no

real object as their

Or Adonai)

I, i,

32.
I, I. is

Cogitata Metaphysica,

The

source of this classification


5.

to be found in the

Hebrew

Rutih Hen, Ch. of being:


1.

According to the Ruah lien, there

is

philosophic manual the following classification

Real beings, D"fiDN D'TJl, which exist outside the mind and of which we

can form an idea either in the mind or in the imagination. 2. Unreal beings, D"J"1DN QrNlP D'TUT, which exist neither in the mind nor outside the mind. They are fictitious 1'DNDH ]VD"O niN'XD WHH py

beings, having existence only in the imagination,


1

GHP N^N. Previous

to this in the

same chapter
is

they are also called "verbal beings," vided into two parts:
a.

"Q^

"1131 p")

DP

]'WP. This class

subdi-

Factitious beings which have no existence in reality, 02'KIP

D'TDH

"V'2T1

^3
b.

D'NXDJ.
Factitious beings which not only have no existence in reality but whose nature

62

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

source, nor have they a counterpart outside the mind. Extramental existences only are real, and ideas in the mind are
real only in so far as they represent those extra-mental existences.

Spinoza, therefore, is trying to establish by his proofs of the existence of God is that God is not a fictitious being, nor a verbal being, nor a being of reason, but a real
being,

What

who has

existence outside our

mind and who


1

is

the

source and counterpart of the idea we have of Him. Substance, says Spinoza, is outside the intellect, that is to say,

not fabricated by the intellect. Only that conception of God, says he again, is a fiction which uses the name of God
it is

not

harmony with His real nature; the true conception of " God is that of a body in nature whose idea is necessary in
in
is

order to represent God immediately/' 3 In order to determine whether an idea

real or not

one

has to ascertain by means of the various approved sources of knowledge whether or not it has an extra-mental object
involves a contradiction, as the words

ynnD hbn HD-PP


Dvran

"a square circle" QHain Jlion "V2T IN IDD ,anron "j>na D'tccon. 3. Beings of reason, which exist only in the mind but have no existence outside BH the mind, as genera and species, niN'XD OH ? | ^DBQ D'NSD3P D3
1

D^DH

"iwzn

DTDH am
this

p
is

onm

The resemblance between


(1)

}yyth pin psyn ^D. classification and that of Spinoza

striking.

The

only differences to be noted are as follows:

The

classification in

Ruah Hen
it

both 2a and 2b. Spinoza applies


to 2b.
(2)

applies the expression "verbal being" to only to what in his classification corresponds

This classification considers the expression "a square circle" as something in the imagination. Spinoza says of a chimera, which to him is the equivalent of a "square circle," that it is neither in the intellect nor in the imagination

which

is

(sec Cog. Ato.,1,3).

Freudenthal is thus not quite right in saying that the distinction ofensjictum, ens chimerae, ens rationis and ens reale does not occur in Jewish philosophy. Cf.

"Spinoza und die Scholastik"


gewidmet,
1

in

Philosophische Aufsatze,

Eduard

Zeller

p. 103.

2
3

Cf. EthifSy I, Prop. 4, Demonst. Tractates de Intellect us Emendatione,

Short Treatise , Second Dialogue,

54 (Opera , III, p. 20, note 12 (Opera, I, p. 34, 11. 15-17).

t).

PROP,

u]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

163

to correspond to it. Again and again Spinoza classifies the sources of knowledge. Not all of his classifications are of

the same type; they are, however, all made up of various mediaeval classifications with some slight modifications of his own, as we hope to show in another chapter. Roughly
1

speaking, Spinoza maintains, clearly so in the Short freafise, II, i, that we may know things either directly or indirectly. Direct knowledge may be either sense perception in its many

forms and derivations, or intuition, the latter of which


Spinoza as
"
clear
distinct

is

comprehendesignated by jmd 2 3 4 or a persion/^ "clear cognition/'. "intuitive science/' \wherein a thing is perceived through its essence ception 5 alone/' that is to say, "intuitively, without any process of
6 Indirect knowledge consists of the inference of working.'^ the unknown from the known, which is described by Spinoza

"art of reasoning," 8 or that mode of perception-" wherein the essence of one thing is concluded from the essence of another." 9
as "true belief/'
7

Now, according
knowledge
idea
is

to Spinoza,

any one of these sources of


any

sufficiently valid to establish the reality of

we happen

to have.

Intuition

and

logical inference are

as valid proofs for the reality of ideas as direct sense perception; to Spinoza, in fact, they are more valid, for sense per-

ception and imagination alone


'

may

lead to falsity. 10

Still, in

Cf. below, Vol. II,

Chapter XVI.
I,

3
3

klaarc en onderscheide bevatting. Short Treatise, II, klaare Kennisse. Op. cit., II, 2, i.
scientia intuitiva.

2.

< 5

Ethics, II, Prop. 40, Schol. 2.

ubi res percipitur per so/am 19 (Opera, II, p. 10,


1.

suam

essentiam.

Tractatus de Intellectus

Emen11.

datione,
6

20).
Ibid.,

sed intuitive, nullam operationemfacientes.

^(Opera,

II, p. 12,

13-

4).
1

waar gelooj. Short


ratio.

Treatise, II, I,

2.

Ethics, II, Prop. 40, Schol. 2.

ubi essentia rei ex alia re concluditur.


1.

Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione,


10

19 (Opera, II, p. 10,

16).

Ethics, II, Prop. 41.

164

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

the proof of the existence of God in the history of philosophy, not all of these sources of knowledge were of use. Direct
sense perception had to be eliminated, for, in the words of Scripture, if a proof-text is necessary, "Man shall not see me and live" (Exodus 33, 20). In fact, Spinoza explicitly
states that this verse should be taken in its literal sense as

an answer to Moses' request that


to

God

should show himself


it

him

in

some perceptible form, which,


1

may be remarked

incidentally, is an oblique criticism of Maimonides' interpretation of the verse as meaning that God's essence cannot be

comprehended by the human intellect in denial of Moses' request that God should become known to him in His true
essence.
2

Historically, therefore, the proofs of the existence


to fall

of
is

God had

back upon the kind of knowledge which


is,

either direct like Spinoza's intuition, or indirect, that


logical reasoning.

by way of

In the history of religious philosophy both these methods of proving the existence of God, the direct and the indirect, were made use of. When theologians, for instance, appeal
to revelation as a proof of the existence of

God, either

to

an

act of historical revelation in the past or to the constantly

repeated revelations in the religious experience of chosen or gifted individuals, they make the knowledge of God something direct and immediately perceived. Similarly when Cicero 3 and, following him, others maintain that the idea of God isjnnate in mam, they also make it an object of

immediate apprehension. Likewise the argument from consensus gentium rests, in its ultimate analysis, on the assumption that God is an object of immediate knowledge. 4 But,
1

Tractatus Theologico-Politicus^ Ch. 2 (Opera, III, p. 40,

11.

12

ff.).

a
3

Moreh Nebukim,
Ibid.

I,

64,

and

I, 4.

De Natura Deorum,

I, 17,

44~45; H, 4,

11.

PROP. TI]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

165

on the other hand, the cosmological argument and the argument from design proceed on the assumption that God cannot be immediately known; He can become known only
art of reasoning. ^To Spinoza, however, be an object of direct knowledge, for God, acnoted, Qod cording to him, is known to us as an in tuition, "as a clear and

indirectly
it

by the
is

distinct idea,

which

is

adequate and

true.

"That

existence

belongs

to

the essence of God," says

Spinoza,

"we can

clearly and distinctly understand" (Short Treatise, I, I, i); "The knowledge of the eternal and infinite essence of God which each idea involves is adequate and perfect "\(Ethics,
II,

Prop.

XLVI); and "By adequate


it is

idea, I

understand an
without
refer-

idea which, in so far as

considered in

itself,

ence to the object, has all the properties or internal signs of a true idea" (Ethics , II, Def. IV). To Spinoza, therefore, the

God, that is to say, the existence of immediate fact of knowledge^ for God, we can have a knowledge of God which is " as~cTear as that
reality of the idea of
is

self-evident as an

with which we also know our body."

But here
is

a difficulty arises. To say that God's existence immediately perceived as an intuition and to declare in-

tuition as a valid source of knowledge, which establishes the reality of the intuited idea, is to start out with a major

premise which would seem to require no further demonstration, and to which no further demonstration could add anything, least of all a demonstration in the Aristotelian sense.

For a demonstration, according to Aristotle, is a syllogism which produces science" 2 and the science it produces in the conclusion must be something not known directly from
the major premise.
in the
1

"

It

has indeed been asked whether even

deductive syllogism of Aristotle the conclusion ever


14 (Opera,
I, 2,
I, p.

Short Treatise, II, 19,

93,

11.

20-22).

Analytic a Posteriora,

71 b, 17-18.

66

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


in

[ETHICS,!
Still,

1 really adds anything to the major premise. there may be some justification for Aristotle

while

reasoning

and in trying to prove that Socrates is mortal from the immediately syllogistically known and undemonstrable premise that all men are morfrom the universal
to the particular
tal,

for, after all,

there

seem to be where the subject proof and the predicate in both the major premise and the conclusion are practically the same. For what Spinoza is practhere does not

logism in so far as there the particular and the universal,

may may

be a real inference in the sylbe a real difference between

even

this saving grace in Spinoza's

tically trying to do is to prove syllogistically that God is existent from the immediately known and undemonstrable

premise that

attempt

to

is existent. Logically it is analogous to an the mortality of Socrates by the syllogism: prove


is

God

The husband of Xanthippe


Socrates
is

mortal,

the

husband of Xanthippe,
is
i>

Therefore, Socrates
in

mortal, **

which there
is

is

here
to

meant that

no inference unless by Socrates' mortality special kind of mortality which came

him

as a result of the fact that he

was the husband of

Xanthippe. And

yet Spinoza goes through all the motions of proving the existence of God. What need is there for proving that which at the very outset is assumed to be immediately

known? The answer

that would naturally suggest itself

is

that

we

did not reproduce Spinoza's argument quite accurately, that the major premise in his syllogism does not in itself establish the existence of God; it only states the fact that we have an
idea of

God

syllogism therefore
'

as an existent being, and the purpose of the is to prove that our idea is real.

We

J. S. Mill,

System of Logic, Bk.

II,

Chs.

and

III.

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

167

should probably be referred to what is known as the ontological proof, to which class of reasoning most of Spinoza's proofs
belong, and we should be reminded that in the ontological proof the major premise is always a statement of what our
idea of

God
be,

ever

it

is and an assertion that our idea of God, whatwhether of a greatest being, or of a most perfect

being, or of a self-caused being, always involves existence, and that the purpose of the proof is to establish the reality of the idea. In refutation of this answer we may say that if

the major premise is assumed not to establish the existence of God, then the conclusion does not establish it. Further-

more, we shall endeavor to show that in its classical formulation by the three authors with whom we shall chiefly concern ourselves here, Anselm, Descartes, and Spinoza, the reality of the idea of God was never sought to be proved by the syllogism, but it was already conceived to be established
in the

major premise by some other

principle.

needless for us to repeat here in detail the stock objection to the ontological argument in its conventional formulation. The objection has become historically as famous
It
is

as the proof itself. Generally speaking, it tries to point out that what the ontological proof establishes is that if God is

conceived of as the greatest being, or the most perfect being, or a self-caused being, He must also be conceived of as existing outside the
existent.

mind and cannot be conceived of


is

as non-

There

nothing

in the proof, the objection con-

tinues, to

show that the idea of God conceived of in any of those forms is not a fictitious and arbitrary idea fabricated by

our mind.
cal

Now

all

these three protagonists of the ontologithis objection,


St.

proof were aware of


it

meet

squarely and
it

directly.

and they all tried Anselm was challenged

to

to

answer

by Gaunilon, and he answered it. Descartes quotes the same objection from Thomas Aquinas and tries to rebut

168
it.
1

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


2

[ETHICS,

Spinoza, too, was confronted with the stock objection 3 by Oldenburg, and he answered it. Furthermore, he also

as stating that "God cannot be a priori" and refutes that statement. 4 What is the proved force of all these answers, rebuttals, and refutations?

quotes

Thomas Aquinas

If we examine closely the answers given by St. Anselm, Descartes, and Spinoza to this most obvious objection, we shall find that they all try to show that the idea we have

of

God

as an existing being does not


its reality
is

upon the syllogism, but that

is

depend for its proof immediately known,

just as the reality of anything that

immediately perceived

and experienced. God, they all seem to say, is an immediate object of knowledge, and the knowledge by which He becomes

known

to us

is

a valid source of knowledge.

This
is

is

their

proof to corroborate

for the existence of


it.

God. Nothing
of knowledge

else

The kind

we

necessary have of God

they hold to be as valid a proof for His existence as a miraculous revelation or a natural personal experience of His
presence.

There
it

is

no need to go further into

this

kind of

immediate knowledge.
shall discuss
fully in

As

far as Spinoza

is

concerned,

we

That
jection

this is
is is is
6

another chapter. 5 the meaning of the answer to the stock ob-

clearly brought out in Descartes,

and

in his case the

answer
answer
is

generally so understood.

The main
and

point of his
7

that "whatever

we

true

"

clearly
its

distinctly perceive
reality,

true in the sense of

having objective

its not being an arbitrary and fictitious idea. The force of the ontological proof in Descartes, therefore, is its clearness and distinctness, its intuitive character, its immediacy

of

Primae Responsiones (Oeuvres, VII,


Epistola 3. Short treatise,
I, i,

p. 115).
3

Epistok

4.
ff.

10.

Cf. below, Vol. II, pp. 155

6
7

Primae Responsiones

(Oeuvres, VII, p. 116).


11.

Mcditationes, III (Oeuvres, VII, p. 46,

8 f.).

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD


manner of self-consciousness.
It
is

169

after the

this self-evident

God that distinguishes Descartes' ontological proof from his first proof in Meditation III, though both are alike in that they reason from the
nature of the truth of the idea of
idea of God to His existence. In the
first proof of Meditation an idea of God is not in itself III, the fact that we possess taken by Descartes to be a proof for His existence, for the

idea might be arbitrary and fictitious. It is therefore necessary to establish the truth of the idea demonstratively, by

reasoning from effect to cause, by showing that the idea we have of God could not have been produced except by a real object corresponding to it. In the ontological proof, on the
other hand, the very nature of our idea of God is evidence of His existence, just as our thinking is evidence of our own existence and as our sense perception is evidence of the existence of the things perceived. It is not at all necessary to assume, as it is done, that Descartes' ontological proof is de-

pendent upon his first and second proofs in Meditation III. It is rather an independent proof, its basis being Descartes'
idea like
reality.

theory of knowledge, according to which a clear and distinct God is self-evidently true and contains objective

Similarly Spinoza

makes

it

unmistakably clear that

his

primarily grounded upon the premise that God's existence is an immediate fact of our knowledge. In antici-

proof

is

pation of the objection of Thomas Aquinas that "God cannot be proved a priori^ because, indeed, He has no cause/' he maintains that "God, however, the first cause of all
things and even the cause of himself, manifests himself 2 The manifestation of God to us through through himself."
Kuno Fischer, Geschichte der neuern Philosophic I, i (jrd ed., Heidelberg, 1889), pp. 309 ff. Norman Smith, Studies in the Cartesian Philosophy, p. 58. 2 Short Treatise, I, i, 10.
1
-,

yo

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

himself as evidenced by the clearness and distinctness and adequacy of the idea we have of Him directly and without

any further reasoning proves His existence. Similar passages to the same effect are abundant in Spinoza's writings. 1 If thus in both Descartes and Spinoza the ontological argument is really psychological, resting as it does upon the view

God is a direct object of our knowledge, can the same be asserted with equal certainty of St. Anselm's proof? On
that
this point there exists a difference of opinion.

On
St.

the one

hand, attempts have been

made

to

show that

Anselm's

argument is ultimately psychological like that of Descartes/ But, on the other hand, these attempts have been refuted on the ground that there is nothing in St. Anselm to warrant
such a construction upon his argument. 3 In troversy, however, one important passage
this entire conin
St.

Anselm

seems to have been


Gaunilon.

lost sight of,

namely,

his

answer to

If we study the true meaning of Anselm's answer to Gaunilon's objection, we shall find that like Descartes and

Spinoza he stresses the point that his ontological proof is based upon the premise that the existence of God is an immediate fact of consciousness. Gaunilon, as may be recalled,
objected to the ontological proof by arguing that the idea of a being than whom a greater cannot be conceived no more

proves the existence of

God than

the idea of an island than


existis

which a more excellent cannot be conceived proves the

ence of that island. Anselm vehemently denies that there


1

See

W.

Beda Adlhoch,

Apel, Spinozas Verhdltnis zum ontologischen Beweise (Leipzig, 1911). " " Der Gottesbeweis des hi. Anselm in Philosophisches Jahrbuch,
also ist es nicht,

VIII-X (1895-1897), XV-XVI (1902-1903): "Verwegenheit

wenn

im Nachfolgenden zu beweisen versucht wird, das Argument sei ein psychologisches " und geschichtsphilosophisches, kein ontologisches (Vol. VIII, 1895, p. 56). See also G. Grunwald, Gtschichte der Gottcsbewcisc im Mitte/a/ter, pp. 31-33.
*

Cf. C.

Baeumker,

Vitelo, p. 305.

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

171

any analogy between the idea of a being greater than all other beings and the idea of an island more excellent than
all

other islands, and exclaims:

"But

I call

on your faith

and conscience to attest that this is most false/* x We read this answer and wonder. We say to ourselves: Simple Saint! if the authority of faith and the dictates of a religious conscience are the ultimate arbiters in the controversy, why go into all this trouble of proving the existence of God?

Why

not quote Scripture and the church doctrine and be done with it? There must therefore be some deeper meaning in
these simple words of Anselm. Is pealing to faith and to conscience
it

not possible that in apis

Anselm

really invoking

the argument from revelation as attested by tradition by which the existence of God is established as a fact of immediate personal experience?
is

Such an argument from revelation


it

common

in

2 Jewish philosophy, and

may

be considered

as partly psychological, in so far as the proof from revelation derives its validity from the fact that it is an immediate ex-

perience, and partly historical truth of the fact of revelation

and
is

social, in so far as the

attested

by an unbroken

chain of tradition universally accredited within a certain 3 group. It may thus be considered as the equivalent of the argument from consensus gentium, which is also social and is
likewise ultimately based

upon the immediacy of our knowl-

edge of God, namely, the innateness of the idea of God. Just as the general agreement of mankind is used by Cicero
as evidence that the idea of
1

God

is

innate, so

is

the generally

2
3

ApologeticuS) Ch. 1. Cf. Moreh Ncbukim, II, 23. Such a historical proof based

upon revelation

is

referred to

by Spinoza

in

fractalus Theologico-Politicus, Ch. 4 (Opera, III, p. 61, 11. 28-31): "The truth of a historical narrative, however assured, cannot give us the knowledge nor consequently the love of God, for love of God springs from knowledge of Him, and knowl-

edge of Him should be derived from themselves certain and known."

common

notions (comminubus notionibus)^ in

172

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

accredited religious tradition within the group taken by the Jewish philosophers to prove the veracity of the fact of reve-

Anselm thus says to Gaunilon that the idea we have God is unlike the idea we have of a most excellent island. The latter may be arbitrary and imaginary; the former is a
lation.
1

of

true and necessary idea, being based upon the immediate experience of God's existence in the act of revelation as attested by religious tradition universally accepted. That the ontological proof must ultimately rest upon a

psychological basis may also be gathered from one kind of opposition to that argument among the scholastics. There

were those who attacked the validity of the proof on the ground of their denial of the major premise, maintaining that the idea of God as a being whose essence involves existence

was not immediately perceived by everybody.

It

was

only well-trained philosophers, they argued, who perceived it as an immediate truth. But admitting that philosophers

immediate truth, these opponents of the ontological proof admitted the validity of the ontological
did perceive
it

as an

2 proof for philosophers. The particular theory of knowledge involved in this sort of reasoning is that indirect knowledge may in the course of time become direct knowledge which is

immediately accepted without the need of demonstration. Spinoza himself intimates this particular view when he says that the desire to know things by the third kind of knowledge

may
that

arise

from the second kind of knowledge. 3


to be reflected also in Descartes'

The
state-

same view seems

ment

"

those propositions indeed which are immediately


first

deduced from

now by
1

principles are known now by intuition, deduction, i.e., in a way that differs according to our
in

Cf. my "Notes on Proofs of the Existence of God in Jewish Philosophy" Hebrew Union College Annual, \ (1924), p. 577. 3 * Ethics C. Baeumker, Vilelo^ p. 301. , V, Prop. 28.

The

PROP,

u]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD


l

173

point of view/*
istence

And
is

so,

when

the knowledge of God's exdirect,

becomes immediate and

whatever

its origin,

said to be proved ontologically instead of demonstratively, for to prove the existence of God ontologically means to perceive it directly as a given fact. The im-

the existence of God

mediacy of the knowledge of God's existence is fully explained by Spinoza toward the end of the Second Dialogue in the Short Treatise and there, too, he seems to intimate that
p

it is

not

all

men

that do have at
I

first

such an immediate

tell you this, that so knowledge of God. "However, long as we have not such a clear idea of God ... we cannot truly

say that we are united with God." We have thus shown, I believe, that Spinoza as well as Descartes and Anselm starts his ontological argument with a

major premise that God's existence


It is

is

a fact of immediate

not necessary, as is generally done, to knowledge. set up a straw-man in the form of an untenable ontological

argument as it is conventionally stated, to riddle it through and through, and then to take up the defence of one particular favorite, either Anselm, or Descartes, or Spinoza, and claim that his particular argument is immune from such " " criticism on the ground that it is not ontological but rather " 2 The point we have been trying to make is psychological/' that all these three protagonists of the so-called ontological

argument are

alike in this respect.

They

are

all

making use of

a "psychological" argument, and their syllogism is tantamount to saying that we know directly, as we can know anything at all, that God exists. There is nothing in the conclusion of the syllogism that is not contained in the major premise. But if this is so, the question may be raised, not
Regulae ad Directionem Ingenii, III (Oeuvres, X, p. 370, 11. 10-13). Adlhoch does this with reference to Anselm; Apel with reference to Spinoza; Descartes is singled out by everybody as an exception.
1

174

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

only against Spinoza, but against Anselm and Descartes as well, What is the significance of the syllogism in the ontological proof?

The answer
premise. But

is

that the syllogism adds nothing to the major

still it is

not altogether redundant. It

may

be

said that the function of the ontological proof is like that of the proposition of an analytical judgment, in which the predicate adds nothing to the subject, and still its use is not alto-

gether unjustifiable. Perhaps the comparison can be put in the following manner. Just as propositions are either analytic or synthetic, so are syllogisms also either analytic or

and the relation of the analytical syllogism to the major premise is like that of the analytical proposition to the subject. To be more specific: The ontological proof for the existence of God is an analytical syllogism just as
synthetic,

the proposition "God is existent' is an analytical judgment, and the relation of the syllogism in the ontological proof to the major premise is like the relation of the proposition "God " is existent to the subject "God/* Neither of them adds
1

anything to the contents of its respective subject or major premise with which it starts, but both of them analyze the
contents of their respective subject and major premise. It was not Kant who was the first to draw the distinction

between analytical and synthetical judgments.

It has

been

shown that the

scholastics before

expressed it by the distinction aliud nota or by similar other distinctions, such as per se and per accidens or in materia necessaria and in materia
it was not unknown and Jewish philosophers, and having known that distinction, they asked themselves what kind of relation was expressed in an analytical proposition. That the relation

him had recognized it and between per se nota and per

contigenti*

It

can also be shown that

to Arabic

Cf. P. Coffey, 'The Science of Logic ,

I, p.

70.

PROP. 11]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD


seem to agree. They only seem
to question

175

could not be real and hence the judgment could not be real

they
real.

all

whether

there could be a justifiable logical relation which was not Thus in the proposition "God is existent/' argues

Avicenna, followed by a chorus of Jewish philosophers, since


essence and existence are identical, the proposition
logical,
is
z

tauto-

and is tantamount to saying "God is God." And Maimonides argues that in a proposition where the similarly predicate is identical with the subject there is no real logical
relation but only the explanation of a name.^

Likewise Ger-

sonides maintains that in the proposition "God is existent" the term "God" is a subject only "in discourse," not "in
existence."
All this
3

be considered as a sort of anticipation of John Stuart Mill's conclusion that an analytical judgment is only

may

verbal, or that

it is

explicative, as others call

it.

And

so

may
it is

we

also say of the analytical or ontological proof that


It is

indeed true to say of an ontological proof what John Stuart Mill says of every form of Aristotle's deductive syllogism. It contains no real infer-

only verbal and explicative.

ence.

It

adds nothing to what


still its

is is

already

known from
For
it

the

major premise. But

use

justifiable.

trans-

an argument. It elicits a truth which is only implicitly contained in the major premise. It puts an immediate fact of consciousness in the form of a syllates a conviction into
logistic reasoning.

It resolves

an idea into

its

component

parts.

Thus when Spinoza proves

the existence of

God

covered

ontologically, he does not pretend to arrive at a newly disfact, but rather to restate in formal language a fact

already known.
1

8 *

Or Adonat) I, iii, I. Cf. above, p. 123. March Nebukim, I, 51; cf. 52. Cf. above, p. Milhamot Adonai III, 3. Cf. above, p. 151.
y

154.

176

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

Truly speaking, if the ontological proof were to be put into a syllogistic formula in such a way as to bring out its entire force, it would have to be as follows:
Everything which
exists.
is

immediately perceived to exist


exist.

God

is

immediately perceived to

Therefore,

God

exists.

Now, none
as given

of the ontological proofs in their various forms


three

by

its

main exponents, Anselm, Decartes, and

Spinoza, prove directly that God exists. What they prove is that the existence of God is known to us by a certain kind

duced

of immediate knowledge. Their various proofs can be reto the following syllogism:
If

we have an idea of God as the greatest, or as the most perfect, or as a self-caused being, then God
as the

is immediately perceived by us to exist. But we have an idea of God as the greatest, or most perfect, or as a self-caused being.

Therefore,
exist.

God

is

immediately perceived by us to

Their direct proof of the existence of God is their respective views that our immediate knowledge of God's existence
implied in the idea we have of God as the greatest, or as the most perfect, or as a self-caused being is valid

which

is

knowledge.

II.

SPINOZA'S

FOUR PROOFS

foregoing discussion of the nature of the ontological proof may serve as a general approach to the understanding of all of Spinoza's proofs of the existence of God. Whatever

The

may

be said

in criticism

of this

ing hardly concerns those of us

mode of ontological reasonwho are now mainly inter-

PROP. 11]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

177

ested in the objective understanding of Spinoza's thought, rather than in passing criticism on it. It may perhaps be

that the alleged immediacy of the idea of God is nothing but an after- thought of a departed traditional belief, just
as the catless grin which Alice saw in Wonderland was nothing but an after-image of a departed grinning cat; or it

may

be that Spinoza is claiming "an arbitrary right to accept and it may perhaps anything he pleases as self-evident ";
l

also be, as

we have been

trying to show, that the reasoning

by which

it is

sought to dissolve this idea into a syllogism,

despite the cogency of its logical form, is nothing but the breaking up of a complex term into its component parts.

But however
him
by
to
its

slight this

proof

may

appear to

us, it certainly

carried conviction to the

mind of Spinoza and of others like whom an immediately and intuitively conceived idea

very clearness and distinctness connoted as much reality as, aye even greater reality than, the undimmed perceptions of unimpaired senses. And perhaps we should be in-

more weight to this reasoning if we could only bear in mind that Spinoza's God is not the God of traditional theology, that his "God" is merely an appeasive term for the
clined to give

most comprehensive principle of the universe, which he supposed to be conceived apriorily as the ideal triangle, but unlike the ideal triangle,

verse and not

its

being the working principle of the unimere ideal pattern, its a priori conception in-

volved an extra-mental reality which the a priori conception of a triangle did not. With these considerations looming before our mind, there remains for us only to deal with the
external structure of the proofs, their origin, their individual history, their growth, and the final form in which they appear

before us.
It
1

may

be recalled that Descartes has three proofs of the

F. Pollock, Spinoza^ p. 129.

178

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


them
in
1

[ETHICS,

existence of God, two of

Meditation III and a third

in Meditation V, corresponding respectively to the three


2 proofs in the Discours de la Methode, IV, in the Principia Philosophiae, I, 18-19, 20-21, and 14, and in the geometrical

formulation of the arguments demonstrating the existence of God at the end of Secundae Responsiones, Propositions II, III, and I. The first two of these three proofs we shall designate respectively as the first and second proof of Meditation III, and the third as the ontological proof. All the proofs
for the existence of

God adduced by Spinoza

in his various

works

may

be traced to these three Cartesian proofs, and

may

be divided accordingly into three groups: First, Descartes' first proof of Meditation III to be found

in Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae, I, Proposition VI,


in

and
I, i,

the proof designated as a posteriori

in Short treatise

',

and referred
in a

to also in a letter to Jelles (Epistola

XL) and
76

note to the Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione, (Opera, II, p. 29, note a).

Second, Descartes' second proof of Meditation III to be found in Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae, I, Proposition
VII, and in the third proof of Ethics, I, Proposition Third, Descartes' ontological proof to be found in Principia Philosophiae

XL

Cartesianae,

I, I,

Proposition V;
I;

in

the

a priori proof of Short Treatise,


Ethics ,
I,

in the first

proof of

Proposition XI; and in letters to Blyenbergh (Epistola XXI) and Hudde (Epistola XXXIV).

fourth proof in the Ethics is a modification of Descartes' second proof of Meditation III, and the second proof in the Ethics, we shall try to show, has been suggested by
Descartes' ontological proof, but
it

The

contains

many

elements

borrowed from mediaeval Jewish and Arabic philosophy.


1

(i) Ocuvres,
'

VII, p. 45,
VI, p. 33,

11.

9
25

ff.,
ff.,

(2) ibid., p. 47,

11. 11.

24
24

flF.

(i) Oeuvres,

11.

(2) ibid., p. 34,

ff.,

(3) ibid., p. 36,

11.

ff.

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

179

with the four proofs of the Ethics, corwith them the parallel proofs found in the other relating
shall here deal

We

writings of Spinoza.

FIRST PROOF

What
in

is

in the Ethics

mainly of interest to us in Spinoza's first proof and its parallels elsewhere is the various forms

which he reproduces Descartes' ontological argument. Spinoza does not summarize Descartes, he does not epitomize
him, nor does he merely paraphrase him. He rather selects what he considers to be the salient features of Descartes' argu-

ment and moulds them

into a form of his own.

If

we com-

pare the various versions of Descartes* ontological proof as given by Spinoza, we shall find that the Demonstration of
Proposition V in Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae, I, and the first part of the a priori proof in Short 'Treatise , I, i,

XXXIV

represent one type; that the proofs in Epistolae XXI and and the second part of the a priori proof in Short
Treatise ,
I,

I,

thus," represent another type;

introduced by the remark "otherwise also and that the first proof of

Proposition XI in Ethics, I, represents a third type. How these three types of Descartes' ontological proof were chiselled

out from the unhewn and rugged block of Descartes' rather

and informal discussion of the ontological proof can be best shown by trying to outline the salient features of Descartes' argument as they must have formulated themdiscursive
selves in Spinoza's mind.

The

starting point of Descartes'

of the idea of

God

in

our mind.

argument is the presence This idea of God, he con-

tends, could not

of our senses, nor

have reached our mind through the medium is it a factitious idea, depending solely on
rather derive this idea of God, so to speak,

our thought.

We

l8o

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


"
the storehouse of our mind."
l

[ETHICS,
first

from

It

is

the

and

fore-

most of the clear and distinct and true ideas born within us. But how do we know that the idea of God is not factitious?

we know it by the fact that and absolutely unlike any other idea, "for unique really I discern in many ways that this idea is not something factitious, and depending solely on my thought, but that
this

To

Descartes answers that


is

the idea

it is

because the image of a true and immutable nature cannot conceive anything but God himself to whose essence
. . .

existence [necessarily] pertains/' 2 That existence pertains to the essence of

God

is

known

by

us, according to Descartes, in

V, in Principia Philosophiae, I, formulation of the arguments demonstrating the existence


of

two ways. In Meditation 14, and in the geometrical

God

at the

he says that

it is

end of Secundae Responsiones, Proposition I, implied in our immediate idea of God as

"a Being supremely perfect/* 3 for since existence is perfection it must be included in that idea as something pertaining to the essence of God. In his Primae Responsiones, however, he declares that the pertinence of existence to essence in

God

is

also implied in our idea of

God

as a self-caused being,

or, as he expresses himself, in a being who possesses necessary 4 existence, for necessary existence is the equivalent of ex-

istence per se, 5 which, according to Descartes, means selfcaused as well as causeless. 6 It is therefore natural for

Descartes sometimes to leave out this intermediary step of


1

Meditations ,
Meditationes,
Meditationes,

(Oeuvres, VII, p. 67,

11.

22
10
9).

f.).

Cf. Meditationes, III (Oeuvres,

VII, p. 51,11. i8ff.).


a
3

V V

(Oeuvres, VII, p. 68,

11.
1.

ff.).

(Oeuvres y VII, p. 67,

Primae Responsiones (Oeuvres, VII, p. 117, 11. 5 ff.). See Gerhardt, Die Philosophischen Schrijten von Gottfried Wilhelm

406: chose."
p.
6

"Car

Leibnitz, IV, 1'Estre necessaire et 1'estre par son Essence ne sont qu'une meme

Primae Responsiones (Ocuores, VII, pp. 109

ff.).

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

181

perfection or self-causation, by which we know that God's essence involves existence, and to speak of our immediate

conception of
existence.

God

as that of a being

whose essence involves

assumption of the pertinence of existence to the essence of God Descartes builds his ontological proof. We

Upon
it

this

find

in

two forms.
first

In the
I

form, the major premise states that "all which

know
it

[i.e.,

distinctly as pertaining to this subject of the innate idea] does really belong to it," x or as he

clearly

and

puts

in

Primae Responsiones

>

"That which we

clearly

and

distinctly understand to belong to the true and immutable nature of anything, its essence, or form, can be affirmed
2

of that thing."

The minor premise

states that

we

clearly

and

distinctly understand that to exist belongs to the nature

of God, and hence the conclusion that we can affirm of God that He exists. This is also the form used in the geometrical

formulation of the arguments demonstrating the existence of God at the end of Secundae Responsiones^ Proposition I. It
is

this

form of the argument that

is

reproduced by Spinoza

in Proposition

and
I, i,

in the first

of Principia Philosophise Cartesianae^ I, part of the a priori proof of Short Treatise^

the phraseology of the

Primae Responsiones being espe-

cially noticeable in the latter.

the idea of

In the second form, Descartes draws a comparison between God and that of a triangle. Both have "a deter-

minate nature, form, or essence, which is immutable and eternal." 3 That determinate nature, form, or essence in the
case of the triangle is implied in its definition; but in the case of God it is implied in our idea of Him as all-perfection
1

Meditationes,

(Oeuvres y VII, p. 65,

11.

17

ff.).
11.

Primae Responsiones (Oeuvres, VII,


Meditationesy

p. 118,
11.

22

flf.).

(Oeuvres, VII, p. 64,

15

ff.).

82

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

or as self-causality. Thus from the definition of a triangle diverse properties follow, viz., "that its three angles are

equal to two right angles, that the greatest side is subtended by the greatest angle, and the like/* J Similarly from our idea of God as an all-perfect or self-caused being it
follows "that an [actual]

and eternal existence pertains

to

His nature/*

The nerve
force of the

would say, the


the essence of
to

of the argument, or, as Spinoza argument (vis argument?)? is the

conclusion "that existence can no

more be separated from

two

having its three angles equal be separated from the essence of a [rectiright angles
its
4

God

than can

linear] triangle."

It

is

this

form of the argument that

is

briefly restated by Spinoza in Epistola XXI, when he says: "If the nature of God is known to us, then the assertion that

God

exists follows as necessarily

from our own nature as


s

it

follows necessarily from the nature of a triangle that

its

three angles are equal to two right angles." part of the a priori proof of Short 'Treatise
',

In the second
i, it is

I,

repro-

duced rather incompletely: "The essences of things are from all eternity, and unto all eternity shall remain immutable.

The

existence of

God

is

essence.

Therefore, etc."

The

con-

from Descartes, should read as follows: Therefore, the essence and existence of God are together from all eternity, and unto all eternity shall reclusion, in the light of our quotations

main unchanged, that

is

to say, existence can never be sep-

arated from the essence of God.


In the Ethics^ Spinoza uses the
1

first

form of Descartes'

Meditationes, V (Oeuvres, VII, p. 64, 11. 18 ff.). use of the triangle having its three angles equal to two right angles as an illustration for the idea of necessity is to be found in Aristotle, Physics, II, 9, 2ooa,

The

17

ff.
2
3

Meditationes, V (Oeuvres, VII, p. 65, Epistola 12 (Opera , IV, p. 62, 1. 5).

1.

24).

<

Meditationes,

(Oeuvres, VII, p. 66,


s

11.

ff.).

Cf. French version (Opera, IX,


11.

p. 52).

Epistola 21 (Opera, IV, p. 130,

4-7).

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD


Reduced

183
to a

ontological proof with some modification.

syllogism, the major premise therein is the statement that everything whose essence involves existence exists. The minor premise is the statement that God's essence involves
existence.

But the conclusion, that God


by proving the contrary

exists, is arrived at

indirectly

to be absurd.

This

is

like

the reasoning employed in St. Anselm's proof. In a letter to Schuller, Spinoza expresses a preference for this kind of
proof, namely, the reductio ad absurdum^ when the proposiIt is also to be noted that in this proof tion is negative. 1 Spinoza finds that existence must pertain to the essence of

God

not in the idea of perfection, as does Descartes in Meditation V, but rather in the idea of self-causality, for Spinoza

refers here to Proposition VII, the


is

demonstration of which

based upon the premise that subtance, or, as he now calls it, God, cannot be produced by an external cause and must

But we have already seen that Primae Responsiones, makes selfcausality the basis of the identification of essence and existence in God. There is therefore no foundation for the ofttherefore be self-caused.
in

Descartes himself,

repeated statement that Descartes bases his ontological proof on the idea of God as a most perfect being, whereas

Spinoza bases his ontological proof on the idea of


self-caused being.
2

God

as a

The

two, as

we have

seen, are identified

by Descartes

himself.

In the light, however, of what we have said, namely, that the basis of the ontological proof is the assertion that we
1 Epistola 64 (Opera, IV, p. 278, 11. 8 ff.): "deducendo rem ad absurdum." Cf. Epistola 63 from Schuller. See above, p. 97, and below, p. 378. 2 It may be said that Leibniz advocated the substitution of "existence/)^ se"

for "perfection" as a criticism of Descartes, whereas Spinoza evidently did so as an interpretation of Descartes. Cf. A. Hannequin, "La preuve ontologique carte sienne deYendue centre Leibnitz" in Revue de Mftaphysique et de Morale IV (1896),
,

PP- 435 436.

184

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

have a valid immediate perception of God's existence and that the so-called ontological proofs merely show how our
our idea of
valid immediate perception of God's existence is implied in God as the greatest or the most perfect being,

or, in this particular proof, as a

existence, Spinoza's

first

being whose essence involves proof in the Ethics is really to be

reduced to the following syllogism: If we have a clear and distinct idea of

whose essence involves

existence, then us to exist. mediately perceived by

God as a being God is imas a

But we have a clear and distinct idea of God being whose essence involves existence.
Therefore,
exist.

God

is

immediately perceived by us to

SECOND PROOF
Against his own ontological proof based upon the inseparableness of existence from the essence of God Descartes himself raises a difficulty

which he considers of no accustomed

little

mo-

ment.

"

We are so much

to distinguish existence

from essence

in the case of other things/'

he says, "that we

do not with

sufficient readiness notice

to the essence of

other things/'

'

existence belongs than in the case of degree In order to remove this difficulty, Descartes

how

God

in a greater

draws a distinction, or rather recalls an old distinction, between possible and necessary existence, declaring that "in the concept or idea of everything that is clearly and distinctly
conceived, possible existence is contained, but necessary existence never, except in the idea of God alone/* 2 It may be

here remarked that by necessary existence, as already pointed out, is meant existence/)^ se, which, according to Descartes
1

Primac Rfsponsioncs
Ibid.
(11.

(Oeuvrfs, VII, p. 116,

11.

f.).

20

ff.).

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD


in the sense of

185

himself, has a negative aspect

uncaused as

well as a positive aspect in the sense of self-caused. 1 With this distinction drawn, Descartes substitutes the expression " " " "necessary existence for the mere word existence in his

ontological proof, arriving at his conclusion that God exists not from the premise that existence is involved in the essence

of God, but rather from the premise that necessary existence is involved in it. It will have been noticed that in his restateof Descartes in Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae, I, Proposition V, Spinoza has already made use of this substi" tution, declaring that the concept of God includes necessary
existence/' that
existence.
first
is to say, necessary existence and not merely In the Short Treatise, I, i, however, and in the

ment

proof in Ethics, I, Proposition XI, the term "existence" without the adjective "necessary" is used.
second proof in the Ethics Spinoza takes up new phrase "necessary existence" and builds again around it a new proof. But why did Spinoza make a new proof out of it? Why did he not embody it in his first proof
in the

Now

this

as did Descartes

and

as he himself did in his restatement of

Descartes in his Principia*

The answer would seem

to be

phrase "necessary existence" had to Spinoza's mind the recollection of the mediaeval brought discussions about possible and necessary existence and of

found

in the fact that the

a mediaeval cosmological proof based

upon that

distinction,

warrant the framing of an appeared new and distinct proof. Thus Spinoza's second entirely proof is of a composite nature. It is ontological and Carall this

and

to

him

to

tesian in form, but its substance

is

enriched by borrowings

from mediaeval sources.


this

We

shall

attempt to disentangle
it

complicated and involved proof and reduce

to its

simple constituent elements.


1

See above, p. 180,

n. 6.

86

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

In mediaeval Jewish philosophy, under the influence of Aristotle, a distinction is made between an internal cause,

which resides

in the

nature of the thing

itself,

and an external

cause, which resides outside of the thing. If the cause resides in the thing itself, an effect must follow from that cause unless there is

external impediment
cause,

an external impediment to prevent it. That may also be considered as a sort of

and thus we have a further distinction between a cause

which produces existence and a cause which prevents or


negates existence. Similar distinctions are familiar also to In Maimonides these students of scholastic philosophy. are implied in the following statement: "Everydistinctions
1

thing that passes from potentiality to actuality has something different from itself as the cause of its transition, and
that cause is necessarily outside itself, for if the cause of the transition existed in the thing itself and there was no obstacle to prevent the transition, the thing would never

have been
been

in a state of potentiality
2

but would have always

In the commentaries upon this passage, distinct technical terms for the contrast between effective causes and impedimental causes are inin a state of actuality/'

troduced. 3

Then, again,

in

tempt
1

to prove that

mediaeval Jewish philosophy, in the atGod is everlasting and can never be

For the distinction between external and internal cause (causa extrinseca^

causa intrinseca), see Metaphysics^ XII, 4, loyob, 22-23; Summa Theologica^ Prima Secundae, Quaest. i, Art. 3, Obj. i. See also Principia Philosophiae Cartesianac, I,

Axiom

ii. Cf. below, pp. 319 ff. For the impedimental cause, see
ejffectus coelestis corporis

Summa
non ex

Obj. 3: Si
2 *

Theohgica y Pars I, Quaest. 115, Art. 6, necessitate proveniat> hoc est propter ali-

quam causam impedientem.


Moreh Nebukim, II, Introduction, Prop. 18. See commentary of Shem-fob on Moreh Ncbukim,
ad. /or.: N'21D, effective
1.

cause; VTID ,p'VD (Arabic:

^ U.

Cf. Cuzari, V, 20, p. 338,

19: p'NJ7

y31B)>
in

impedimental cause. The impedimental cause is also mentioned by Avicenna his Al-Shifa*. Cf. M. Horten, Die Metaphysik Avicennas^ p. 267.

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

187

deprived of His existence, it is argued that God's existence could not be negated or taken away except by some cause, but that cause would have to be either like God himself or
unlike himself; and as neither of these is possible, it is concluded that God's existence can never be negated. To quote:

"God
as the

is

everlasting,

being proved to coming of the non-existent into existence must have a

and will never cease to exist. For a have no beginning cannot pass away. Just

cause, so also the disappearance of a thing from existence requires a cause. Nothing vanishes from existence on its own

account, but on account of

its

opposite.

God, however, has

nothing opposite Him, nor, for that matter, anything like Him. For if anything were like Him in every respect, it would be identical with God himself and they could not therefore be described as two. As for assuming something

God to be the cause of His ceasing to exist, it is likewise impossible for the following reason. That opposite
opposite
thing could not be without beginning, for it has already been proved that God's existence alone is without beginning, nor

could

it

have been created,

for everything created


if so,

must be

an

produced by the eternal God; but, the effect make its cause disappear?"
effect
x

how can

Then, also, in mediaeval Jewish philosophy, in consequence of an Avicennian view, the origin of which I have 2 discussed in another place, a distinction is made between
necessary existence per se" and "possible existence />^r se." Necessary existence per se is that which Spinoza would call
"

causa jui y something whose existence is independent of any cause. 3 "Everything that is necessary of existence in respect to its own essence has no cause for its existence in any man1

Cuzari, V,
Cf.

8, 5.
ff.

my

Creseas' Critique of Aristotle , pp. 109-112, 680

Cf. above, p. 127; below, p, 252.

88

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


x

[ETHICS,

ner whatsoever."

owes

its

Possible existence per se is that which existence to some cause. "Everything that has a

its existence is in respect to its own essence only of existence, for if its causes exist, the thing likepossible wise will exist/' 2 Furthermore, the possible per se is said

cause for

to

become impossible
its
if

in

the absence of the cause


its

upon

which

existence depends, for "if

causes have never

existed, or

they have ceased to

exist, or if their causal re-

lation to the thing has changed, then the thing itself will not
exist/'
3

But,

still,

when

the cause from which

it

follows

by by
its

necessity does exist, then the thing, though only possible its own nature, is said to be necessary with reference to
cause.
It

there

is

may thus be said that within everything possible the distinction of being possible in itself but necessary

with reference to
there
is

its cause. According to this view, therefore, a fourfold classification of being, divided first into two main groups, into that which is causeless and hence

necessary by
existence,
its

and that which requires a cause for its the latter of which being then subdivided into
itself
its

three aspects, namely, possible in itself, necessary by 4 cause, and impossible in the absence of any cause.

This fourfold classification of being

is

reproduced by
divides
all

Spinoza

in Cogitata

Metaphysica^

I, 3,

when he

things into necessary, impossible, possible,

and contingent.

Necessary existence, in Spinoza as in mediaeval philosophy, is exemplified by God. As an illustration for the impossible
Spinoza mentions the "chimera,"
1

which

like the

words "a

Moreh Nebukim^
Ibid., Prop. 19.

II,

Introduction, Prop. 20.


J

Ibid.
II,

4 5

See commentary of

Shem-Tob on Moreh Nebukim,

Introduction, Prop. 19.


a goat-stag
I,

So

also in Descartes, as, for instance, in the

French version of Meditation III


is

(Oeuvres y IX, p. 34).


(rpa7e\a</>os)

Aristotle's illustration of a non-existent being

and sphinx.

Cf.

De

Interpretatione y

I,

i6a, 16-17;

Physics, IV,

208 a, 30.

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD


"
rightly called a verbal being.

189

square nation and


ble"
is

circle
is

exists neither in the intellect nor in the imagi-

The term

"possi-

being brought about or being made necessary by a cause, and the term "contingent" is used by him to designate that aspect of the possible wherein it was said by the mediaevals to be possible in consideration of its own essence. "A thing is said to be possible when we understand its efficient cause, but do not know whether it is determined. Therefore, we may consider that
to be possible

used by Spinoza

in the general sense of

which

is

neither necessary

[i.e.,

by

itself]

nor

impossible [i.e., by itself]. If now we attend merely to the essence of a thing and not to its cause, we say it is contingent;
that
is,

when we

God

and chimeras."

consider anything between the extremes That these two terms "possible" and
for the

"contingent" were meant by Spinoza the possible as used by the mediaevals

may

two aspects of be gathered from

the context of the passage quoted and from parallel passages in the other works of Spinoza. 1 He then makes the following statement: "If any one wishes to call that contingent

which

I call

possible

shall not contradict him.

and possible what I call contingent I For I am not accustomed to dis-

pute about mere names. It will be sufficient if it is only admitted that these arise not because of something real, but
only because of a deficiency in our perception (defect us
nostrae perception is}.' 2 The last statement is a repetition of what is said earlier in the same chapter: "For some, these
1

two terms are considered defects of things, although, they are nothing more than a deficiency in our
(defect us nostri intcllectus)."
1

in truth,

intellect

The
I,

reference
7,
11.

is

no doubt to
Nota
i;
I,

Cf. Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae,

Prop.

Lemma
30
ff.);

I,

'Tractatus

tie

Intellectus Emendatiorie,
i;

53 (Opera, II, p. 19,

Ethics,

Prop. 33,

Schol.
2

IV, Defs. 3 and

4.

Cf. below, pp. 310, 399, 410.


Cf. Metaphysics, V, 30, io25a, 24; below, p. 399, a Cf. Ethics, I, Prop. 33, Schol. i.

and

Cogitata Metaphysica, I, 3. Vol. II, pp. 13, 109, 160.

190

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

controversy between Avicenna and Averroes as to whether possibility is merely a conceptual aspect or a real It is also to be noted that Spinoza's property of being.
the
1

"I lofty declaration here in Cogitata Metaphysica, I, 3, that am not accustomed to dispute about mere names/' as well
as Blyenbergh's statement in one of his letters to Spinoza

that

"you have taught me that one must not quarrel over


2

words/'

is

reminiscent of a similar expression used in


writings. to Spinoza's second proof in the Ethics,
all
3

Hebrew, Arabic, Latin, and Greek philosophic

Coming now
find that
it is

we

replete with

those distinctions and lines of

reasoning which we have abstracted from mediaeval sources. Spinoza refers to the distinction between an internal and an
external cause

when he speaks of

a reason or cause which

"must

outside it."

either be contained in the nature of the thing or lie 4 He also distinguishes between a positive cause
if

and an impedimental cause when he says that


1

a thing

See commentary of
Cf.

Shem-Tob on Moreh Nebukim^


11.

II,

Introduction, Prop. 19.

Epistola 20 (Opera, IV, p. 101,

4-5 and
1

24).

Abraham Ibn Daud, Emunah Ramah, I, 6 (p. 20): ... PD3 UPON imjfcnpl Bp PR *D ,n2nnp 00 nr i ? onwi ,DPH nr -prya *w *b DN nnNi If this name does not please you, call it by what"We call soul nefesh. ever other name you like, for we are not sticklers for names." Similarly Algazali in
. .

his Tahafot aI-Fa/asifat y III (ed.

Maurice Bouyges,
which

p. 109,

1.

9), says: \j+~*f

o^*
from

O^-~Jl
the

4it_VjiA

Xi >Ui

1-L*,

in the published Latin translation

Hebrew

tructio Destructionis] is

version of Averroes' Tahajot al-Tahajot (Happalat ha-Happalah, Desrendered as follows: "si autem non appellabilis hoc actionem

non

est disputatio

de nominibus."

OYIDBO JT^

This translation was accessible to Spinoza.


pression in a letter to
p. 269,
11.

H3H ,hy& Hf 1N"lpn *? DW.) ]' Descartes makes use of the same ex-

25-26):

Henry More. Cf. Correspondance, DXXXVII (Oeuvres, V, "Ego vero non soleo quidem de nominibus disputare."

Similar expressions occurring in Greek and in other Arabic sources are quoted

by

S.

Mittelalters, p. 216, n. 13.


disiensis, Scripta

Horovitz in his Die Psychologic bei den jtfdischen Religions-Philosophen des As Greek examples he quotes from Alexander Aphro-

Minora (ed. Bruns), II, p. 183, 1. 17: dvonaruv pb ovv ouSeis <0&'os, and from Galen, Opera (ed. Kiihn), I, p. 155: jutts 5i obSkv diafapdp&a Trpds ro>s,
rd 6v6^ara ^aXXdrroi'ras.
4

"Haec vera

ratio seu causa vel in natura rei contineri debet, vel extra ipsam."

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD


it

191

exists, why exists; and if it does not exist, there must be a reason or cause which hinders its existence or which negates it." Furthermore,

"there must be a reason or cause

he follows the main outline of the mediaeval argument for the everlastingness of God when he argues that if a reason
or cause be granted "which hinders which negates His existence ... it

God from
must be
it,
.
.

existing, or

either in the
is

nature

itself

of

God

or

must

lie

outside

that
.

to say, in

another substance of another nature.

But substance

possessing another nature could have nothing in common with God, and therefore could not give Him existence nor

negate

it."

Finally, he reproduces the mediaeval

own

classification of being into necessary, possible,

and his and im-

possible when he states that "the nature of the thing itself and shows the reason why a square circle does not exist the reason, on the other hand, why substance exists follows
.
.

from its nature alone," 3 and when he further says that it is not from its own nature "but from the order of corporeal
nature generally,"
it
i.e., its

cause, that "it

must
it is

follow, either

that a triangle necessarily exists, or that


to exist/'
4

impossible for

But more than


existence of

this.

There

is

a mediaeval proof for the

God based upon

the distinction between neces-

sary existence and possible existence which, as

we

shall

now

1 "Ratio, seu causa dari debet, cur existit; si autem non existit, ratio etiam, seu causa dari debet, quae impedit, quominus existat, sive quae ejus existentiam tollat." 2 "Si ... ratio causa dari possit quae impedit, quominus Deus existat,
. . .
.

vel

quae ejus existentiam

tollat

ea, vel in ipsa Dei natura, vel extra

ipsam dari

deberet, hoc est, in alia substantia alterius naturae. ...


esset naturae, nihil

cum Deo commune

substantia, quae alterius habere, adeoque, neque ejus existentiam

At

ponere, neque tollere posset." " * Ex. gr. rationem, cur circulus quadratus non existat, ipsa ejus natura indicat; Cur autem contra substantia existat, ex sola etiam ejus natura sequitur." .
.

"At

ratio,

cur circulus vel triangulus

existit, vel

cur non existit, ex eorum

natura non sequitur, sed ex ordine universae naturae corporeae; ex eo enim sequi debet, vel jam triangulum necessario existere, vel impossibile esse, ut jam existat."

192

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

proceed to show, served Spinoza as a pattern for his second forms of proof. This mediaeval proof is one of the several
as the cosmological proof. Spinoza, as we has changed it into an ontological proof. In order to recreate the complete setting of this second proof of Spinoza, it is necessary for us to trace the develop-

what

is

known

shall see,

ment of the cosmological proof out of which it has arisen. The cosmological proof is based upon the principle of causalin ity, reasoning from effect to cause, which, when expressed its most general terms, asserts that every form of coming
into being or change requires a cause.

The

principle of

causality alone, however, was not considered sufficient to be used as a proof for the existence of God. It had to be sup2 plemented by some other principle. In Plato that supwas the creation of the world. The plementary principle

cosmological proof as used by him to the following syllogism:


cause.

may

therefore be reduced

Everything that comes into existence must have a

The world came

into existence.

Therefore, the world must have a cause.

This form of the cosmological proof was also used by the

Moslem Mutakallimun and their Jewish followers, among whom it was known as the proof from creation, though its
not always recognized. 3
identity with the Platonic proof from efficient causation was With the denial of a created uni-

verse by Aristotle the cosmological proof assumed a new form. The principle of causality was still retained, but the theory of creation was replaced by the theory of the imposCf. my "Notes on Proofs of the Existence of God Hebrew Union College Annual, I (1924), pp. 584 ff. 3 Timaeus 28 A.
1

in

Jewish Philosophy" in 'The

See
cit. t

my "Notes

on the Proofs of the Existence of God

in

Jewish Philosophy,"

op.

p. 584, n. 44.

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

193

sibility of an infinite regress. In Aristotle two versions of this type of the cosmological proof occur, one couched in terms

of motion and the other in terms of potentiality and actuality. Assuming the world to be a process of motion or a process of
the actualization of the potential, and assuming also that both these processes require a cause and that there can be

no

infinite series of causes of

any kind, the two forms of the

proof run as follows:

A
Every
series of things

moved and moving must have

an unmoved mover.
a series of things moved and moving. Therefore, the world must have an unmoved mover.

The world

is

B
Every
series of transitions

from potentiality into actuis

ality

must have a cause which


is

pure actuality.

The world

a series of transitions from potentiality

into actuality.

Therefore, the world must have a cause which


actuality.

is

pure

given by Aristotle in the 1 Eighth Book of the Physics, the second in the Metaphysics. To these two Aristotelian versions of the cosmological proof
first
is

The

of these versions

Avicenna, and before him Alfarabi, added a third version couched in terms of possibility and necessity. This new version

was introduced by them because they considered it to be more general and more universally applicable than the
It will
diflfer

others.

be noticed that this

new
in

version does not

essentially

from the other two,

for motion, potentiality,

and

possibility are only different


is

ways

which the principle

of causality
1

expressed and are in a sense interchangeable


8,

Metaphysics, IX,

10498, 24

f.,

and XII,

7,

loysb, 3

f.

194

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

In Greek the same term, Siwa/us, means both potentiality and possibility, and Aristotle defines motion as the actuality of that which is potential so far as it is potential
terms.
J

and
it is

also as the actuality of that

which

is

movable so

far as

movable. 2 Maimonides,

who

besides the two Aristotelian

versions of the proof uses also the Avicennian version, introduces the latter by the following remark: "This is taken from the words of Aristotle, though he gives it in a different

From Maimonides it was taken over by Thomas Aquinas, who makes use of it as the third of his five proofs of the existence of God. 4 From him it was passed on into
form."
3

modern philosophy,
sion as his

so that

Kant

uses the Avicennian ver-

model cosmological proof.

We

shall

endeavor to

show that
for it
his

this is also the basis of Spinoza's

second proof.

The Avicennian
knowledge of
it tries

version as reproduced by

was Maimonides from


it is

Maimonides most likely drew Spinoza divided into two parts. In the first

whom

part,
all

to establish the fact that in the universe

among

the things that actually exist there must be one which has eternal existence, inasmuch as it is impossible either that all

things should be eternal or that

all

things should be transient.

In the second part, drawing upon the distinction between


necessary and possible (and also impossible) existence, it tries to prove that the eternal being must have necessary
existence, that
or, as
is

to say,

it

Spinoza would say,


is

must be independent of any cause, it must be causa sui. The proof

based, again, as in Aristotle's versions, upon the impossibility of an infinite regress. Reduced to its syllogistic
for this

form, Avicenna's version of the proof runs as follows:


1

Physics, III,
2

I,

20ia,

IO-H.

Physics, III, 2, 202a, 7-8.

3
*

Moreh Nebukim,

II, i.

Summa Vheologica, Pars I, Quaest. 2, Art. 3.

Cf. Contra Gentiles, Lib.

I,

Cap.

13.

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD


series of transitions

195

from possible existence Every into necessary existence must have a cause which has necessary existence.

The world

is

a series of transitions from possible exist-

ence into necessary existence. Therefore, the world must have a cause which has
necessary existence. modification of the Avicennian proof was introduced 1 by Crescas. Crescas denies the impossibility of an infinite series of causes and effects and thereby removes one of the

premises of the Aristotelian proofs of the existence of God in all of its forms. But still he retains the principle of
causality, maintaining that everything possible,
i.e.,

every-

thing which by its own nature may or may not exist, must have a cause to give preference to existence over non-existence.

That cause must

itself

be uncaused, that

is,

it

must

have necessary existence. Once such a cause is given, argues Crescas, it may have an infinite number of effects arranged
not impossible. 2 How Crescas conceived of this possibility does not concern us here. 3 Suffice it to say that on the mere principle of causation, namely, that any series of causes and effects, whether infinite or
in a causal series, for infinity
is

finite,

must have a first uncaused cause, Crescas establishes new cosmological proof for the existence of God. The

characteristic feature of this proof, in contradistinction to the Aristotelian and the Avicennian, as will have been
is the elimination of the principle of the impossiof an infinite series of causes and effects. But still like bility the older Aristotelian proofs it retains the principle of causal-

noticed,

ity,

which principle is couched, as in Avicenna's proof, in terms of possibility and necessity. Truly considered, Crescas'
1

Or Adonai,
Cf.

I, iii, 2.

Or Adonai,

I,

ii,

3.

my

Crescas' Critique of Aristotle, pp. 67-69, 490-497.

196

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

new proof is simply

a restoration of the Platonic proof from

efficient causation or of the proof from creation as used by Moslem and Jewish theologians, the only difference between

them being that whereas the older proof starts with the conception of a universe created in time Crescas' proof starts

with the conception of a universe which


its

own

nature.

Reduced

only possible by to its syllogistic formula, Crescas'

is

proof runs as follows: Every series of possible beings must have a cause
necessary being. a series of possible beings. Therefore, the world must have a cause which

which

is

The world

is

is

necessary being. It is this proof of Crescas that Spinoza quotes, or rather paraphrases, in a letter to Meyer (Epistola XII) at the end of

lengthy refutation of the ancient arguments against infinity: "But here I should like it to be noted in passing that the more recent Peripatetics, as I at least think, mishis

understood the argument of the Ancients by which they strove to prove the existence of God. For, as I find it in the

works of a certain Jew, named Rab Ghasdai,


lows.
If there
is

it

reads as

folall

an

infinite regression of causes,

then

things which exist will be things that have been caused. But it cannot pertain to anything that has been caused that it should necessarily exist in virtue of its own nature. Therefore there
is in nature nothing to whose essence it pertains should exist necessarily. But this is absurd: and there therefore also that. 2 Therefore the force of the argument lies

that

it

not in the idea that


1

it is

impossible for the infinite actually to


first

On
The

this

form of transliteration of Crescas'

name,

original passage in the

Or Adonai^

I, iii, 2,

see below, p. 295, n. i. reads as follows: "Whether

causes and effects are finite or infinite, there is no escape from the conclusion that there must be something which is the cause of all of them as a whole, for if there

were nothing but

effects, those effects

would have only possible existence per sc and

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

197

exist, or that a regression of causes to infinity is impossible, but only in the impossibility of supposing that things which

do not

exist necessarily in virtue of their

own

nature, are not

determined to existence by something which does exist necessarily in virtue of its own nature, and which is a cause,
not an effect/*
evident that Spinoza understood well the portent and significance of Crescas' proof. He only seems to be misIt
is

taken in

its historical

background when he describes

it

as a

restoration of the original argument of the "ancients" (presumably Aristotle and his followers) which was corrupted by

the misunderstanding of the "more recent Peripatetics" (presumably the scholastics). Quite the contrary, Crescas' argument is in direct opposition to the argument of those

"ancients," though

it

may

be considered, as we have pointed

out, as a restoration of an

argument

still

more

ancient,

this cosmological proof of of possibility and necessity and Avicenna couched in terms as modified by Crescas by the elimination of the principle of

namely, that of Plato. are now going to

We

show how

the impossibility of an infinite series of causes and effects was taken up by Spinoza and remodelled into an ontological
proof.

Just as Avicenna begins his proof with a classification of being, so Spinoza begins his proof with a classification of our
ideas of being. Real beings, says Avicenna, fall, in the main, into two classes. There is one being, and one only, whose existence is necessary by his very nature; all others owe their

existence to

some external cause;


if

in

themselves they are only


is

possible; but

the cause of their existence

present they

would thus need something to cause the preponderance of their existence over their non-existence. But that which would bring about this preponderance of their existence

would be the cause of those

effects,

and that

is

what

is

meant by God."

198

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


is

[ETHICS,
if

are called necessary with reference to their cause, and

that

cause

removed they become thereby impossible. Similarly


classifies

Spinoza

our ideas of being with reference to their

reality or existence as that which is necessary by its own nature and those which by their own nature are only possible,

but become necessary by virtue of some cause from which


they follow by necessity, or become impossible when that cause is absent. To this class belong our ideas of all beings

which require a cause. Only one new class is introduced here by Spinoza, that which is impossible by its own nature, which is contrasted both with that which is necessary by
is possible by its own was not unknown to mediaeval Jewish philosophers, though Spinoza's immediate source may have been Descartes. As an illustration of an idea whose

its

own nature and with


But

that which

nature.

this class, too,

existence is necessary by its own nature Spinoza cites substance or God. A square circle is his example of an idea it is whose existence is impossible by its own nature *

only a "verbal being/' as he says elsewhere. The existence of a circle or a triangle is taken by him as a typical illustration of an idea which in itself has only possible existence and

becomes either necessary or impossible according


is

as the cause

present or absent.
closely following Avicenna.
classification of

Thus far Spinoza has been But when on the basis of this
1

our ideas of

its

own by God

Anything whose nature involves a self-contradiction is called impossible by nature and according to Jewish philosophers cannot be made possible even
in the ordinary course of nature. Cf. Maimonides, Morch Nebukim, I, 75, and Fifth Arguments, and Descartes, Meditationcs, VI (Oeuvrfs, VII, p. 71,

First
11.

18-20).
3

his note in Cogitata Metaphysica, I, I, that

Spinoza does not mention here the illustration of a chimera. Were it not for "by chimera is understood a being which

by nature involves a contradiction," one would be tempted to say that its impossibility is due only to the lack of proper causation and not to a self-contradiction in
its

nature.

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

199

God

being he attempts to construct a proof for the existence of he leaves Avicenna behind. To begin with, like Crescas,

he eliminates the impossibility of an infinite series of causes. But then he leaves Crescas, too. For Crescas still reasons
cosmologically and a posteriori, from effect to cause, from the existence of things possible to the existence of a thing
necessary. But Spinoza starts with an immediately perceived idea of a being whose existence is necessary by its own nature, the clearness and distinctness of which idea is in itself proof

and tries to resolve this immediately perceived truth into an analytical syllogism, which, as we have seen, is the main function of the ontological proof. The passage from the major premise to the conclusion is achieved, as in
for its reality,

proof and as in Anselm's proof, by showing the abof the contrary. Thus the Avicennian cosmological surdity proof as modified by Crescas is transformed by Spinoza into
his first

an ontological proof after the manner of Descartes. Reduced to its syllogistic formula, Spinoza's second proof runs as
follows:

If

we have

a clear

and
is

distinct idea of

God

as a being

whose existence

necessary by His own nature,

then God is immediately perceived by us to exist. But we have a clear and distinct idea of God as a being whose existence is necessary by His own nature.
Therefore,
exist.

God

is

immediately perceived by us to

The

basis of the ontological proof, as

we have

seen,

is

our

valid immediate perception of God's existence. This form of the proof merely shows how our valid immediate perception of

God's existence

is

implied in our clear and distinct


is

idea of

God

as a being

whose existence

necessary by His

own

nature.

200

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


THIRD AND FOURTH PROOFS

[ETHICS,

almost an anti-climax to pass from that involved and complicated second proof of Spinoza to his third and fourth
It
is

proofs which are based

upon a

single source, namely,

Des-

cartes' second proof in Meditation III. There is one phase, however, which is of interest, namely, Spinoza's endeavor to convert Descartes' proof from a cosmological argument, as it is reproduced by him in his third proof, to an ontological

argument, as he gives
seen

it

in his fourth proof.

We have already

has done it with another cosmological argusecond proof. Generally speaking, it may be said that whatever any one may attempt to prove of God demonstratively, a posteriori, can also be proved of him ontologi-

how Spinoza
in his

ment

cally, a priori, if it is assumed that the thing to be proved forms our immediate and self-evidently true idea of God. Now, in his second proof in Meditation III, Descartes takes

the attributes of creation, conservation, or power, just as in his ontological proof he takes the attribute of perfection

and argues that creation, conservation, or must imply existence no less than perfection and selfpower causality. But there is the following difference, as it is at first assumed by Descartes, between creation, conservation, or power, on the one hand, and perfection and self-causality, on the other. The latter two are immediately perceived as our very idea of God and hence they yield an ontological

and

self-causality,

proof, but the former are not immediately perceived as our very idea of God; they are derived demonstratively, a posteriori,

from His actions, and hence they yield a cosmological proof. But here Spinoza seems to argue that power, too, is immediately perceived as our idea of God, just as perfection and self-causality in the view of Descartes, and as greatness view of Anselm.

in the

Why

not then construct an ontologi-

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

201

cal

proof on the attribute of power?

This reasoning marks

the relation between the third and the fourth proofs of Spinoza. In his third proof Spinoza reproduces Descartes'

second proof of Meditation III in its original cosmological form. In his fourth proof he converts it into an ontological

between the third and fourth proofs is clearly brought out in Spinoza's own introductory words to the fourth proof: "In this last demonstration I wished to
proof.

The

relation

prove the existence of God a posteriori,

in

order that the dem-

onstration might be the more easily understood, and not because the existence of God does not follow a priori from

same grounds/' But to come to the proofs themselves. Perhaps by way of general introduction I may say what I intend to do in
the
the next few paragraphs.
I

intend to show, in the

first

place,

that Descartes' second proof in Meditation III is only a modification of the traditional proof from creation. In the

second place,
this

intend to explain

why

Descartes describes
(b)

proof either (a) as a proof

from man's existence or

as

a proof from man's conservation. In the third place, I intend to explain how it happens that this proof is restated by

Spinoza in his third proof as a proof from power. Descartes' second proof in Meditation III is described

by himself as a proof from the individual's consciousness of own existence to the existence of God. It is thus a cosmological proof, reasoning from effect to cause, and, truly speaking, it is only verbally different from the proof of
his
1

creation which, as has already been mentioned, was made use of by Plato and by Moslem and Jewish theologians as well
as

by Christian theologians. The only difference between the old proof from creation and Descartes' second proof is
2
1

Meditationcs, III (Oeuvres, VII, p. 48,

11.

f.).

John of Damascus, De Fide Orthodoxa,

I,

3, First Proof.

201

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

that the older proof argues from the existence of the world whereas Descartes argues from man's own existence or life.
1

change in the vocabulary of the proof, or rather this additional vocabulary, is already to be found in the writings of early authors. St. Augustine, for instance, in rethis

But new

producing the argument from creation, says: "And therefore, whether we consider the whole body of the world
.
. .

or whether

we consider

all life
2

...

all

can only be through


in argu-

Him who

absolutely

is."

Similarly,

Maimonides,

an eternal being in the universe, says: "Consequently nothing whatever would exist [if all things were transient]; but as we see things existing and find ouring for the existence of
selves in existence,

we conclude

there

must be an
1 '

eter-

nal being that

not subject to destruction. 3 An analogy between St. Augustine's contention that we have a conis

sciousness of our

own

existence and a similar contention by

Descartes in his discussion of the nature of the

human mind

has been pointed out by one of his objectors. 4

These quotations are

sufficient to

show that the vocabu-

lary used by Descartes in his second proof in Meditation III has grown out of the older proof from creation. But it can be further shown that there is a structural similarity between

the old argument from creation and Descartes' argument from man's consciousness of his own existence. We have
5 already shown in a previous chapter how the argument for the creation of the world started with the tentative question

Kuno
De

Fischer

designates

Descartes'
I,
i

second

proof as

"anthropological."
sive

Geschichtc der neuern Philosophic^


3

Civitate Dei, VIII, 6:

"Ac
esse
is

(3rd ed., Heidelberg, 1889), p. 308. per hoc sive universi mundi corpus

omnem
logical
*

vitam

nisi

ab

illo

the vocabulary of the argument

non posse, qui simpliciter est." This change in sometimes described as a change from a cosmoVilelo^ pp.

form to a psychological. See C. Baeumker, Moreh Nebukim^ II, i, Third Argument.


Objcctiones Quartac (Ofuvres, VII, p. 197, Cf. above, pp. 98 ff.
11.

320

ff.

4
*

24

ff.).

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD


itself or

203

whether the world came into being by


ternal cause.

Similarly, sciousness of his own existence begins with the question, "From whom do I then derive my existence? Perhaps from

by some exDescartes' proof from man's con-

myself or from my parents, or from some other source less He concludes naturally that it must perfect than God?"
r

be derived from God.


Allied with the argument from creation is the argument from the divine government or conservation of the world/ This argument, instead of reasoning from the single and com-

pleted act of creation, reasons from divine providence, that is to say, from God's guidance and governance and conser-

vation of the world.

"Conservation"

is

a mediaeval term

for the continuation of existence after the

and

it is

considered as direct an effect


itself. 4

world was created, 3 of God's causality as

This argument from divine government or conservation of the world is another form of cosmological reasoning, and it was considered as somewhat
the act of creation

even

superior to the argument from creation, for it can be used if the world is supposed to be eternal, inasmuch as

God
1

cause of
2

can be conceived as the governor of the world and the its conservation without the world necessarily hav11.

Meditationes, III (Oeuvres, VII, p. 167,

ff.).

Second Proof: "Secunda ex earum Porro ipsa quoque rerum creatarum compages, conservatione et gubernatione. conservatio, atque gubernatio, nos decent Deum esse, qui universum hoc coagmenI,

John of Damascus, De Fide Orthodoxa,

3,

tarit, sustentet, et conservet, eique provideat." In John of Damascus this proof from conservation and government is distinguished from the proof of design as well as from the proof of creation. Cf. Contra Gentiles, Lib. I, Cap. 13, end.
3

Contra Gentiles, Lib. Ill, Cap. 65: "Conservatio

rei

non

est nisi continuatio

esse ipsius."
4

See Moreh Nebukim,


exists."

1,

69:

"Here

wish to show that

God is

the cause of every

event that takes place


it

in the world, just as

He is

the creator of the whole universe as

now

have already shown, and

Again: "God, however, is himself the form of the universe, as we it is He who causes its continuance and permanency." Cf.

Ethics, I, Prop. 24, Corol.; Epistola 18 (Opera, IV, p. 82, 11. 24 ff. and 4 ff.); Epistola 20 (p. 98, 11. 15 ff. and 33 ff.); Meditationes, III (Oeuvres, VII, p. 49, 11. 5 f.).

204 ing

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


come
into existence in time.
1

[ETHICS,

Thus we find

that Descartes

proposes a change in the form of his proof from man's existence or creation by transforming it into a proof from conservation, declaring that, even if we assume that we have always existed and need no author of our existence, we still

need an author of our conservation. 2 It might therefore be said that Descartes' argument from man's existence corresponds to the argument from creation and his argument from man's conservation corresponds to the argument from
divine government.
Cartesianae^
I,

Spinoza, in his Principia Philosophiae Proposition VII, explicitly rejects the argu-

and retains only the argument from I, Proposition XI, Third Proof, however, in summarizing Descartes* second proof in Medi" tation III, he continues to use the term existence," which would seem to be a return to the "existence" form of Desexistence

ment from

conservation. Here in Ethics ^

cartes' proof. But "existence" may mean both to "come into existence" and to "continue to exist." In this proof
in the Ethics
it

may

therefore be taken in the latter sense.


it is

deduced, in mediaeval phithe attribute of power, or that possesses He is omnipotent. 3 Though wisdom and will may enter into the act of creation, still it is said that it is through "power"
the act of creation

From

losophy, that

God

that

God

creates. 4

It

is

for this reason that

Descartes speaks

of the
1

"power"

to create or to conserve,

and Spinoza

still

The

compatibility of the belief in the existence of

God with

the belief in the

eternity of the universe is assumed by Maimonides. See Moreh Nebukim^ I, 76, Sixth Argument: "But he seems to forget that we are at issue with those who,

whilst they believe in the existence of God, admit at the same time the eternity of the universe."
2

MeditationeS) III (Oeuvres, VII, p. 49,

11.

12

ff.).

Emunot
Ibid.

we-De'ot, II, 4; Cuzari, V, 18, 7-9. Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa I'heologica, Pars

I,

Quaest. 9, Art. 2:
.
.

sed per antequam essent, non erant possibiles esse solam potentiam divinam, in quantum Deus poterat eas in esse producere."
creaturae,
.

"Omnes enim

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

205

more

explicitly says: "posse Proposition XI, Third Proof), and he also speaks of "potentia conservandi" (Prin. Phil. Cart. y I, Prop. VII, Lemma II).

existere potentia est" (Ethics , I,

Descartes* second argument

may

therefore be referred to, as

indeed Spinoza does seem to refer to it, as the argument from power, and it may be considered as one of the variations
of the mediaeval arguments from creation or divine govern-

ment.

Reduced

to its syllogistic formula, Descartes' second arin his third

gument
proof

in

may

Meditation III as restated by Spinoza be given as follows:


in its existence

Everything that continues


a cause.

must have

and the world continue in our existence. Therefore, we and the world must have a cause.
This syllogistic form
Principia.
is

We

clearly brought out in Spinoza's

In the Ethics

it is

somewhat obscured, owing

to

Spinoza's predilection for indirect

proof of the reductio ad

absurdum type of argument. But it can be easily brought into accord with the argument employed in the Principia. It is an a posteriori cosmological argument, pure and simple, different from the arguments from creation or only verbally
,

government.

The proof in the form in which be fully unfolded as follows:

it is

given in the Ethics

may

We

have the idea of the existence of ourselves as

finite

beings and we also have the idea of the existence of God as an infinite being. There are three possibilities as to the truth of these ideas.
First, they are both false,

and therefore

"

nothing exists."
is

Second, only the idea of our own existence


1

true,

and

"Ergo

vel nihil existit."

206 "
therefore,

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


there
is
x

[ETHICS,

nothing which necessarily exists except-

ing things finite/* Third, both ideas are true, and therefore a "being abso2 lutely infinite also necessarily exists/' The first of these possibilities is to be rejected, for

"we

ourselves exist/'

The second
there
is

possibility

is

to be rejected, for "if, therefore,


exists excepting things

nothing which necessarily


follows that things finite are
infinite

finite, it

more powerful than the


(as
is

absolutely

being, and

this

self-evident)

is

argument is to be understood argument against our being ourselves the authors of our existence. Descartes' argument originally is that if we were ourselves the authors of our existence we should have endowed ourselves with every perfection of which we possessed any idea and which we include
absurd/'
force of this
in the light of Descartes' in

The

in the

our idea of God. Spinoza presents here the same argument form of a reductio ad absurdum. He proceeds as folIf

we must we must be the authors of our own existence. Therefore, the idea we have of our own existence is more powerful than the idea we have of God's
lows:

we

exist

and God does not


s

exist,

then

exist "in ourselves,"

that

is

to say,

existence,

inasmuch as "inability to

exist

is

impotence, and,

on the other hand, ability to exist is power." 6 But we have set out with the assumption that we have an idea of God as
as infinite being

and of ourselves

as finite beings.

Hence, a

self-contradiction.
1

2 3
4

id, quod jam necessario existit, non nisi cntia "Vel Ens absolute infinitum necessario etiam existit."

"Si itaque

finita sunt."

"Atqui nos
"Si itaque
est."

existimus."

entia finita

quod jam necessario existit, non nisi entia finita sunt, sunt ergo potentiora Ente absolute infinite: atque hoc (ut per se notuni) absurid,

dum
5

"Atqui nos, vel in nobis, vel in alio, quod necessario existit, existimus." "Posse non existere impotentia est, et contra posse existere potentia est."

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

207

Consequently, the third possibility must be true, and " therefore the being absolutely infinite, that is to say, God,
necessarily exists/'
x

So much

for Spinoza's third proof.

We

shall turn

now

to

his fourth proof.

Suppose we say that our clear and distinct idea of God


that of a being of the highest power, i.e., of the highest power to create or to conserve, just as Anselm said that it
is is

said that

the idea of the greatest being and as Descartes himself it is the idea of the most perfect being or of a self-

caused being. We should then be able to frame an ontological proof from the idea of God as the cause of existence or
conservation. Descartes himself has already performed this conversion of his second proof into an ontological proof from
siones:
in the following passage in his Primae Respon"Further, because we cannot think of God's existence as being possible, without at the same time, and by

"power"
2

He

taking heed of His immeasurable power, acknowledging that can exist by His own might, we hence conclude that He

really exists

of nature

and has existed from all eternity; for the light makes it most plain that what can exist by its own
exists.
is

power always

And

thus

we

shall

understand that

being of the highest power, not by any intellectual fiction, but because it belongs to the true and immutable nature of that being to necessary existence

comprised

in the idea of a

exist."

Descartes thus has three forms of the ontological


the idea of a most perfect being. the idea of a self-caused being. the idea of a most powerful being.
is

proof:
1.

2.

3.

From From From

What
1

Spinoza

really trying to

do

in his fourth

proof

is

"Ergo ens absolute

infinitum, hoc est (per Defin. 6.)


11.

Deum,

necessario existit."

Oeuvrcs, VII, p. 119,

11

ff.

208

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

simply to reproduce the third form of Descartes' ontological


proof.

Reduced
follows:
If

to a syllogism, Spinoza's fourth

proof runs as

we have

a clear

and

distinct idea of

God

as a being

of the highest power, then ceived by us to exist.

God

is

immediately per-

But we have a
Therefore,
exist.

clear

and

distinct idea of

God

as a be-

ing of the highest power.

God

is

immediately perceived by us to

Here, again, the proof merely shows how our valid immediate perception of God's existence is implied in our clear and distinct idea of God as a being of the highest power.

The
valid

basis of the ontological proof, as

we have

said,

is

this

immediate perception of God's existence. There remains now only the last part of the Scholium of Proposition XI to be explained, the part which contains a
provisional objection quoted in the name of "many persons*' against "this demonstration." In order to simplify the discussion of this part of the Scholium, we shall preface it by
a few general remarks. First, the demonstration of which Spinoza says here that its force may not be easily grasped by many persons refers
to the third proof and not to the fourth proof given at the beginning of the Scholium. It will have been noticed that

the fourth proof is not given by Spinoza as an independent proof but as a Scholium to the third proof. And so when he

says in that Scholium that "many persons, nevertheless, will perhaps not be able easily to see the force of this demonstration," the reference
is

to the third proof.

is

Second, the provisional objection raised in the Scholium to be read in the light of Spinoza's discussion in his Scho-

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THK EXISTENCE OF GOD


VII
in

209

Hum

to Proposition
I.

Principia Philosophiae Carte-

sianae,

Third, the answer to this provisional objection is to be read in the light of Spinoza's Demonstration of Lemma I of the same Proposition in his Principia. In the chojium to Proposition VII in the Principia y Spinoza discusses Descartes' distinction between "difficult"
(difficile)

and "easy"

(facile)

creation or conservation.

He

interprets these terms as referring to the production of "more perfect" (perfectius) and "less perfect" (imperfectius) things respectively. In this Scholium to Proposition XI here in

the Ethics Spinoza reproduces the same distinction, explaining the expression "more difficult to produce" (factu difficiliores) as referring to

attributes pertain."

that "to which they conceive more By the same token we may say that
the production of that to which they may thus further con-

"easy" production

is

We perceive clude that by his distinction between "more difficult" and "easy" production here Spinoza again means, as in the Principia^ the distinction between the production of the "more
less attributes pertain.

perfect" and the production of the "less perfect."

With
sons"

this distinction in view, says Spinoza,

"many

per-

third proof, it will be recalled, starts with the hypothesis that we have two ideas, one of God as an infinite being and another of man as

will try to refute the third proof.

The

God

a finite being, and proceeds to argue that if man exists and does not exist it will be contrary to the hypothesis. But these "many persons" will say, contends Spinoza, that the

distinction between

God and man

as infinite

and

finite

means

a distinction between infinite perfection and finite perfection or between having an infinite number and a finite num-

ber of properties. But it has just been said that the difference between the "more perfect" and the "less perfect" corre-

2io

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

spends respectively to the difference between "difficult" existence or production and "easy" existence or production. Accordingly, the existence denied of God and the existence

man are of two different kinds entirely, one being "difficult" existence and the other being "easy" infinitely existence. To deny therefore infinitely difficult existence of
affirmed of

God while affirming easy existence of man does not imply a contradiction of our idea of God as an infinite or most perfect
being. Quite the contrary, it is because we conceive of God as an infinite and most perfect being that His existence be-

comes

infinitely

difficult,

and hence He does not

exist,

whereas man, being conceived as finite and imperfect, thereby has existence which is easy, and hence he does exist.
Spinoza could have put into the mouth of these "many persons" the following illustration. Suppose we have two

one of our possessing a million dollars and the other of our possessing one dollar. The first idea is more perfect
ideas,

than the second, inasmuch as more attributes or properties pertain to it. But because the idea of having a million dollars is more perfect their existence is more difficult and consequently they do not exist in our pocket, whereas the idea of having one dollar is less perfect; therefore its existence is

easy and

it

does exist in our pocket.


provisional objection
tentatively raised in

To

this

the

name of "many persons" Spinoza answers by


l

recalling his

old distinction between things "which are produced by external causes" and things "which can be produced by no external cause." Of the former, he argues, it is indeed true
to say that the greater the perfection the more difficult its existence and the smaller the perfection the easier the existence.

Hence the idea of a

million dollars has less possi-

bility of existence than that of one dollar, for the perfection


1

Ethics,
I,

I,

Prop. II, Schol.


i.

Cf. Principia Philosophiae Cartesianac^

I,

Prop. 7,

Lemma

Nota

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD


is

211

as well as the existence of a million dollars

not intrinsic.

The

perfections of beings dependent upon external causes are themselves external perfections, and the more of them there

are the

upon
those

external causes.
things

more dependent the existence of the beings becomes "For whatever perfection or reality

may have which

are produced

by external

causes, whether they consist of many parts or of few, they owe it all to the virtue of an external cause, and therefore
their existence springs

cause alone and not from their own."

from the perfection of an external But if you have an


x

out of

idea of anything with a set of internal perfections, growing its own nature, then the possibility of its existence in-

if

creases in proportion to the number of perfections, so that we get an idea of an infinitely perfect being its existence

becomes absolutely necessary. "In an idea or concept of everything, existence either as possible or as necessary is contained." 2 "For, as we cannot affirm existence of nothing, as

we

content to approach zero as

detract from the perfection of a concept and conceive its its limit, so much do we detract

from its possible existence. If we conceive this degree of perfection to be infinitely diminished, even to zero, it will con-

no existence, or but an absolutely impossible one. On the other hand, if we increase this degree of perfection to
tain
infinity

we conceive

that

it

and so

to be absolutely necessary."

has the highest possible existence 3 This kind of internal

perfection which grows out of the nature of things, as distinguished from external "marks of perfection which men

from ignorance and tradition are accustomed to esteem as such," 4 is to be understood only as "so much reality or
being."
infinite
1

God, therefore, who is conceived as having an number of perfections growing out of His own nature,
s

Ethics, I, Prop. 11, Schol.

Principia Philosophiac Cartesianac,

I,

Axiom
3 *

6.

Cf. Prop. 7,

onst.

Ibid.) Prop. 7,
//</.

Lemma I, DemLemma I, Demonst.

Hid.) Prop.

7,

Lemma

I,

Nota

2.

212

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


1

[ETHICS,

has the most reality and being. You cannot argue, as would those "many persons/' that because God is infinitely perfect

His existence
exist.

is

infinitely difficult,

and hence

He

does not

Only external perfections may be said to increase the difficulty of existence; internal perfections, on the contrary,

increase the possibility of existence. Such internal "perfection consequently does not prevent the existence of a
thing, but establishes
it;

imperfection, on the other hand,

prevents existence, and so of no existence can we be more sure than of the existence of the Being absolutely infinite or
perfect, that
is

to say,

God."

To sum up our main conclusions: Historically there were two kinds of proofs for the existence of God, based upon two kinds of knowledge, indirect and direct. The indirect kind
of knowledge gave us the various cosmological and teleological proofs. The direct kind of knowledge gave us the proofs

based upon revelation, the innateness of the idea of God, and universal assent. The ontological proof as stated by Anselm, Descartes, and Spinoza is not an independent proof.
It
is

only a different

way

upon
the

direct knowledge.

of formulating the old proofs based In Anselm, it is a modified form of


assent.

argument from universal


it is

In

Descartes and
in-

Spinoza

a modified form of the

argument from the

nateness of the idea of God.

Of the

in the Ethics , the first

four proofs for the existence of God given by Spinoza and third correspond respectively to

Descartes' ontological proof in Meditation V and his cosmological proof in the second proof of Meditation III. Descartes' first proof in Meditation III is not reproduced

by Spinoza
and
1

in the Ethics,

but

is

reproduced by him

in the

Short Treatise and in his Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae,


is

referred to in his correspondence


I,

and

in

De

Intellectus

Cf. Ethics ,

Prop.

9.

Ethics,

I,

Prop,

u,

Schol.

PROP, ii]

PROOFS OF THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

213

Emendatione
is

"Tractatus. Spinoza's second proof in the Ethics a modification of Descartes' ontological proof in Meditation V, enriched by elements borrowed from a cosmological
in

proof

Hebrew
is

in the Ethics

philosophic sources. Spinoza's fourth proof the conversion of his third proof, which is

cosmological, into ontological form, which conversion


also

was

made by Descartes himself. The idea of God which is assumed


is

in the ontological in

proof

to imply existence

differently phrased
it is

the different

forms of the proof.

In Anselm,

being. In Descartes, it is or of a self-caused being, or of the most powerful being. the first ^ second and Spinoza's three ontological proofs
',

the idea of the greatest the idea of the most perfect being,

make use of three descriptions fourth proofs in the Ethics which may be reduced to two. In the first proof, the idea of God is that of a being whose essence involves existence.
In the second proof,
it is

that of a being whose existence

is

necessary per

se.

These two can be reduced to what Des-

cartes described as a self-caused being. In the fourth proof, it is the idea of a being who is most powerful. This difference

terminology, however, is only verbal. Any other term, such, for instance, as the most real being (ens realissimum), can be used, if it is assumed to be that which is immediately
in

perceived of God, without introducing anything new in the ontological proof. The recurrent claims for the discovery of

new
meet

ontological proofs for the existence of


in

God which we
upon
analysis,

philosophic literature generally prove,

nothing but the substitution of some new terms for such older terms as the greatest, the most perfect, the selfto be

caused, and the most powerful. Oftentimes, these so-called newly discovered ontological proofs are not even ontological,

but rather disguised cosmological proofs.

CHAPTER

VII

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT


I.

THE FRAMEWORK OF

SPINOZA'S UNIVERSE

IN OUR analysis of the Ethics so far we have found that of the first thirteen propositions twelve deal with the traditional

problem of the nature of God, which we have discussed in the chapters on the definition, unity, and simplicity of sub-

and one proposition deals with the proofs of the exGod. The remaining propositions of the First Part of the Ethics similarly deal with a problem which in traditional philosophy would go under the title of the relation of
stance,
istence of
to the world. Spinoza starts out in Proposition XIV with a recapitulation of his denial, both in Short Treatise, I, 2, and in Propositions II-VI in the First Part of the Ethics,

God

of the fundamental belief of

all

mediaeval philosophers that

between God and the world there is a distinction of pure form and matter, the two constituting, as it were, two substances. "Besides God," he therefore maintains, "no substance can be nor can be conceived" (Prop. XIV). His demonstration of this proposition is again a summary of

what he has already

said in the Short 'Treatise,

I, 2,

and

in

Propositions II-VI, namely, if the world were of a nature absolutely distinct from that of God, all the difficulties which the mediaevals themselves had pointed out against the

assumption of the existence of two deities or against the assumption of the emanation of a material world out of an
*

immaterial cause by
2

the

ordinary process of necessary

causality
1

would recur and would be unanswerable (Dem2

Cf. above, p. 83.

Cf. above, p. 88.

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT

215

onst.).

He

the nature of the universe, including matter, which

thus concludes that there cannot be anything in is not in

God

himself,

who

according to

all

sole cause of the universe.

"Hence
is

traditional opinions is the it follows with the greatis

est clearness, firstly, that


in

God

one, that

to say (Def. VI),


I).

nature there
1

is

but one substance" (Corol.


to

But

this

" "is absolutely infinite (ibid.), and therefore cannot be fully known by the finite intellect. 2 It is only the in-

one substance or God, again according

all

traditional

opinions,

finite intellect (infinitus intellectus)* i.e., the infinite intellect

of

God

(infinitus

Dei

intellectus) f that

can perceive every-

thing which pertains


its infinite

one substance, that is to say, attributes. The finite "human mind can only get
to this
s

to

know

those things which the idea of an actually existing

body involves, or what can be inferred from this idea." But inasmuch as "this idea of the body neither involves nor expresses any other attributes of God than extension and 6 thought," it follows that the human mind knows God "in
so far only as

tension"
so far as

He is considered under the attribute of exand "under the attribute of thought, and not in He is considered under any other attribute." 8 And
7

so, just as his discussion of the impossibility

of two substances

in the Short 'Treatise culminates in the

statement "that we

9 posit extension as an attribute of God," so also here Spinoza concludes with the statement that "it follows, secondly,

that the thing extended and the thing thinking are either attributes of God or affections of the attributes of God"
(Corol. II).
1

Cf. above, p. 117.

Cf. above, p. 142.


1.

Ethics, II, Prop. 7, Schol. (Opera, II, p. 90,

4).

Epistola 66 (Opera, IV, p. 280,


*

11. 11.

8-9).

Epistola 64 (Opera, IV, p. 277,


Ibid.
Ibid.
(11.

10-13).
i

6
8

18-19).

Ibid.

(11.

28-29).

(11. 23-24). Short Treatise, I, 2,

18.

21 6

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


last expression,
is

[ETHICS,

The
God,"

a reference to the

"or affections of the attributes of modal system of extension and

thought, which Spinoza describes most fully and clearly in 2 the Short treatise T and his correspondence with Schuller. The full scheme of Spinoza's system of extension and thought

may

be pieced together from these two main sources.


it
is

In

its

bare outline

as follows:

There

is,

to begin with, sub-

stance or

God

with infinite attributes.

Of

these only two

and thought. From these attributes there follows a series of modes, to wit, (i) immediate infinite modes, (2) a mediate infinite mode, and (3)
attributes are

known

to us, extension

finite

modes.

Of

extension, the immediate infinite

mode

is

motion-and-rest; of thought, the immediate infinite mode is the absolutely infinite intellect (intellectus absolute infini-

Only one mediate infinite mode is specifically named by Spinoza, and that is the face of the whole universe (fades totius universi). He does not make it clear, however, whether
tus).
it is

mode

of extension or of thought or of both.

The

finite

modes are the particular things (res particulares}. Substance and its attributes are called by Spinoza natura naturans^ the entire modal system of extension and thought is called by him natura naturata^ and within the latter he distinguishes
between the two
classes of infinite

modes, which he

calls

"general," and the single class of finite modes, which he calls


"particular." As a skeleton framework to hold together and to unify the fragmentary pieces of the visible universe, this scheme of

one of the stages, an advanced stage, to be sure, in the long development of similar schemes since man began to distinguish between the visible and the invisible and to discern behind phenomenal sporadic changes
Spinoza
is

to be regarded as

Ibid. y

1,

8-9.

Epistolae 63-64.

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT

217

and a certain causal connection. Any attempt to interpret this scheme of Spinoza as an adumbration of any specific theories of modern science is justifiable in the same sense as the Stoics were justified in transforming the gods and goddesses of Olympia into the natural forces and moral
a certain unity
principles of their

own

philosophy, or as Philo and the medi-

aeval Jewish, Christian, and


fied in investing the

Moslem

God and

theologians were justiof the Bible with signifangels

icances of their

own
all

philosophic principles.

There

is

indeed

a justification in

such attempts at allegorical methods of

interpretation, whether applied to Homer, the Bible, or the works of Spinoza, but only in so far as they are confined to

an effort to show that all these systems of myths, religion, and philosophy were inspired by a common striving to see the universe as a whole and to interpret it as a unit, and how in reaching out for the truth they almost attained it. But the allegorical method of interpretation becomes a perversion of truth when confused with the method of historical research.

The

first

step in understanding any author

is

to find

out what he means by what he says and how he came to say it in a certain particular manner. In Spinoza's skeleton
ditional philosophy,

framework of the universe, the terms used are those of traand the concepts represented by these

terms, as well as the connection between them, are likewise reminiscent of skeleton frameworks of the universe invented

happen to know also that philosothe ages have come to whatever new views phers throughout they have happened to arrive at as a result of criticism of

by

his predecessors.

We

older views and a modification of the views criticized by have already seen how Spinoza's propositions in them.

We

the Ethics so far can be best explained as a criticism and modification of his mediaeval philosophic background.

We

shall therefore try to

show how the

entire

scheme of Spinoza's

21 8

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

theory of extension and thought has grown out of a typical scheme held by mediaeval philosophers.

The mediaeval

skeleton framework of the universe in


its finer

its

bare outline and without any discussion of points starts out, like that of Spinoza, with
finite in

subtle
is

God who

in-

His perfections; but unlike Spinoza's, it assumes God to be pure form, whose sole activity is thinking. The product of God's thinking is an Intelligence, which is likewise pure
form and the activity of which
Intelligence,
is

likewise thinking.

But

this

owing on the one hand, necessary of existence, for it is the inevitable product of divine thinking, and, on the other hand, only
possible of existence, for

to the dual aspect of its existence, being,

by

its

own nature and without

cause
ity in

it

could not have come into being, contains also a dualits nature, the duality of necessity and possibility.

Out of

the necessary element in its nature there emanates another Intelligence, which is again pure form and the activity of which is again thinking; but out of its possible

element there proceeds a sphere which is material and the activity of which is motion. As the astronomy of the Middle

Ages posited a plurality of such concentric celestial spheres, the number of which varied according to different views but
generally spoken of as nine, the process is repeated until we come to the last in the series of the concentric spheres,
is
1

the so-called lunar sphere, and to the last in the series of the Intelligences, generally spoken of as the Tenth or Active
Intelligence.

others, has in
sity.

This so-called Tenth Intelligence, like all the its nature the duality of possibility and necesits

Out of

possibility there arises the underlying genis

eral

matter which

common
is

to all the sublunar things

and

the nature of which

pure possibility
their

and

Then by
1

the motion of the spheres


II, 4.

common

potentiality. circular

Cf.

Moreh Nebukim,

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT

219

motion as well as the particular variations in their common circular motion this common underlying matter is predisposed for the assumption of the general as well as the particular forms by which the simple elements and the compound
things are differentiated

among themselves from each

other.

The forms themselves

from the primary forms of the four elements to souls and minds, which are also called forms

flow from the activity of the Tenth Intelligence, 1 which means that they ultimately flow from God.

Thus, according to this scheme, the entire universe divided into matter and form. These two exist together
matter

is

in

the physical part of the universe, but form exists apart from 2 in the world of the Intelligences and in God. While on the whole matter owes its existence to God as its ultimate

does not come directly from God, inasmuch as God is pure form, and by a mediaeval principle, which may be formulated as omne materiale e materially matter cannot arise
cause,
it

from form. Matter


tion at a stage for by what

arises somewhere in the process of emanaremoved from God, and its origin is accounted I have described elsewhere as "emergent

emanation/'
derived his

In order to simplify the process of showing how Spinoza own scheme from the mediaeval scheme, it is necessary for us to separate in the latter its essential from its
non-essential elements.
is
1

The

essential element in the

the main philosophic thesis that


The most obvious
this

God

is

scheme form and pure

sources from which Spinoza could have derived his knowlmediaeval scheme are Moreh Nebukim^ I, 72; II, 4; and Shem-Tob's commentary on Moreh Nebukim y II, 13.

edge of
2

For a difference of opinion, however, with regard

to the immateriality of the

Intelligences, see below, p. 223.


* Cf. my paper, "The Problem of the Origin of Matter in Mediaeval Jewish Philosophy and Its Analogy to the Modern Problem of the Origin of Life," in Pro-

ceedings of the Sixth International Congress of Philosophy , p. 602. * Cf. ibid., pp. 603-604.

220

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


the material

[ETHICS,

hence

directly.

The

universe did not proceed from Him non-essential elements are the assumptions

which happened

to be part of the mediaeval scientific conof the universe, namely, the theory of celestial ception spheres, the theory of the plurality of Intelligences, and the

theory that the universe was finite in extent, being enclosed within an all-surrounding sphere. They were, however, not essential to the scheme itself. The non-essential character
of these scientific assumptions in the mediaeval scheme is attested by the fact that in the history of philosophy, even
before Spinoza, they had been eliminated or modified one by one without affecting the main philosophic thesis of the immateriality of God. The theory of the finite extent of the

was an Aristotelian heritage in the history of philosophy, was attacked by Crescas at the beginning of the fifteenth century, as it was again attacked by Bruno about two centuries later, so that by the time of Spinoza the infinity of the universe was already treated as a philouniverse, which
* 2

sophic commonplace. The theory of celestial spheres was eliminated from consideration in respectable scientific circles with the fall of the Ptolemaic astronomy in the sixteenth century, and even before that time two important features of that theory, namely, the difference between the matter and
the motion of the celestial bodies and those of terrestrial

had been disposed of by Crescas. 3 With the elimination of the celestial spheres there would necessarily have
bodies,
to follow the elimination of the plurality of the Intelligences,
for the

val view

number of the Intelligences, according to the mediae4 itself, was determined by the number of the spheres.
one Intelligence of pure form would have to remain

But
1

still

Cf. my Crescas' Critique of Aristotle, pp. 115-117. 3 Cf. Cf. ibid., pp. 115, ii 8. ibid., pp. 118-120.

<

Cf.

Moreh Nebukim,

II, 4.

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT


main
thesis of

221

for as long as the

God

and

for as long as the origin of the material world

as pure form remained was ex-

plained not as an act of special creation out of nothing but as a process of emanation out of the substance of God. Thus
sories

the mediaeval scheme, stripped of its non-essential accesand modified to fit the new scientific conceptions of the universe,

Spinoza as follows: There


activity
is

must have presented itself to the mind of is God, a pure form, whose sole

The product of God's thought is an which is also pure form, but in the nature of Intelligence, which there is a duality of necessity and possibility. Out of
thinking.
this Intelligence

emanates the physical universe,

its

matter

out of the possibility of the Intelligence's nature, and its form, motion, and thought out of the necessity of the Intelligence's nature.
It is this

main

thesis,

which on the whole had survived

all

the changing conceptions of the universe up to the time of Spinoza and from which the intermediary Intelligence was

eliminated only whenever emanation gave place, as, for instance, in the case of Descartes, to a special act of creation

out of nothing, that Spinoza constantly and repeatedly makes the subject of a frontal attack. 1 He does not dwell on the
absurdity of the mediaeval theories of celestial spheres or on the plurality of Intelligences, for these were already dead issues in his own time and were not essential, as we have
seen, to the

main

thesis.

He

does indeed discuss the problem

of infinity, but not especially with reference to the infinite

extent of the universe, but with reference to certain general aspects of the problem which were still vital issues in his own
it only in a letter in which he answers a addressed to him and in a scholium to a proposiquestion tion in which he refutes some unnamed opponents. 2 The

time,

and he does

Cf. above,

Chapter IV.

Cf. below,

Chapter VIII.

222

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


thesis,

[ETHICS,

main

attacked by him directly. He shows that if God is pure form, then the interposition of another form between God and the universe will not remove the diffi-

however,

is

culty of how matter could arise from form by the ordinary 1 process of necessary causality. As an escape from this diffi-

culty he takes the bold step of

making the material universe

proceed by necessity directly from God, with the inevitable consequence that God himself becomes material, or, to use

own terms, extension becomes an attribute of God. In a letter to Oldenburg Spinoza seems to allude to this method of reasoning leading to his conclusion with regard to extension when he says: "And, on the other hand, things which
his

they [the theologians], on account of their prejudices, regard as created, I contend to be attributes of God, and as misunderstood by them/' 2 The conclusion arrived at by Spinoza that God was material is not new in the history of philosophy. The most
notable exponents of this view in European philosophy are the Stoics, who may have perhaps arrived at their materialism, like Spinoza, as a result of a criticism of the Platonic and Aristotelian dualism. 3 Though the Stoic view was not

unknown to mediaeval Jewish philosophers, for in a work written in Arabic by an unknown Jewish or Moslem author and preserved in a Hebrew translation it is quoted in the

name

of Zeno,

i.e.,

Zeno of Citium, 4

still

ever attempted to bridge the gulf between

none of them had God and the

world by endowing God with materiality. Ibn Gabirol's Fons Vitae, to be sure, is said to have given rise to such a
Cf. above, p. 91. Epistola 6 (Opera, IV, p. 36, 11. 21-23). This explanation for the Stoic materialism has been suggested by Zeller, but Cf. Zeller, Philosophic der Gricchcn, III, i (4th edition), rejected by him.
3 *
ff. English translation: Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics, pp. 127 ff. See David Kaufmann, Die Spurtn Al-Batlaj&si's in der jiidischen Religions 1

is

pp. 125

Philosophic (Budapest, 1880).

Hebrew Text,

p. 36,

11.

10

ff.

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT


David of Dinant, but
1

223

view

in

representation of the real goes only so far as to assert, as do also


3

from being a true view of Ibn Gabirol. Ibn Gabirol


this is far

Bahya Ibn Pakuda

is

and Judah ha-Levi, that the distinction of matter and form also to be found in the Intelligences or angels, a view

which was taken over from him by Duns Scotus and his followers and maintained by them against Thomas Aquinas.

Leo Hebraeus

refers to this

view and ascribes

it

to

Plato. 4
free

himself, even according to Ibn Gabirol, was of matter. Crescas, to be sure, comes near attributing

God

extension to

God when,
it

after defining space as extension

and assuming
in

to be infinite

and the world to be

in

it,

he

support of his view the old rabbinic dictum that quotes God is the place of the world. 5 Logically, if God is the place
of the world and the place of the world is extension, God must have extension as one of His attributes. But Crescas
stops short of drawing this daring conclusion. God still continues to be to him pure form, and in the problem of creation, in order to bridge the gulf

between the immaterial God

and the material world, he has to resort to the solution of endowing God with will and purpose and design. It is said that in Bruno there is an intimation that extension is one
of God's attributes, 6 but if this really represents Bruno's reasoned-out view, then to say of Bruno, as does Pollock,
Cf. Erdmann, Grnndriss der Geschichte der Philosophic, 192 and 188. But according to Albertus Magnus, David of Dinant's view that God is "principium ma" was due to the influence of Alexander of Aphrodisias: "Alexander teriale omnium etiam in quodam libello quern fecit de Principio incorporeae et corporeae subslantiae,
1

quern secutus est quidam David de Dinanto in libro quern scripsit de TOOT/J, hoc est, de divisionibus, dicit Deum esse principium materiale omnium" (Summa Theologiae,
2

Pars

I,

Tract. IV, Quaest. 20,


I, 6.

Membrum

2,

Quaestio Incidens).
1

Hobot ha-Lebabot,
Cuzari, IV, 3.

* 4

Cf. commentaries

Jol Yehudah and Ozar Nehmad on V,

8, 6.
is

Dialoghi a" //more, III, p. 244 (Bari, 1929).


s

Cf. p. 246, where Avicebron

referred to.
6

Cf.

my
la

Crescas' Critique of Aristotle, p. 123.


11.

Pollock, Spinoza, p. 104. Cf.

De

Causa, III, p. 261,

14-18 (ed. Lagarde).

224

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


"he rejects the notion of formless matter"
his view.
x

[ETHICS,
is

that

wrong emphasis on
is

What

put the should have been said


to

that he rejects the notion of matterless form. Clearer than all these intimations as to an extended God is the statein a letter to

ment made by Henry More


reads:

Descartes, which

an extended thing/' 2 Spinoza, however, did not come to his view by merely adopting the statements of the Stoics or of Bruno or of More,
to be

"God seems

or by merely carrying out to its logical conclusion the hint thrown out by Crescas. He had been forced to it, as we have

shown and as

in a

previous chapter, by the logic of the situation a result of his thorough and critical examination of

the various mediaeval solutions of the problem of the rise

of matter out of an immaterial God. Finding all the solutions of this difficulty under the theory of emanation unsatisfactory, and refusing to resort to the theory of creation ex nihilo or to the theory of the co-existence of an eternal matter alongside God, he was forced to the conclusion that God

was not immaterial.

II.

PROPERTIES, ATTRIBUTES, AND

MODES

We have thus seen how the main outline of Spinoza's skeleton framework has developed out of the mediaeval framework. We shall now try to show in a similar manner
the development of the individual parts within that framework the infinity of God's attributes, the two known
attributes of extension

and thought, and the modal system

under the two known attributes.


'

Ibid.

Descartes, Correspondance, DXXXI (Oeuvres, V, p. 238, 1. 21): "Res enim extensa Deus videtur esse." Cf. Dunin-Borkowski, Der jungc DC Spinoza, pp.
2

359
*

Cf. above,

Chapter IV.

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT

225

infinity of God's attributes is implied throughout the mediaeval discussions of the nature of God, especially in the
1 oft-repeated statement that God is indescribable. A close and almost verbal resemblance to Spinoza's statement as to the infinity of attributes is to be found in Crescas, who, in

The

discussing a certain Talmudic passage in which the excessive enumeration of divine attributes is discouraged, explains it on the ground that such an enumeration "would appear as an
2 His attempt to limit that which is infinite in number.'* Albo puts it still more directly when he says: pupil Joseph "It must be understood that the perfections which exist in

God are unlimited in number, that is to say, they are infinite with reference to their plurality." 3 The term "perfection" is used here by Albo as synonymous with "attribute." With
these mediaeval thinkers, to

separate from the world and to

whom God was immaterial and whom the attributes were

it was only logical that should insist not only upon the infinite degree of perthey fection of each attribute but also upon the infinite number

expressions of divine perfections,

of attributes. For them to say that God possessed an infinite number of attributes meant nothing more than to say that

God's powers and perfections were inexhaustible.


world,
if

But with the gradual disappearance of the separation of God and the

not their complete identification, in the Renaissance philosophy, as for instance in the philosophy of Bruno, and with the general acceptance in opposition to Aristotle of the
belief in

an

infinite

number of

finite attributes to

God

worlds, the ascription of innaturally assumed a new meaning.


it

To

the minds of

some people

of the existence of an infinite


1

must have conveyed the idea number of independent worlds.

Cf. Moreh Nebukim, I, 59. Or Adonai) I, iii, 3 (p. 24a).

'Ibkarim, II, 25.

Cf. above, p. 117.

226

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


"

[ETHICS,

Thus
God."
his

be constituted as
x

there must Schuller asks of Spinoza whether or not many worlds as there are attributes of

Spinoza tries to set him aright on this point. In answer to Schuller, 2 where reference is made to the SchoII,

lium to Proposition VII, Part


clear that

and
3

in other places

where

the infinite attributes are discussed, Spinoza makes it quite by infinite attributes he does not mean an infinite

number of independent

worlds, but rather an infinite

number

of aspects of one single infinite universe, analogous to the mediaeval conception of the infinite attributes of God.

The
to us.

God, however, are not known some of them we are able to affirm of God, and Only
infinite attributes of

even these, according to the mediaevals, do not tell us anything about the true essence of God. They are only inadequate terms by which we express the various ways in which

God

attributes

manifests himself through nature. The selection of which are admissible of God constitutes one

phase of the problem of attributes in mediaeval Jewish philosophy, and various lists have been drawn up by various
philosophers.

Saadia

enumerates
s

edge. Bahya Ibn Pakuda Ibn Zaddik's 6 eternity.


7

life, power, and knowlmentions existence, unity, and

existence, power, knowledge, abundance, justice, goodness, mercifulness, life,


truth.

list

contains

Judah ha-Levi, dividing attributes into actional, relational, and negational, mentions under them respectively the following groups: (a) making poor and rich, casting
1

Epistola 63. Cf. Short Treatise,

I, i,

Emunot
s

we-De'ot, II,
y

Epistola 64. note 3 (Opera, I, p. 17, 11. 33 4: Q3P1 ,^1D' ,'["!.


8,

ff.).

Hobot ha-Lebabot I, 10: lIDlp ,1R ,NM. 'Olam Katan, III (pp. 57 ff.): ,]Dm ,3'BD ,pH2C
,'n.

,T0y

,DZ>n ,1133

,rMOXD
(a)

DDK
7

Cuzari, II,

i:

,Dp131
(f)

top /JOTI
;

Dim
,

,00110 *]K ^DtfO ,T0yD1 BP11D

rriN ,'n

NIWI

01

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT

227

down and

exalting, merciful and gracious, jealous and revengeful, strong, almighty; (b) blessed and praised, glorified, holy, exalted and extolled; (c) living, one, first and last.

Abraham Ibn Daud mentions eight:


*

unity, truth, existence,

eternity,

"We
may
made
to

knowledge, will, and power, but concludes: do not contend that there are no other attributes which
life,

be similarly affirmed of God, provided only that it be clear that they are to be understood in such a way as

2 Descartes likewise imply no plurality in His essence/' enumerates a similar list of attributes "in so far as they may

the light of nature alone/' 3 His list mentions eternal, omniscient, omnipotent, the source of all goodness

be

known by

and

truth, creator of

all

things,

and

infinite perfection.

attributes of
call

Spinoza does not altogether disregard these traditional God. But they are not to him what he would

"the proper attributes of

God"

in the specific sense in

which he uses the term "attribute," namely, "that which


sence."
the intellect perceives of substance, as if constituting its es5 They are called by him propria y "that is to say,

without them

God would

indeed be no God, but

still it is

not they that constitute God: for they reveal nothing of the character of substance, through which alone God exists." 6 The contrast between attributes and properties is also implied in his opening statement in the Appendix to the First Part of the Ethics, where he divides the contents of the First Part into two problems, namely, (i) "the nature of God and
(2) its properties."
7

By "the
(p. 52):

nature of

God" he means

there the attributes.


'

Similarly in the Tractates de Intellectus


,yTIY!
a

M
3 <

Emunah Ramah,

II,

iii

/PIP!

,TROn ,NXO:n ,JlDKn /

,nmn.

ibid. (p. 56).

Principia Philosophiae, I, 22. 28. Short Treatise, I, 2,

Ethics, I, Def. 4.

6
7

Short Treatise,

I, 3,

i,

and note

i.

Cf. above, p. 112.

228

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

Emendatione he says of "one" and "infinite" that "these are not attributes of God which set forth His essence."
x

These properties are further described by Spinoza either as being "an extraneous denomination, such as that He exists
immutable, etc.," or as 2 What he means here having "reference to His activity." by an "extraneous denomination" is not quite clear. But
through himself,
is

eternal, one,

a passage in the Cogitata Metaphysica may throw light upon In that passage, using the traditional term "attribute" rather loosely in the sense of his own term "property," he
it.

enumerates the following eleven properties: eternity, unity,


greatness, immutability, simplicity,
life, understanding, will, concurrence. These, he says, are divided power, creation, by some into incommunicable (incommunicabilia) and com-

a division which he charmunicable (communicabilia) 3 acterizes as "more nominal than real," for all of them are
to be

incommunicable or homonymous, inasmuch as there


in their

can be no similarity

meaning when applied

to

God

and when applied to other beings. Spinoza himself divides them into those which explain God's "active essence"
(actuosam ejus essentiam), such as "understanding, will, life, omnipotence, etc.," and those which only explain "His mode of existence" (ejus modi existendi), such as "unity, eternity,

Now, in his correspondence, Spinoza speaks of the properties as being explanations of the expression 5 necessary existence or of the identity of essence and exist6 ence, the latter of which, as

necessity, etc."

we have shown,
7

is itself

derived

from the nature of necessary existence.


1

Taking, therefore,
I, 2,

76, note z (Opera, II, p. 29).

Short Treatise^

29.

This distinction has been traced by Freudenthal to Thomas Aquinas and HeereCf. "Spinoza
.

boord.
Zcller

und

die Scholastik,"

in Philosophische dufsatze,

Eduard

gewidmetjV. n6.

Cogitata Metaphysica, II,


5

n.
6

Epistola 35.

Epistola 83.

Cf. above, pp. 126

ff.

PROP. 14]
all

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT


we may conclude
is

229
that the "ex-

traneous denomination

these passages together, "

an explanation of God's

"mode

of existence" or of the expression "necessary existence/* And thus Spinoza's properties correspond to what Mai-

monides described as
2

(i)

1 explanation of a name, and (2)

actions,

both of which are distinguished by him from essenIn a letter to Oldenburg, evidently referring of attributes, Spinoza writes: "I say that

tial attributes.

to these lists

many
and
God,
I

all

attributes which they [the theologians of his time] others at least who are known to me attribute to

3 By "things created" regard as things created." (creaturas) he undoubtedly means what Maimonides calls

"actions."

According to Joel the distinction between attributes and


properties referred to by Spinoza
tion

made

is analogous to the distincCrescas between essential attributes and attriby

butes merely as intellectual conceptions. 4 The analogy is wrong on several grounds. First, the intellectually conceived attributes of Crescas

may have
s

a closer relation to

Spinoza's definition of attributes


properties.

than to his definition of


attri-

Second, Crescas' intellectually conceived

butes imply a certain conceptual theory of universals which Spinoza's properties do not. Third, Crescas' intellectually

conceived attributes, as I have shown, are one of several forms of anti-realistic conceptions of attributes in Jewish 6 philosophy, of which Maimonides' "explanation of a name"
is

an extreme type, and which, incidentally,


1

may

be traced to

Moreh Ncbukim,
Ibid.,
I,

I, 51.

*
3

52.

Joel,

Epistola 6 (Opera, IV, p. 36, 11. 19-21). Zur Genesis der Lehre Spinoza s, pp. 19
Cf. above, p. 152.

ff.;

Joachim,

A Study oj the Ethics

of Spinoza, p. 42, n.
s

Cf.

my
n.s.,

Review,

"Crescas on the Problem of Divine Attributes" in Jewish Quarterly VII (1916), pp. 1-44, 175-221. Cf. above, pp. 150 ff.

230

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


by
Aristotle
also as the explanation of a

[ETHICS,

the nominal definition mentioned

and described

by him

name. 1

The

fact that

Spinoza divides properties into those which are explanations of the expression necessary existence and those which describe actions shows quite clearly that they are traceable to what Maimonides describes as explanations of a name and
actions.

But even

as propria, not all the attributes that

have been

used by the mediaevals with reference to God are of interest to Spinoza. Many of them are only adjectives which happen
to

have been applied to God

in the traditional literature

of

religion.

Spinoza passes them by and confines himself only " We shall not to those which are of a philosophic character.

trouble ourselves very

much about
2

have of God, but


philosophers can

we
tell

shall only inquire briefly into

the ideas that people what the


"
so-called philoattributes which do

us about it."

Of these

sophic propria, or, as

he

calls

them

here,

not pertain to God," he reproduces a list which concludes with the phrase "and so forth": "A being existing through or of itself, cause of all things, omniscient, almighty, eternal,
3 simple, infinite, the highest good, of infinite compassion." In a foot-note to this passage, he describes these attributes

which do not pertain


be attributed to

to

God

as "certain

modes which may

God"

either in consideration of both his

known

attributes, such as eternal, self-subsisting, infinite, cause of all things, immutable, or in consideration of the

attribute of thought only, such as omniscient, wise, etc., or in consideration of extension only, such as omnipresent,
fills all,

etc.

list

of propria under the loose

name

of attri-

butes

is

given in the Cogitata

unity, greatness, immutability, simplicity,


1

Metaphysica, namely, eternity, life, understand-

Analytica Posteriora > II, 10, 93 b, 29-37. Short Treatisf, I, 7, 2.

Ibid.

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT

231

1 In a letter to Hudde ing, will, power, creation, concurrence. he enumerates four propria, eternal, simple, infinite, indivisi-

of which are reduced by him to the single property of 2 In a later letter to Hudde he refers not only perfection.
ble, all

"the remaining similar 3 by him to one property. properties In a letter to Tschirnhaus he mentions as properties the asto these four properties but also to

"

and

to their reduction

He exists necessarily, that He is unique, immutable, infinite, etc." 4 In the Appendix to the First Part of the Ethics there is an indirect reference to properties, of which he mentions necessary existence, one, acting by the
sertions "that

necessity of His
in

own

nature, cause of
5

Him, predestination. being given by him in the Short 'Treatise^ the cause of all things, divine providence, and divine prelist

things, all things of three propria is namely, that God is

all

destination.

in traditional philosophy had passed do not according to Spinoza reveal anything of the nature of God. Even in mediaeval philoso-

These propria which


^

for divine attributes,

phy they were taken,


understood

as a rule, as

homonymous terms

to be

in a sense entirely unrelated to their


It

meaning.

was

well, indeed, for the

ordinary mediaevals to give


at this point, for

up
to

their inquiry

about the nature of

God

them God was absolutely distinct from the universe, as pure form must be distinct from matter, and consequently what they called attributes could not tell us anything of the nature or essence of God or what God is. They told us only what He is not or what He does in the world the so-called
1 Cogitata Metaphysica, II, I-H. The origin of this list in various Latin sources given by Freudenthal, "Spinoza und die Scholastik," in Philosophische Aujsatoe

is

Eduard
1 5

Zeller

gewidmet, p. no.
*

Epistola 35.

Epistola 36.

Epistola 83.

Appendix

to Ethics,
I,

I.

Short 'Treatise,

3, 5,

and

6.

232

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

negative and actional interpretations of divine attributes. But according to Spinoza God is as material as the world>

and His essence,

therefore, apart

from His actions, does

re-

veal itself in the nature of the physical universe. God or substance, to be sure, is unknown to us in His infinite fullness,

and even that part of Him which is known to us is known to us only through attributes which are not substance itself but
only "that which intellect perceives of substance/'
2

Still,

the intellect perceives them "as if constituting its essence/' 3 that is to say, as if constituting the essence of substance.

While the mediaevals considered the essence of God unknown, because the knowledge gained of God's essence is
not so positive as the knowledge that one may gain, according to their theory of knowledge, of the essence of other
beings, Spinoza considered the essence of God in so far as it could be known through nature as positive as, and even

more

knowledge one may gain, according of knowledge, of the essence of any partheory ticular being. One must therefore go, according to Spinoza, to the physical universe, to consider its ways, and to be wise
positive than, the
to his

own

as to the nature of
If

God.

are to attempt to reconstruct hypothetically the of Spinoza's study of nature and of his reasoning process which ultimately led him to the discovery of the two known

we

attributes of
Aristotelian

God, we must assume that he started with the method of classifying being. Three classifica-

tions of being are to be found in Aristotle, namely, the ten

categories, substance and accident, and matter and form. Of these three classifications, the first must have been dis-

missed by Spinoza outright as something unuseful for his


purpose.
1

Not only did


I,

it

seem to him, as

to others after

Moreh Ncbukim,
Ethics,
I,

52.
J

Dcf.

4.

Ibid.

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT

233

him, to be logically faulty, but it is also reducible to lower forms, for it is based upon the distinction of substance and
the nine categories outside of substance being nothing but an enumeration of various accidents casually 1 The classification of substance and accident, or selected.
accident,

rather of substance and mode, to be sure, is used by Spinoza 2 as the ultimate classification of being in his own system, and rightly so, since in his own system only one substance is

assumed.

In the system of Aristotle, however, where three

kinds of substances are assumed, the classification of substance and accident could not be ultimate, since substance

presupposes already the distinction of matter and form, for the three substances in Aristotle are matter, form, and concrete things composed of matter and form. 3 Spinoza must

have therefore started his revision of the mediaeval scheme with the last of the Aristotelian classifications of being,
namely, matter and form.

Then as a next step, we may assume, Spinoza must have modified Aristotle's classification of matter and form to suit
particular theory of the materiality of God. In Aristotle, as we have seen, matter and form are substances,
his

own

each of them existing "in itself." Though in concrete com4 posite things form does not exist "in itself," for it is inseparable from matter and cannot exist apart from matter, still form can also be pure and exist "in itself" apart from

matter, as in the case of his own God. To Spinoza, however, form could never be pure and exist apart from matter, for even God, he has already shown, must be material. Matter

and form,

therefore, could not be substances;

they could be

only attributes of substance,

such substance, and that


1

is

and there could be only one God. Particular things are not
*

Cf. above, p. 62.

Cf. above, p. 67.

Cf. above, pp. 63 Cf. above, p. 68.

f.

234

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

CETHICS,

That they cannot be substances he has already shown from the very same terms used in the mediaeval defisubstances.
nition of substance.
1

Then Spinoza must have taken one further step and changed the terms "matter'' and "form" into "extension" " and thought." The reason for his doing so will become clear to us when we consider the ambiguity of the old terms matand form. In Aristotle and throughout the Middle Ages matter and form were correlative terms. They were applied
ter

simultaneously to everything within the hierarchy of beings that lie between the lowest matter and the highest form.

by Spinoza in his own with reference to the two known specific and restricted sense attributes of God without leading to some confusion. It

They could not

therefore be used

was

in

fact this multifariousness of

meaning of the terms

matter and form that led mediaeval philosophers to classify

them according to their different applications and to label them by certain distinguishing adjectives, so that in Thomas Aquinas there are no less than fifty-one varieties of matter and no less than one hundred and twenty-one varieties of form. 2 In order therefore to avoid confusion, Spinoza had to find certain equivalents for matter and form which would have the traditional sanction of expressing the same contrast and which would also stand respectively for one traditional specific matter and for one traditional specific form. Such two terms he found in extension and thought. The

common matter
Aristotle
fact,
it is

underlying the four elements, according to

and
the

his
first

commentators, is something extended; in kind of matter that is extended, and hence

could be called extension.


opinion
1

There

is

indeed a difference of

among

his

mediaeval commentators as to whether


"Materia" under
c

Cf. above, Chapter III.

Cf. L. Schiitz, 'Thomas-Lexikon (1895):

and "Forma" un-

derb.

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT

235

extension was the underlying common matter of the four elements itself or whether it was a sort of form of a still
further inextended matter, in which case the underlying

common matter of the four elements would

be

itself composed

of matter and form, respectively known as prime matter (materi a prim a) and corporeal form (forma corporeitatis).

The
roes,

latter

was the opinion of the leading Arabic and Jewish

philosophers, such as Alfarabi, Avicenna, Algazali, Aver-

Joseph Ibn addik, Abraham Ibn Daud, and Joseph Ibn Aknin, though there was a difference of opinion among

them as to the nature of the forma corporeitatis. The origin and history of this controversy about the forma corporeitatis have been discussed by me elsewhere. Crescas, however,
1

argues for the elimination of the inextended prime matter and makes the forma corporeitatis or extension itself at once
the prime matter and the underlying

common matter

of the

four elements. 2

also held, according to the testimony of Isaac Abrabanel, by his son Judah Abra3 banel, better

The same view was

known as Leo Hebraeus, author of the Dialoghi cT Amore. However it is, the common matter underlying the
four elements

inseparable from
as extension.

was conceived to have extension as something it, on which account it could be spoken of

further justification for the substitution of extension for matter by Spinoza was the fact that Descartes

defined matter as extension, 4 though, perhaps, not in the same sense in which Crescas identified the two. The reason
for Spinoza's substitution of

thought for form

ous, for the highest form or God is and throughout the Middle Ages as pure thought.
1

quite obvispoken of by Aristotle


is

Cf.

my

Crescas' Critique of Aristotle in the notes

on pp. 579-590, of which

summary
3

given on pp. 99-101. Ibid.) pp. 102-104, 261-263; notes 26-32 on pp. 598-602.
is

Ibid.) p. 600.

Principia Philosophiae, II, 4, and

cf.

Spinoza, Epistola 83.

236

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

But "extension" and "thought" are abstract terms which


"the
intellect perceives of substance, as if constituting its
1

essence."

It is

only through their respective activities that

they become manifest to our senses. Now, in Aristotle and throughout the Middle Ages God as pure thought was conceived as an active principle. Thought meant thinking, and that process of thinking is always active and is never in a
state of quiescence.

This

is

the trend of Aristotle's stateit

ments when he says of God's thought that


because
it

"thinks

itself
.
.
.

shares the nature of the object of thought. For that which is capable of receiving the object of thought,
is thought. And it is active when it possesses Therefore the latter (possession) rather than the former (receptivity) is the divine element which thought
i.e.

the essence,

this object.

seems to contain."

Maimonides re-echoes these statements

when he
and the
is

declares that
intelligibile"
in action." 3

"God

is

the intellectus^ the intelligent,


is

and that "God

an

intellect

which

Extension or matter, however, is difalways ferent, according to Aristotle and the mediaevals and also 4 It is set it is never active, it is always passive. Descartes;
into motion by an external agent, which ultimately terminates in God, who is the cause of motion in matter, but who is himself not matter and is not in motion. The view is most
clearly set forth

by Maimonides: "The

principles of

any

individual

compound substance are matter and form, and there must needs be an agent, that is to say, a mover which
substratum
in

sets the

motion, and thereby renders

it

pre-

disposed to receive a certain form. The agent which thus predisposes the matter of a certain individual being is called
1

Ethics,
a J *

I,

Def. 4.

Metaphysics, XII, 7, io72b, 19-23.

Moreh Nebukim,

I,

68.
cf.

Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae, II, Prop. 12, and

Descartes, Principia

Philosophiat) II, 36.

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT

237

the immediate mover. Here the necessity arises of inquiring into the nature of motion, the moving agent and the thing

moved.

But this has already been explained sufficiently; and the opinion of Aristotle may be formulated in the words
that matter
is

not the cause of

its

own motion.
2

This

is

the

important proposition which leads the existence of the prime mover."

to the investigation of

Spinoza accepts the old philosophic view with regard to God's thought that it is the act of thinking and that God is therefore an intellect which is always in action. But he disagrees with the old philosophic conception of matter as something inert. In one of his letters he directly criticizes

Descartes for maintaining that the variety of things can be

deduced "from extension in no other way than by supposing that this was the effect produced in extension by motion which was started by God," 3 and gives as his own view that it must be "explained through an attribute, which expresses
eternal

and

infinite essence/'
is

Since according to his

own
ex-

view extension
tension

an attribute of
less

God just

as thought

is,

than thought, and just as is so extension is motion, not motion imthought thinking parted to it by an external agent, but something which ex-

must be active no

presses the activity of its own nature. These actional aspects of the attributes of extension and thought are what Spinoza
calls
1

immediate

infinite
I,

modes.
21-25; XII,
6,

Cf. Metaphysics,

3, 9843,

107 ib, 28-30.

Moreh Nebukim^

II,

p.

315. * Letter to Tschirnhaus (Epistola 83). Spinoza's statement that "matter is badly defined by Descartes as extension" is not to be taken literally as an objection to Descartes' identification of matter with extension.
It is to

Introduction, Prop. 25; Crescas' Critique of Aristotle , Letter from Tschirnhaus (Epistola 82).

be taken

in con-

nection with the entire letter of Tschirnhaus and as referring especially to the latter's restatement of the opinion of Descartes that the variety of things can be

deduced "from extension

in no other way than by supposing that this was the effect produced in extension by motion which was started by God." Cf. also the definition of matter in Cogitata Metaphysica, II, 10 (Opera, I, p. 269, 11. 31-33).

238

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


infinite

[ETHICS,

The immediate
Spinoza
(2)

mode

of thought

is

designated by

in four

ways:

(i) Intellect (Intellectus , Verstaari)*

2 Absolutely infinite intellect (intellectus absolute infinitus). 3 (3) An infinite power of thought (potentia infinita cogitandi). (4) The idea of God (idea Dei).* The term intellectus in the

two designations is to be understood here not only in the sense of the thinking subject but also in the sense of the act of thinking, that is to say, not only in the sense of the
first

intellect, vovs, but also in the sense of intellection, j/irjcns, on the principle reproduced by Maimonides as the common

opinion of the philosophers that "God is the intellectus > the intelligent, and the intelligibile" and that "all intellect is
identical with its action; the intellect in action
different
is

not a thing
is

from
is

its

action, for the true nature


s

and essence of
also re-

the intellect

comprehension/'
6

This principle
is

produced by Spinoza. to Spinoza there is no potential


tellect is actual, 7 it will

When

it

recalled that according

intellect

but that every


subject,
is

in-

become

clear

how

the term intellectus ,

which

literally

means the understanding

used by

of the act of understanding. When, therein the third designation he describes the infinite mode fore, of thought as potentia infinita cogitandi, the term potentia
in the sense

him

not to be taken in the sense of potentiality or faculty or the power to do something but in the sense of the power displayed in doing something, for ordinarily, as says Maiis

monides,

"when we assume

the intellect to be potential,

we

necessarily distinguish two things, the potential and the potential intelligible object." 8
1

intellect

3 <
s

Letter from Schuller (Epistola 63), and Short Treatise, I, 9. * Letter to Schuller (Epistola 64). Epistola 32 (Opera, IV, p. 173,
Ethics, II, Props. 3, 4, Moreh Nebukim, I, 68.

1.

18).

and

8.

Cf.

I,

Prop. 21, Demonst.

6
?

Ethics, II, Prop. 7, Schol.

Cf. below, Vol. II, pp. 24, 45. Cf. below, Vol. II, pp. 24, 45.

Ethics, II, Prop. 48, Schol.,

and Ethics,

I,

Prop. 31, Schol.

Moreh Nebukim,

I,

68.

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT


is

239

The mode

active sense of the term intellectus

made

clear

by

Spinoza himself in his description of the immediate

infinite

of thought in the Short Treatise. He says that "it has been from all eternity, and to all eternity will remain im-

mutable.
clearly

...

It has

one function, namely, to understand


all

x The emthings at all times/' phasis in these statements is on the terms "eternity," "immutable/' and "at all times," and they reflect the following

and

distinctly

statements of Maimonides:

"Now
is

it

which always there is in Him at no time a mere potentiality, that He does not comprehend at one time, and is without comprehension at another time, but He is an intellect in action always." 2
is

God

an

intellect

in action,

has been proved that and that


. .
.

Spinoza continues to describe there the function of the


finite

in-

mode

of thought as that "which produces invariably


satisfaction,

an
to

infinite

and most perfect


it

which cannot omit

do what

does."

This seems to

reflect Aristotle's de-

scription of the constant activity of the First Principle or God: "And its life is such as the best which we enjoy, and

enjoy for but a short time. For it is ever in this state (which we cannot be), since its actuality is also pleasure and
.

the act of contemplation

is

what

is

most pleasant and best."

The expression idea Dei we take to be the equivalent of the expression intellectus absolute infinitus as a description of the immediate infinite mode of thought. These two expressions, however, indicate

two

different aspects of that


intellectus, as

immediate

infinite

mode.

The term

we have

seen, literally refers to the thinking subject, the vovs in Aristotle's enumeration of the threefold aspect of God's

thinking, namely, the


1

j>oDs,

the
2

v&rjcns,

and the voyrbv or


I,

Short treatise, Short Treatise ,

I, 9, I, 9,

3.

Moreh Nebukim,

68.

3.

Metaphysics , XII,

7, loysb, 14-24.

240
voovjjitvov.

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


The term
idea in idea Dei
is

[ETHICS,

a transliteration of

elSos in the specific sense of eldos vorjT&v (forma intelligibilis)* and hence it reflects the object of thought, the vor\rbv or

voovnevov in Aristotle's threefold enumeration.


as in

God,

according to Aristotle,

himself, the thinking subject, object of thought are identical,


absolute infinitus

But inasmuch Maimonides, and Spinoza the act of thinking, and the
the expressions intellectus

identical in meaning, both designating the immediate infinite mode of thought. That the relation between the "idea of God" and the "ab-

and

idea Dei are

solutely infinite intellect"


like that of object of

of course, in

God

was conceived by Spinoza to be thought to the thinking subject, which, are identical, may be shown from the fol.

lowing passage. In Proposition IV of Ethics , II, Spinoza says can be one only." In the Demthat "the idea of God
.
.

onstration of this proposition he proves it by the contention that "the infinite intellect comprehends nothing but the
attributes of
in

God and His

affections,"
it

which are

all

united

God

as one.

This passage makes

considered by as the object of thought to the with which it is identical. Another proofthinking subject text may perhaps be found also in the following passage:
the "infinite intellect"

"idea of

God" was

quite clear that the Spinoza to be related to

"We

must remember,

besides, that our


is

mind,

in so far as it

a part of the infinite intellect of truly perceives things, God (Corol. Prop. XI, Part II), and therefore it must be that the clear and distinct ideas of the mind are as true as
2 If in this passage the plural (Dei ideae)." "Dei ideae" means the ideas of God in the "infinite intellect

the ideas of

God

of
it

God"
is

rather than the ideas of

God

in

"our mind," then

quite evident that the relation between the "idea of


Cf. below, Vol. II, pp. 46-48, 93.

Metaphysics, XII, 9, 10753, 3-5.


Ethics, II, Prop. 43, Schol., end.

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT

241

God" and

the "infinite intellect of God/' i.e., the absolutely infinite intellect, is like that between the clear and distinct
ideas of our

lation
ject,

mind and our mind, that is to say, like the rebetween the object of thought and the thinking subwhich two are identical in God.

students of Spinoza take the idea Dei as the mediate infinite mode of thought corresponding to the fades totius
universi

Some

extension. 1

which they take as the mediate infinite mode of This view, however, is dictated only by the

necessity of finding a special mediate infinite mode of thought in order to round out the symmetry of the modal system.

No

statement

in

Spinoza could be found which would

defi-

nitely corroborate it. On the contrary, the following passage in the Short Treatise would seem to contradict it. Says

Spinoza:

"And

since, as a

matter of

fact,

nature or

God

is

one being of which infinite attributes are predicated, and which contains in itself all the essences of created things, it

produced in thought infinite idea (oneyndige Idea), which comprehends ob2 The "injective the whole of nature just as it is realiter"
is

necessarily follows that of all this there

an

idea" in this passage undoubtedly refers to the idea and from the context of the passage it is quite clear Dei,
finite

that
this

cannot be a mediate mode of thought, for right after statement Spinoza says definitely: "Wherefore also, in
it

the ninth chapter of the First Part, tion created immediately by God."

I
3

called this idea a crea-

Furthermore, the use

of the idea Dei in the Demonstration of Proposition XXI of Ethics, I, leaves no doubt that it is an immediate rather than
a mediate
1

mode

of thought. 4

Pollock, Spinoza, pp. 187-188, referring also to Ed.

Zeitsehrijt

Bohmer, "Spinozana," in fur Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 42 (1863), pp. 107-116;
1

Joachim,
3
i

Study oj the Ethics of Spinoza, p. 94. Short Treatise, Appendix II, 4 (Opera, I, p.
Ibid. (p. 117,
11.

17,

11.

24-29).
Cf. below, p. 378.

29-31; p. 607,

10).

242

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


infinite

[ETHICS,

The immediate
Spinoza
in

mode of extension
Motion.
1

is

designated by
rest.
3

two ways:

(i)

(2)

Motion and

The addition of rest to motion must have been suggested to " him by Descartes, who speaks of motion and rest as two 3 Whether Descartes diverse modes of a body in motion." meant by this addition that rest was a real entity, himself
or whether he used
tion
it

which has been raised

only as a rhetorical flourish, is a quesin connection with another pas-

4 But it would seem that Spinoza had sage in Descartes. taken it to mean something positive, in opposition to Aris-

totle

and the mediaevals,

to

whom

rest

was only the privation

of motion. 5

The positive character of rest is affirmed by when he says that "as is self-evident, the same force Spinoza

required to give a body at rest a certain velocity as is required to bring the same body with that given velocity to
is
6

rest/*

or

quantity of motion.
sistance

when he says that "by force we understand the ... In bodies at rest by force of rewe understand the quantity of rest." 7 It is interest-

ing to note that Crescas in his criticism of Aristotle similarly maintains, though in a different sense, that there is a quantity of rest as there
is

a quantity of motion. 8

It

has been

suggested that by motion and rest Spinoza means energy in motion and energy in position, or kinetic and potential
9

energy.
Letter from Schuller (Epistola 63), and Short Treatise, I, 9. Short Treatise, 1, 2, 19, note 7 (Opera, I, p. 25, 11. 26-27); II, notes to Preface; 6 (Opera, I, p. 90, 11. 26-27); U, 20, II, 19, 4, note 4 (Opera, I, p. 98, 1. 35); Appendix II, 15 (Opera, I, p. 120, 1. 24); Ethics, I, Prop. 32, Corol. 2; Epistola 64;
1

Meyer's Preface to Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae (Opera,


3

I, p.

132,

1.

13).

Principia Philosophiae, II, 27.


Pollock, Spinoza, p.

no.
II,

Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae,


Ibid., Prop. 22,

Physics, IV, 12, 22ib, 12-13. Def. 8 (2).

Demonst., and Prop. 37, Corol. Cf. E. Schmitt, Die unendliche

Modi

bei

Spinoza (Leipzig, 1910),

Cf.

my

p. 47, n. 2. Crescas' Critique of Aristotle, pp. 287-288.

Pollock, Spinoza, p. 113.

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT

243

In the history of philosophy an immediate creation of God has been sometimes called a son of God. Thus Philo describes the intelligible world,
tion of

which was an immediate crea-

God and

created by

Him

from eternity, as a son of

God, whereas time, which is not an immediate creation of God but is the offspring of the cosmos, is described by him
God. 1 This designation has gone over to Christian theology, and Spinoza refers to the Christian side
as a grandson of

of

it

elsewhere in his works. 2

But

Philo's statement

is

also

3 reproduced by Azariah dei Rossi, and it is also reflected d* Amore.* Following tradition, in Leo Hebraeus' Dialoghi

immediacy of these two modes by saying of motion that it is "a son, product, or effect created immediately by God," and of understandtherefore, Spinoza characterizes the
infinite

ing that it "is also a son, product, or immediate creation of 5 God, created by Him from all eternity/'

Spinoza's God, though He can no longer be contrasted with the universe as the immaterial with the material, can
still

be contrasted with

it

as the simple

whole with the ag-

gregate whole. His God, as we shall show in the next chapter, is not identical with the physical universe. He transcends
it

in a certain special sense of the

term transcendance. 6

And

so, the aggregate totality of the physical universe, in so far as it is the necessary result of the activity of God's attributes

finite

of extension and thought, is called by Spinoza also an inmode of God, but in order to differentiate it from the
it

other infinite modes he calls


distinction between
Quod Deus

a mediate infinite mode. This


infinite

immediate and mediate

modes,

Sit Immutabilis, VI, 31.


I,

Cogitata Mctaphysica,

10;

Epistola 73; Ethics, IV, Prop. 68, Schol.


(ed. Cassel).

'Enayim, Imrc Binah y Ch. 4, p. 100 Diahghi d'Amorc t III, p. 244 (Bari, 1929).
'or

Me

Short Tnatisf,

I, 9,

2-3.

Cf. below, p. 322.

244

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

however, does not occur in all the writings of Spinoza. In the Short Treatise he does not mention it. On the contrary,
the distinction drawn there
finite
is

not between two kinds of inas

in

modes but rather between infinite modes, extension and understanding in thought, and

motion

particular

things, the former of which are immediately created by God whereas the latter are said to be created by God by a sub-

sidiary instrumental cause.

God

is

therefore called

by him

the proximate cause of the infinite modes but the remote But the cause, in a certain sense, of the particular things.
1

distinction between
is

immediate and mediate

infinite

modes

referred to several times in the Ethics?

and a mediate
in a letter to

infinite

mode

is

specifically

named by Spinoza
to that

Schuller.'

The name given by Spinoza


is

mediate

infinite

mode

"the face of the whole universe" (jades

totius universi).*

The phraseology
Biblical

manner

of this expression is reminiscent of the of describing the totality or wholeness of

a certain extent of territory. Thus say "over the entire earth/' it says

when

the Bible wants to

"upon

the face of

all

the

earth," which in the Vulgate is translated by super faciem totius terrae (Dan. 8, 5), or by super faciem universae terrae

(Gen.
(II

7, 3, I
1

Sam. 30,
Zech.

16), or

by super faciem omnis

terrae

Sam.

8, 8,

5, 3).

The term fades may

also reflect

the Greek Trp6<rwjrov in the sense of "person," for the Latin " 5 " has acquired the fades as well as the Hebrew word for face

meaning of "person" under the influence of the Greek term. Accordingly the fades totius universi may mean the whole
universe taken as an individual, in conformity with Spinoza's statement that "we may easily conceive the whole of
1

Short Treatise,
Ethics,
I,

I,

3,

2 (8).

But

cf.

Ethics,

I,

Prop. 28, Schol.

Prop. 23, Demonst.; Prop. 28, Schol.; Appendix (Opera, II, p. 80,
3

1.

17).
t

Ibid.

D.

Epistola 64.

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT


l

245

nature to be one individual/*

In coining or adopting this

expression for the mediate modes, Spinoza may have also " " faces been influenced by the Cabalistic term (parzufim, from 7rp6(ra?7roj>), which stands for the mediate emanations

from the Infinite (En Sof) following from Him through the mediacy of the Sefirot. Abraham Herrera in his Puerto, del
y

Cielo refers to these mediate

emanations as the "faces of the

reads:

universe of the infinite." In the Spanish original, the phrase 2 In the Hebrew "parzupim del mundo del ynfinito."

version, the
is

same term "parzupim/' or rather "parzufim,"

In the abridged Latin version made from the He4 brew, the phrase reads: "Personae Systematis(,) Infiniti." Whether Spinoza had before him the Spanish original in
used. 3

manuscript or the Hebrew version printed


1655, twenty
ler,

in

Amsterdam

in

years prior to the writing of his letter to Schul-

dated "29 Julii, 1675," where the phrase "facies totius universi" occurs, it can be easily seen how Herrera's description of his mediate emanations by the phrase "parzupim of
suggested to him the phrase universi" as a description of his own mediate "facies totius
the universe of the infinite
infinite

"

mode.

" is exexpression "the face of the whole uni verse himself as meaning "the whole universe plained by Spinoza

The

which, although it varies in infinite ways, yet remains always the same/' s This explanation, it seems to me, may refer to

two principles
In the
1 2

in Spinoza's philosophy.

first
to

place,

it

may
del Cielo

refer

to the

Cartesian and

Scholium

Lemma

7, after Prop. 13 of Ethics^ II.

Cf. Livro Quarto de

La Puerta

De Abraham Cohen

de Htrrera y Cap. 3,

fol.

HAI'M
3

38b. "

Library of the "Portugeesch Israelietisch Seminarium ETS in Amsterdam. A copy of this passage was made for me through the courtesy
in the
J. S.

MS.

of the Librarian, Dr.

da Silva Rosa.

Sha'arha-Shamayitn,ll,3'. *)1D Porta Cce/orum, II, 3, p. 45.


Kpistola 64.

JW

246

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

Spinozistic principle of the preservation of the proportion of motion and rest. 1 According to this principle, the preservation of the proportion of motion and rest in the parts

composing the body of an individual

results in the preser-

vation of the form (forma) 2 or shape (figurd)* of that individual as a whole. Consequently the preservation of the

proportion of motion and rest in the particular parts which compose the physical universe and constitute it as an individual whole will preserve the face (fades), i.e., the form (forma) and shape (figura), of the universe as a whole. As

we may
ual,

Spinoza says elsewhere: "Thus, if we advance ad infinitum y easily conceive the whole of nature to be one individ-

whose

parts, that

is

to say, all bodies, differ in infinite

4 ways without any change of the whole individual." " In the second place, it may refer to the principle of the

order and interdependence of nature as a whole (totius naturae ordo et cohaerentia) , s fades thus meaning ordo et
cohaerentia.

"

This principle

is

also

spoken of by Spinoza as

"the order of the whole of nature or the connection of


causes'" (prdo totius naturae, sive

causarum connexio)? or as

the fixed and unchangeable order of nature or the chain of natural events" (fixux et immutabilis naturae ordo sive rerum

"

naturae concatenations or as "the concatenation of causes" (concatenatio causarum)* With reference to this principle,
too, nature as a

whole

may

be considered as an individual
as the

consisting of parts,

"inasmuch

power of nature
all

is

simply the aggregate of the powers of


See

her individual

Lemma

7, after

Prop. 13 of Ethics,

II.

Cf. below, Vol. II, p. 69, n. 4.

EthicSy IV, Prop. 39,

Demonst.

See Axiom 3 preceding

Lemma

4, after

Prop. 13 of Ethics,

II.

Scholium to
6
^

Lemma

7, after Prop. 13 of Ethics, II.

tfractatus Thcologico-Politicus,

Ch. 16 (Opera, III, p. 191,

11.

5-6).

Ethics, II, Prop. 7, Schol.

Vractatus Theo/ogico-Po/iticus, Ch. 3 (Opera, III, p. 45,


Ibid.,

11.

34-35).

Ch. 4 (Opera,

III, p. 58,

1.

21).

PROP. 14]
x

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT

247

Now, this order of nature, according to Spinoza, may be explained either by the attribute of thought or by the attribute of extension, according as the compocomponents/'
nent parts of the universe are considered either as modes of
2 thought or as modes of extension.

By

the

same token, we

Spinoza the order or the face of be also explained by the joint may activity of both attributes, if the component parts of the universe are considered as modes of both thought and

may

infer that according to

the whole universe

extension.

Consequently, the mediate infinite mode designated by Spinoza as "the face of the whole universe/' if taken with
reference to the principle of the preservation of the proportion of motion and rest, will be a mode of extension only,

but

if

the whole of nature, will be a

taken with reference to the principle of the order of mode of both extension and

thought. As Spinoza does not say that "the face of the whole universe" is a mode of extension only and as he

nowhere
verse"
is

specifically

mentions a mediate

infinite

mode

of

thought, we may conclude

that "the face of the whole uni-

a mediate infinite

mode

of both extension and

thought. In our presentation of the system of infinite modes we have in some respects parted from the interpretations

which one may find in the Spinoza literature, and in some other respects we have placed ourselves on the side of one class of interpreters as against that of another class. 3 Among
the interpreters of Spinoza there are some who take the "face of the whole universe" to be only a mode of exten1

Ibid.,
>

Ch. 16 (Opera,
classification

III, p. 189,

11.

21-23).

Ethics, II, Prop. 7, Schol.

For a

of the various interpretations of infinite modes, see


5
ff.

E. Schmitt, Die uncndliche Modi bei Spinoza (Leipzig, 1910), pp.

248
1

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

sion,

but in order to preserve the symmetry of extension and thought, they supply by conjecture the missing mediate

infinite

mode
to
fill

of thought out of other parts of Spinoza's


Spinozistic

expressions have been borthat lacuna in Spinoza's list of infinite up modes: (i) God's idea (idea Dei). 2 (2) "The constant form of reasoned thought or Necessary Logical laws." 3 Supwritings.

Two

rowed

port for the

first

conjecture

is

adduced from the

fact that

certain descriptions of the idea Dei would seem to make it the ideal counterpart of the fades fotius universi. 4 Martineau,

who

is

any textual support

the author of the second conjecture, does not adduce for his view. I am inclined to reject

both these conjectures, for the following reasons.

As we

have already seen, the expression fades totius universi may include both the modes of extension and the modes of
5 Then, as we have also shown, the idea Dei is an immediate mode of thought and the equivalent of the intellectus absolute infinitus. Finally, Martineau's "Neces-

thought.

sary Logical laws" cannot be a mediate infinite mode parallel to the fades fotius universi, for from a statement in

Meyer's Preface to Spinoza's Prindpia Philosophiae Carte-

may be indirectly inferred that the "Necessary laws" are parallel to "motion and rest" and conLogical sequently must be identical with the "absolutely infinite
sianae
it

intellect"

and are therefore an immediate

infinite

mode. The
is

passage reads as follows: absolute, but its extension

"And
is

as the

human body

not

laws of motion and rest,


1

determined according to natural so also mind or human spirit is not


list

See

ibid. y p. 116, n. 4,

where a
is

of authors holding different interpretations

of the fades totius universi


2

^ 4

Cf. Pollock, Spinoza, p. 188. Pollock, Spinoza y p. 187; Joachim, Study oj the Ethics of Spinoza, p. 94. Martineau, Study of Spinoza y p. 200.

given.

Joachim, op. '/., p. 95. Cf. above, pp. 239 ff.

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT


is
*

249

absolute but

determined through ideas by natural laws

of thought." In the philosophy of Aristotle and in the Aristotelian philosophy reproduced by the mediaevals sometimes for the pur-

pose of refutation, a distinction

is

drawn between the

uni-

verse as a whole and the particular things within it. The universe as a whole is said to be eternal and immutable, to

have neither beginning nor end, never to have been different nor ever to change, but always to remain the same. 2 The
ever, are different.

particular things in the sublunary part of the universe, howThey are called transient and are said

to be subject to constant change 3 and to the process of generation and corruption. 4 Following tradition, Spinoza simi" general," which are the larly distinguishes between the
infinite
lar

modes, and the "particular," which are the particu5

modes are described by him as and as remaining always the same, 7 whereas the particular things are described by him as "tranwhich did not exist from all time, or have had a sient 8 9 beginning" and as "individual mutable things." But these transient things, according to the mediaeval
things.
infinite
6

The

eternal

and immutable

do not act sporadically and haphazardly. They subject to the necessary and immutable laws which govern the universe as a whole and the influence of which reaches every part of it. This view has been summed up in
Aristotelians,

are

all

the following statement of Maimonides: "This whole order [of the universe], both above and here below, is never dis1

Preface to the Pnncipia Philosophiae Cartesianac (Opera, Aforeh Nebukim, II, 13, Third Theory.
lbid.,\\, 10.
<

I, p.

132,

11.

12

ff.).

/#</., II, 11.

Short Treatise,

I, 8.
i

6 8 9

Epistola 64. Ibid., I, 9. 2 (p. 563). Short Treatise, II, 5, 5 (Opera, I, p. 62, 11. 32 ff.). Cf. 100 (Opera, II, p. 36, 1. 22). Tractatus de Intellects Emendatione,

250

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

turbed or interrupted, and nothing new is produced in it which is not in its nature and nothing happens in it which

Furthermore, even according to Maimonides himself, to whom the world does not follow from God by mere necessity but by knowledge, God's eternal
is

contrary to law."

of such a nature that in determining the changes in particular things it determines them in such a way that

knowledge

is

order."

they follow "according to an imperishable and immutable 2 So also Spinoza maintains that the "individual

mutable things" (haec singularia mutabilia) "are produced and are ordered" according to "fixed and eternal things"
that is to say, the infinite modes, (res fixae aeternaeque) which are of an eternal and immutable nature. The sequence of individual mutable things is, therefore, "to be sought
,

inscribed in them, as

from fixed and eternal things only, and also from the laws 3 it were in true codes."

fixed and eternal things, though they are themselves modes which by definition can neither be nor be cononly

These

ceived without substance, 4 may still be considered with reference to the individual mutable things which are dependent upon them as substance is considered by Spinoza with refer-

ence to modes, that is to say, the individual mutable things can neither be nor be conceived without the infinite modes.

The relation between them, therefore, is like that between substance and mode, namely, the relation between the whole
and the part or between the universal and the
This
5

particular.

"It is the significance of the following passage: indeed be said that these individual mutable things so
if I

may
inti-

mately and

may depend upon those essentially, that are fixed that the former without the latter can neither
so speak,
'

March Nebukim,
Ethics, I, Def.
5.

II, 13.

Ibid., Ill, 21.


11.

Tractatus de Intellcctus Emendatione t

101 (Opera> II, p. 36,


s

35

ff.).

See above, pp. 74

ff.

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT


Hence

251

be nor be conceived.

although they

may

these fixed and eternal things, be individual (singularia), nevertheless,

on account of
will

their presence

everywhere and their extensive

be like universals to us, or so to speak, the genera power, of the definitions of individual mutable things, and proxi-

mate causes of

things." If this interpretation of the passage just quoted is correct, then the "fixed and eternal things" do not refer directly to

all

substance or to attribute but only to the infinite modes, both the immediate and the mediate, though, of course, indirectly
they

may

include also substance and attribute, inasmuch as

they, too, are fixed and eternal and are the cause of the existence of the infinite modes. According to some interpreters

of Spinoza, however, the fixed and eternal things refer directly to substance, attribute,

and even finite modes. 2 The " fixed and eternal things" application of the expression
to the infinite modes, that
is

to say, to the absolutely infinite

intellect,

motion and

rest,

verse, reflects the expression "eternal things"

and the face of the whole uniwhich was

applied by the mediaevals to the Intelligences, motion, and the universe as a whole, when these were assumed with Aristotle to be eternal. 3 The expression goes back to Aristotle
himself. 4 Again, the characterization of the infinite
as singularia in the passage

modes

quoted

is

in

conformity with

what we have said above, namely, that Spinoza's substance or God is in some respect transcending the universe and is
a simple whole as contrasted with the universe, or, as he
1

'Tractatus de Inttllectus

Emendatione,

101 (Opera, II, p. 37,

11.

ff.).

For different interpretations of the meaning of the res fixae et aeternae, see E. Schmitt, Die uncndliche Modi bei Spinoza (Leipzig, 1910), pp. 68-69. J See my Crtscas' Critique of Aristotle pp. 287, 291, and note 18 on p. 645, note 31 on p. 662, note 32 on p. 663. The Hebrew expression underlying "eternal
,

things"
*

is:

D'TOan onain.
IV, 12, 22 ib, 3-4.

rA

del fora, Physics,

252
calls
it,

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

natura naturata^ which is an aggregate whole. Consequently, substance is the only true whole or universal, and

modes are in their relation to it only singularia. In mediaeval philosophy a distinction is made between the possible per se, the possible per se but necessary in consideration of its cause, and the necessary per se. This disthe infinite
tinction
is

based upon an Avicennian proposition which


as follows:

is

"Everything that has a cause for its existence is in respect to its own essence only possible of existence, for if the causes exist, the thing
likewise will exist, but
if

reproduced by Maimonides

the causes have never existed, or

if

they have ceased

to exist, or if their causal relation to the


r

thing has changed, then the thing itself will not exist." The origin, history, and implications of this proposition

have discussed elsewhere. 2 According to this threefold division of possibility and necessity, the particular things are
called possible per se, the celestial spheres are called possible per se but necessary in consideration of their cause, and God
is

called

necessary per se

a division

based

upon the

Aristotelian division of the universe into

the transiently

able. 3

movable, the eternally movable, and the eternally immovSpinoza reproduces this mediaeval threefold division

of possibility and necessity in different connections in several 4 But here he applies it to his theory of places in his works.
infinite

modes.

He
"

and
as
1

"

necessary

changes, however, the terms possible to "transient" and "eternal," with which,

"

we have

5 seen, they are connected.

The

particular things,

Moreh Nebukim^

II,

Introd., Prop.

19; cf.

my

Crescas* Critique of /Iristotle,

P-

332 *

Crescas Critique of

An static

pp. 109-1

Metaphysics, V,
ff.
1

5,

10153, 33-34.

n, 681-685. See Crescas' Critique of Aristotle p. 109 and


>

pp. 680
5

See above, pp.


Cf.

87

ff.

my

Crescas' Critique of Aristotle, pp. 109

ff.

and 680

ff.

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT

253

i.e., possible perse. while transient or possible per se, are not to be considered as transient or possible in consideration of their cause. God is

he says, are transient,

The infinite modes,

"Now some objects are in i.e., necessary per se. themselves transient; others, indeed, are not transient by virtue of their cause. There is yet a third that is eternal and
eternal,

imperishable through
time, or have

its

own power and


The

might.

The
all

tranall

sient are all the particular things

which did not

exist

from

had a beginning.

others are

those

modes [marginal note adds: the general modes] which we to be the cause of the particular modes. But the third is God." But while Spinoza operates on the whole with mediaeval conceptions and uses mediaeval terms, he always tries to
have stated
J

emphasize the two points upon which he fundamentally differs from the mediaevals, namely, the necessity of God's
causality and the denial of God's immateriality. This emphasis upon his two points of difference from the mediaevals

be discerned in the explanations he offers for the meaning of the old expression natura naturans as applied to God in contrast to natura naturata as applied to the world.

may

The

distinction between
is

God and
In the

the mediaevals,

twofold.

the world, according to first place, God is the

cause and the world His effect, and by cause they


intelligent cause, a creator, acting

mean an

purpose.

In the second place,

by design and with a God is immaterial and the


is

substances, a superior or immaterial substance as against the world which consists of material substances. These two distinctions between God
all

world material, so that God, if at all, 2 is a substance beyond

He

to be called substance

and the world are sometimes


1

illustrated
62,
11.

by the contrast beCf.


2 (p. 563).

Short treatise, II,


Cf. above, p. 67.

5,

(Opera,

I, p.

28

ff.).

254

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

Whatever the

tween the expressions natura naturans and natura naturata. origin of these two expressions and whatever

their variety of meanings, 1 it is sufficient for our present in purpose to know that they were used by Thomas

Aquinas

a sense which implied the two fundamental distinctions be-

tween

God and
is

the world as

we have

stated them.

2 things that happen naturally,'* by which he means, of course, that God is an intelligent and purposive

says he, versal cause of

called natura naturans because


all

He

is

God, "the uni-

cause.

This universal cause, he says again in another place, belongs "to some superior substance, in which sense God is

said

by some

to be natura naturans''

Spinoza seems to

refer to this last passage

when he says of the natura naturans

that "the Thomists likewise understand


their natura naturans
all

God by
it)

it,

but

was a being
to

(so they called

beyond

substances."

Now, Spinoza wanted


sponded
namely,
to

make

use of these two expressions


in his

as respective designations of

what

philosophy corre-

God and

God

the world in mediaeval philosophy, and the modes. But still he did not want to use

meaning by which they connoted a distincbetween an intelligent cause and a premeditated effect or between an immaterial substance and a material substance. What did he do? He simply revised their meaning. natura naturans as including substance and its atDefining tributes and natura naturata as including all the modes, the
in their old

them

tion

infinite as well as the finite, 5

he describes the differences be-

tween them
1

in

such terms that when we study them closely

Cf. H. Sicbeck, "Ueber die Entstehung der Termini natura naturans und natura naturata" in Archivjur Geschichte der Philosophic > 3(1889-1890), pp. 370 ff. Commcntaria in Librum Btati Dionysii De Divinis Nominibus, Caput 4,

Lection.
3

Summa

fhtologicay
I, 8.

Prima Secundac, Quaest.


s

85, Art. 6.

Short Treatise,

Ibid., I, 8; Epistola 9.

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT

255

discover that they are aimed directly against the Thomisconception of the meaning of these expressions. In the first place, wishing to make it clear that, while he retains the
tic

we

original

cause, he does not mean by

meaning of natura naturans as that of a universal it an intelligent and purposive


. . .

cause, Spinoza says that "by natura naturans we are to understand God in so far as He is considered as a free

cause," by which he means to say, in so far as He acts by the necessity of His own nature, 2 whereas "by natura naturata I understand everything which follows from the
*

necessity of the nature of God, or of any one of God's attributes." 3 In the second place, in opposition to the Thomists, who used the two expressions to designate a distinction between God as an immaterial substance and the world as a

material substance, Spinoza, who denies finite substances and considers the distinction between God and the world as
that between substance and mode, explains natura naturans by his own definition of substance and natura naturata by " his own definition of mode. He thus says again: By natura

naturans we are to understand that which


is

is

in itself

and

conceived through itself/* whereas "by natura naturata understand ... all the modes of God's attributes in so

far as they are considered as things which are in God, and which without God can neither be nor can be conceived." 4

Another difference between Spinoza and the mediaevals, again growing out of his attribution of materiality to God,
is

his contention that the

"two

attributes

may

be conceived

as really distinct that is to say, one without the assistance of the other." s This passage, like so many other utterances
'

Ethics >

I,

Prop. 29, Schol.

Ibid., I, Dcf. 7.

3
4 s

lbid. y I, Prop. 29, Schol.

Ibid. t I, Prop. 29, Schol.,


Ibid., I, Prop. 10, Schol.

and

cf.

Defs. 4 and

5.

256

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

of Spinoza, is to be understood as a veiled criticism of the mediaevals- in this case, of their conception of the interrelation of matter and form. According to Aristotle and the
mediaevals, though there exists a pure form, such as God and the Intelligences, still in the physical universe matter and form are only relative terms. Not only does not either one of them exist without the other, but neither one of them can be conceived without the other. Matter is matter only

with reference to some form, and form is form only with reference to some matter. Furthermore, since God is pure form, then matter, under the theory of emanation, must
ultimately have been produced by pure form, and it is form which continues to be the active, producing principle in

non-being; it is inert. It which constitutes the existence of bodies, and it


itself is
1

matter.

Matter

is is

form
form

which

sets

matter
is

in

motion. 2

Form

is

said to exist in matter,

said to exist through form. 3 As against this, Spinoza maintains that extension and thought, which in his 4 philosophy are the successors of matter an^ forrn, are two

and matter

attributes of substance, existing in

it

together from eternity,

each having the same sort of existence as the other, and each having its own independent form of activity, extension that
of motion and rest, and thought that of thinking. Unlike form which produces motion in matter, thought does not

produce motion in extension. Motion is an activity of extension itself. Extension and thought, again, are not cor-

which cannot be conceived but through each can be conceived independently of each other other; they with reference to substance only. Nor does thought exist in
relative terms,

extension any more than extension exists through thought.


1

Cf.

my

Crcscas* Critique of Aristotle, pp. 257

ff.

Ibid., pp. 89, 299,


<

672-673.

Ibid., pp. 99, 257

ff.,

577, n. 15.

Cf. above, p. 234.

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT

257

"For
butes

this is the
is

nature of substance, that each of its attriconceived through itself, since all the attributes

which substance possesses were always together, nor could one be produced by another; but each expresses the reality
or being of substance/*
l

But

still,

though distinct from each other, extension and

thought, again unlike matter and form, do not imply a plurality in the nature of substance. The reason why the

mediaevals considered matter and form to constitute a

wherever they existed together is not that they could be physically separated but that they were considered by them two distinct substances, each of which was supposed
plurality

supposed to be in contrast to the other, matter being potential, form actual, matter being the cause of corruption, form the cause of
to exist in itself
3

and each of which was

also

4 But according to Spinoza, extension and generation. thought are not two substances but attributes of one sub-

stance,

and they are only that

"

which

intellect perceives
s

of

substance, as if constituting its essence.*'


trast

There

is

no con-

between them of potentiality and actuality, or of imperfection and perfection. They are both expressing two
different phases of the activity of substance, which in substance itself are one. Consequently, from the fact that the

two attributes are conceived as


is

distinct

from each other

it

not to be concluded that


different substances

"

two
lian

"

after the

they constitute two beings or manner of the Aristote-

and mediaeval matter and form. The independence of each attribute which Spinoza insists upon is merely to emphasize his denial of the interdependence of matter and form
1

Ethics ,

I,

Prop. 10, Schol.


Cf. above, p. 67.
s

Cf. above, p. 113.

Cf. above, p. 236.


6

Ethics,

I,

Def.

4.

Ibid., I, Prop. 10, Schol.

258
in

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


it is

[ETHICS,

mediaeval philosophy;

not an independence which

implies the reality of the attributes in their relation to substance or a reality in the difference between themselves,

with the result that the unity of substance can no longer be logically maintained. The relation of the attributes to

each other

is

of the same order as their relation to substance.

Just as the difference

between attribute and substance

is

only a conception of the human mind, so the difference between the attributes themselves is only a form of conception
in the

human mind,
its

"for this
is

is

the nature of substance, that

conceived through itself." * It is in this sense only that the "two attributes may be conceived as that is to say, one without the assistance of really distinct

each of

attributes

the other."
Still,

while extension

is

an attribute of God,

it

must not

be confused with corporeality in the popular anthropomorphic conception of God. Spinoza dismisses this popular form
of anthropomorphism which imagines "God to be like a man, composed of body and soul and subject to passion," without

much

ado, "for

all

the divine nature


this last

men who have deny that God

in
is

any way looked into 3 Behind corporeal."

statement there are the long discussions of the rabbis

and of

the religious philosophers since Philo, who sought to spiritualize or to explain away the anthropomorphic exall

Maimonides portions of the Bible. them when he emphasizes the importance of "God's incorporeali ty and His exemption from all passions," as doctrines "which must be explained to every one according to his capacity, and they must be taught by way of
pressions in
certain

speaks for all of

<

Ibid.

>

Ibid.
cf.

Ibid., I,

Prop. 15, Schol.

This Scholium belongs to Prop. 14;

Freudenthal,

"Spinozastudien," in Zeitschrift fur Philosophif, 108 (1896), p. 251, of this chapter is a discussion of the first part of this Scholium.

n. 2.

The

rest

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT


and women,
to the stupid

259

tradition to children

and igno-

rant/

'

The argument, however, which Spinoza reproduces in the name of philosophers for the incorporeality of God does not
represent any of the standard philosophical arguments re2 produced by Maimonides, but it does represent the argu-

ment quoted with approval by Maimonides in the name of the Kalam. The argument in Spinoza reads as follows: "That He cannot be so they conclusively prove by showing that by body we understand a certain quantity possessing length, breadth, and depth, limited by some fixed shape;
and that
is

to attribute this to

God, a being absolutely

infinite,

the greatest absurdity/' The Kalam argument in Maimonides reads as follows: "If God were corporeal, He would

be

finite,

which

is

true;

a certain dimension

and if He were finite, He would have and a certain fixed shape, which is equally
3

Spinoza's passage is clearly a paraphrase of Maimonides' passage with the additional inclusion of the current definition of "body."
a correct conclusion."

But the mediaevals, proceeds Spinoza, deny of God not only body but also matter and extension in general, and thus
by removing from divine nature "substance itself, corporeal " or extended," they affirm that it was created by God." This leads Spinoza to a recapitulation of his arguments against
creation, namely: if have arisen from Him

God
?

is

Of course,

pure form, how could matter the mediaevals have their

different solutions of the

none of them
vine power
it

problem of the origin of matter; " by what disufficiently explains, however, could have been created." This is quite a good
4 points against creation.
*

summary of his main


1

He concludes,

Moreh Nebukim,
Ibid., I, 76,

I,

35.

Ibid.,

and

II, i.

Third Argument.

Cf. above,

Chapter IV.

260

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

that as he always does after an argument against creation, extended substance is one of the infinite attributes of God."

"

Spinoza then reproduces two arguments by which the philosophers have endeavored to prove the incorporeality of

God:
First, that corporeal substance, in so far as it is substance, consists, as they suppose, of parts, and therefore they

"

deny that

it

can be

infinite,

and consequently that

it

can

pertain to God/' So far I have been unable to find the source of this argument in the form in which it is given here by

Spinoza.

made up

impression is that it is a composite argument of the following parts: (i) The standard argument for the incorporeality of God on the ground that God is one

My

and indivisible, whereas corporeality implies composition and divisibility. Maimonides puts this argument as follows: "There is no unity unless one discards corporeality, for a
corporeal thing is not one, but composed of matter and form, which are two distinct things by definition; and furthermore x it is divisible." Exactly the same argument is given by

Descartes

and

also

by Spinoza

in the Short Treatise*

(2)

The

Aristotelian denial of the existence of an infinite cor4


s

poreal magnitude, which is reproduced by Maimonides and elaborately discussed by Crescas. 6 That this argument is of a composite nature may be inferred from the following

statement with which Spinoza introduces it: "But for the sake of a fuller explanation, I will refute my adversaries
1

arguments^ which, taken altogether (omnia),


Moreh Nebukim,
Cf. below, p. 268.
1

come

to this."

I,

35.
I,

Principia Philosophiae,
Short Treatise ,

23; Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae,

I,

Prop. 16.

I, 2,

18 (Opera,
8 ff.;

I, p.

24,

11.

12-15).

Cf below,
.

p. 269.

Physics, III, 5, 2043,

Metaphysics, XI, 10, io66b,

ff.

Moreh Nebukim, II, Introduction, Prop. I. Or Adonai, I, i, i I, ii, i; cf. my Crescas'


;

Critique of Aristotle, pp. 135

ff.

PROP. 14]

EXTENSION AND THOUGHT


"
al together
is

261

"

Taken

undoubtedly a reference to the com-

posite nature of the argument.

argument
nature
in its
is

as reproduced here in the Ethics

further proof that the is of a composite


l

the fact that in the Short Treatise

it is

reproduced

simple form, without any mention of infinity. "A second argument is assumed from the absolute perfection of God. For God, they say, since He is a being absolutely perfect, cannot be passive; but corporeal substance, " This argument, too, is since it is divisible, can be passive. found in Descartes 2 and in the Short Treatise* and is implied

Maimonides' fourth proof for the existence, unity, and incorporeality of God from the concept of actuality and
in

potentiality.

which

parts of the Scholium to Proposition XV, taken up with a refutation of the alleged arguments against the possibility of an infinite corporeal substance, will be discussed in the next chapter.
is
1

The remaining

Short Treatise,

I, 2,

18 (Opera,

I, p.

24,

11.

11-15).

3 <

Principia Philosophiae, I, 23. 18 (Opera Short Treatise y I, 2,

I,

p. 24,

11.

15-18).

Moreh Nebukim^

II, i,

Fourth Argument.

CHAPTER

VIII

INFINITY OF EXTENSION

THE arguments
an

infinite corporeal

of his "opponents" against the possibility of substance are introduced by Spinoza

incidentally in connection with his discussion in the Ethics of the traditional rejection of extension as an attribute of

God. The cause of this rejection, declares Spinoza, is to be found in the alleged incompatibility of extension with the
infinity of the divine nature, for extension,

assumed
1

to be

divisible

and consisting of

parts, cannot be infinite.

And

thereupon Spinoza proceeds to adduce, as he says, "one or two/' but actually three, of the "many examples" by which his opponents have tried to show, on the assumption of the
divisibility of corporeal substance, that it could
finite.

not be in-

In the Short Treatise^ however, this traditional argufor the rejection of extension as a divine attribute is
infinity.
is

ment

reproduced without any reference to the problem of

According to
divisible

this earlier version of the

argument, extension

said to be rejected as an attribute of

and consisting of

parts,

2 simplicity of the divine nature. za's refutation of the argument

because, being incompatible with the In both these places Spinoit is

God

an attempt is the same show that extension need not necessarily be divisible and composed of parts. This he does by drawing a distinction between extension as an attribute and extension as a mode and by showing that while the latter is divisible the
to
1

Ethics, I, Prop. 15, Schol.: "First, that corporeal substance, in so far as it is substance, consists, as they suppose, of parts, and therefore they deny that it can be infinite, and consequently that it can pertain to God." 3 Short Treatise,!, 2, 18 (Opera, I, p. 24, 11. 11-15): "For since extension is divisible, the perfect being would have to consist of parts, and this cable to God, because He is a simple being."
is

altogether inappli-

PROP. i5,scHOL.]

INFINITY OF EXTENSION
In the Short treatise
*
*

263

former
clearly

is

simple.

this distinction is

drawn;

in the Ethics

there

is

only an emphasis on

the indivisibility and simplicity of substance, with the implied inference that modes only are composed of parts and divisible.

But

here, again, in the Short Treatise the refutation aims

to establish

the Ethics

it

merely the simplicity of extension, whereas in aims to establish its infinity as well as its sim-

In the Ethics, furthermore, Spinoza reinforces his plicity. refutation of his opponents by introducing a new distinction,
it

namely, a distinction between quantity regarded "as exists in the imagination" and quantity regarded "as it
former being "finite, divisible,

exists in the intellect/' the

and composed of parts" and the latter being "infinite, one, a distinction, he says, which will be and indivisible" "plain enough to all who know how to distinguish between the imagination and the intellect." 3 Both these distinctions mentioned in the Ethics occur also in two different places in
the Tractates de Intellectus Emendatione. In one place there, Spinoza says that the idea of quantity, if the understanding
(intellectus) forms it absolutely, is infinite, whereas the idea of quantity, if the understanding perceives it by means of a cause, is finite. 4 This distinction is undoubtedly identical

with his distinction between extension as an attribute and


extension as a mode, the former of which is infinite and the latter finite. In another place he speaks of the errors into which those "who do not accurately distinguish between in-

and he mentions as one of the errors their belief that extension must be finite. 5 Finally, these distinctions between substance and mode and between
tellect

and imagination"

easily

fall,

Short Treatise;

I, 2,

21-22 (Opera,
11.

I, p.

26,
1.

11.

6-7).
1.

Ethics, I, Prop. 15, Schol. (Opera, II, p. 58,


Ibid. (Opera, II, p. 59,

i6-p. 59,

i).

3
*

20-32).
108 (Opera, II, p. 39,
11.

Tractates de Intellectus Emendatione,


Ibid.,

4-14).

87 (p. 32,

1.

35-p. 33,

1.

3).

264
intellect

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

tinction,

and imagination, with the addition of a third disnamely, that between the infinite and the indefinite,

occur again in one of Spinoza's letters to Meyer. 1 It is the purpose of this chapter to isolate the problem of
the infinity of extension from the problem of the applicaof extension as an attribute of God, and to place this aspect of Spinoza's discussion of the problem of infinity, both
bility

the

arguments of

his

unnamed opponents and

also

his

criticism thereof, in the light of its historical setting. shall deal here with certain texts of Crescas some of which

We

have already impressed Joel and other students of Jewish


philosophy with their obvious resemblance to certain pas2 As mere parallel sages in Spinoza's discussion of infinity. are interesting enough, if only to increase the passages they

number of such

parallels that

may

be culled from the wide


It

philosophic literature of the Middle Ages. be of somewhat greater significance if it is

may

perhaps

shown that even

Spinoza's refutations are found

among

those offered by

Crescas, but here, too, as we shall see, they may be found also in the works of other writers. But the matter grows in

importance when we notice that the three "distinctions" mentioned by Spinoza in his letter remind one of three refutations by Crescas of three arguments which correspond
respectively to the three "examples" of Spinoza. The matter becomes of still greater importance when, as we hope

show, Spinoza's entire discussion of the indivisibility of infinite extension is found to involve many difficulties which
to

can be cleared up by the aid of a thorough understanding


of Crescas' position on the same subject.
1

Epistola 12.
Cf.

M. Joel, Dow Chasdai Creskas* religionsphilosophische Lehren, p. 22, n. i. Cross-references to Spinoza are also to be found in: M. Schreiner, Der Ka/am in der judischer Literatur^ p. 27, n. 5; I. I. Efros, The Problem of Space in Jewish
a

Mediaeval Philosophy, pp. 93, 97, 107;


Crescas , p. 40, n. 36.

M. Waxman, The Philosophy of Don Hasdai

PROP. 15, SCHOL.]

INFINITY OF EXTENSION
say that

265

It is safe to

rectly

whomsoever in particular and dihave had in mind when assailing his opSpinoza may

ponents for denying the infinity of corporeal substance, it is ultimately the views and arguments advanced by Aristotle

came out

Aristotle it was who boldly the conception of an infinite which had against been held by some of his predecessors, and it is in his writ-

that he

is

contending with.

With

ings that we find the most elaborate discussion of the subject. a long array of arguments, in which all his characteris-

tic theories of physics and metaphysics come into play, Aristotle exploded the theory of the existence of any possible phase of the infinite. This negation of the infinite, with the

in Aristotle's Physics, Metaand De CaeloJ had passed into the stock-in-trade of physics philosophic lore of mediaeval thought, where it played an

avalanche of arguments found


,

important part,

for it enters as

chief proofs for the existence of

an element into one of the God, namely, the cosmological

infinite regress.

proof based upon the assumption of the impossibility of an A few new arguments against infinity may

have been added later, the old arguments of Aristotle may have been changed, garbled, misinterpreted, split up, and reclassified, but it is always to Aristotle that any mediaeval discussion of the impossibility of an infinite can be traced.
It
is,

therefore, of the

utmost importance

for us to

know

to

what extent the reasons attributed by Spinoza

to his un-

denying the infinity of corporeal substance do actually agree with what we know to be the views
for

named opponents

of Aristotle.

main reason why Aristowas their belief that substance is composed of parts. "Wherefore the corporeal whole heap of arguments," he says, "by which philosophers
If

we were

to believe Spinoza, the

tle

and

his followers rejected infinity

Physics, III, 4-8; Metaphysics^ XI, 10;

De

Caelo,

I,

5-7.

266

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


to

[ETHICS,

commonly endeavor
finite, falls to

show that extended substance


its

is

the ground by

own

weight, for all these

arguments suppose that corporeal substance is made up of r It would also seem that it is not the mere divisibility parts."
of extended substance that Spinoza understood to be the assumption underlying the arguments against infinity, but
into heterogeneous parts and its comof those parts, so that extended substance, acposition cording to Spinoza, was not considered by his opponents

rather

its divisibility

as a continuous quantity.

Thus he

says:
is

"Wherefore those
of parts or of

who

think that extended substance

made up

not to say madly. It

bodies really distinct from one another are talking foolishly, is as though one should attempt by the
circles to

mere addition and aggregation of many


whole essence/'

make up

a square, or a triangle, or something else different in its 2 He furthermore compares the relation of

the parts of which corporeal substance is supposed to be composed to that of points to a line. "In the same way,
others,

who have persuaded themselves


also find
line is

that a line

is

made

they not divisible to infinity." 3 Finally, Spinoza seems to imply that the assumption of the divisibility of corporeal substance, which is supposed to underlie the rejection of its infinity, is analogous to the belief in the discontinuity of nature as held by those who admit the existence of

up of points, could would prove that a

many arguments by which

a vacuum, and thus he concludes the argument that "since, therefore, it is supposed that there is no vacuum in nature

(about which I will speak at another time), but that parts must be united, so that no vacuum can exist,

all

the

it fol-

lows that they cannot be really separated;


1

that

is

to say,

Epistola 12 (Opera, IV, p. 55,


Ibid. (p. 55,11. 11-16).
Ibid. (p. 56,
11.

1.

i6-p. 56,

1.

i).

' 3

2-4).

PROP. 15, SCHOL.]

INFINITY OF EXTENSION
it is

267

that corporeal substance, in so far as be divided." '

substance, cannot

And yet how strangely un-Aristotelian are these views attributed by Spinoza to Aristotle. Aristotle, as we know him from his own writings, no more considered corporeal
substance to consist of heterogeneous parts than a line to consist of points, for both body and line are to him continu-

ous quantities and infinitely divisible. "It is impossible," he says, "that anything continuous should be composed of
as, for instance, a line of points, since a line is a continued quantity, but a point is indivisible." 2 And what is true of a line is also true, according to Aristotle, of the " there is the same reasoning with other magnitudes, for

indivisibles;

respect to magnitude, time, and motion; for either each or no one of these consists of indivisibles and is divided into

Following out this line of reasoning, he concludes that "it is also evident that everything which is continuous is divisible into things always divisible." 4 And it is
indivisibles."

because of his belief in the continuity of corporeal substance that Aristotle rejects the existence of a vacuum and maintains "that there is not an interval different from bodies,

an interval which divides the either separable or actual whole body, so that it is not continuous, as Democritus and
or even perhaps Leucippus say, and many other physicists as something which is outside the whole body, which remains continuous." 5 Thus for every view ascribed by Spi-

noza to

his

opponents we

may

find in Aristotle a statement

Spinoza argues that his opponents denied the existence of an infinite because they
1

to the contrary. Then there is another difficulty.

Ethics,
*

I,

Prop. 15, Schol. (Opera,


I, 231.1,

II, p. 59,

11.

16-19).

Physics, VI,
i

24-26.
4
,

a s

Ibid. 2316, 18-20.


Ibid., IV, 6, 213,1,

Ibid., 23 ib, 15-16.

31-2135,

2.

268

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

erroneously believed that infinite substance must be divisible, whereas he maintains that infinite substance is indivisiAristotle himself discusses the possibility of an indivisible infinite substance, but, while admitting that there
ble.

Now,

is

an indivisible substance and that that substance can be

called infinite, he argues that the term "infinite" when applied to that indivisible substance will not mean infinite

except in the sense in which a voice is called "invisible," but that, he concludes, is not what he means by the term "infinite" when he investigates whether an infinite exists.

How

then can Spinoza argue against those who deny the existence of an infinite and at the same time use the term "infinite" in a sense

which

is

explicitly rejected

by

his

oppo-

nents ? Is he not committing here the fallacy of equivocation ? It has been suggested that in attacking his opponents for
conceiving corporeal substance as an aggregate of distinct bodies it was Descartes whom Spinoza was aiming at. 2 In proof of this a passage is cited in which Descartes rejects extension as a divine attribute on account of its divisibility.

A closer examination of this passage, however, will reveal that


while
it

are found "in authors,

contains one of those arguments which Spinoza says by which they endeavor to show that

corporeal substance is unworthy of divine nature, and cannot pertain to it," 3 that argument is not used by Descartes
to prove that corporeal substance cannot be infinite. Descartes simply endeavors to show that inasmuch as extension
is

divisible,

and inasmuch

as divisibility indicates imper-

fection, extension
1

cannot be an attribute of God. 4

This

Ibid., Ill, 5, 2043, 8-14;

a *

Cf.

H. H. Joachim,
I,

Metaphysics, XI, 10, io66b, 1-7. Study of the Ethics of Spinoza, p. 30,
11.

n. I.

Ethics,

Prop. 15, Schol. (Opera, II, p. 58,

13-16).

is

4 Principia Philosophiac, I, 23: "Thus since in corporeal nature divisibility included in local extension, and divisibility indicates imperfection, it is certain that God is not body." Compare Spinoza's Principia Philosophiae Cartfsianae, I, 1

Prop.

6.

PROP. i5,scHOL.]

INFINITY OF EXTENSION

269

exactly corresponds to the second of the two arguments which Spinoza ascribes, both in the Ethics and in the Short
Treatise, to those

who denied

extension as an attribute of

only that Tschirnhaus said to Leibin the name of Spinoza, that Descartes erniz, evidently 2 But it does roneously attributed divisibility to extension.
It
is

God. 1

in this sense

not

mean

matter and

that Descartes believed in the heterogeneity of its divisibility into irreducible parts on account

of which he had to deny its infinity. Quite the contrary* Descartes believed that matter, whose essence is extension, 3

Furthermore, Descartes was far from considering corporeal substance to consist of parts really distinct from one another, for, by denying the existence of
is

infinite in extent. 4

atoms

and of a vacuum, 6 he held extension


7

to be continuous
cer8

and

infinite in divisibility.

Though he admits "that

tain sensible bodies are


1

composed of

insensible particles,"

Ethics, I, Prop. 15, Schol. (Opera, II, p. 58, 11. 9-13): "A second argument is assumed from the absolute perfection of God. For God, they say, since He is a be-

ing absolutely perfect, cannot suffer; but corporeal substance, since it is divisible, can suffer: it follows, therefore, that it does not pertain to God's essence." Short
treatise, I, 2,
it is

18 (Opera,

I, p.

24,

11.

13-15): "Moreover,

when extension

is

divided

passive,

and with God (who

is

other being, because He is the first the cause." See Wolf's note on p. 178. Cf. above, p. 260. 2 "Extensionem non inferre divisibilitatem, inque eo lapsum esse Cartesium."
Cf.

never passive, and cannot be affected by any efficient cause of all) this can by no means be

K.

I.

Gerhardt, "Leibniz und

Spinoza," in Sitzungsberichte der

kb'niglich

prfussischen Akademie der H'issenschaften zu Berlin, 1889, p. IO 77> reprinted also in I,. Stein, Leibniz und Spinoza, p. 283.
*

Cf. Princtpia Philosophiae, II, 4,


2.

and Principia Philosophiae Cartcsianae,

II,

Prop.
4

Cf. Princtpia

Philosophiae, II, 21, and Principia Phihsophiae Cartesianae,

II,

Prop.
s

6.

Cf. Principia Philosophiae, II, 20,


5.

and Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae,

II,

Prop.
6

Cf. Principia Philosophiae, II, 16-19,


3.

and Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae ,

II,
*

Prop.

Cf. Principia Philosophiae, II, 34,

and Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae,

II,
8

Prop.

5,

Demonst.

Principia Philosophiae, IV, 201.

270

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

he himself takes great pains to point out that these parts are not indivisible and insists that his view has more in common
with that of Aristotle than with that of Democritus.
that
l

All

we may
is

gather, therefore, from Descartes*


is

own

state-

ments
the

that, while extension


it is

divisible

and hence cannot

be applied to God,

same way

as,

not divisible into indivisible parts in according to Spinoza's arguments here


if it

against his opponents, a line would have to be divisible were conceived to consist of points.
It

was thus not

Aristotle

and

his followers

whom

Spinoza

ascribed to his opponents the discreteness of corporeal substance as the reason for their denyits infinity. Still less could he have meant Descartes, for Descartes not only like Aristotle believed in the continuity of extension, but also like Spinoza held it to be infinite. Un-

could have meant

when he

ing

less, therefore,

we

are inclined to say that Spinoza willfully

imposed upon his opponents views which they would disclaim or that he unwarily misunderstood their position, we are bound to look for some new meaning that may lie concealed behind his uttered words.
to find out

We

must particularly try

whether

it is

not possible that Spinoza uses here

the terms "indivisible" and "divisible" in

some
it

special

and

generally unknown
special,

sense, for

it is

in the discovery of

such a

uncommon

use of these two terms,

would seem,

we may find an answer to the questions raised by us. We must therefore acquaint ourselves thoroughly with the sources from which we have reason to believe Spinoza had
that

drawn

knowledge of the ancient controversy about inorder to learn the exact meaning of the terms he uses, to fill out the gaps in his fragmentary statements, and
his
finity in

to restate the full implications of his argument of which words are sometimes mere suggestions.
1

his

Ibid., IV, 202.

PROP. i5,scHOL.]

INFINITY OF EXTENSION

271

Allowing ourselves to be guided by the gentle hand of Averroes through the uncharted texts of Aristotle's writings,
for
it

was Averroes by

whom

Spinoza's predecessors had

been so wisely guided in their pursuit of the same subject, we may restate for our purpose certain pertinent facts with
regard to Aristotle's conception of infinity, by definition, must be divisible, for "if it
will
(i)
is

An

infinite,

indivisible, it

not be

infinite, unless in the

same manner

as voice

is

Those, however, who say that there is the infinite do not assert that it thus subsists, nor do we investigate it as a thing of this kind, but as that which cannot be passed
invisible.
*

through."

(2)

divisible infinite

must be one of the

fol-

lowing three:

(a)

quantity existing as an accident in a

corporeal subject, 2 corporeal substance.


poreal subject
is

(b)

An incorporeal quantity, (c) An inAn accidental quantity existing in a cor-

dismissed as something irrelevant to the

conception of infinity under discussion. Then an incorporeal infinite quantity is dismissed on the ground that there is no

To quote Averroes: "It cannot be an incorporeal quantity, for since number and magnitude are inseparable from sensible objects, it follows that whatever
incorporeal quantity.

an accident of number and magnitude must likewise be inseparable, and infinity is such an accident, for finitude and
is

infinity are

two accidents existing in number and magnitude, inasmuch as the essence of number and magnitude is not
3

identical with the essence of the infinite."


finite incorporeal
1

Finally, an in-

substance

is

rejected on the ground of the

Physics, III, 5, 2043, 12-14. Cf. Metaphysics ) XI, 10, io66b, 5-7. Cf. Averroes' Middle Commentary on the Physics, Book III, Summa iii, Chapter 4: "If the infinite is divisible, it must inevitably bean incorporeal quantity
a

or a quantity existing in a subject or one of the incorporeal substances." Paraphrased also by Crescas, Or Adonai, I, i, i (p. 4a). Cf. my Crescas Critique of Aristotle,
J

pp. 137 and 330.

Averroes,

loc. cit.

Critique of Aristotle, pp. 137

Paraphrased also by Crescas, he. and 330.

cit. (p.

4a-b).

Cf. Crescas*

272

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


if it

[ETHICS,

absurdities that would ensue


ible.

were supposed to be divis-

We shall quote

the argument on this last point in three

versions:

evident that
sisting in

In Aristotle the argument is given as follows: "It is also it is not possible for the infinite to be, as sub-

energy and as essence and a principle: for whatever of it is assumed will be infinite, if it is partible: for the part essence of infinite and the infinite are the same, since the

and is not predicated of a Hence it is either indivisible, or divisible into insubject. finites. But it is impossible that there can be many infinites in the same thing. As air, however, is part of air, so likewise infinite is a part of infinite, if it is essence and a principle. It But this is impossiis, therefore, impartible and indivisible.
infinite is essence or substance,
ble, since it is infinite in energy; for it is necessary that it should be a certain quantum." Averroes' version of the same argument runs as follows:
l

"

After

we have shown

that the infinite cannot be an incor-

poreal nor a corporeal quantity, there is nothing left but that it should be an incorporeal substance, of the kind we
intellect, so that the thing assumed to be described as infinite, and infinite being itself are one in definition and essence and not different in reason.

affirm of soul

and

infinite, that

is,

However,
of

if

we assume

the infinite to be of this kind,

its

essence thus being at one with its definition, then, as a result its being infinite, we shall be confronted with the question
it is

whether

divisible or indivisible.

[In the first case,]

if it

be divisible, then the definition of a part and the whole of it will be the same in this respect, as must necessarily be the
case in simple, homoeomerous things. But if this be so, then the part of the infinite will be infinite. For the parts must inevitably either be different from the infinite whole or not
1

Physics, III,

5,

204a, 20-29. Cf. Metaphysics^ XI, 10, io66b, 11-19.

PROP. 15, SCHOL.]

INFINITY OF EXTENSION

273

be different therefrom. If they be different, then the infinite will be composite and not simple; if they be not different,
then the definition of the part will be the same as that of the whole, for this reasoning must necessarily follow in the case of all things that are homoeomerous. Just as part of air is
air,

and part of

flesh is flesh, so part of infinite is infinite,

forasmuch as the part and the whole in each of these are one in definition and essence. If a difference is found in the parts
of homoeomerous bodies, it is due only to the subject which is the receptacle of the parts and not to the form, for if we

imagine the form of a homoeomerous body without a subject, the parts and the whole thereof will be the same in all respects

and without any

difference.

[In the second case,] if

we say

that the infinite incorporeal substance is indivisible, which must be the case of an incorporeal qua incorporeal, then it
infinite except in the sense in which a point is said to be infinite. In general, the treatment of the existence of an incorporeal infinite is irrelevant to the subject under discussion."

cannot be said to be

This Averroian version of Aristotle's argument is briefly restated by Crescas in the following terms: "Again, we cannot help asking ourselves whether this incorporeal substance
is

divisible or indivisible.

If

it

is

divisible, since it

is

also

incorporeal, simple, and homoeomerous, the definition of any of its parts will be identical with that of the whole, and since the whole is now assumed to be infinite, any part thereof will likewise have to be infinite. But it is of the utmost that the whole and a part thereof should be alike absurdity
[in infinity].

And
must

if it is indivisible,

which, indeed, as an
it infinite,

in-

corporeal, as a point
1

it

be,

we can no

longer call
2

except

is

said to be infinite/'
cit. y

Averroes, he.

quoted

in

my

Or Adonai,

loc. cit. (p. 4:1).

Crescas' Critique ofAristotle, pp. 3 j 1-332. Cf. Crescas' Critique of Aristotle, p. 137.

274

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

The gravamen

of this Aristotelian argument against an

have been gathered, is that if it were divisible its parts would each have to be either infinite or finite, neither of which is possible. It is this
infinite incorporeal substance, as will

argument that is reproduced by Spinoza in his first "example": "If corporeal substance, they say, be infinite, let us conceive it to be divided into two parts; each part, therefore,
will

infinite is

be either finite or infinite. If each part be finite, then the composed of two finite parts, which is absurd. If
l

each part be infinite, there is then an infinite twice as great It will be recalled as another infinite, which is also absurd."
that
it
is

by

this

proved
It
is

in Propositions

very same reasoning that Spinoza has XII and XIII that an infinite must

be indivisible. 2

simply a matter of ordinary good reasoning that any

attempt at a refutation of Aristotle's arguments against infinity will have to proceed from his own premises and will

have to use terms

in his

own

sense.

The

infinite will

have

to be a quantitative term, "for it is necessary that it should be a certain quantum," 3 as Aristotle plainly puts it. It will

have to be

divisible.

This at once renders

it futile

to seek to

establish an infinite incorporeal substance which is not quantitative and not divisible and of which the use of the term
infinite

merely means

its

exclusion from
as a point
is

the universe of

finitude in the

same sense

said to be infinite.

The
will

infinite, the existence

of which any criticism of Aristotle

seek to establish, will thus have to be an incorporeal

quantity, inasmuch as an infinite quantity existing as an accident in a corporeal subject has been disposed of by Aristotle himself as something inconsistent with the conception of infinity. /
1

But an

infinite

quantity has been rejected * j


11.

Ethics,
a

I,

Prop. 15, Schol. (Opera,


*

II, p. 57,

28-33).

Cf. above, pp. 156-157.

Cf. quotation above, p. 272,

PROP. 15, SCHOL.]

INFINITY OF EXTENSION

275

by
an

Aristotle on the

exists.

The

first

ground that no incorporeal quantity step, therefore, in proving the existence of

infinite will

quantity. will be divisible in conformity with the definition of the term infinite, will at the same time also have to be homoeomerous,

be to establish the existence of an incorporeal Furthermore, this incorporeal quantity, while it

as everything incorporeal perforce must be, and consequently, as a second step, a way will have to be found by which the

parts into which it is divisible will not each be infinite like the whole nor finite unlike the whole.
It is exactly this process of reasoning that is employed by Crescas in his criticism of Aristotle. Endeavoring to show

that an infinite is possible, he first seeks to establish the existence of an incorporeal quantity. He does so by proving, by arguments which do not concern us here, that a vacuum

does exist, not indeed within the universe, dispersed throughout the pores of bodies and thus breaking up their continuity, as was held by Democritus, but rather outside the universe,
the view held by the Pythagoreans. 1 The vacuum is nothing but tridimensional extension, or, as Crescas calls it, "in-

corporeal dimensions'* as contrasted with a


is
2

plenum which

tinction

The significance of this dis"corporeal dimensions/' may be fully appreciated when compared with the

is

view of Aristotle. Tridimensionality, according to Aristotle, either the essence of matter or a form of matter, for there

a difference of opinion among his commentators on that 3 In either case, tridimensionality is always corporeal, point.
is

for

even

if it is

a form of matter, as a form

it

cannot exist
outside the

without matter.
universe
1

But

to Crescas the

vacuum

is

tridimensionality which
',

has an independent,

Cf.

my

Crescas' Critique of Aristotle


I, ii,
i

pp. 53-60.

Cf. Crescas' Critique of Aristotle', p. 187. Cf. Crescas' Critique oj Aristotle y p. 101 and n. 18 on pp. 579-590. Cf. above,
(p. 146).

Or Adonai,

PP- 234-235-

276

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

Furthermore, this incorporeal tridimensionality, argues Crescas, is a continuous quantity, i.e., a magnitude, inasmuch as it is described in terms of a continuis

incorporeal existence.

ous quantity rather than in those of a discrete quantity, for it said to be "great and small" rather than "much and few."
I

As such
that
it

it is

infinite in divisibility.

must likewise be infinite in would have to terminate either at a body or at another vacuum. That it should terminate at a body, however,
limit
it is

But Crescas argues also extent, "for if it had a

impossible.

It will, therefore,

have to terminate at another

2 vacuum, and that will go on to infinity." But here Crescas seems to become conscious of the

diffi-

by ment, against an

culty raised

Aristotle, in Averroes' version of the arguinfinite incorporeal substance.


it is

The

infinite

vacuum

is

divisible, but

also

homoeomerous.

This

being the case, the parts of the infinite vacuum will either be identical with the whole in definition or not. If they are,

then the parts will each be infinite like the whole; if they are not, then the whole will be composed of heterogeneous parts. The passage in which Crescas refutes Aristotle's argument

and

in

which he also seems to touch upon

this difficulty

may

be given here in full: "We say that the argument is fallacious and a begging of the question. For he who assumes the existence of an incorporeal infinite

magnitude likewise affirms

the existence of an incorporeal quantity. By the same token, it does not follow that the definition of the infinite would have
to apply to its parts, just as such reasoning does not follow
in the case

of a mathematical

line.

Nor would

there have to

be any composition in it except of parts of itself." 3 This passage of Crescas is evidently meant to be a refuta1

Or Adonai)
Ibid.

I, ii,

(p. 153).

Cf.

my

Crescas' Critique of Aristotle, p. 189.

' 3

Or Adonai y

loc. cit. (p.

Ha).

Cf. Crescas

Critique of Aristotle , p. 179.

PROP. 15, SCHOL.]

INFINITY OF EXTENSION

277

argument contained in the passage quoted above from Averroes and of which Crescas himself has given a paration of the

phrase.

It will be recalled that Averroes argues against two alternatives in the case where the infinite is assumed possible to be both homoeomerous and divisible. First, if the parts are each infinite like the whole, then the parts of an infinite

will

be

infinite,

which

is

absurd.

Second,
is

each

finite,

then the infinite whole


is

the parts are composed of dissimilar


if

therefore no longer homoeomerous, which is to the assumption. Now, in this passage Crescas contrary evidently tries to answer both these alternatives. As against

parts and

the

first,

to be of the

he seems to say that though the parts are assumed same kind as the whole, they are not each inwhole, for "it does not follow that the defini-

finite like the

tion of the infinite

would have

to apply to all its parts, just

matical

as such reasoning does not follow in the case of a matheline.'' As against the second, he seems to say that

though the parts are

finite,

the infinite whole would not be

composed of dissimilar parts, for "nor would there have to be any composition in it except of parts of itself."
examine, however, this passage closely, we find reasoning is not quite fully explained. In the first Crescas does not fully explain why in an infinite place,
that
its

When we

which

is

assumed

to be

homoeomerous and

infinite in essence

the parts should not each be infinite like the whole. He merely asserts that it would not have to be so in the case of

an
low

infinite, just as

in

something similar would not have to folthe case of a mathematical line. But we may ask

ourselves:

The

infinite

under discussion

is

infinite in

its

essence just as a mathematical line is linear in its essence, and since the parts of the line are linear like the whole, why

whole?

should not also the parts of the infinite be infinite like the In the second place, when Crescas, arguing appar-

278

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

ently against the second alternative, tries to show that the infinite would not be composed of dissimilar parts even if its
parts were each
to be
is

finite,

he simply says "nor would there have

any composition in it except of parts of itself." What the meaning of this statement? Joel, probably starting with the a priori belief that Crescas

must have used the analogy of the mathematical line in the same way as it is used by Spinoza in his letter to Meyer, paraphrases this passage as follows: "So wenig die Linie aus Punkten bestehe, so wenig habe man sich die unendliche

Ausdehnung aus Theilen zusammengesetzt zu denken."

This paraphrase seems to take the passage as a refutation of an argument which assumes that the infinite is composed of

But as we have seen, quite the conthe analogy of the mathematical line is meant to be trary, a refutation of that part of the argument, paraphrased by
heterogeneous parts.
Crescas himself from Averroes, in which it is urged that if the infinite does not consist of heterogeneous parts, then the
parts of the infinite will each have to be infinite. In order to get at the meaning of this difficult passage

we

call to our aid everything that was possibly known to Crescas about a mathematical line and its definition and out

must

meant by

of this try to reconstruct imaginatively what he could have his allusion to a mathematical line as a solution
infinite.

of the difficulty raised against the existence of an

Two main
known

facts

about a mathematical
In the
first

line

must have been

to Crescas.

place, he

was acquainted with

Euclid's definitions of a line, of which there are two. But it must have been the second of these definitions 2 with which

Crescas operated, for


frequently quoted
1

it is this

second definition which

is

most

in the texts

with which Crescas was ac-

M.

Joel,

Elements,

Don Chasdai Creskas' Book I, Def. 3.

religionsphilosophische Lehren, p. 22.

PROP. 15, SCHOL.]


1

INFINITY OF EXTENSION

279

quainted.

This definition reads:

"The

extremities of a line

are points." In the second place, Crescas was well acquainted with Aristotle's statements that a line is a continuous quan2

tity

and that "everything which

is

continuous

is

divisible

into things always divisible/' 3 According to these statements, then, a line is divisible into parts which are lines, and

presumably a line can also be said to be composed of those lines into which it is divisible. Now the following question
be raised against these statements of Aristotle. Since the parts into which a line is divisible and of which they are also composed are according to Aristotle lines, they must also

may

be defined as
line,

lines.

But by Euclid's second

definition of a

the extremities of a line are said to be points. Consequently, if a line is divided into as well as composed of lines, a line must be also divided into and composed of points.

contrary to Aristotle's statement that a line continuous quantity and does not consist of points. 4
this
is

But

is

This question must have undoubtedly been in the mind of Crescas when he made his allusion to the definition of a

mathematical

line.

In his brief statement that the definition

of the parts, of both the infinite and the line, is not identical with that of the whole and that both would not be composed

except of parts of themselves, he gives us some clue as to


this question would be. He would answer that incorporeal quantities, which are continuby saying ous and homoeomerous like a mathematical line and the

what

his

answer to

it

infinite

vacuum, have no

in discrete quantities,

different units, or in

parts. Parts are to be found only such as number, which is made up of corporeal continuous quantities where

the parts differ from the whole in accidental qualities, as,


1

Averroes* Epitome of the Physics, III (Hebrew version), p. rob.

Cf. Isaac

Israeli, Sefer Yesodot, II, p.


3

45

(ed. Fried).
*

Physics, VI,
Ibid.,

i,

2313, 24.

Ibid.,

VI,

I,

ijib, 15-16.

VI,

I,

ijia, 24-26.

280

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


an actual
line

[ETHICS,

for instance, the parts of

which

differ

from the
in

whole
line as

in length.

If Aristotle does speak of a

mathematical
is

being infinitely divisible, the divisibility

merely

thought and

in capacity; in reality infinite divisibility

means

nothing but a denial that the line consists of parts different from the whole. Or, to put the matter in other words, in the
case of a discrete quantity, or of a corporeal continuous quantity, the whole is both divisible into parts and composed of those parts into which it is divisible; but in the case

of an incorporeal continuous quantity, while the whole is infinitely divisible into parts, it is not composed of those
parts into which it is infinitely divisible. In the case of the former, the parts are actual and co-exist with the whole; in
the case of the latter, the parts are only potential and do not co-exist with the whole. This is what is behind Crescas'

statement that the definition of the whole need not necessarily

apply to the parts, for the parts are never actual and do never co-exist with the whole, and this is also what he

not composed "except of parts of itself," i.e., of parts which do not exist outside the whole or beside the whole. If Crescas had carried out
is

means by saying that the whole

his

argument

in full

discussion as to "whether the formula

he would have drawn upon Aristotle's [i.e., definition] of the

* parts must be present in the formula of the whole or not," in the course of which discussion Aristotle says: "For even

if

the line

when divided

passes

away

into

its

halves, or the

man

into bones

and muscles and

flesh, it

does not follow that

they are composed of these as parts of their essence, but rather as matter; and these are parts of the concrete thing, but not of the form, i.e., of that to which the formula refers." *
Metaphysics, VII, 10, 10346, 23-24. Metaphysics, VII, 10, 10353, 17-21. This interpretation of Crescas' passage fully worked out in my Crescas' Critique oj Aristotle ^ pp. 391-394.
2

is

PROP. 15, SCHOL.]

INFINITY OF EXTENSION

281

In other words, to be divisible does not always

mean

to be

composed.

The essential point in Crescas' answer to Aristotle's argument rests, as we have seen, upon the distinction between the vacuum outside the world and the plenum within it, or between incorporeal extension and corporeal extension. The answer given by Spinoza to the same argument, reproduced by him in his first "example/' is based upon a similar distinction. What Crescas calls incorporeal extension or vacuum or space logically corresponds to what Spinoza calls extended substance or the attribute of extension, and what Crescas calls corporeal extension corresponds to what Spinoza calls To both of them, the the particular modes of extension.
1

former

is infinite,

whereas the latter


it is

is finite.

Spinoza thus
"
ex-

says in his letter to Meyer, and "

in

answer

to the first

ample

mentioned

upon a
infinite

failure to

argument is based "between that which must be distinguish


in the Ethics, that the

very nature, or in virtue of its definition, and that which has no limits, not indeed in virtue of its esits

from

sence, but in virtue of


his

its

cause."

From

a comparison of

subsequent elaboration of this distinction in the letter with his corresponding discussion of the same distinction in
the Ethics* in the Short Treatise^ and in the Tractates de Intellectus

Emendatione

it is

clear that the distinction

is

that

between extension as an attribute and as a mode. That the latter is described by the expression "in virtue of its cause"

may
1

be explained by the fact that Spinoza regards the relation of substance to mode as that of cause to effect. 6
Cf. Crescas' Critique of Aristotle t pp. 116-118. Kpistola 12 (Opera, IV, p. 53, 11. 2-5). Ethics, I, Prop. 15, Schol. (Opera, 11, p. 58, 1. i6-p. 59, 21-22 (Opera, I, p. 26, 11. 6-17). Short treatise, I, 2,

1.

19).

Tractatus de Intellects Emendatione,


Cf. above, p. 76,

108 (Opera, II, p. 39,

11.

4-14).

and below,

p. 324.

282

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


his

[ETHICS,

With

adoption of the old distinction between the two

his description thereof.

kinds of extension, Spinoza also follows his predecessors in But before we take up this point,
to explain Spinoza's use of the terms

we have

"

indivisible

"

and "divisible

"

in these descriptions.

We have seen how

the

term "divisible"
bility.

First, it

may may apply

apply to three different kinds of divisito

what the mediaevals would

call

an incorporeal continuous quantity, such as Crescas Vacuum or a mathematical line, which is free of any accidents. This is
said to be divisible to infinity into parts which are homogeneous with the whole, that is to say, a vacuum into vacuums and

a line into lines. Second,

it

may apply to what

the mediaevals

would

a corporeal continuous quantity which is subject to qualitative or quantitative accidents. This is said to be
call

divisible into parts

the whole differ

which while not generically different from from it and from one another by certain

qualitative or quantitative accidents. Thus, to use the illustration given by Averroes in the passage quoted above,

while parts of air are air and parts of flesh are flesh, the parts differ from the whole and from one another in size or quality
or in

some other accident. Third,


is

it

may

apply to a discrete

said to be divisible into parts which are with the whole and of which the whole is comheterogeneous posed. Now, the first of these three kinds of divisibility is
divisibility only in potentiality but not in actuality, for no actual division into infinity is possible. To say therefore of a thing that it is potentially infinitely divisible is tantamount

quantity which

to saying that actually

it

is

indivisible.

In fact, Aristotle

defines a continuous quantity as that which is divisible, describes such a quantity also as indivisiinfinitely
himself,

who

not being infinitely divisible in actuality. "Since, however, the term indivisible (adialptrov) has two meanings, according as a whole is not potentially divisible,
its

on account of

PROP. 15, SCHOL.]

INFINITY OF EXTENSION
is

283

ble or

is

actually undivided, there


*

nothing to hinder us
this pas-

from thinking an indivisible whole, when we think of length


(that being actually undivided)/'

Drawing upon

sage of Aristotle,
indivisible
is

Thomas Aquinas
is

threefold, as
is

similarly says: said in De Anima^ III.


is

"Now

the

First,

the continuous

indivisible, since actually it


.
.
.

although potentially divisible.


visible
is

The

undivided, third kind of indi-

what

is

altogether indivisible, as a point

and unity,

which cannot be divided either actually or potentially/' 2 Now, in order to remove the difficulties we have pointed
out at the beginning of the chapter with regard to Spinoza's reproduction of the views of his opponents and also in order
the infinite extension which Spinoza affirms to be of the same kind with reference to divisibility as that which
to

make

Aristotle denies,

we must assume

that

when Spinoza
an

in his

arguments

against Aristotle's denial of

infinite extension
it

insists that extension is indivisible

he does not mean that

is indivisible like a point, that is to say, indivisible even potentially, but rather that it is indivisible like a continuous

quantity in Aristotle's
that
it is

own

indivisible in actuality.

use of the term, which means He is thus not arguing

against Aristotle from a new assumption which Aristotle would not admit, but he is rather arguing against him from
Aristotle's

own assumption. And, similarly, when he argues that his Aristotelian opponents believe that extension is divisible and is composed of parts, he does not mean to say
that they believe that extension
1

is

divisible into,

and com-

De /4nima,

III, 6, 430!), 6-8.

Theologica^ Pars I, Quaest. 85, Art. 8: "Dicitur autem indivisibile uno modo sicut continuum tripliciter, ut dicitur in 3 de Anima (text. 23 et deinceps)
:

Summa

est indivisibile, quia est

indivisum in actu,

licet

sit divisibile in

potentia.

Tertio

modo

dicitur indivisibile

quod

est

omnino

indivisibile, ut

punctus et unitas,

quae nee actu nee potentia dividuntur" (quoted (1895), un der "indivisibilis").

also

by

Schiitz in

Thomas -Lexikon

284

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


of,

[ETHICS,

posed

heterogeneous parts as
to say
is

what he means

were a discrete quantity; that, thinking as they do of extenif it

sion only as that

which

is

subject to accidental differences,

they believe it to be divisible into parts which are quantitatively different from one another, and from such an assumption they argue against the existence of an infinite extension

as one would argue against the infinite of a line or of matter if one started out with the divisibility assumption that a line is composed of points and that matter is composed of heterogeneous atoms dispersed in a
in

the

same way

vacuum.
this:

The
is

point which

have been trying

to

make

is

When

extension
is

opponents with a belief that Spinoza divisible, he does not mean to say that extension
charges his

held by them to be divisible into indivisible parts. What he means to say is that in their use of the divisibility of ex-

argument against its infinity they failed to distinguish between extension as an attribute, or what the
mediaevals would
as a
call

tension as an

an incorporeal extension, and extension


it is

mode, or

what the mediaevals would


former, because

tension.

The

a corporeal exdivisible into homogeneous


call

parts, can be called indivisible, and can therefore be infinite. The latter, however, because it is divisible into parts which

are quantitatively different, cannot be infinite. The attribute of extension is described by Spinoza in the

same terms

in which the infinite incorporeal substance is described in the passage quoted above from Averroes. It is "infinite from its very nature, or in virtue of its definition"

or "in virtue of
tension
it is

its

essence."

Like Crescas' incorporeal ex-

continuous and has no parts, for "part and whole are not true or real entities, but only things of reason, and
consequently there are in nature
1

[i.e.,

substantial extension]

Epistola 12 (Opera, IV, p. 53,

11.

2-5).

PROP.

5 ,scHOL.]

INFINITY OF EXTENSION

285

neither whole nor parts." x It, therefore, "cannot be divided into parts, or can have no parts "; 2 but, as we have already pointed out, by this Spinoza simply means what Aristotle

would have sometimes described as being continuous and infinitely divisible and what Crescas would have characterized as not being

mode

" and divisible 3 just as any corporeal object, in parts the view of his predecessors, is divisible either into heterogeneous parts or into parts which are qualitatively or quanti.

composed except of parts of itself. The of extension, on the other hand, is "composed of finite
.
.

tatively different from each other. "Further/' says Spinoza, "as regards the parts in nature, we maintain that division, as has also been said already before, never takes place in substance, but always and only in the modes of substance.

want to divide water, I only divide the mode of 4 substance, and not substance itself/' Similarly, in the pasThus,
if I

sage quoted above from Averroes, we read: "Just as part of air is air, and part of flesh is flesh, so part of infinite is infinite, forasmuch as the part and the whole in each of these

and essence. If a difference is found in the parts of homoeomerous bodies [like air and flesh], it is due only to the subject which is the receptacle of the parts and not to the form, for if we imagine the form of a homoeomerous body without a subject, the parts and the whole
are one in definition

thereof will be the same in


difference/'

all

respects

and without any

be sure, Bruno, too, in his criticism of Aristotle's rejection of infinity dwells upon the absence

To

of parts in the
1

infinite,

but there

is

more

in Spinoza's state-

3
*

I, 2, 19 (Opera, I, p. 24, 11. 19-21). Kpistola 12 (Opera, IV, p. 53, 11. 12-13). Ethics, I, Prop. 15, Schol. (Opera, II, p. 59, 11. 2-3).

Short Treatise,

Short Treatise,
Cf.

I, 2,

21 (Opera, IV, p. 26,

11.

6-1

1).

The same illustration from


1.

water occurs also


5

in Ethics, I, Prop. 15, Schol. (Opera, II, p. 59,

35~p. 60,

1.

3).

De rtnfnito

universo et

Mondi,

Dial. II, p. 337 (ed. Lagarde).

286

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


is

[ETHICS,

merit than in Bruno's, and the excess of Crescas.

strongly reminiscent

Thus when Spinoza maintains


ence of an

against Aristotle the existdivisible.

infinite, indivisible extension, he does not reject

Aristotle's conception of the infinite as

something

The

indivisibility of his extension

is

not like the indivisibility

of a point, but rather like the indivisibility which Aristotle sometimes applies to a continuous quantity which is otherwise described by him as infinitely divisible. Again, when he charges his opponents with considering extension as divisible
points, he does not mean that they held extension to be a discrete quantity, similar to the discreteness of a line if it were supposed to consist of points; he only means to say that, denying the existence of pure

and composed of distinct

extension, they considered extension divisible and composed of parts on account of the qualitative or quantitative differences in the parts of the material subject in which it existed,
in the

and thus they argued against the infinity of extension same way as one could argue against the infinite divisimatter
if

bility of a line or of

one started with the assumption

that a line was composed of points and that matter was up of heterogeneous parts dispersed in a vacuum.

made

Against the existence of an

infinite extension there is an-

other argument the purpose of which is to show that the assumption of an infinite would give rise to the absurdity of one infinite being greater than another. This argument appears under various forms in many works of Hebrew and

Arabic philosophic literature, and it also occurs in the writings of Bruno. We shall restate here two versions of this

argument.

One
1

version

is

found
in

in Saadia,

by Crescas, and
Emunot
we-De'ot,

Bruno.

in Gersonides, followed In Gersonides, the argument is


(4).

I,

3,

Eighth Theory

PROP. 15, SCHOL.]

INFINITY OF EXTENSION

287

illustrated by the movements of the heavenly spheres and is aimed against the eternity and hence the infinity of time in

the past. Several propositions are assumed in this argument. First, some of the heavenly spheres move faster than others.

Second, in the same given time, the fast-moving spheres perform a greater number of rotations than the slow-moving.
Third, one infinite cannot be greater than another. Out of these propositions the argument may be formulated as follows:
If time be infinite in the past, then the fast-moving

number of

and slow-moving spheres will have performed an infinite rotations. But since the number of rotations of
the fast-moving sphere

must be greater than that of the slow-

moving, one

be greater than another. 1 In Bruno's argument the same difficulty is raised, but the illustration is taken from the division of infinite distance into an infinite
infinite will

number of paces
Spinoza's second

(or feet)

and an
"

infinite

number of

miles.

example follows closely these two arguments, resembling in form more that of Bruno than that of " Gersonides. Again, if infinite quantity is measured by
equal parts of a foot each, it must contain an infinite number of such parts, and similarly if it be measured by equal parts
Milhamot Adonai, VI, i, 1 1 (pp. 341-342) "Having laid down these premises, I contend that, if past time were infinite in quantity, it would follow that there could be no swift motion and slow motion among the spheres. The argument runs as
1
:

"

follows: The number of rotations performed by the swift-moving sphere in the past time, which is assumed to be infinite, must of necessity be infinite, and the same must be true of the number of rotations performed by the slow-moving sphere.

But inasmuch
infinite

as one infinite

number cannot be

greater nor smaller than another

number, it will follow that no one sphere is of swifter motion than another, for if one sphere moved more swiftly than another, the number of rotations of the swift sphere would of necessity be greater." This argument is reproduced in Or Adonai, III, i, 3 (p. 643).
Dial. II (p. 338): "El. Particolarmente di quello fare proposito nostro de gl' infiniti passi, et infinite migla che uerrebono un infinite minore, et un* altro infinite maggiore nell' immensitudine de 1'uniuerso."
3

De I* infinite universe etMondi,


al

che fa

Cf.

on the same page: "la dimensione

infinita

non 6 meno de

infiniti piedi,

che de

infinite migla."

288

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

of an inch each; and therefore one infinite number will be r twelve times greater than another infinite number." In his answer Bruno endeavors to show that in the infinite
there can be no distinction of

number and measure. "It

is

an absurdity to say that in the infinite one part is greater and another is smaller, and one part has a greater proportion
to the

whole and another a smaller/'

numerable and the immeasurable there


or less, few or

is

Again: "In the inno place for more

measure."

any distinction of number or is also made by Galileo: "These are some of those difficulties which arise from dis-

many, nor

for

similar statement

courses which our finite understanding makes about infinites, by ascribing to them attributes which we give to things finite and terminate, which I think most improper, because

not with

those attributes of majority, minority, and equality agree infinites, of which we cannot say that one is greater

sort of

4 than, less than, or equal to another." Exactly the same answer is given by Crescas to Gersonides' argument,

contains some of the same expressions: "The fast spheres will, indeed, in a certain time perform the same number of rotations that slow spheres will

and, strangely enough,

it

perform
1

in a greater time,
I,

when

the
11.

number of
33-37).

their rota-

Ethics,
2

Prop. 15, Schol. (Opera,


pp. 337-338:

II, p. 57,

Op.

cit. t

"Essendo che implica contradittione che ne

1'infinito

sia

parte maggiore, et parte m'more, et parte che habbia magglore et minore proportione a quello."
3

De Immense
"

et

Innumerabilibus,

II, 8

(Opera Latina,

I, i, p.

284):

Innumero nempe atque immense non


Esse potest
pluris, modici, pauci,

locus ullus

Quae numeri
(English
p.
1

et

atque minoris, mensi discrimina cernimus esse."

translation

quoted

from

J.

Lewis

Mcln tyre's Giordano Bruno,


Nuove
Scienze,
I,

88.)

Discorsi e Dimostrazioni matematiche intorno a due

in

Le

Opere di Galileo Galilei (Firenze, 1890-1909), Vol. 8, p. 77, 11. 35 ff., quoted by Bertrand Russell in his Scientific Method in Philosophy p. 192, from Tho. Weston's
,

translation, p. 47.

PROP. i5,scHOL.]

INFINITY OF EXTENSION

289

of such a kind as can be described by the terms much and few, great and small, within a certain time limit, that is
tions
is

the number and the time are finite, and due to the fact that the fast sphere and the slow sphere cannot perform the same number of rotations
to say,
this

when both
is

indeed

in equal time.
is infinite,

But when the time

or the

number of rotations

neither of these can be described by the terms

much and

few, great and small, equal and unequal, for all these terms are determinations of measure, and measurabil-

ity does not

apply to an

ensue

if

both the fast

Hence, no absurdity will and the slow spheres have performed


infinite.

an

infinite

number of

number of

their rotations

rotations in the past, inasmuch as the cannot be properly described as

x great and small and unequal." similar distinction is to be discovered in Descartes' dif-

ferentiation between the infinite


illustrations he gives
it
is

and the

indefinite.

From

the

clear that

by the indefinite he

means that whose parts cannot be expressed by any number.

He
no

furthermore describes the indefinite as that which has


limits only "in a certain sense,"
is

from which

it

may

be

inferred that the real infinite

that which has no limits.

The

difference between the indefinite

and the

infinite, ac-

cording to Descartes, is whose parts cannot be expressed by any number and that which has no limits. By this distinction Descartes, like

therefore a difference between that

Crescas and Bruno, disposes of such questions against the existence of an infinite as, e.g., "whether the half of an infinite line is infinite."
2

The other
1

version of the argument


i,

is

found

in

Avicenna,

Or Adonai,
5,

III,

(p. 670).
I,

Principia Philosophiac,
Schol.

26,

and Principia Philosophiae Cartesianae,

II,

Prop.

* Al-Najat, II: Physics (Rome, 1593), p. 33, reproduced in Carra de Vaux's Aviccnnc> p. 201.

290
1

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


4

[ETHICS,

Saadia and Bahya, 2 Abraham ibn Daud, 3 and Crescas cites it in the name of Altabrizi in an Altabrizi.
Algazali,

abridged and modified form.


"

We

quote

it

here from Crescas:

Suppose we have a line infinite only in one direction. To this line we apply an infinite line [which is likewise infinite

only in one direction], having the finite end of the second line fall on some point near the finite end of the first line.
It

would then follow that one

infinite

[i.e.

the

first line]

would be greater than another infinite [i.e., the second line]. But this is impossible, for it is well known that one infinite
cannot be greater than another/'
s

refutation given by Crescas of this argument is again based upon the distinction between the infinite in the sense

The

of the indefinite or of its being incapable of measurement and the infinite in the sense of its having no limits. To quote:
impossibility of one infinite being greater than another is true only with respect to measurability, that is to say, when we use the term greater' in the sense of being greater
'

"The

by a certain measure, and that indeed


an
infinite is

immeasurable.

is impossible because In this sense, to be sure, the

first

one-side infinite line [in Altabrizi's argument] will not be greater than the second one-side infinite line, inasmuch as
is

neither of them
the
first line is

measurable

in its totality.

Thus indeed

not greater than the second, though it extends the second on the side which is finite." 6 What Crescas beyond is trying to do is to point out the possibility of an extension
1

Ma fyajid al-Falasifah,
347we-De'ot,
I, 3,

II,

(p. 126),

quoted by
(3);

me

in Crescas* Critique of Aris-

totle, p.
2

Kmunot

Eighth Theory

Robot ha-Lebabot>

I, 5.

J
*

Emunah Ramah, I, 4. Commentary on Maimonides' Twenty-five


Crescas' Critique of Aristotle
',

Propositions, Prop.

I,

quoted

in

my
5

Or Adonaiy Or Adonai>

I, i, I, ii,

I i

pp. 145-146. (p. 5a-b). Cf. Crescas' Critique 0} Aristotle ^ p. 149. Cf. Crescas' Critique oj Aristotle > pp. 190-191. (p. 153).

PROP. 15, SCHOL.]

INFINITY OF EXTENSION
in the sense that its parts

291

which

cannot be equated with or explained by any number and still is not infinite in the sense that it has no limits. Such, for instance, are the
is infinite

lines in Altabrizi's

but

argument, which are infinite on one side on the other. When two such immeasurable but limfinite

ited infinites are given, then while indeed one of

them cannot

be conceived as greater than the other in the sense that the total number of its parts can be expressed by a number which
is

greater,

still it

in

the sense that

can be conceived as greater than the other it can extend beyond the other on the
infinite

limited side.

The reason why one immeasurable

can-

not be said to be greater than another, says Crescas, is that their parts cannot be expressed by any number and therefore the terms great
It
is,

and small are inapplicable to them. " " as a refutation of his second therefore, example
Spinoza
in his letter to

in the Ethics that

Meyer charges

his

opponents with the failure to make a distinction "between that which is called infinite because it has no limits, and that

whose parts we cannot equate with or explain by any number, although we know its maximum and minimum/' concluding " that, had they made such a distinction, they would also have
1

understood which kind of


than another

infinite

can be conceived as greater

infinite, without any complication, and which cannot be so conceived." 2 The wording of Spinoza's answer
is

strikingly reminiscent of both Crescas and Descartes. Back again to Aristotle, byway of Averroes, Altabrizi,
for the source of Spinoza's third

and

"exCrescas, we must go ample." In the De Caelo, Aristotle advances a series of arguments to prove from the circular movements of the heavenly spheres that the heavens cannot be infinite, for if they were
infinite

they could not revolve in a


11.

circle.

One of
11.

these

Fpistola 12 (Optra, IV, p. 53,

5-8).

Ibid. (p. 53,

14-15).

292

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


1

[ETHICS,

arguments, reproduced by Crescas from Averroes, runs as


follows:

Let Let
Let

ACE be an infinite circle. CA and CB be infinite radii. CA revolve on its centre C.


CB
be fixed.

Let

If an infinite sphere could rotate

upon

itself,

then

CA

would sometimes have to fall on CB. But the distance AB is infinite, and an
cannot be traversed.

infinite distance

Consequently, CA could never fall on CB. Hence, no infinite body could have circular motion.

An argument advanced by Altabrizi seems


tion of this Aristotelian argument.
It is

to be a modifica-

more general than

the Aristotelian argument in that it is detached from the illustration of the movements of the spheres. Crescas reproduces it in the name of "one of the moderns" as a rein-

it

forcement of Aristotle's argument. In Crescas' restatement read as follows: "The same difficulty [according to this

version of the argument] would arise in the case of any two


lines

common point if they were supposed distance between any two such lines at the point where they are intersected by a common chord would undoubtedly increase in proportion to the extension
emerging from a
to be infinite.

The

of the lines, and as the lines are assumed to be infinite, the


distance between
1

them would
Cf.

likewise have to be infinite.


27 ib, 27-27 2a, 7; Crescas' Critique

Or Adonai,

I, i,

(p. 73).

De

Cae/o,

I, 5,

of Aristotle, pp. 169 and 379-380.

PROP. 15, SCHOL.]

INFINITY OF EXTENSION
z

293

the
if

In almost exactly But this is self-evidently impossible." same terms Spinoza states his third "example." "Lastly,

from one point of any infinite quantity it be imagined that two lines, AE y AC which at first are at a certain and determinate distance from one another, be infinitely extended, it is plain that the distance between B and C will be continually increased, and at length from being determinate will be
y

indeterminable."

tion

In his answer Crescas again brings into play the distincbetween the infinite and the indefinite. He endeavors

show that while any given distance between any two points in the infinitely extending lines must be finite, the distance between them may be said to be infinite in the sense that whatever distance we take there is always a greater distance beyond it. It is analogous to what Aristotle says of magnitude and number that, while they are both finite in actuality
to

they are

infinite in capacity, in so far as

magnitude

is infi-

nitely divisible

and number

is

infinitely addible.
is

They
is

are

in this sense infinite, "for the infinite

not that beyond

which there

is

nothing, but
3

it is

that of which there


in part:

always

something beyond."
[infinitely] in the
[infinitely],

To

quote him
as

"To

this the

opponent of Aristotle
but
it

may

answer that distance increases

same manner

number

is

said to increase

bility of infinite

always remains limited. That the possiincrease is not incompatible with its being

actually limited may be seen from the case of infinite decrease, for the examination into contraries is by one and the

same

science. 4 It has
it is

been demonstrated

in the

book on Conic

Sections that
r

possible for a distance infinitely to decrease


Cf. Crescas' Critique of Aristotle^ pp. 171
IT, p. 57,
11.

Or Adonai,
Ethics,
I,

loc. cit.

and 381-382.

a 3

Prop. 15 (Opera,

37

ff.).

Physics, III, 6, 207.1, 1-2.


Cf. Metaphysics,

XI,

3,

06 1 a,

19.

294

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


still

[ETHICS,
is

and

never completely to disappear. 1

It

assume, for instance, two lines which, by


they are extended, are brought
other, and
infinity.
still will

how

possible to much farther


to

by so much nearer

each

If,

never meet, even if they are produced to in the case of decrease, there is a certain distance
in
it

which always remains and does not disappear, a fortiori


the case of increase

should be possible for a distance,


. .

though

infinitely increased,
is

This, to be sure,

2 always to remain limited. remote from the imagination, but reason

3 compels us to assume it." Now, Spinoza does not furnish us with any direct answer to the third "example," though his distinction between the

infinite

and the

indefinite

may

apply to

it.

But when he

Meyer that his opponents failed to dis" between that which we can only undertinguish, thirdly, stand but cannot imagine, and that which we can also imsays in his letter to
4

agine,"
last

may we

not assume that

it is

a reminiscence of the

statement by which Crescas concludes his lengthy refu-

tation of the
third
full

argument which is the exact prototype of the "example"? Had Spinoza taken the trouble to give a expression to what he had in mind when he quoted remi-

niscently this third distinction, he would undoubtedly have given us a paraphrase of this last quoted of Crescas' refutations, as

he did,

in part, at least, of his

two other

distinc-

tions; or, perhaps, he


1

would have gone


Theorem
13.

still

further and said


des figure's,

Apollonius, Conic Sections, II,

See

Munk, Guide

I,

p. 410, n. 2.
2

Or Adonai, I, ii, I Or Adonai, he. cit.

(p. i6a).
(p. i6b).

Cf. Crescas' Critique of Aristotle, p. 207. Cf. Crescas' Critique of Aristotle, p. 21 1, That the

last

ment and not merely


remarks:

statement of Crescas about imagination and reason refers to the entire arguto the passage immediately preceding it may be gathered from

Maimonides, who, speaking of the problem cited from the Conic Sections, similarly "This is a fact which cannot easily be conceived, and which does not

come within

the scope of the imagination" (Moreh Nebukim, Epistola 12 (Opera, IV, p. 53, 11. 8-10).

I,

73, Prop. 10).

PROP. 15, SCHOL.]

INFINITY OF EXTENSION

295

with a generous but rather patronizing gesture:

Nam,

ut

ipsam apud Judceum quendam Rab Ghasdaj


y

vocatum, re-

sic sonat.

The

transliteration of IJasdai ('KIDF!)

method of

transliterating the

Hebrew

Ilet

(!"!)

by "Ghasdai" follows Spinoza's own by gh. Cf. his Compendium Gram-

matices Linguae Hebraa, Cap. II (Opera, I, p. 288, 1. 18). The form "Jacdai" (Opera, IV, p. 61, 1. 35) which occurs in Leibniz's copy of the letter evidently represents the Spanish-Portuguese transliteration of the name.

ments published by Fritz Baer


the

name

is

In old Spanish docuDie Juden im Christlichen Spanien, I (1929), usually written "Azday." But the following forms also occur: "Adin his

zay"

(p. 712),

"nAzday"
generally

(pp. 499, 676), "Azay" (pp. 616, 723), "Azdray" (p. 1000), "Nazday" (p. 699). In these documents the personal name is followed by the surname "Cresques," but it occurs also without it (pp.

"Atzay"

(p. 676),

dola's

In Giovanni Francesco Pico della Miran741, 1000), as here in Spinoza's letter. Examen Doctrinae Vanitatis Gentium, VI, 2, the name is transliterated

"Hasdai" and

is

not followed by the surname.


Cf.

references to Crescas in the works of Isaac ben

Nor is the surname given in the Shem-Tob and Shem-Tob ben

Joseph ben Shem-Tob.


2

my

Crescas
11.

Critique of Aristotle, pp. 32-33.

Epistola 12 (Opera, IV, p. 61,

17-18).

THE CAUSALITY OF GOD


I.

MATERIALITY AND CAUSALITY OF GOD

AFTER

God

recapitulating his position as to the materiality of in Proposition XIV, Spinoza proceeds in logical order
is

to state his conclusion that there

nothing in the material


it

world which

is

not in God,

or, to

put
is, is

in the

words of

his

God, and nothing can either be or be conceived without God." Taken by itself, this proposition would seem to be nothing but a repetiProposition XV, "whatever
in

own

tion of the ordinary assertions of the

omnipresence of

God

which are current

in the literature of

Spinoza himself acknowledges as

much when

every religion. he says that

In fact,

"like Paul, and perhaps also like all ancient philosophers ... I assert that all things live and move in God; and I

would dare Hebrews as


tions/'
r

to say that
far as
it is

agree also with

all

the ancient

possible to surmise

from their tradi-

By

"all

ancient philosophers"
refers in his

refers not only to the Stoic poets

whom

Paul himself

he undoubtedly Aratus and Cleanthes, to statement "as certain also

2 poets have said," and not only to the Stoics in general, whose God was material like the God of Spinoza, but also to those who like Aristotle conceived of God as

of your

own

immaterial, for, though immaterial and hence separated from the universe, that God was still He in whom the universe could be said to have
its

formal, efficient, and

being, inasmuch as He was final cause. 3 Similarly by the "anits

cient
1

Hebrews" Spinoza does not


a

refer only to the teachings


3

Epistola 73.

Acts

17, 28. Cf.

Commentaries ad loc.

Cf. below, p. 302.

PROPS. 15-18]

THE CAUSALITY OF GOD

297

of the

Bible but also, and perhaps more particuto the teachings of Judaism at the time of Paul, in its larly, Palestinian and Hellenistic branches, for the omnipresence

Hebrew

of

The

emphasized by both of these branches of Judaism. on this point, used by both the rabbis and Philo, is the statement which is quoted constantly in
is

God

classic expression

the Middle Ages by Jewish as well as Christian philosophers, 1 namely, that God is the place of the world. The belief in the omnipresence of God has continued to be a religious common-

place in Judaism as well as Christianity and Mohammedanism, and has been maintained by every shade of religious
opinion, though, perhaps, not always without some slight shade of logical inconsistency. The most pertinent passage for our present purpose, both on account of its source and on

account of

Hymn

its phrasing, of Unity, which


all
. .

is

is

the following quotation from the included in the Jewish liturgy:


fillest all;

"Thou encompassest all, Thou art in all.


.

and

and since Thou

art

Thou

art not separated or

detached

from anything, nor is any place empty or devoid of Thee. Thou art and existeth in all; all is Thine, and all is from
.

Thee."

'

But while the proposition taken by itself contains nothing new, it is used by Spinoza in a different sense. He himself alludes to that difference in its use when he says in his reference to Paul and all ancient philosophers that he agrees
with their assertion, "though in another way." What the difference between them is becomes clear in Proposition XV,
for this proposition
is

to be understood as a criticism of the


in first affirming that all things are
is

mediaeval inconsistency
in

God and
1

then denying that matter

in

God. For when

ii,

i;

Genesis Rabbah 68, 9 ft al., Philo, De Somniis, I, 11; Crescas, Or Adonai, I, Leibniz, Nouveaitx Essais, II, 13, 17. Cf. my Crescas' Critique of Aristotle,
>

pp. 123, 201.

Shirha-Yihud,

III.

298

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


all is

[ETHICS,

the mediaevals reiterated their statements that

God

is all

and

from God and

in

reservation with regard to matter was not from God nor


side of
nihilo,

God, they had to make a mental matter. God was not matter, and
in

God, according

to Aristotle;

God. Matter existed by the it was created by God ex

according to the generally accepted view of all the three religions; it appeared somewhere in the process of

emanation, according to the emanationists. The statement that God is all and all is from God and in God could not be
taken in
its full

and

literal

sense that

"

whatever is,

is in

God

"

except by one
terial.

who

like

Spinoza asserted that

God was ma-

means to assert, only this that Proposition that matter as well as form is in God, or does it namely, mean more than this? Does it not mean a complete denial
But
is it

XV

of the separation of God from the world, with the inevitable consequence of the disappearance of God as a distinct being
either in thought or in reality?

In the history of philosophy Spinoza's conception of God has been characterized by different names. In his own day, it was called deism of the type that flourished then in France,
1

and

it

was
this

also stigmatized as a disguised kind of atheism.

3 imputation of atheism was renewed by Jacobi, Hegel quibbled about its being akosmism rather than atheism. 4 Novalis met the charge of atheism by declaring Spinoza

When

man a declaration which explains use of the term God rather than its meanSpinoza's profuse ing. The term pantheism is the one which has been most
a God-intoxicated
5
1

Epistola 42.
3

Kpistola 43.

Veber die Lehre des Spinoza in briefen an den llerrn Moses Mendelssohn, 1785.
p. 74;

Werke (1819), Vol. IV, i, p. 216. Encyclopddie der philosophischen Wissenschaften, I, 50 (ed. Bolland), Vorlesungen uber die Geschichte der Philosophie (ed. Bolland), p. 891.
Cf. Jacobi's
4
5

Schriften (ed. Paul

Kluckhohn, Leipzig [1892]), Vol.

Ill, p. 318,

253.

PROPS. 15-18]

THE CAUSALITY OF GOD


it.

299

often applied to
ings of Spinoza

Avenarius,

who

has stratified the writ-

on the basis of the use of the terms Na-

ture, God, and Substance, just as the higher critics stratify the Pentateuch on the basis of the use of the terms Jehovah

and Elohim, has discovered three phases

in

the develop-

ment of Spinoza's pantheism, which he designates by the


and Substantive All-in-one
will find it

following terms: Naturalist All-in-one, Theistic All-in-one, l a distinction in which one

hard to discover any difference.

Windelband

these subtleties aside and declares outright that Spinoza's conception of God is "complete and unreserved

brushes

all

pantheism."

The problem before us, however, is not to devise a fitting term by which Spinoza's conception of God can be adequately described, but rather to find out whether his God is absolutely
identical with the aggregate totality of particular things or

whether

He does in some way transcend it. When we leave what others have said about Spinoza's God and turn to what

he himself has said about Him, we find that the matter does not become any clearer. Though he makes reference to the
characterization of his religion as one which "does not rise above the religion of the Deists," 3 he does not definitely
disclaim

Perhaps he saw no need of disclaiming it, since the author of that statement had done it himself when he
it.

said that "unless

am

mistaken

in

my

conjecture, this

man

does not include himself in the ranks of the Deists, and does not allow men to return to the least bit of religious worship." 4

Nor does he
1

disclaim the charge of atheism except in so far as


All-Einheit^ Thcisitischc All-Einheit, Substanzialistische
ersten

Naturalistischc

All-

Einheit. Cf.

R. Avenarius, Ucbcrdie bcidcn

Phasendcs Spinozischcn Pantheis-

mus
2

(Leipzig, 1868).

Gtschichte der Philosophic (jrd edition), p. 336; English translation,


J

A History

of Philosophy y p. 409.
4

Epistolae 42 and 43.

Epistola 42.

300
the term

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


meant
in his

[ETHICS,

inordinately honors this evidence from silence are his positive statements. While in one place he asserts that "those who think that the Tractatus Theologico-Politicus rests

man who is "wont to desire No more conclusive than and riches."


time a
x

on

this,

namely, that

God

and nature (by which they mean a certain mass, or corporeal 2 matter) are one and the same, are mistaken/' in another place he asserts that "I could not separate God from nature
as all of
still

have any knowledge have done/' 3 and in another place he identifies the terms God and nature.
I

whom

All that one can with certainty gather from these passages

is

that while Spinoza did not identify God with nature conceived as an inert mass of matter, he did identify Him with
it when conceived in all its infinite attributes. Nor, finally, can we get more light on the question from his statement that "the universe is God," s for here, too, the statement may merely mean, as may be judged from the context, "that

things [that is to say, including matter] emanate neces6 But does it also mean that sarily from the nature of God."
all

God

is

nothing but the aggregate of particular things which

constitute the universe?

light

Since the uttered statements of Spinoza do not throw any on the question, we shall try the use of the historical

method in order to solve our problem. We shall give an analysis of the salient features of the traditional conception of God which Spinoza constantly uses as the target for
critical

his criticism.
it

We

shall also try to find

out what elements of

he criticized and ultimately rejected. Finally we shall try to reconstitute Spinoza's conception of God out of those
1

Kpistola 43.
3

Kpistola 73.

Kpistola 6. Short Treatise, Epistola 43.


Ibid.

I, 2,

12 (Opera,

I, p.

22,

11.

9-13).

PROPS. 15-18]

THE CAUSALITY OF GOD


God which were
tries to
left

301

elements of the traditional


uncriticized.

by him
is

The God of tradition whom Spinoza sometimes depicted by him disdainfully


morphic crudity as
1

dethrone

in all his

anthropo-

He was

vulgar.

But

this

may

pictured in the minds of the be considered only as an occasional

departure from what is really his general practice. As a rule, the conception of God which he criticizes is that of the philosophers, of the "men who have in any way looked into the
divine nature/'
*

This conception of

God

is

marked by two
All the

main

characteristics, immateriality

and

causality.

problems raised about the nature of God by philosophers throughout the Middle Ages can be grouped together under
these two terms.
rise to
bility,

The

immateriality of

God

it is

which gives

His unity, simplicity, immutability, and incomparaout of which springs the complexity of problems which

go under the general name of attributes. But such a conception of God's immateriality takes God completely out of the universe, which is not what the mediaeval philosophers

wanted

to do.

And

so,

immediately after they establish

the absolute immateriality of God, they turn around and try to introduce God back into the universe by establishing a
certain causal relation between them.
sality of
It
is

through the cauis

God

that the world comes into being and

ruled

and guided by Him. God's omnipresence, omniscience, omnipotence, and benevolence of which they all speak are
nothing but different ways of expressing the fact of divine
These, then, are the two main characteristics of of traditional philosophy. Now Spinoza's criticism of this conception of God in Ethics, I, falls into two parts,
causality.

the

God

corresponding to these
1

its

two main

characteristics,

immate-

E.g., Ethics,
>

I,

Prop. 15, Schol.

Ibid.

302
riality

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


and

[ETHICS,

causality. The first fifteen propositions are all a of the immateriality of God, culminating in Propcriticism in the statement that "whatever is, is in God," osition

XV

which, as we have shown, means that everything, including matter, is in God. Beginning now with Proposition XVI to
the end of the First Part, he criticizes the old conceptions of the causality of God. In this chapter, however, we shall deal

only with Propositions XVI-XVIII. In order to be able to follow Spinoza's criticism, we must first give a formal statement of what the mediaevals meant

by divine
into four:
final.

causality.

Causes have been divided by Aristotle

the material, the formal, the efficient,

and the

Beginning with this commonplace of philosophy, the mediaevals asked themselves which of these causes God is.

He

cannot be the material cause, they said, for

God

is

im-

material.

He must
is

therefore be the three other causes.


this point.

Mai-

monides

worth quoting on
its

"It has been shown


except the First the

in the science of physics that everything,

origin material, the formal, the efficient,

Cause, owes

to the following four causes

and the

final.

These are
itself

is

sometimes proximate, sometimes remote, but each by called a cause. They also believe and I do not
their belief
final cause.

differ

from

formal, and

that God, blessed be He, " r

is

the efficient,

Now,

in

seen, Spinoza

opposition to the mediaevals, as we have already makes God a material cause. Again, in opposi-

unmakes God

Spinoza then to him, if he were to retain the Aristotelian terminology, would be a material,
as the final cause.

tion to the mediaevals, as

we

shall see subsequently,

God

formal, and efficient cause.


Aristotle

But

this

terminology even in

was not unalterably fixed. The final and efficient causes are identified by him with the formal cause, and thus
1

Morch Nebukim,

I,

69.

PROPS. 15-18]

THE CAUSALITY OF GOD

303

the only real contrast between causes is that of the material and formal. 1 This identification of the three causes is found
also in

Maimonides.
2

in natural things the efficient, formal,

"Aristotle has already explained that and final causes are

how in Spinoza's reasoning, of the old Aristotelian terms matter and with his discarding form, the old designation of causes as material and formal " In creation," he says, "no other causes likewise disappears. concur except the efficient one." 3 God is therefore spoken
identical."

We

can readily see

of by him as the efficient cause, for even as a material and formal cause, it is only through the active properties of ex-

cause

tension and thought that God is conceived as cause. Efficient is thus to him the most applicable description of God,

efficient in the
all

most general sense of active and as the sum of conditions that make for causality. There is a suggestion

of this kind of reasoning in Spinoza's statement that "since substance is the principle of all its modes, it may with greater
right be called active than passive."
4

But

in

order to show

the difference between his conception of God as efficient cause and that of the mediaevals, he analyzes their conception of efficient cause and tries to show in what respect he de-

parts from them. In the Short treatise, where an entire chapter is devoted to the explanation "that God is a cause of all things," 5

Spinoza borrows a current eightfold classification of the Aristotelian efficient cause, which has been traced to the

work of
1

Dutch philosopher by the name of Burgersdijck, 6


327-330 (3rd
edition).

Zeller, Philosophic der Griechen, II, 2, pp.

English trans-

lation, Aristotle, I, pp.


3

355~35 8

Moreh Nebukim,
Short Treatise, Short Treatise,

III, 13.
I, p.

Cogitata Mctaphysica, II, 10 (Opera,


I, 2, I, 3.
I,

268,
11.

11.

25-26).

4
s

25 (Opera,

I, p.

26,

29-31).
Cf. A. Trendelenburg, Historische

Institution** Logicae, Lib.

Cap. XVII.

304
to

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


in

[ETHICS,

show "how and

what sense God

is

a cause." This eight-

fold classification, with the exception of the eighth, which appears later in the Scholium of Proposition XXVIII, is em-

bodied

in

Propositions

XVI-XVIII

of Ethics,

I.

The
is

corre-

spondence between them, preliminary to our discussion of


the meaning of these seven kinds of efficient cause,
here-

with given:

Ethics, I

Short 'Treatise,
7.

I,

Prop. Prop.
Prop.

XVI XVI
XVI
XVI

Universal cause

Corol.

i.

Emanative, productive,
active, efficient cause
2

Corol. 2 ....
Corol. 3. Corol. i
.

4.

Cause through himself


(essential) First, initial cause

Prop. Prop. Prop. Prop.

6.
5.

XVII XVII XVIII

Corol. 2.

3.
2.

Principal cause Free cause Immanent cause

However, while Spinoza has borrowed the scheme and terminology of the classification from Burgersdijck, he has made
free use of
this
list
it

for his

are

own purpose. The causes enumerated in what the mediaevals themselves would have

ascribed to God, but when used by Spinoza there is an implication that these causes are more truly applicable to his

own conception
But
let

of God's causality than to theirs. us follow out this implied contention of Propositions XVI-XVIII that only God as conceived by Spinoza is in the
true sense a universal,
efficient, essential, first,

principal, free,

and immanent cause.


Beitrage zur Philosophic, Vol. Ill, p. 317 (Berlin, 1867); Ch. Sigwart, Benedict de Spinoza's kurzer Tractat (2nd ed.), p. 171; A. Wolf, Spinoza's Short Treatise, pp.

spondence of Prop.
3

Sigwart seems to have overlooked the correcit., p. 172. 6 and Corollary i of Prop. 16 in the Ethics to the 7th and ist classifications in the Short Treatise.
1

Cf. Sigwart, op.


1

uytv/oejende, daarstellende, doende, werkende.

PROPS.

5-i 8]

THE CAUSALITY OF GOD

305

the mediaevals, from the principle that God is a pure simple form and that "a simple element can produce only " a simple thing it appeared as an inevitable conclusion that,

To

necessary emanation was to be the theory explaining the origin of the world, the direct emanation from God must be
if

one simple Intelligence and that matter must therefore emerge subsequently in the process. According to this view,
1

while of
all

God may

indeed be considered as indirectly the cause

the variety of material things, He is directly only the cause of one simple thing. In this sense, then, God is

really

what was

called a particular cause as contrasted with

a universal cause, for the latter kind of cause meant the 2 Thus while the mediaeability to produce various things.
vals

would undoubtedly
3

insist

upon

calling

God

a universal

cause,

they could not

really call

Him

a universal cause in

the strict sense of the term.

direct cause of both extended

But to Spinoza, since God is the modes and thinking modes,

God

can truthfully be called a universal cause. Furthermore, Spinoza's God can be called a universal cause

with more right than the God of the mediaevals for still another reason. Though the mediaevals believed like Spinoza that God is infinite, still they did not believe, for reasons

we
all

shall discuss later, that

God

ever did or ever will create

the infinite things which He has in His mind and which might be created. The world is finite as contrasted with God
*

was a. particular and not did not create everything that was in His mind. But to Spinoza, just as from the two known
is infinite.

who

Their

God

therefore

a universal cause, since

He

attributes arise the

the infinite attributes, which are


1

known modes of the world, so also from unknown to us but which


2

Moreh Nebtikim,

I,

22.

Short Treatise,
p. 254, n. 2.

I,

3,

2 (7).

*
4

Cf. quotation from Cf. below, pp. 314

Thomas Aquinas,
ff.

above,

and 411

ff.

306
exist

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

and are conceived as an idea in the infinite intellect of God, arise an infinite number of modes unknown to us. The world is as infinite as God, though only two of its modes are
1

known
XVI.

to us,

true sense of the term.


It
is

and God therefore is a universal cause in the This is what lies behind Proposition
fullest expression

a denial of the mediaeval view that the world

of God's being. If the world were finite, he argues, then God could be called only a particular cause and not a universal cause. But the
is finite

and not the

world

is

not

finite,

for

"from the necessity of the divine

numbers of things in infinite ways (that is nature to say, all things which can be conceived by the infinite intellect) must follow" (Prop. XVI). Hence God can be truly
infinite

called a universal cause.

But in what manner do the modes follow from God? In the Middle Ages it was said that they follow from God by the process of emanation, and emanation was defined as a
special kind of efficient causation

which applies exclusively

to the action of an immaterial agent

upon a material

object.
is

"Inasmuch

as

it

has been demonstrated that

God

incor-

poreal and has also been established that the universe is His work and that He is its efficient cause ... we say that the

universe has been created by divine emanation and that God is the emanative cause of everything that comes into God then is called by the mediaevals being within it."
l

the efficient cause only in a restricted sense, in the sense of

emanative cause.

But

to Spinoza, that distinction

between

the act of a corporeal agent and the act of an incorporeal agent does not exist. He therefore declares unqualifiedly

that

"God

is

the efficient cause,'*

that

is

to say, the efficient

cause
1

in its general unrestricted sense. and


66.
*

In the Short Treatise


II, 12.
i.

Cf. Epistolae 63, 64, Ibid.

Moreh Nebukim,
Ethic s^
I,

Prop. 16, Coroi.

PROPS. 15-18]

THE CAUSALITY OF GOD


still

307
that

he makes his point

clearer

when he says

God

can be called indifferently the "emanative," "productive," "active," or "efficient" cause, all of which "we regard as one

and the same, because they involve each other." Probably the mediaevals themselves would subscribe
self (per se y essentially),

to

Spinoza's next statement that "God is cause through himand not through that which is acci-

dental (per accidens)."*

But

still,

since the world of

which

they maintain God is the cause is unlike God in nature, God being immaterial and the world being material, then, despite their protestations, God must be considered not as an essential cause but as

an accidental cause, for one of the mean-

ings of essential cause, and the one which Spinoza has found in Bergersdijck and Heereboord, is that the cause produces

something of its own kind. When the cause produces something which is not of its own kind, it is called accidental
Consequently, since according to the mediaevals the world which was produced by God is not of His kind, for God is immaterial and the world is material, God then is
cause. 3

only an accidental cause. Similarly the mediaevals would whole-heartedly subscribe to Spinoza's fourth characterization of divine causality contained in his declaration that
cause.'*
4

In fact,

God

"God is absolutely the first has been called the first cause ever

God

But behind this statement of Spinoza's that the "absolutely" first cause there is an unexpressed argument that the mediaevals could not with full right call
since Aristotle.
is
1

Short Treatise
Ethics,
I,

',

1,
1

3,

2 (i).

Prop.

6, Corel. 2.

Cf. Burgcrsdijck, Institutions Lo$icae, Lib. I, Cap. XVII, Theor. XV-XVI; Heereboord, Hermcneia Logica, Lib. I, Cap. XVII, Quaest. XVI: "Similiter, cum animal sibi simile generat, dicitur causa per sc generati animalis; cum generat

monstrum,
Ethics,

dicitur causa per accidens."


I,

Prop.

6,

Corol. 3.

308
their

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


God
an absolutely
is is

[ETHICS,

first

cause.

Spinoza, a distinction
causes.

made between two kinds


is

In the source used by of first

One

called the absolutely first cause (causa absocalled a first cause in its

lute prima)

and the other

own kind

(causa prima suo genere). An absolutely first cause is described not only as a cause which is the first in a series of
causes, but also as one which
else.
1

is

in

no way dependent upon

In fact, absolute independence of anything anything else, whether external to God or within Him, is what the

mediaevals themselves
as the first cause
in

insist upon when they describe God and as necessary existence. 2 It is with this

mind

He

that Spinoza argues here against the emanationists. seems to say: Inasmuch as according to the emanationists

God

could not produce matter directly by himself but only through His emanations, i.e., the Intelligences, God is de-

pendent, as it were, on his own emanations. He is therefore not an absolutely first cause. It is only Spinoza's God who

produces everything directly by the necessity of His own nature and is in no way whatsoever dependent upon anything else that can be rightfully called an absolutely first cause.
II.

GOD

AS FREE CAUSE
l

and first, God is also a and free cause. 3 With these Spinoza introduces principal another one of his fundamental departures from mediaeval
Besides universal\
efficient , essential\

philosophy. of freedom

On

may

the whole, Spinoza's views on the problem be treated under three headings: i. The

definition of the terms "free"


1

and "necessary."
I, I,

2.

How

Cf. Burgersdijck, Institutions Logicae, Lib.

Cap. XVII, Theor.

1-2; Heereboord,

Hcrmeneia Logica, Lib.

Cap. XVII, Quaest.

XXIX, XXVI; idem.

Meletemata Philosophica, Disputationts ex Philosophia Selcctae, Vol. II, Disp. XVII. a Cf. Ma)?a$id al-Falasijah, II, ii, 5-6 (pp. 139-140): "He [who is described as having necessary existence] does not depend upon anything else." Cf. also Emunah

Ramah,

II,

(p. 47),

Ethics,

I,

quoted below, Vol. II, p. 40. Prop. 17 and Corol. r-2; Short Treatise,

I,

3,

2 (3-5).

PROPS.

5-i 8]

THE CAUSALITY OF GOD

309
in

our interpreta3. tion of Proposition XVII we shall deal only with the first two topics, leaving the third topic to be discussed in our interpretation of the next group of propositions.
is free.

God

How man is not free.

Here

His own understanding of the terms

free

and necessary

is

made
and

quite clear free which exists


is

by Spinoza himself: "That thing is called from the necessity of its own nature alone,
itself alone.

determined to action by
is

That

thing,

on

the other hand,

which by another is fixed and prescribed manner/'


to this definition?

called necessary, or rather compelled, determined to existence and action in a


x

But how did Spinoza come and simply to explain the metaphysical and philological reasoning which had led

We shall

try briefly

Spinoza to formulate this definition. The problem of freedom is sometimes discussed by the mediaevals as a problem of possibility. The question whether
anything is absolutely free is thus stated as a question whether anything is absolutely possible. In Crescas, for
instance, the headings over the chapters on freedom read: "An exposition of the view of him who believes that the

nature of possibility exists/' "An exposition of the view of him who believes that the nature of possibility does not

There is a suggestion of this method of formulatthe problem of freedom in the Short Treatise where in the ing chapter on "Divine Predestination" Spinoza raises the
exist."
2

question "whether there are in nature any accidental things, that is to say, whether there are any things which may hap-

The phraseology used here pen and may also not happen." reflects the Aristotelian definitions of the accidenby Spinoza tal and the possible. The former is reproduced by Crescas
'

as that which
1

"has
7.
I, 6,

in itself the possibility


a

of being and of

Ethics,
*

I,

Def.

Or Adonai,

II, v, 1-2.

Short Treatise,

2.

3 io

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


x

[ETHICS,

not being'*;

the latter

is

given by Aristotle himself as that


2

which

"may

either be or not be."

have already called attention on several occasions to the mediaeval threefold division of possibility and necessity,
namely,
(i) possible

We

per

se y (2) possible

per

se

but necessary

necessary per se. We have also called attention to the fact that Spinoza has made
in consideration of its cause,

and

(3)

use of this threefold classification and that he has designated the possible per se by the term contingent and the possible

per

but necessary in consideration of its cause by the 3 Now, the question raised by the general term possible.
se

mediaevals through Crescas whether the nature of the possible exists really means whether pure possibility, i.e., possibility per se y exists.

Crescas' answer

is

in the negative.

There

is

for for everything a cause


in

nothing in nature which can be described as pure possibility, can be found. So actually nothing
nature
possible per se; everything which necessary in consideration of its cause.
is
is

se is se

possible per Possible per


it is

does not represent an actual thing in nature;

only a

logical distinction

secundum

quid.*

It is this

conception of

the possible per se as merely a logical distinction secundum quid that must have led Spinoza to designate it by the term

contingent, which, in Spinoza's definition of it, appears also as purely a logical distinction in things. According to this
view, then, actually existent things fall only under two divisions, those which are necessary by their cause and those which are necessary by their own nature. These two meanings of necessary, in fact, correspond to two out of the five meanings that Aristotle attaches to the term. That which
1

Or Adonai,

I, i, 8.

Cf.

my

Crescas' Critique oj Aristotle , p. 249

and

p. 551, n. 2;

Physics, VIII, 5, 2565, 9-10.


a * <

Metaphysics t IX, 8, io5ob, 1 1-12. Cf. Crescas' Critique oj Aristotle, p. 551, n. 3. Cogitata Metaphysica, I, 3; Ethics, IV, Defs. 3-4. Cf. above, pp. 188 ff. HD 1X3. Cf. Or Adonai, II, v, 3: ... nrn33 .
.
.

PROPS. 15-18]
is

THE CAUSALITY OF GOD


its

311

cause corresponds to necessary in the necessary by Aristotle describes as compulsory, 1 and that sense which

which

is

necessary by

its

own nature corresponds

to necessary

in the sense

which Aristotle describes as that which cannot

be otherwise. 2

What
is

Spinoza does, then, in his definition of


its

freedom
call
call

in the Ethics is to simplify the terminology

that which
that which

necessary by

elsewhere, "is only, pelled. or no other than [the status of being] the first cause/' 3 This on the whole corresponds to the mediaeval definition of

is necessary by its "True freedom/* says Spinoza

and to and to cause necessary or com-

own nature

free

freedom. "Free will/* says Judah ha-Levi, "qua free will, has no compulsory cause." 4 Similarly Crescas defines free will as the ability "to will and not to will without an external cause/'
s

This definition of freedom


in in

is

applied by Spinoza to
Corollaries.

God

Proposition Starting out the proposition itself with the statement that God's
its

XVII and

two

action flows from His own nature and is without compulsion, he further explains in the first corollary that the compulsion comes neither from without nor from within Him, that is to
say,

God

concludes
cause.

is generally called a principal cause, and the second corollary that only God is a free All these would on their positive side seem to be
is

what

in

merely a reassertion of views commonly held by mediaevals. But as elsewhere, Spinoza's statements here have also a negative side

and are intended


it is

to

emphasize something
in this case,

in opposi-

tion to the mediaevals.

have to guess what


negate.
1

He makes

it

Fortunately, that he wants to emphasize and clear for us in his Scholium.


*

we do not

J
s

Metaphysics, V, 5, 1015.1, 16. Short Treatise, I, 4, 5.

Ibid., 34.
4

Cuzari, V, 20.

Or Adonai,

II, v, 3 (p.

48 b).

312

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

On

the whole, the mediaevals would have subscribed to

Spinoza's proposition that "God acts from the laws of His own nature only, and is compelled by no one." x In fact, in
the

Hymn
we

of Unity, which

is

incorporated in the Jewish


it:

liturgy,

find a statement that reads almost like

"Thou

wast not compelled to perform Thy work, nor wast Thou in need of any help." 2 But still the mediaevals considered

God's causality as an act of will, power, or intelligence. Will, power, and intelligence are the three terms which are generally

used by mediaevals

in

connection with creation, 3 with

the proviso, of course, that all the three are identical in God. 4 It is by means of will or power or intelligence that the mediaevals find themselves able to resolve all the difficulties about divine causality. The mediaeval philosophers, for instance, admit that God cannot "produce a square the di-

agonal of which
bilities."
5

Still

God
same

that
as

He
if

its side, or similar other impossithe question is raised that "to say of can produce a thing from nothing is ... the
is

equal to

when

we were

to say that

He

could

produce a

square the diagonal of which is equal to its side, or similar 6 impossibilities," or "what has made God create at one time
rather than at another,"

"He

willed

it so;

or,

they answer to this question that His wisdom decided so." 8


7

As against this, Spinoza opposes his own view of causality, and in the process of unfolding it he emphasizes, allusively, to be sure, the distinction between his view and theirs. The
1

Ethic 3 >

I, Prop. 17. Shir ha-Yihud, V.

Emunot

we-De'ot, II, 4; Cuzari, V, 18, 7-10;

Moreh Ncbukim,

II, 18,

Second

Method.

Cf. above, p. 204.


53.
I,

Moreh Nebukim, II, Ibid. II, 13, and cf. Moreh Nebukim, II,
y

Cf. above, p. 155. 75,


i; I,

75, 5; III, 15;

Emunot

wt-De'ot, II, 13.

13,

Second Theory.
f.

Ibid. y II, 14.

Cf. above, p. 100. Cf. above, pp. 100

lbid. y II, 25.

PROPS. 15-18]

THE CAUSALITY OF GOD

313

fundamental difference, out of which all others arise, is his elimination of will and design from the causality of God. This is what he means when he says in the first corollary of
Proposition XVII that "there is no cause, either external to God or within Him, which can excite Him to act." By a

cause within
nation of will
nihilo

God

he means will and design. With the elimiand design from the nature of God, creation ex

becomes an impossible act, as impossible as any of the things which the mediaevals themselves considered impossible, such, for instance, as the assumption that "God
could bring about that it should not follow from the nature of a triangle that its three angles should be equal to two
'

right angles."

Then Spinoza takes up another point. One of the reasons that led the mediaevals
to

to attribute

God

intelligence

opposite alternative, for to

and as a result of this, "we must remove from God anything that looks like an imperfection in Him." 3 Abraham Herrera, in his unpublished Tuerta
2

an imperfection in be "free from imperfections,"

was the utter absurdity of the deny them of Him would imply His nature. God, according to them, must
will

and

del Cie/o, of which a printed Hebrew version has existed since 1655, puts the matter in the following way: "The

eternal and omnipotent God, whom we call the First Cause, acts not from the necessity of His nature but by the counsel

of His intellect, which is of the highest order, and by the choice of His free will," 4 for "to an Agent who is first and

most perfect we must attribute that kind of action which on account of its superiority and priority excels any other kind
of action, and that
1

is

the voluntary kind of action, for


2

it is

Ethics^
'

'I,

I,

Prop. 17, Schol.

'Ikkarim,

I,

15;

Moreh Nebukim^

I,

35.

'IMarim, 11,7. 11,7Sha'ar ha-Shamayim^ III,


6,

beginning.

3H

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


all

[ETHICS,

the natural and necessary actions and does in fact constitute their entelechy and the realization of

more perfect than


their perfection."

refers

undoubtedly to Herrera that Spinoza "I know, indeed, that there are many says: who think themselves able to demonstrate that intellect of
It is

when he

the highest order and freedom of will both pertain to the nature of God, for they say that they know nothing more
perfect which they can attribute to 2 the chief perfection in ourselves."

Him

than that which

is

But Spinoza goes still further in his criticism of Herrera. Herrera touches upon a question which had been constantly raised in the Cabala, namely, whether God could create the infinite number of things which are in His intellect
or whether His power of creation was limited to that which He has created. The question is stated by Moses Cordovero
as follows:

adepts in
it

by which some of the Cabala have been perplexed, namely, whether the
shall raise a question

"We

Infinite, the

in

King of Kings, the Holy One, blessed be He, has His power to emanate more than these Ten Sefirot or

express ourselves in this way. The question is a legitimate one, for inasmuch as it is of the nature of His benevolence to overflow outside himself, and inasmuch as it
not, if
is not beyond His power, it may be properly asked why He has not produced thousands of millions of emanations. It should indeed be possible for Him to produce many times

we may

Ten

Sefirot in the

same way

as

He has produced

this

world."

made: and by

In the discussion of this question by Herrera two points are First, that "if God had acted from His own nature
necessity,
is

He would

have inevitably produced everyinfinite/'


4

thing that
1

in

His power, which would be


3

Sec-

Ibid.)
3

Argument IV.

Ethics,

I,

Prop. 17, Schol.

Pardes

Rimmonim

II, 7.

Shaar ha-Shamayim,

III, 6,

Argument

III.

PROPS.

5-1 8]

THE CAUSALITY OF GOD

315

has created by will and design, He has purond, since posely created only a part of that which is in His intellect,

God

in order to

"We

shall

be able to create other and more perfect things. say briefly, that it is because He does not act by

the necessity of His infinite nature that the Infinite, blessed be He, even though He is infinite, has not brought into exist-

ence or created an infinite number of things in an infinite time, which He comprehends and includes in His immovable

produced them in positions, and places, into which His


eternity, nor has

He

infinite superficies, infinite

power and
has brought times and

magnitude extend.

by and purpose, and it is because of this that into existence and created finite things in
in finite places,

He

acts only

the freedom of His will

He

finite

and to these things and into these things only extended himself, so that He might be superior to His creatures not only in an infinite degree of perfection but
has

He

also in infinite power,

and

if

He

ever wills

He may

create

other things more excellent and greater and in more suitable, wider, and longer places and positions, all of which He com-

prehends and includes most perfectly in His eternity and greatness. This view offers more easily [than any other view] a vindication of the infinite power and nature of the First
Cause, namely, the view we have maintained that for every one of the created things, however excellent it may be, He
is

able to produce something


is

more

excellent/'

similar

Metareproduced by Spinoza "If God acts from necessity, He must have created physica. a a duration than which no greater can be conceived/*

argument

in the Cogitata

That Spinoza had

in

mind the statements we have just


is

re-

produced from Herrera


'

evident from
"

his following

summary

of the views of his opponents:


Ibid., Ill, 7.
3

But although they conceive

Cogitata Metaphysica y II, 10.

316

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

God

theless

as actually possessing the highest intellect, they neverdo not believe that He can bring about that all those

things should exist which are actually in His intellect, for they think that by such a supposition they would destroy His power. If He had created, they say, all things which are
in

His

intellect,

He could have created nothing more, and


God

this,

they believe, does not accord with


then they prefer to consider

God's omnipotence; so

as indifferent to all things,


x

and creating nothing excepting that which He has decreed to create by a certain absolute will.** Spinoza's own criticism of this solution of the problem is that it virtually sacrifices God's power in order to retain His perfection. "Therefore, in order to make a perfect God, they are compelled to
incapable of doing all those things to which His extends, and anything more absurd than this, or more power opposed to God's omnipotence, I do not think can be
2

make Him

imagined."

having gone to all the trouble of intelligence and will, explain them away as terms. They say "there is nothing in common homonymous There is only between His essence and our essence.
after

The mediaevals,

ascribing to

God

a resemblance between
are different."
is
3

them

in

name, but

in essence

they

Similarly of will they say that "the term will homonymously used of man's will and of the will of God,

there being no comparison between God's will and that of man." 4 Spinoza restates this view in great detail in the Scholium to Proposition XVII, in the course of which he

explains the homonymous use of terms by the illustration of " the term "dog," which is used for the celestial constellation

of the
1

Dog and
I,

the animal which barks."


a

This illustration
ff.

Ethics y

Prop. 17, Schol.


III, 20.
is

Ibid.

Cf. below, pp. 411

Moreh Nebukim,

Ibid., II, 18,

Second Method.

similar illustration

mentioned

in Cogitata Metaphysica, II, 11.

PROPS. 15-18]
is

THE CAUSALITY OF GOD


*

317

and in Maimonides and Averroes. 2 The introduction here on the part of Spinoza of the discussion about the homonymity of will and intellect when applied to God, which, as we have seen, is nothing but a restatement of the common mediaeval view, would seem to be entirely
found
in Philo

superfluous unless we assume that he wanted to make use of it afterwards as a refutation of the mediaevals in their
attribution of will and intellect to God.
refutation occurs in the Scholium.

However, no such Probably what Spinoza

meant
say

to

convey

to the reader,

so, is

that since intellect

though he does not definitely and will are to be applied to

God

only homonymously, they are meaningless terms, and consequently God's activity might as well be described as

following from the necessity of His nature. This in fact " Since ... it is is what he argues in one of his letters:

is

admitted universally and unanimously, that the will of God eternal and has never been different, therefore they must
is the necessary ask them whether you the divine will does not differ from the human will, they

also

admit (mark

this well) that the


.
. .

world

effect of the divine nature.

For

if

will reply that the

former has nothing

in

common

with the

latter except in

God's
the
if

will,

name; moreover they mostly admit that understanding, essence or nature are one and
3

same thing."

the will of

God

is

Spinoza's contention in this passage that eternal then the world must be admitted

to be the necessary effect of the divine nature reflects Maimonides' elaborate arguments on the incompatibility of the assumption of an eternal will of God and the belief in crea-

tion
1

by

design.

Df

Plantations

Noe XXXVII,
y

155.

Maimonides, Mi Hot ha-Higgayon, Ch. 13; Averroes, Epitome of the Isagogc (Mabo in Kol Meleket Higgayon, p. 2b). Cf. note in Klatzkin's Hebrew translation
2

of the Ethics (Torat ha-Middot),


3

p. 348.
4

Epistola 54.

Moreh Nebukim^

II, 21.

318

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

opposite of will and design, in the Middle Ages, is not only necessity but also chance. Thus Maimonides, in clasof creation, mentions in opposisifying the various theories
tion to intelligent creation not only the Aristotelian theory of necessity but also the Epicurean view of accident and chance. 1 The difference between chance on the one hand,
will and necessity on the other, is that chance denies the existence of a cause at all in creation, whereas will and

The

and

necessity both assume the existence of a cause, though each " But it would conceives the cause to act in a different way.

be quite useless to mention the opinions of those who do not recognize the existence of God, but believe that the existing
state of things
is

the result of accidental combination and

separation of the elements and that there is none that rules or determines the order of the existing things." 2 Spinoza

and necessity and makes the interesting observation that if God is assumed to act by a will whose laws are unknown to us, His activity really amounts to chance: "This
similarly tries to differentiate between chance
in

one of

his letters

already impels

me

briefly to explain

my

opinion on the

question whether the world was created by chance. My answer is that, as it is certain that Fortuitous and Necessary
are two contrary terms, it is also clear that he who asserts that the world is the necessary effect of the divine nature
also absolutely denies that the world was made by chance; he, however, who asserts that God could have refrained from

creating the world

is

affirming, albeit in other words, that


3

it

was made by chance/'

So also

in

asks his correspondent: "Tell me, I seen or read any philosophers who hold the opinion that the
1

another letter Spinoza pray, whether you have

Ibid. y II, 13

and

20;

cf.

Emunot

we-De'ot,

1, 3,

Ninth Theory; Cuzari, V,

20.

Moreh Nebukim,
Epistola 54.

II, 13.

PROPS. 15-18]

THE CAUSALITY OF GOD

319

world was made by chance, that is, in the sense in which you understand it, namely, that God, in creating the world,

and yet transgressed His own of these statements is, as is quite implication evident, that the attribution of will to God really amounts to the denial of causality and to the explanation of the rise

had

set himself a definite aim,


x

decree."

The

of things by chance.
III.

THE MEANING OF IMMANENT CAUSE

is reaffirmed by on several occasions in a positive way, as, for inSpinoza " of every existing thing there is stance, when he says that

His denial of chance or of causelessness

some certain cause by reason of which it exists." 2 He further" more defines the cause of a thing by the statement that if
were impossible that the thing reminiscent of Crescas' statement in " his definition of a cause that should the cause be conceived
this [cause] did not exist it
3

should exist,"

which

is

not to exist the effect could not be conceived to exist."

Now,

causes, according to Aristotle, are either external (ecros) to the thing 5 or present (evvirapxovTa) within the thing. 6 So also Spinoza on several occasions asserts that "we must look
for this cause in the thing or outside the thing,"

several other occasions he speaks of external causes. 8

and on and internal


7

What

these internal

explanation. formal causes as internal, whereas the efficient cause


Epistola 56.
Ethics, I, Prop. 8, Schol.;
cf.

and external causes are needs some Aristotle himself designates the material and
is

de-

Epistola 34;

Short Treatise,

I, 6,

2.

Short Treatise,

I, 6,

4.

Or Adonai,
7

I,

i,

3.

Cf.

my

Metaphysics, XII, 4, 10700, 23. Ethics, I, Prop. 8, Schol. 2; Short Treatise,


Epistolae 34 and 60.

Crescas' Critique of Aristotle, p. 221. 6 Ibid., 22.

4; Epistola 34. I, 6, Ethics,!, Prop. 11, Schol.; Ill, Prop. 30, Schol.; Ethics, III, Affectuum Defini-

tiones, 24, Expl.;

320
scribed

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


1

[ETHICS,

by him as external. But inasmuch as the efficient cause is said by Aristotle to be sometimes the same as the formal cause, 2 the efficient cause may thus according to him
be both an internal and external cause. Although Aristotle does not give any concrete examples of what he means by
external

and

from

his

own

internal causes, such examples may be gathered writings as well as from the writings of his

followers.

Of an

external cause the following are two examples: First, a physical object which is spatially external to an-

other physical object. Thus Maimonides, drawing upon Aristotle, says that "everything must needs have a mover,

which mover
e.g.,

be either outside the object moved, as, the case of a stone set in motion by the hand, or within

may

the body of a living being," which In a passage corresponding to this Aristotle says that "of those things which are moved essentially, some are moved by themselves (vet)' aurou, i.e., by

the object moved, as,

e.g.,

is

moved by

its soul. 3

an internal cause) and others by something else"; 4 and later, in explanation of things which are moved by something else,
he says: "Thus, a staff moves a stone, and
s

is

moved by

hand, which is moved by a man." Second, an incorporeal being, like God, causing motion in a corporeal object. In this case, says Maimonides, the term
"external"
is
6

is

to be taken in the sense of "separate,"

that
in-

to say, separate

from body (xupiaros rov aw^aros) or

corporeal.

Similarly of an internal cause two examples


1

may

be found.

Metaphysics, XII, 4, royob, 22

ff.

Physics, II, 7, 198*1, 24-26.


Ibid., VIII, 5, 256a, 6-8.

Moreh Nebukim,

II,

Introduction, Prop. 17.


s

<

Physics, VIII, 4, 2545, 12-14.

6
7

>-

Moreh Nebukim,

II, I:

^"03,

OJ^

xw/n<rr6s

PROPS. 15-18]

THE CAUSALITY OF GOD


body and
is

321

First, the soul which exists in the

inseparable

from the body and is the cause of its motion. We have already quoted above a statement from Maimonides where
the soul
is

called an internal cause of motion.

In a corre-

sponding passage Aristotle similarly illustrates those things which contain in themselves the principle of motion by the

example of the motion of an animal.


to species

Second, universal concepts such as genus with reference and both of them with reference to the individual
species combined make up a definition are therefore related to the essence defined as cause to

essence.

Genus and

and

for a good definition, according to Aristotle, must not only set forth the fact but it should also contain (kvv2 This Aristotelian view is Ttoipxtw} and present the cause.
effect,

implied in Maimonides' contention that God cannot be " there are defined by genus and species on the ground that no previous causes to His existence by which He could be
defined/'
totle
is

Furthermore, since a definition according to Arisof the form, 4 it may be called a formal or internal
is

cause.

It

to be

noted that Aristotle uses the same term

ivvirapxtw in describing both the nature of the causality of the definition and the nature of the cause which he calls internal (twirapyuv).

he does not mean

evident then that by internal cause only a cause which inheres in the effect,
It is

but also a cause

in

which the

effect inheres.
is

The

essential

characteristic of an internal cause therefore


it is

the fact that

inseparable from its effect, either as the soul is inseparable from the body or as the definition is inseparable from the definiendum, for, as says Aristotle, the whole is in its
1

Physics, VIII, 4, 2546, 15-16. De Anima, II, 2, 4133, 15. Cf. Analytica Pos(eriora y II, 10, 9jb, 38

ff.

Moreh Nebukim,

I,

52. Cf.
I, p.

Munk, Guide desfcgarcs,

I, p.

190, n. 3; Friedlander,

Guide oj the Perplexed, 4 Metaphysics, VII,

178, n. 2.

II, 10363, 28-29.

322

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

parts and the genus is in the species just as the parts are in 1 the whole and the species is in the genus.

Middle Ages we meet with a contrast between immanens in such expressions as actio transient and actio immanens or causa transient and causa immanens* These two terms reflect Aristotle's external (CKTOS) cause and internal (tvvirapxuv) cause. That this is so we have the testimony of Spinoza himself, who

Now,

in the

the terms transicns and

says:

(which

"immanent (inblyvende} is all the same to me)/'

or internal (innerlyke) cause The term immanens , there-

fore, by analogy with Aristotle's term tvvirapxuvy describes not only a cause which resides in the effect but also a cause in which the effect resides, for the essential meaning of an

immanent
its effect.

cause, as

we have

said,
',

is its

inseparability from

The

term transcendent

however, does not mean

Middle Ages the same as transient. It means to be logically greater or more general, especially to be logically greater and more general than the ten categories so as not to be contained under them. 4 In this sense it is used in the enumeration of the so-called transcendentales which are rein the

by Spinoza. The term transcendens is thus neither synonym of transient nor the opposite of immanens. In fact, in the case of an immanent cause of the second kind we have mentioned, i.e., immanent in the sense in which the genus is the immanent cause of the species, the cause,
ferred to
5

the

though immanent,
as
1

may

also be called transcendent in so far


its effect.

it is

more general than

The conception

of a

2 3

Cf. Physics, IV, 3, 2ioa, 17 and 19. Cf. R. Eucken, Geschichte der philosophi sc hen Terminologie, p. 204. Cf.

Short Treatise, II, 26, J (Opera, I, p. lio, 11. 22-23). W. Hamilton, Lectures on Logic, I, p. 198 (ed. 1866); C. Prantl, Geschichte der Logik, III, p. 245; R. Eucken, Geschichte und Kritik der Grundbegrife der
4

Gegenwart, pp. 79-80. s Ethics, II, Prop. 40, Schol.


pp. I23f.

I;

Cogitata Metaphysica,

I, 6.

Cf. below, Vol. II,

PROPS. 15-18]

THE CAUSALITY OF GOD


is

323

transcendent immanent cause


terms.

thus not a contradiction in

In the light of this discussion, when Spinoza says here in Proposition XVIII that "God is the causa immanens and

not transiens of

all

things/'

we may ask

ourselves in which

of their two senses does he use the terms immanens and


transiens.
It is quite clear that when he denies that a causa transiens of all things he means to say that

God God

is

is

neither a spatially external cause of all things nor a separate immaterial cause of all things. It is equally clear that when

he affirms that
does not

God
that

is

the causa immanens of


is

all

mean

God

in all things after the

things he analogy of

the soul in the body in the Aristotelian manner of expres1 sion, though among the Stoics God's immanence in the world

expressed in terms of His being the soul, the mind, or the reason of the world, and hence of His being in the world only
is

as a part of

it.

Proposition

XIV

of Ethics,

I,

where Spinoza

things are in God, and similarly the two Dialogues in the Short Treatise, where he likewise says that all things are in God as parts are in the whole, make it quite

says that

all

clear that the

immanence of God does not mean that God


body, but rather that
is

is

in all things as the soul is in the

all

things are in

God

as the less universal

in the

more universal

or, to use Spinoza's

own

expression, as the parts are in the

1 The general misunderstanding of Spinoza's description of God as an immanent cause by taking it in the sense that God is a cause who resides in His effects

after the analogy of the soul in the body occurs already in John Colerus' biography of Spinoza, published in Dutch in 1705; "In order to understand him, we must consider that . the immanent cause acts inwardly, and is confined without
. .

Thus when a man's soul thinks of, or desires something, it is or remains in that thought or desire, without going out of it, and is the immanent cause thereof. In the same manner, the God of Spinoza is the cause of the universe " wherein He is, and He is not beyond it. (English translation: The Life of Benedict
acting outwardly.

de Spinoza, London, 1706, reprinted at The Hague, 1906, pp. 67-68.) 2 Cf. Zeller, Die Philosophic der Griechen, III, I, pp. 140-142; p. 151 (4th edition).

324
whole. of
all
1

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


Spinoza's statement that God is the things is thus not an assertion that
all

[ETHICS,

immanent cause

God

is

identical

with the aggregate totality of


that

God

is

only a denial the external and separable and hence immaterial


things;
it is

cause of all things. Inseparability from the effect, as we have seen, is the essential characteristic of Aristotle's internal
cause. Spinoza makes the meaning of this term clear when " he defines the immanent cause negatively as that which by

no means produces anything outside itself 2 and as that in which "the effect remains united with its cause in such a

"

way

that together they constitute a whole." 3 therefore says that all things are in God he the same thing as when Aristotle says that
in a genus. 4

When
man

Spinoza

means exactly
exists in

animal as a species
that
all

things are in God again exactly the same thing as when Aristotle says that the 5 "part is in the whole" and as when Burgersdijck says that "animal is a whole per se in respect to man and beast," 6 that
is

he further says as parts are in the whole he means

And when

to say, the species as parts in a whole.

man and

It is in this sense that

beast exist in the genus animal God is the im-

manent cause of
genus
is

all things; He is their internal cause as the the internal cause of the species or the species of

the particulars and as the whole is the internal cause of its parts. Now the universal, even though it does not exist separately from the particulars, is not logically identical with

of the particulars, for to Spinoza the universal is an ens rationiSy which means that it has a certain kind of conthe

sum

ceptual existence, even though conceptual in the sense that


Cf. above, pp. 74 ff. Cf. also Epistola 32 to Oldenburg. 12 (Opera, I, p. 30, 11. 24-25). Short Treatise, I, First Dialogue,
Ibid.,

it

Second Dialogue,

3 (p. 31,

11.

20-22).
s

Physics, IV, 3, 2ioa, 17-18. Institutiones Logicae, Lib. I, Cap.


cst

Ibid., 16.

XIV,

p. 52 (ed.

Cambridge, 1680): "Animal

totum [per

se] respectu

hominis et bestiae."

PROPS. 15-18]
is

THE CAUSALITY OF GOD


the mind, as

325

invented

by

we have shown

in

our discussion of

1 his definition of attribute.

corresponding conceptual distinction

Consequently there is to be a between God and the

aggregate totality of modes. Being thus the immanent cause of all things in the sense that He is inseparable from

them but still logically distinct from them, God may also be said to transcend them according to the old meaning of the
term
tinct

"

transcendence," namely, that of being logically dis-

and more general. With the totality of modes or what Spinoza calls the fades totius universi God is not identical;

He

is

identical only with himself.

With

reference to the

totality of modes God is therefore called an immanent cause, but with reference to himself He is called causa sui y which,

as

we have already shown, 2 means

the denial of any kind of

cause whatsoever, whether external or internal.


tinction implied in Spinoza's thought

This

dis-

between one kind of

whole, God, which transcends its parts and is their cause, and another kind of whole, the fades totius universi, which is the sum of its parts, is clearly stated by Proclus: "Every

wholeness

(6X6717$) is either prior to parts or consists

of parts.

... A whole
fore, is that

according to subsistence (/ca0' i;7rapu>), there-

to

which consists of parts, but a whole according cause (/car' airiav) is that which is prior to parts." 3

a question may be raised. If God is related to the of modes as the universal to particulars or as the totality whole to the parts, then inasmuch as the universal as well

But here

God which

as the whole has only conceptual existence, the existence of Spinoza has sought to establish is only a con-

ceptual kind of existence, conceptual, presumably, in the sense of being invented by the mind. God is thus an ens rationis
1

Cf. above, pp. 146

ff.

Cf. above, p. 127.

Institutio fheohgica,

LXVII

(in Plotini

Enneades^ ed. Creuzer et Moser,

Paris, 1855).

326

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

reale. But this would seem to be contrary to trend of Spinoza's proofs for the existence of God, the whole which was to establish God as an ens reale*

and not an ens

This question

is

raised

by Spinoza himself

in

the First

Dialogue
Desire.

in the Short 'Treatise.

He

puts

it

in the

mouth of

"Methinks," says Desire, "I see a very great confusion in this argument of yours; for, it seems you will have it that the whole must be something outside of or apart from
its parts,

which is truly absurd. For all philosophers are unanimous in saying that the whole is a second intention (tweede kundigheid), and that it is nothing in nature apart
"

from human conception (begrip)" 2 The "second intention is the scholastic intentio secunda which is applied to such universals as genus

and
said

species,

and what Desire

is

arguing

is

by Spinoza to be the whole, is nothing but an ens rationis or intentio secunda like a universal and
that God,
is

who

God cannot

Spinoza to say, "outside of or apart from its parts. In his answer in the First Dialogue, speaking through the
character of Reason, Spinoza first disclaims the imputation that he considers God as a whole "outside of or apart from its parts" by pointing out the difference between a transeunt

therefore be, as Desire erroneously assumes "

cause

and an immanent cause and by insisting that an immanent "by no means produces anything outside itself." Then in the Second Dialogue, speaking through the char-

acter of Theophilus in answer to another question raised by Erasmus, he states that though the whole like the universal
is

an ens rationis there are two differences between them.

First,

"the universal

(algemeeri)

results

from various

disin-

connected individuals, the whole, from various united


1

Cf. above, pp. 161

ff.

2 3

Short Treatise
Cf.

-,

First Dialogue,

10.
y

R. P. M. Fernandez Garcia, Lexicon Scholasticum Philosophico- < Thcologicum


Cf. below, Vol. II, p. 122.

p. 361.

PROPS. 15-18]

THE CAUSALITY OF GOD


'

327

Second, "the universal only comprises parts of the same kind, but the whole, parts both the same and
dividuals."
different in kind/'
2

These two

differences,

it

may

be re-

marked

incidentally, reflect

two of the several senses of

the term whole discussed by Aristotle. Corresponding to Spinoza's description of the whole in the first difference,
there
is
.

means

the following passage in Aristotle: "A whole (6\ov) that which so contains the things it contains
. .

that they form a unity," in the sense of

"making up

the
is

unity between them," as "the continuous and limited


whole, when
there
is

a unity consisting of several parts pres3 ent in it." Corresponding to Spinoza's description of the universal in the second difference, there is Aristotle's stateto the effect that the

ment
is

whole

in the sense

of the universal

said of a thing which comprises parts which are of the same " kind and have common characteristics, for universal (jca06Xoi>),
is denominated as being a and a whole because they contain many things, are predicated of particulars, and are all one according to the predicate. Thus man, horse, and God are all of them one, because they are all living things." 4 Inasmuch as the whole and the universal despite their being both entia rationis are admitted by Spinoza to differ from one another on two points, we may also argue on behalf of

and, in short, that which

certain whole, are universal

Spinoza that this particular whole, namely God, though it may be called an ens rationis like any universal, differs from
universals on still a third point, namely, that it is called an ens rationis only in the sense that its real existence can be discovered only by the mind, by the ontological proofs based

upon the adequacy of the idea of God


1

in

our mind. In truth,

Short Treatise,
Ibid.

I,

Second Dialogue,

9.

3 3

Metaphysics, V, 26, icxrjb, 27-28, 28-29, 32-33.


Ibid., 29-32.

328

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


God
is

[ETHICS,

Attributes, on the other hand, have no reality apart from God; they are said to be perceived by the intellect or the mind in the sense that they are in-

however,

an ens

reale.

Or, to make use of a modern distinction, or substance or the whole is according to Spinoza a concrete or real universal, whereas attributes are according
vented

by the mind.

God
to

him only abstract


IV.

universals.

GOD

AS CONSCIOUS CAUSE

the different terms describing God's causality which Spinoza has discussed, accepting some of them and

Among

him.

rejecting others, the term "conscious" is not mentioned by shall try to show that though Spinoza explicitly

We

denies that
acts

God

acts

by

will

and design,

insisting that
still

He
the

by the necessity of His own nature, he


is

admits that

God

a conscious cause.

In Aristotle as well as

among

mediaeval philosophers, conscious causality by itself did not imply will and design, nor did it exclude necessity. Thus
Aristotle's necessary activity of

God, which was without

design, was

a conscious sort of activity. The contempla2 tion of himself is the activity which Aristotle ascribes to God.
still

furthermore described by " the act of contemplaAristotle as an act of pleasure, for tion is what is most pleasant and best." 3 Still this conis

This self-consciousness of

God

and is unacMaimonides explains the design. companied by difference between unconscious necessary activity and conscious activity
is

a necessary sort of activity

will

and

scious necessary activity as follows:

cause

is

said to act

by necessity and unconsciously when the effect follows from it "in the same manner as the shadow is caused by a body, or heat by fire, or light by the sun." A cause is said to act
1

Cf. above, pp. 146


Ibid.)

ff.

Metaphysics, XII, 9, 1074!}, 33-35.

XII,

7,

i072b, 24.

PROPS. 15-18]

THE CAUSALITY OF GOD

329

by necessity but consciously when the effect is said to follow from it in the same way as "when we say that the existence of the intellect necessarily implies the existence of
the intelligible object, for the former is the efficient cause of the latter in so far as it is an intelligible object/' But

Maimonides goes further and explains that although Aristotle admitted consciousness on the part of God, and ascribed to Him a certain self-satisfaction with His activity, " we do not call this design and it has nothing in common with design," inasmuch as "it is impossible for Him that He should wish "For example, man is pleased, satisfied, to be different/ and delighted that he is endowed with eyes and hands, and it is impossible that he should desire it to be otherwise, and yet the eyes and hands which a man has are not the result of his design, and it is not by his own determination that he has certain properties and is able to perform certain actions/' This would seem to be also the position of Spinoza. God is a necessary cause acting without will and design but still
1

a conscious cause. Not only does Spinoza's theory of the attribute of thought and his belief in the unity of nature 2 point to that conclusion, but his description of the function of that infinite mode of thinking as producing invariably " "an infinite or most perfect satisfaction 3 is almost a verbal reproduction of Aristotle's or Maimonides' characterization

of the consciousness of the activity of God. Indeed Spinoza denies of God the emotions of joy and sorrow when he says that "God is free from passions, nor is He affected with any
affect of joy or sorrow,"
4

but

this

sciousness he ascribes to
sciousness

God must

merely means that the conbe unlike our own con-

mediaevals.
1

Indeed

view which was commonly held by the in the Cogitata Metaphysica he refers
a

More/i Nebukim, II, 20. Short Treatise I, 9, 3.


',

Cf. below, Vol. II, pp. 13 ff. and p. 337. Ethics, V, Prop. 17. Cf. below, Vol. II, pp. 283

ff.

330 "
to

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

personality" (personalitas) as a term which theologians apply to God and dismisses it as something of which he is un-

able to form a clear and distinct concept. Still he makes it quite clear that God knows himself and that His understand-

ing by which

and power by which

He knows himself does not differ from His will He created the world, that is to say,
1

God
1

conscious of himself, but His consciousness of himself does not imply design and purpose.
is
Cogitata Mctaphysica y II, 8. In connection with this attempt to solve the problem of the consciousness of Spinoza's God, compare the discussions in the following works: A. Trendelenburg, Historischc Beitrage zur Philosophic (1855), II, pp. 59 ff.;

seligkcit

neuendeckter Tractat von Go//, dcm Menschen und desen GliickM. Joel, Zur Genesis der Lehre Spinoza s (1871), pp. 13-17; G. Busolt, Die Grundzuge der Erkenntnisztheorie und Metaphysik Spinozas ( 875), pp.

C. Sigwart, Spinoza
(1

866) , pp. 94-95

F. Pollock, Spinoza (1880), pp. 352 ff.; J. Martineau, Study of Spinoza (1882), pp. 334 ff.; E. E. Powell, Spinoza and Religion (1906), pp. 47 ff.; E. Lasbax,

117

ff.;

La

Hierarchic dans /'Univers chez Spinoza (1919), pp. 187

ff.;

H. Hoffding, Spinozti

Ethica (1924), pp. 49- 50.

CHAPTER X
DURATION, TIME, AND ETERNITY

THE

next group of propositions of Part I and the subsequent parts of the Ethics are strewn with references to eternity and duration. By way of general introduction we shall discuss here Spinoza's definitions of these two terms, and with

them

also his definition of time.

I.

THE STORY OF DURATION

is

" right to their originals," by which he meant, as he proceeded to explain, "sensation and reflection," which to him were the
original sources of
all

When Spinoza's contemporary Locke discovered that there some reason in the general impression that duration, time, " and eternity have something very abstruse in their nature," he suggested a way out of the difficulty by tracing them

An equal abstruseness confronts one in reading the variety of statements in which Spinoza contrasts the terms duration, time, and eternity. In our attempt to clear up this abstruseness, we may perour knowledge.
1

nals of these terms

haps equally follow Locke's advice to turn right to the originot indeed to the originals in the sense

of what Spinoza considered as the sources of our knowledge, but rather to the originals in the sense of the literary sources on which Spinoza drew in his discussions of the

meaning of these terms. Here no less than in the other problems which we have already examined Spinoza operated with terms and ideas which had been long in vogue in the philosophic literature with which he was acquainted, modi1

Locke, Essay Concerning

Human

Understanding,

II, 14,

2.

332
fying

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


them whenever he had reason
to to

[ETHICS,

them

new

uses in his

own

do so and turning scheme of reasoning. particular

The

task which

we have

set ourselves in this chapter, there-

analyze briefly the historical background of the of duration, time, and eternity, to show that there meaning are certain common principles underlying all the mediaeval
fore, is to

discussions on the

meaning of these terms, however differently expressed they may be in language and phraseology, to collect all the historical strands, and out of them to weave together Spinoza's conception of duration, time, and eternity. In Plotinus' elaborate discussion on time there is a hissurvey of all the views that make time dependent motion. Among these he reproduces Aristotle's view on upon " time which in his paraphrase reads that time is the number
torical

The original definition of time by Aristotle, in its locus classicus, reads in full that "time is
or measure of motion/'
f

number of motion according to prior and posterior/ 12 The addition of the term "measure" by Plotinus may be explained on the ground that the term number in the definition
this,

the

according to Aristotle himself, not to be taken in its ordi3 nary meaning, and that the term measure is sometimes subis,

stituted

by Aristotle

for the

term number. 4

Rejecting the
it

Aristotelian definition of time, Plotinus defines

as some-

thing independent of motion. Perhaps it will help us to understand how time is conceived by him apart from motion if we recall that motion does not appear in the first

two of Plotinus' emanated stages of being, which

in

order of

priority are: (i) the Intelligence (VoOs), (2) the universal soul 0/wxi) T P KOV/JLOV), and (3) the all-encircling celestial

sphere (7repi0opd).
1

Motion appears only

in the sphere,
For
cd.

but

Enneads,

III, vii, 8 (ed.

Creuzer et Moser, Paris, 1855).


all
J

Volkmann
22ib,
7.

(I-eipzig, 1883) raise


a

chapter numbers by one in


1-2.

subsequent references to Enneads.


Ibid., IV, 12,

Physics, IV,

u, 2190,

Ibid., 4-9.

DEF. 8]

DURATION, TIME, AND ETERNITY

333

time appears, according to Plotinus, in the universal soul. Repeating Plato's statement, which appears also in a modified form in Philo, that time is the image of eternity, 1 Ploti-

nus identifies time with the

life

of the universal soul

in

contradistinction to eternity, which is identified by him with the life of the Intelligence. 3 Now, the life of the universal
soul has a certain kind of extension (idcrra(ns) 4 sion
s

and succes-

is a process of transition from one act of thought (diavoia) to another, 7 the unity of which exists only by virtue of a certain kind of

(c(/>e?)s).

It

is

varied (aXAr?) 6 in

its

nature. It

continuity

(cruj/exeta).
.

It is a
. .

continuous acquisition of exAll these character-

istence (wpoo'KT&tJLei'oi'

kv TO; cli/cu). 9

izations of the

life

of the universal soul are true also of time,


life.

which

is

identical with that

It is

"the

life (fany)

of the

soul consisting in the movement by which she passes from one state of life (0los) to another," I0 or, it is "the length of

the life" of the soul, "proceeding in equal and similar changes advancing noiselessly," and "possessing a continuity of

energy" ((rvvex& T T W tvepydas exo^). But this kind of time which proceeds "in equal and similar changes advancing noiselessly" cannot by itself become fixed
11
<>

and

definite;
12

it

cannot be measured and divided into definite


to be

portions.

For time

measured and divided there must

be an external standard of measurement, which external standard is the movement of the all-encircling sphere. "So
that
1

if

some one should say that the movement of the sphere,


y

fimacus jyD; Enneads

III, vii,

urn llercs Sit,

XXXIV,
vii, 10.

165,

Procemium; Philo, DC Eo> $uis Rcrum Diviand DC Mutationc Nominum, XLVII, 267.
J

F.nncads, III,

Ibid., III, vii, 2, end.

Ibid., Ill, vii, 10 (p. 177,

1.

29).
6

Ibid.
Ibid.

(1. (1. (1.

25).

Ibid.
Ibid.

(1.
(1.

28).

27).
10

42).

Ibid.

47).
I I

IK*.

(11.

32-33).

/to/., Ill, Vii,

P I78,11.3-4 ).
.

Ibid.

(11.

30-30.

334

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

after a certain

manner, measures time as much as possible,

by its quantity indicating the corresponding quantity of time, which cannot in any other way be grasped or conceived, he
indeed will not adduce an absurd explanation of time." l The time which we use, then, in our daily course of life is
essentially the

same
from

as the time

which

is

an image of eteroff

nity;
it is

it

differs

it

not in kind but only in degree, in that

a certain definite portion of it,

measured

by the move-

ment of the
course of
it is

sphere. Thus,
i.e.,

in opposition to Aristotle, Plotinus

maintains that time,

the time which


or

made life, is only measured not generated by motion. 2 And in still another respect Plotinus differs from Aristotle. According to Aristotle, time is primarily defined as the measure of motion, though
but
he declares that
in a

use in our daily manifest by motion,

we

secondary sense it may also be said that time is measured by motion. 3 But according to Plotinus, time is primarily measured by motion. "Hence some philosophers have been induced to say that time is the measure of motion instead of saying that it is measured by motion." 4 Finally, it is Plotinus* contention that inasmuch as time is
within the universal soul,
to

within the universal soul, the universe, which is said to move may on that account also be said

move and

What we
time
is

have its being within time. out of this analysis of Plotinus' discussion of get that there are two kinds of time. One is indefinite
to
5

time; the other

is

definite time.

Both of these kinds of time

are genetically independent of motion. They are essentially the same: the life of the world soul and an image of eternity. But definite time has some connection with motion in so
'

Ibid.

(11.

48-52).

a
3

<

52-54). Physics, IV, 12, 22ob, 14-16. Cf. Cre seas' Critique of Aristotle , p, 646, n. 22. Enneads, III, vii, 12 (p. 179, 11. 21-23). (P- ! 7 8 , ! 26). Ibid., Ill, vii, 10 (p. 177, 11. 21-23);
(ii.

ibid.

"

DEF. 8]

DURATION, TIME, AND ETERNITY

335

measured by it. The main contrasts between the Aristotelian and the Plotinian definitions of definite time are
far as it is
(i) according to Aristotle time is generated motion; according to Plotinus, time is only made maniby fest by motion; (2) according to Aristotle, time is the measure of motion; according to Plotinus, time is measured by

thus twofold:

motion.
Plotinus, as will have been noticed, uses the

same term

time for both definite time and indefinite time. But an enigmatic passage in the Encyclopaedia of the Il}wan al-afa, x which we are going to show to contain a formulation of Plotinus' definition of time, supplies us

with a special term for

indefinite time.

The Ihwan al-afa enumerate

four definitions of time.

Two

of them, the second and third in their enumeration, read as follows: "It is also said that time is the number of a duration which
2

the motions of the celestial sphere; or, it is said that time is is numbered by the motions of the celestial

sphere/*

The

first

of these definitions

is

clearly the Aristo-

telian definition

reproduced only

in part, as in Plotinus,

and

definition,

with the use only of the original term number. The second it will be noticed, is just the reverse of the first.
In the
first, it is time which numbers motion; in the second, motion which numbers time. The contrast, then, is just

it is

1 The development of the conception of duration in Arabic and Hebrew philosophic texts presented in the succeeding pages has already been discussed by me on several occasions in the following places: "Note on Crescas' Definition of Time" in the Jewish Quarterly Review, n. s., (1919), pp. 1-17. This was revised,

and incorporated in the notes to Prop. XV in Crescas' Critique of Aristotle, especially in note 9 on pp. 636-640 and in note 23 on pp. 651-658, and in the Introduction on pp. 93-98. It was also used by me in "Solomon Pappenheim on Time and Space and His Relation to Locke and Kant" in Jewish Studies in Memory of Israel Abraham (1927), pp. 426-440. The subject is presented here in revised, enlarged, and new form. 3 Fr. Dieterici, Die Naturanschauung und Naturphilosophie der Araber, pp. 1415; Arabic text: Die Abhandlungen der Ichwdn Es-Safa, p. 35.
amplified,

336
like the

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


one made by Plotinus between
his definition

[ETHICS,

and that

of Aristotle. Again, like Plotinus this definition also implies that there are two kinds of time, one indefinite and the other
definite,

and that the

indefinite time

becomes

definite

by

the motion of the sphere. But more than Plotinus, this definition gives a special name to the indefinite time. It calls
it

duration.

If

we assume

then, as

in doing, that the

Ihwan al-afa's

we are certainly justified definition is a brief formu-

lation of Plotinus* lengthy discussion on time, then we may restate Plotinus* conception of time as follows: The essence

of time

is

duration, which

is

independent of motion and

exists within the universal soul.

fixed portion of duration

Time is only a definite and determined by motion.


consider Plotinus as the source

If this

is

true, then

we may

of a variety of definitions of time which occur alike in mediaeval Arabic, Hebrew, and Latin sources as well as in modern

philosophy and in which the term duration, sometimes under the guise of other terms, appears as something independent of motion. Such definitions, of course, do not always repro-

duce Plotinus accurately or even follow him completely. They are changed, modified, become combined with other

and completely lose their original form. But can always be traced, I believe, to Plotinus, and with a they little effort their variations from the original Plotinian definidefinitions,

tion can always be accounted for. I shall try to reproduce a few examples of the variety of forms which this Plotinian definition of time has assumed in Arabic, Hebrew, Latin, and

other philosophic writings down to the time of Spinoza. We shall first deal with Arabic and Hebrew texts, and then

with texts in Latin and other languages. In surveying the Arabic and Hebrew philosophic texts we may discover three sets of definitions in which the influence
of Plotinus
is

recognizable or the term duration

is

made

use

DEF. 8]
of.

DURATION, TIME, AND ETERNITY


first set,

337

the Plotinian conception of time, either mention of the term duration or without it, is used, with the

In the

inition.

as in the Ifrwan al-afa, in opposition to the Aristotelian defIn the second set, the Plotinian conception of time,

out

again either with the mention of the term duration or withit, is used in combination with the Aristotelian definition,

and

as

term duration

supplementary to it. In the third set, the is embodied within the phraseology of a cur-

rent definition of time which, not unlike that of Aristotle,

made time dependent upon notion. Of the first set of definitions we have an example in " Saadia's reference to one who imagines that time is external to the sphere and that the world is within it." From the
T

context

it is
is it

definition

unmistakably clear that the contention of this that time is by its nature independent of motion
has been put forward in opposition to the defiThe statement that "time is external

and that

nition of Aristotle.
to the sphere

and the world

is

within it"

is

reminiscent of
"

similar statements

sphere exists
avrrj Kal

made by Plotinus, namely, that and is moved within time" (tv xpbvq yap
is

the
Kal

ean

Kal Kivelrai) 2 or that the activity of the soul

constitutes time and "the universe

within time"

(6 de tv

similar allusion to the Plotinian conception of time as opposed to that of Aristotle is found in Altabrizi. He enumerates four definitions of time.

Three of these

either identify

But one of it belong to motion. these, the fourth one, states that time is neither a body nor
time with motion or
4 anything belonging to a body.
1

make

This,

it

seems to me,

is

Etnunot we-De'of,

I, 4.

3
*

Enneads,
Ibid.
(1.

III, vii,

(p. 178,

11.

17-18).

26).

Commentary on Maimonides* Twenty-five

Propositions, Prop. 15.

Cf.

my

Crescas* Critique oj Aristotle^ pp. 635-636, 656.

338

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

merely another way of saying that time is neither motion nor anything belonging to motion, for body is that which alone has motion. To deny that time is dependent upon

motion

is,

therefore, merely to repeat Plotinus' contention

against Aristotle.

An
found
tion,

echo of the Plotinian conception of time


in Crescas.

may

be also
defini-

Openly rejecting the Aristotelian


l

he defines time as "the measure of the duration of


rest

motion or

between two instants/'

He

furthermore

indicates the significance of this definition as an attempt to free time from motion when he says, again in opposition to
Aristotle, that as a result of his
in the soul. It

new

definition, time exists

only may be remarked here that by "soul" Crescas does not mean the universal soul of Plotinus, but

human soul. But when Crescas further argues, as a consequence of his definition of time, that there had existed time prior to the creation of the world, 2 the implication is that prior to the creation of the world time, or rather
rather the
duration, existed in the
ing to the views of Philo

mind of God as did eternity accordand Plotinus. Time in the created

world, however, is essentially not different from time or duration before the creation of the world. It is not generated

by motion, but only measured by motion. Crescas could thus repeat with Philo and Plotinus that time is an image of
eternity.

Of the second set of definitions we have a good example in Maimonides. Though following Aristotle in saying that time is an accident of motion 3 and hence could not have existed
prior to the creation of the world,

Maimonides

states that

we

may
1

have

in

our mind an idea of a certain duration which


ii,

Or /ldonai

I,

u.

Cf.

my

Crescas' Critique of Aristotle, pp. 289,


3

651-

658,93-98.
3

Ibid.

Moreh Nebukim^

II,

Introduction, Prop. 15.

DBF. 8]

DURATION, TIME, AND ETERNITY

339

existed prior to the creation of the world. He calls that dura" tion a supposition or imagination of time but not the reality

of time."

Maimonides' "supposition or imagination of


"

time" seems to be the same as Plotinus' image of eternity," i.e., a duration which is independent of motion. But whereas
Plotinus "image of eternity" is time itself and is essentially of the same nature as eternity in so far as both are inde1

pendent of motion, Maimonides' "imagination of time" is essentially different from time; it is only a pseudo-time, inindependent of motion, whereas time, properly so called, is generated by motion. The Plotinian time is thus combined by Maimonides with the Aristotelian time and
as
it is

asmuch

made to supplement it. The view of Maimonides is adopted by Albo, and is restated by him in a new way. He says there are two kinds of time. One is "unmeasured duration which is conceived only
thought and which existed prior to the creation of the world and will continue to exist after its passing away." " This he calls absolute time," in which there is no distinction
in

of equal and unequal or of before and after, and which he identifies with what Maimonides has described as an "imagination of time."

The

other kind of time

is

that which

is

"numbered and measured by the motion of the sphere, to which are applicable the distinctions of before and after, of equal and unequal." 2 These two kinds of time, as I have
said in the case of

Maimonides, are undoubtedly the

result

of a combination of the Aristotelian time and the Plotinian


time.

Examples of the third


definition
'

set of definitions are to

be found

in

the works of several authors.

Saadia has two versions of a


(i)

which belongs
II,
1

to this type:

"Time

is

nothing

Ibid., II, 13.


,

8.

Cf.

my

Cre seas' Critique of Aristotle t p. 658.

340

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


x

[ETHICS,
(2)

but the extension of the duration of bodies."

"The

es-

sence of time is the duration of these existent things." 2 Abraham bar Hiyya, in whose text there is a doubtful reading of one word, gives a definition of time which like the definitions of Saadia reads either (i) "that time is nothing but

" the extension of existent things" or (2) that time is nothing but a term signifying the duration of existent things." 3 Similarly Algazali gives a definition, evidently meant by

him

to be a paraphrase of Aristotle's definition,

which reads

a term signifying the duration of motion, that that is to say, the extension of motion/' 4 It will be noticed that the common element in all these definitions is the use of the

"

time

is

terms extension and duration and that these terms extension

and duration are used

in

connection with "bodies,"

or "existent things," or "motion," all of which means the same thing, for by "existent things" here is meant "bodies,"
All these definitions, despite use of the term duration, or extension, imply the detheir pendence of time upon motion, and may be traced, I believe,
to a definition the phrasing of which reads that time is the extension (biaarrHJia) of motion, and which is attributed by

and "bodies" have "motion."

Plutarch and Stobaeus to Plato and by Simplicius to Zeno and is included by Plotinus among the definitions which

make time dependent upon motion. 5


Throughout my discussion of Arabic and Hebrew texts I have used the term duration. Now, this term, derived from " " the Latin durare^ literally, to be hardened," and hence, to
continue, to last, to remain," has been used in the Middle
1

Emunot

we-De'ot, II,
y

u.

lbid. y I, 4.

Hegyon ha-Nefesh I, p. 2a. Maka$id al-Fala sifah, II, iii (p. 192). Cf. De P/acitis, I, 21, and Eclogae, I,
Enneads^ III,
vii, 6.

8, in Diels,

Doxographi Graeci,
i,

p.

318;

Simplicius on Categories in Zeller, Philosophic der Griechen y HI,


edition);

p. 184, n. 6 (4th

DEF. 8]

DURATION, TIME, AND ETERNITY


in

341

Ages

in a certain technical sense in

connection with time. In

Hebrew, no more than in Greek, however, is there any term of the same derivative technical meaning which is etymologically of the same origin. But the texts which I have discussed contain three Arabic and eight Hebrew terms which, though etymologically unconnected with the Latin duratio, can be shown from their context and implications to have the same technical meaning as the Latin duratio. These three Arabic and eight Hebrew terms can be
Arabic and
arranged etymologically in three groups. (i) The terms in the first group all go back to a root meaning "to stretch, to
1

extend," and are used in philosophic Arabic and Hebrew as some of the equivalents of the Greek Stdcrrcuns, "extension,"

which, as

we have

seen, occurs in Plotinus as one of the char(2)

acteristics of indefinite time.

The term

in the

second

group comes from a root meaning to join, to keep together," and is the equivalent of the Greek <7i>j>ex 6a > "continuity," which, again as we have seen, occurs in Plotinus as one of the
characteristics of indefinite time.
(3)

"

The terms

in the third

group go back to roots meaning

"

to remain, to survive, to

exist," and are the equivalents, though not etymologically of the same origin, of the Greek (rwexeia, and reflect the expressions of continuity and existence used by Plotinus in

connection with indefinite time.


philological digression will

The importance
in

of this

come out

our discussion of

Latin texts which


1

we now

begin.

The

I.

three groups of terms are as follows: <** (Ihwan al-Safa and Algazali), mD,ny (Hebrew translations of Algazali).

jloi^l (Maimonides), "]E?Dn (Samuel Ibn Tibbon's translation of Maimonides

and Albo), JTD'N


II.
lii

(IJarizi's translation

of Maimonides).

(Saadia),

DVp,

JTntttPn (Judah Ibn Tibbon's translation of Saadia),

(Abraham bar
in.
Cf.

IJiyya).

ropmnn (Crescas). my Crescas' Critique of Aristotle, pp. 638, 639, 655,

656.

342

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


I

[ETHICS,

In Latin philosophic texts, as far as

have been able to

examine them, we find on the whole the conception of duration combined in a variety of manners with the Aristotelian
definition of time.

good example of

it is

to be

found
that

in

Augustine's treatment of time. Augustine starts out by saying that time

is

"by
is

which we measure the motion of bodies."

In this he

But he certainly following the phraseology of Aristotle. does not stop with this. He soon asks himself what time is
in itself.
2

Aristotle.

In this again he is repeating a question raised by He then proceeds to show that time cannot be

identical with the

motion of a body, 4

in

which again Aristotle

an accident of motion but

himself would agree with him, for to Aristotle time is only is not motion itself. 5 But still it

would seem that Augustine means to deny by his statement more than the identification of motion and time. It would
to make time more independent of mowas done by Aristotle, though still not altogether independent of motion as was done by Plotinus. That time was not according to Augustine altogether independent of motion and hence purely subjective in its nature is evidenced

seem that he means


tion than

by the

fact that

when he suggests

that time

is

a certain

kind of "stretching out" (distentici) he immediately adds that he does not know of what it is a stretching out and

marvels "if

it

be not of the mind


It
is

itself."

His answer to
itself,

this is in the negative.


in effect,

not of the mind

he says

but
I

it is

rather in the mind.

mind, that

measure

my

times."

"In thee it is, O my Time indeed is the measit is

ure of motion, as said Aristotle, but


1

not motion
26.

itself

but

Confessions, XI, 23.

Ibid.,
*

XI, 23 and

3 s

Physics IV, 10, 2i7b, 32.


',

Confessions, XI, 24.

Physics, IV, 10, 21 8b, 9-18.


Ibid.,

Confessions, XI, 26.

XI,

27.

DEF. 8]

DURATION, TIME, AND ETERNITY

343

only the
I

memory
I

of motion that time measures.

"In

thee,

say,

in

measure times. The impression which things make thee as they pass by doth still remain, even when the things

do

still

themselves are gone, and this impression it is which, being * Thus a connection of time with present, I measure."
is

assumed by Augustine, but a connection not with is still present, but with the image of motion which exists in the mind after the motion itself is gone. This is far from the purely ideal conception of time which intermotion
motion that
preters of Augustine generally attribute to him. It is certainly unlike the purely ideal conception of time which we
find in Plotinus
tion

and Crescas and in the pseudo-time or durawhich according to Maimonides and Albo existed prior to the creation of the world. It is nothing but a modification

of Aristotle's definition of time which must have been suggested to Augustine by Aristotle's own contention that in

some respect time

2 exists only in the soul.

For our immediate purpose, however, the chief importance of Augustine's discussion of time consists in the term distentio
which he uses on several occasions
of time. 3 In this word distentio ,
in describing the

nature

it

seems to me, we

may

discern a technical term used as the equivalent of duratio. The term distentio is the equivalent of the Greek 5cdcrraort,s,

and

it

will

traceable to the

be recalled that terms meaning "stretching out" Greek SiAoracris were used in Arabic and

Hebrew
itself is

texts for duration

and that the term

5ta0Ta<ris

used by Plotinus as one of the characteristics of his

indefinite time or duration.

The

Aristotelian definition of time


'

use of the concept of duration in connection with the is to be found in the writings

ibid.

3 3

Physics > IV, 14, iija, 16-23.


Confessions y XI, 23, end, and 26.

344

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


all

[ETHICS,

of almost

only to what

the leading scholastics. Confining ourselves is common to all of them, we may discern in

them the following general characteristics. Duration is assumed by them as a genus of which time is a species, for they
speak of duration as being of three kinds, (a) eternity, (if) aevum, and (c) time. While time is generally defined after
1

Aristotle as being the measure of motion, duration is conceived as something independent of motion. Two definitions

of duration

may
is

be discerned in their writings.

One

reads

that duration

tion of existence.

the permanence or perseverance or continua2 The other reads that it connotes a certain

succession. 3

Both these expressions, "permanence or perse-

verance or continuation of existence" and "succession," as will be recalled, are used by Plotinus among his characterizations of his indefinite time,
is

the underlying meaning of

and the first of these expressions some of the terms used by Araconcept of duration.
I

bic
1

and Hebrew authors

for the

One

Cf. Suarez, Disputation*-s Metaphysicac, Disp. L, Sec.


in

II, i:

"Primo, ac praeci-

pue dividitur duratio


simpliciter dicta."
. . .

creatam et increatam.
i:

Duratio incrcata est aeternitas

"Duratio igitur creata dividi potest primo in perDividitur ergo ulterius duratio creata permanens in durationem immutabiliter natura sua permanentem, quae aevum appellatur, et
Sec. V,
. .

manentem

et successivam.

in earn quae licet permanens sit." Sec. VIII, i: "Agimus ergo de duratione habente continuam successionem, de qua Philosophi disputant cum Aristotele in 4. Phys. co quod tempus, Physicum motum consequi videatur." Cf. also Marc.
. . .

Anton. Galitius,

Summa

Totius Phtlosophiae Aristotelicae


in scholis versatis
I, I:

ad mentem

S. Bonaven-

turae, Pars I, Lib. IV, Tract. II, Quaest. Ill:

"Tres durationes communiter a Docpatentissimum esse opinor." "Dicitur enim durare res, quae in sua

toribus assignari solere,


a

omnibus

Cf. Suarez, op.

'/.,

Disp. L, Sec.

existentia perseverat:

unde duratio idem esse censetur, quod permanentia in Bonaventura, Commcntaria in Qiiatuor Libros Scntcntiarum, Lib. II, Dist. XXXVII, Art. I, Quaest. II: "Continuatio in esse non est aliud quam duratio." a Cf. Suarez, op. cit. Disp. L, Sec. II, i: "Est ergo prima opinio Ochami, et Gaesse."
t

supra dicentium, durationem distingui ab existentia, quia existentia significat absolute, et simpliciter rem esse extra suas causas: duratio vero dicit existentiam
brielis

vel possit coexistere res, quae durare quod duratio dicat existentiam, quatenus apta est ad coexistendum successions " Cf. also Lon Mahieu, Franfois Suarcz, p. 374.
dicitur:

connotando successionem, cui vel coexistat,


vel aliter,

DEF. 8]

DURATION, TIME, AND ETERNITY

345

gets, however, the impression that these typical scholastics did not consider duration as something purely subjective, any more than Augustine did. Whatever they believed the

seem to have some kind of objectivity. All their discussions on that point would seem to be attempts at different interrelation of duration to its object to be, they
it

attached to

pretations of Aristotle's statement that time, in so far as it 1 is the number of motion and not motion itself, is in the soul.

The
tion
is

scholastic distinction between duration

pears also in the discussions of Descartes


defined by Descartes as a

and time apand Locke. Dura-

mode

of consideration of

2 Whether the the perseverance in the existence of a thing. thing is moved or unmoved it has duration, and duration

of the same kind.

Time, however, applies only to things in and is defined by him as the measure of motion. 3 motion, Locke follows on the whole the same tradition, but instead
of defining duration, like Descartes, as the perseverance in existence, he defines it as the distance (= extension, Stdoracris)

by

the train of ideas

between any parts of that succession furnished to us which constantly succeed one another
4

in the

understanding.

It will

have been noticed that the


in

two characteristic expressions used by Descartes and Locke


in their definitions of duration,

existence

"

namely, "perseverance

definitions

and "succession/* correspond exactly to the two of duration which we find among the scholastics
to Plotinus.

and which can be traced

Furthermore,

if

we

substitute Plotinus' "soul" for Locke's "understanding," we shall find that Locke's characterization of duration is

reminiscent of Plotinus' characterization of indefinite time.


1

Physics, IV, 14, 22ja, 16-23.

'
J 4

Principia Philosophiae,
Ibid.,

I, 55.

and

I,

57.

Essay Concerning

Human

Understanding

II, 14,

1-3.

346

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


1

[ETHICS,

This idea of succession which constitutes duration, continues Locke, is not derived from motion. Time, however, is connected with motion, and
is

defined by

him

as duration

measured by motion. 2

The cumulative

effect of all these definitions of

time in

the Greek, Arabic, Hebrew, and Latin philosophic traditions, from Plotinus down to Locke, stands out clearly in its main outline. There is duration. This duration is not generated

by motion.
nus
it is

It

is

something generated

in the

mind. In Ploti-

In Augustine it is identified with memory or the impression of things gone that remains in the mind. In Maimonides and Albo, who call it
said to be in the universal soul.
either an imagination of time or absolute time,
to be
it is

also said

something which

is

formed

in

our mind.

In Crescas,

similarly said to be in the soul. In Locke it is said to the human understanding, consisting of the train of be in

time

is

ideas within

it. Furthermore, this duration exists apart from the physical world. In Saadia it is said to be external

to,

that

is

to say apart from, the sphere.

In Altabrizi,

it is

said not to belong to anything corporeal.

In Maimonides,

have existed prior to the creation of the world. In Descartes and Locke it is said to apply to things which have no motion. Finally, this duration is considered as something indefinite and indeterminate. Time is
it is

Crescas, and Albo

said to

generally taken to differ from duration.


as to

Though
is

there

is

no

general agreement tion or not, it is generally agreed that time applies to things which have motion. It is considered as a definite portion of

whether time

generated by mo-

motion, and this definiteness,


attained by
1

it

is

generally admitted,

is

its

being measured by motion.


3

Ibid.,

6.

Ibid.,

17

and

19.

DEF. 8]

DURATION, TIME, AND ETERNITY


II.

347

DURATION AND TIME

IN SPINOZA

mould of thought that we must cast Spinoza's on duration and time. In presenting the subexpressions
It is in this
ject,
first deal with those aspects of duration in contrasted with time, leaving for subsequent discussions all the other aspects of it in which it is contrasted

we

shall

which

it is

with eternity.

The fullest definition of duration is given by Spinoza in the Cogitata Metaphysica. * "Duration," it reads, "is the attribute under which we conceive the existence of created
actuality." Substantially it reechoes one of the two types of definitions of duration which we have reproduced above from scholastic
things, in so far as they persevere in their

own

authors and and in sua

in

which continuatio in

esse y

permanentia in

esse,

existentia perseverat are the expressions indis-

criminately used.

The immediate
seem
to be

literary source of Spinoza, however,


in the following

would

found

statement of Descartes:

merely think that the duration of each thing is a mode under which we shall conceive this thing, in so far as it perseveres to exist."''
Still

"We

that of Descartes

when we compare closely Spinoza's definition with we shall notice three differences. First,

Descartes
it it

calls duration a "mode," whereas Spinoza calls an "attribute." Second, Descartes only says in so far as perseveres to "exist," whereas Spinoza uses first the term

"existence" like Descartes, but then adds the term "actuality" in the statement "in so far as they persevere in their own actuality/* Third, Descartes simply says "thing,"

whereas Spinoza speaks of "created" things.


1

The

question

Cogitata Metaphysica,
2

I, 4.

Principia Philosophiae,

I, 55.

348

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


is

[ETHICS,

was merely as a matter of free paraphrasing that Spinoza happened to make these three verbal changes or whether there was some well thought out reason which led him to introduce them. With respect to the substitution of the term attribute for mode, we shall try to show that it was done by Spinoza at
before us

whether

it

the suggestion of Descartes himself.

While

in his

formal definition Descartes calls duration a

mode, elsewhere he refers to it indiscriminately as belonging " either to modes of things" (rerum modos) or to "affections of things" (rerum ajjectiones). Modes and affections are used
1

by Descartes as interchangeable terms, both of them in contrast, on the one hand, to "things" and, on the other hand, to "eternal truths which have no existence outside our
2

thought."

Now, according

to Descartes, while the terms

modes, qualities (or affections), and attributes are on the whole analogous in meaning, still they are used in different
senses

when they

are considered with reference to their ap-

3 plication to substance.

Consequently, though in his formal definition of duration, as we have seen, he uses the term "mode" and elsewhere he also refers to it as an "affection,"

he

insists that the


it

most proper term

to be used in connec-

tion with

is

"attribute."

"And
them
in

even

in

created things

that which never exists in


existence

and duration

in

any diverse way, like the existing and enduring thing,


4

should be called not qualities or modes, but attributes."


1

My

statement
I,

is

based upon the following consideration.

In Principia Philo-

sophiae,

48, Descartes divides all objects into (i), things, or (2), affections of* things, and B, eternal truths having no existence outside our thought. Then he

proceeds to say: "Of the things we consider as real, the most general are substance, duration, order, number." I take it that of these four examples, the first, substance, is an illustration of A (i), things, whereas the other three, duration, order, number,
are illustrations of

(2), affections

of things.

Later

in 50, instead

of "things and

affections of things," he uses the expression "things or


'

modes of things."
Ibid.

Ibid., I, 48.

Ibid.,

I,

56.

DEF. 8]

DURATION, TIME, AND ETERNITY

349

Spinoza thus had very good reason for substituting the term "attribute" for "mode" in the definition of duration.
Still

occasionally he slips back to the use of the term "affec1

tion," which to him as to Descartes is synonymous with "mode." Thus in the following passage he says: "For, as was noted in the first Part of the discussion, duration is an

affection (ajfectio) of existence."

Similarly, Spinoza had a very good reason for introducing the term "actuality" to explain the term "existence." The

term "existence," when used by Spinoza or


in the definition of duration,

his predecessors

was meant

to emphasize

two

was meant to emphasize that things. it was existence and not motion that was required for the conIn the
first place, it

ception of duration, inasmuch as duration was independent of motion. This, as we have seen, is the common characteristic of duration throughout the history of that term. Descartes

makes himself explicit on that point when he says, "For we do not indeed apprehend that the duration of things
3

is different from that of things which are In the second place, it was meant to emphasize that there is no duration in beings which have no existence, as, for instance, fictitious beings and beings of

which are moved

not moved."

reason.

and "entia rationes."


self

Suarez definitely excludes from duration "ficta" 4 Now, the word "existence" by itsufficient as

would perhaps have been

an emphasis of

the second point.

Still, in order not to leave

any room

for

in their

doubt, Spinoza adds the phrase "in so far as they persevere own actuality ," that is to say, the existence must be
is only in thought. It not impossible that in phrasing this definition Spinoza was Cf. below, Vol. II, pp. 193-194.
Cogitata Metaphysica, II,
3 I

an actual existence and not one which


is

(Opera,

I, p.

250,

11.

13-14).

Principia Philosophiae,

I, 57. I, i.

Suarez, op.

cit.,

Disp. L, Sec.

350

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

directly influenced by Suarez, who insists that duration is to be attributed to a thing which exists in actuality. 1 The same

idea that duration requires an actually existent object is ex" Duration pressed by Spinoza also in the following manner:
is

an affection of existence, not of the essence of things." a " " By essence he means the concept of a thing which may

or

may

not have existence outside our mind.

In the same

vein he also says: "The duration of our body does not denor upon the absolute nature pend upon its essence of God the body is determined to existence but
.
.

The duration, therefore, of our and action by causes. body depends upon the common order of nature and the constitution of things." 3 The dependence of duration upon
.
.

actually existing things is clearly expressed in the following passage: "Before creation no time and duration can be

imagined by us. ... Hence duration presupposes that things either have been created before it or at least exist with it." 4
that Plotinus gives as one of the characterof his indefinite time or duration that it is "a continuity " " " " of energy." 5 Energy may mean there actuality as well
It

may be recalled
"

istics

as

activity."

same token, the introduction by Spinoza of the qualifying term "created" in the expression "of the existence of created things" had a certain definite purpose. Indeed

By

the

means by
1

But Spinoza something different. By the term "created" Spinoza does not mean here the traditional conception of
Suarez uses
it it
Ibid.\ "Igitur in

also in connection with duration. 6

universum durare solum tribuitur


cit.
t

rei

existens est." Cf. Galitius, op.


ratio est
2
3

Pars

I,

Lib. IV, Tract. II, Quaest.

actu existenti, et prout "


I,

2:

Du-

pcrmanentia

rei in

suo esse actual!, quieto, et perfecto."


I.

Cogitata Metaphysica, II,


Ethics, II, Prop. 30,

Demonst.

On essence and existence, see also below, p.

383.

Cogitata Mttaphysica, II, 10.

5
6

See above, p. 333. See quotation above,

p. 344, n. i.

DEF. 8]

DURATION, TIME, AND ETERNITY


its

351

creation with

inevitable implication of

he means by it conceived as having duration must have their existence dependent upon a cause, irrespective of the question whether
in time ex nihilo.

What

coming into being is that the things

they had a beginning in time or not. Or, as Spinoza himself says, duration is to be attributed to things "only in so far as
their essence is to be distinguished

from their existence/'


is

'

that
their
this

is

to say, in so far as their existence

not necessary by

own nature but must be brought about by a cause. If is the meaning of Spinoza's statement, we can find a his-

background for it. It corresponds to the contention of Suarez that even if the angels or the heavens were assumed to have been created by God from eternity, they would still have
torical

duration, inasmuch as they would still have been called created 2 beings in so far as their existence is conditioned by a cause.

Spinoza's definition of duration as an attribute, or mode, or affection of existence may bring up the question of the relation of duration to existence. Are they identical, or is
there
is

some

difference

between them? and

if

the latter,

what

the difference?

To

question explicitly. the scholastics, and Spinoza must have been conscious of it, for some statements in his writings, as we shall try to

be sure, Spinoza does not raise this But the question had been raised by

show, seem to aim at


is it

it.

The question

as to

"how

duration

related to existence," as stated by Suarez, reads: "whether is something distinct from the thing itself, or whether it is
it."
3

completely identical with


1

Three views are reported.


ab

Cogitata Metaphysica, II, I. Cf. use of "created" below, p. 383, n. 5. Op. cit., Disp. L, Sec. Ill, v: "Unde si Deus creasset angelum, ut coelum

aeterno, non esset in eo durationis principium, et nihilominus duratio eius creata


esset, et essentialiter differens
*

ab aeternitate."

Disp. L, Sec. I, i: "Hinc ergo nascitur difficultas, quomodo duratio ad existentiam comparetur; an scilicet, sit aliquid distinctum ab ipsa re, aut prorsus idem sit." Cf. Galitius, op. cit., Pars I, Lib. IV, Tract. II,Quaest. II: "An duratio

Op.

tit.,

realiter differat

ab existentia?"

352

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


differ
is

[ETHICS,

According to some, duration and existence


other in re and realiter, that

from each
1

to say, they are separable

and each of them can be conceived without the other. Others, as Bonaventura, Banez, and other Thomists, consider the difference between them as a modal difference, like that which exists between a substance and a mode or between two modes. 2 Suarez, Scotus, Occam, and Biel, however, consider duration and existence as being inseparable
though
distinct

from each other, the distinction between


reason. 3

Similarly Descartes, after disof distinction, the real, the modal, cussing the three kinds and that of reason (ratione), the last of which he defines as

them being one of

that "between substance and some one of

its

attributes

not possible that we should have a distinct knowledge of it,'* 4 concludes that "because there is no substance which does not cease to exist when it ceases to

without which

it

is

endure, duration

is

only distinct from substance by reason."

Evidently drawing upon these discussions, Spinoza likewise says: "From which it clearly follows that duration is distinguished from the whole existence of a thing only by reason. For, however much duration you take away from any thing,
so

existence you detract from it." In the light of this statement, when Spinoza chose to

much

of

its

define duration as an "attribute" of existence, he used the

term attribute
defines
it

in the strictly technical sense in

which he

namely, as a purely subjective aspect of the thing of which it is used. This is an indirect corroboration of our interpretation of Spinoza's attribute as

in the Ethics^

something purely subjective.


1

Suarez, op.
1 3

/.,

Disp. L, Sec.

II.
f.;

Leon Mahieu, Francois Suarez, pp. 372 Cf. Le"on Mahieu, pp. 373 f. Principia Philosophiae, I, 60 and 62.
Cf.
Ibid., I, 62.
6

Galitius, he.

cit.

Cogitata Metaphysica,

I, 4.

DEF. 8]

DURATION, TIME, AND ETERNITY

353

In the passage just quoted, Spinoza, as will have been noticed, uses the expression "the whole existence of a thing"

when he wishes
reason.

to prove that duration differs

from existence

only by expression "the whole of existence" of course, that there may be a part of existence and implies, hence a part of duration. This leads Spinoza in the passage

The

quoted to introduce

his definition of time. It is possible, he says, to take off a certain portion of the duration of a thing. But "in order to determine this we compare it with the

duration of those things which have a fixed and determinate * Or as he says motion, and this comparison is called time."
in

another place:

"No

time because
less,

we imagine some

one doubts, too, that we imagine bodies to move with a velocity

we

or greater than, or equal to that of others." 2 Here then have a definition of time in terms of duration the like of

which we have already met in Plotinus, in the Arabic Ihwan al-afa, in the Jewish Crescas, and in many scholastics. Spinoza's contemporary Locke, as we have seen, restates it.
His immediate source, however, must again have been Descartes in the following passage: "But in order to com-

prehend the duration of

all

things under the

same measure,

usually compare greatest and most regular motions, which are those that create years and days, and these we term time." 3

we

their duration with the duration of the

Essentially, thus, time and duration, according to Spinoza, are the same. Time is not a new attribute of things, it is

not different from the attribute of duration, nor does it add anything to duration. It is only a definite portion of duration

measured by motion.

Thus Descartes: "Hence

this

[time]

adds nothing to the notion of duration, generally 4 And so also Spinoza: taken, but a mode of thinking."
1

Ibid.

Principia Philosophiae,

I, 57.

Ethics, II, Prop. 44, Schol. Ibid.

354
"

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

Therefore, time is not an affection of things but only a of thought or, as we have said, a being of reason; it is a

mode mode mode

of thought serving to explain duration/' Thus duration is a mode of existence, and time
of duration.
It is

is

analogous to the successive relations be-

tween time, motion, and body in Aristotle. Motion, according to the mediaeval Aristotelian phraseology, is an accident
of body and time is an accident of motion. 2 Substitute the terms duration and existence respectively for motion and

body and the term mode


analogy.

for accident

and you get a perfect


Everything which

The upshot

of all this discussion

is this.

may be conceived of as existing or as not existing, depending upon some cause for its existence, has existence superadded
by Spinoza a created thing. Now, existence of a thing merely means the fact that the concept which we form in our mind of a thing has an
to its essence.
is

Such a thing

called

object outside our mind to correspond to it. The concept is the essence of the thing; the outside reality is the existence of the thing. Now the mind in which the concept is formed

does not create the existence.

The

existence

is

given.
it

But

when
hends
in its

the
it

existence, compresomething enduring, as something persevering actuality, and it cannot perceive it otherwise. Existas

mind comprehends that given

ence does not appear to the mind as a point, but as some sort of extension. This conception of the mind of the external existing object as

actuality, or, in other words, this attribute

something persevering in its own under which we


is

conceive existence,

is

that which

called duration.

Duration

thus refers only to things which have existence, and then only to the existence of such things and not to their essence. "It
1

Cogitata MttapJtysica,

I, 4.

Moreh Nfbukim,

II, 13, First

Theory.

DEF. 8]

DURATION, TIME, AND ETERNITY


it

355

should be noted under duration, as

will
it

be of use when
is

below we are discussing eternity, that

conceived as

greater and less and as if it were composed of parts, and then r Note only as an attribute of existence and not of essence/'
the expression "as if it were composed of parts/* for duration according to Spinoza is a continuous quantity and does not

of discrete parts such as moments. 2 Or, again, " Spinoza speaks of duration as existence considered in the 3 abstract, as if it were a certain kind of quantity."
consist
If

we were now

to

compare Spinoza's and

Aristotle's

conceptions of time with respect to the problem of their subjectivity and objectivity, we should find that there is
little

difference.

partly ideal.
latter's

Both assume time to be partly real and In so far as Aristotle's motion and Spinoza's
real.

existence are outside the mind, the former's time and the

duration are

In so far as the measure of time

of Aristotle and the duration of Spinoza are conceptions of the mind, they are both ideal. In fact the same dual nature of time

we

shall find

throughout the mediaeval definitions,

despite the controversies among their various proponents on that point. None of the mediaevals believed in the absolute ideality of time.

The only
ideal time

place
is

Not even Augustine went where we find a conception

as far as that.

of absolutely

where time can be conceived to

exist in a

mind

which has existence without a body and without a physical world to draw its thoughts from, such as God and Plotinus'
universal soul.

Of such

a nature

is

the time of Plotinus,

existence prior to the creation of the world, the imagination of time of Maimonides, and the

the time of Crescas, in

its

absolute time of Albo.


1

Cogitata Metaphysiea,
1

I, 4.

Epistola 12.
Ethics, II, Prop. 45, Schol.

356

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

have been found

Exactly the same definitions of duration and time which in the Cogitata Metaphysica are to be found
1

in Spinoza's letter to

Meyer.

Using there the term


"

"

modes

"

as the equivalent of the expression

created things" in the

Cogitata Metaphysica, meaning thereby something whose essence does not necessarily involve existence, he says that " we can only explain duration is that by means of which the existence of modes." He then goes on to say that from

duration, there arises time of determining duration, concluding that purpose " time is merely a mode of thinking or, rather, of imagining." 2 The additional phrase "or, rather, of imagining" is of no
the fact that
for the

we can determine

special significance here.

It is

probably nothing but a reminis-

cent expression of Hobbes' statement that "time is a phantasm of motion." 3 Hobbes himself meant by phantasm not

"imagination" as opposed to "thought," but rather imagination in the general sense of not being "the accident or
affection of any body" and of not being "in the things without us, but only in the thought of the mind." 4 This is exactly

what Spinoza meant by suggesting "imagining"

as an alter-

native for "thinking." It is not impossible, too, that the use of the term "imagining" by Spinoza is a faint reminis-

cence of the Platonic and Plotinian saying that time "image" of eternity.

is

the

thus assumed by Spinoza to have two characteristics. First, the existence of an object which is said to be conceived under the attribute of duration must be only

Duration

is

a possible existence, depending upon God as its efficient 5 cause, which he describes in the Cogitata Metaphysica by

the term "created things" and in his letter to


1

Meyer by

the

Fpistola 12.
Ibid. (Opera, IV, p. 57,
11.

*
3

7-8):

"cogitandi, scu potius imaginandi

Modos."

Elementa Philosophiae, Pars II, Cap. VII, 3. s See Ibid. below, Vol. II, pp. 80 ff.

DEF. 8]

DURATION, TIME, AND ETERNITY

357

This differentiates duration from eternity, which we shall discuss later. Second, duration is to be conceived as unlimited, unmeasured, and undetermined. This
differentiates duration from time.

term "mode."

These two characteristics

of duration are contained in the term "indefinite" which

Spinoza uses in his definition of duration in the Ethics. "Duration," he says, "is the indefinite continuation of exr Note incidentally his use of the term "continuaistence."
tion," which, as will be recalled, like the terms

"permanence"
in

and "perseverance,"
definition of duration.

is

used by the scholastics

their

In the explanation to this definition in the Ethics Spinoza, it seems to me, is trying to bring out the double meaning of the term "indefinite" as corresponding to the two characteristics of duration. In so far as duration applies to existence which is not necessary by its own

nature, Spinoza says, "I call it indefinite because it cannot be determined by the nature itself of the existing thing." In so far as duration is unlimited and unmeasured and is, as

we have
definite

seen above, "the whole existence of a thing" and not merely a portion of it, Spinoza says that he calls it in-

"because

it

cannot be determined ... by the

effi-

which necessarily posits the existence of the thing but does not take it away." By the "efficient cause" he
cient cause,

means here God, who


cause of
lect."
3

all

The

" described by him as the efficient things which can fall under the infinite intelimplication of the statement here that if durais

tion were not indefinite


(tollit)

God would have

been taking away

statement

the existence of the thing can be explained by the in the Cogitata Metaphysica that "however much

of duration you take away (detrahis), so do you take away from it."
*
1

much

of

its

existence

Ethics, II, Def. 5.

Ethics,

I,

Prop. 16, Corol.

i.

Cogitata Metaphysica,

I, 4.

358

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


it is

[ETHICS,

Time, as we have seen, does not

differ essentially

from

duration; only a limited portion of duration. Spinoza thus sometimes speaks of duration as "indefinite time"

(tempus

indefinitutri),

and contrasts
1

it

with "finite time"

(tempus finitum), "limited time" (tempus limitatum) y and

And, vice versa, he (tempus definitum). " of time as "determinate duration (duratio speaks also determinata)? It is for this reason that Spinoza sometimes
"definite time"
3 speaks of "duration or time" as if the two terms meant to him the same thing. In this indeed Spinoza is really reverting to Plotinus' use of the term time and also to those

Jewish philosophers who used the term time for that motionfree time which, as we have been trying to show, is known
in scholasticism

under the name of duration.


III.

ETERNITY
its

The term

eternity started on

career in the history of

philosophy with two meanings. Like the twofold meanings with which so many of our other philosophic terms have
be designated Briefly stated, the difference between these two meanings is as follows. To Plato eternity is the antithesis of time and it means the exclusion
started
their historical

careers,

they

may

the Platonic and the Aristotelian.

of any kind of temporal relations. To Aristotle eternity is only endless time. The question before us is, how did it happen that eternity, which prior to Plato, for all we know, had

meant simply endless


exclusion of time?

time,

came

to

mean with Plato

the

to this question seems to be that the term has acquired its new meaning in Plato from the eternity nature of the eternal beings to which it was exclusively ap1

The answer

Ethics, III, Prop. 8 Ethics,


I,

and Dcmonst.

"

Ethics,

I,

Prop. 21, Demonst.

Def.

8.

DEF. 8]

DURATION, TIME, AND ETERNITY

359

plied by him.

Beginning as an adjective of those eternal beings, designating only one of their characteristics, namely,
that of ceaseless existence,
it

came

to be used, as

it

so often

happens with terms, as a surrogate for those beings. Those "eternal beings" became simply "the eternals" by the same
process that "port wine' became simply "port." The adjective eternal thus became with Plato a substantive, the eternals. In this capacity of a substantive, the term eternal
1

was used by Plato not only


ence but as inclusive of
all

in the sense of ceaseless exist-

the other properties which characterized those beings for which the term eternal substituted. The new and enlarged concept formed out of the term etercharacteristics

became in fact a sort of epitome of all the which the ceaseless existing beings were by In other differentiated from the other kinds of beings.
nity as a surrogate

words,

it

tween

his

epitomized to Plato all the essential differences beworld of ideas and his world of sense.
all

This process of investing the term eternity with

the

connotations of the eternal beings to which it happened to be exclusively applied went on, as we shall try to show, throughout the history of philosophy, and it is the tracing of
this process that constitutes the history of the term.

To

Plato the differences between the world of ideas and

the world of sense

may

be

summed

up, for our present pur-

pose, under two headings. In the first place, the world of ideas is beginningless, whereas the world of sense had a be-

ginning in an act of creation. In the second place, the world of ideas is immovable, immutable, and indivisible, whereas

The

subject to motion, change, and division. ideas, therefore, which alone in the opinion of Plato were eternal in the original sense of beginningless became the the world of sense
is

Eternals, and the term eternity, because of its exclusive application to the ideas, came to include in its meaning all the

360

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


in

[ETHICS,

other characteristics of the ideas.

stand

Eternity thus came to Plato for permanence, unity, immutability, identity, and indivisibility. It was no longer infinite time, but rather

freedom from any sort of temporal relations, for time to Plato, as later to Aristotle, was connected with motion. The
relation of time to eternity was conceived by him as that of the world of sense to the world of ideas. Time was thus

described by him as the moving image of eternity. To Aristotle, however, there was more than one kind of
1

beginningless being. The universe as a whole, the celestial spheres, motion, the immaterial Intelligences, and the Im-

movable Mover were all eternal beginning and no end. Eternity,

in the sense of

having no

therefore,

had with him as

many meanings
plied.

as the

number of beings
to

When

applied

to which it was apthe universe or to the movable

meant nothing but infinite time, and this was inseparable from motion. For while indeed, argues Aristotle, the object which has infinite motion cannot truly
spheres, eternity

be described as being in time, which in the strict technical sense of the term means to be comprehended by time and

transcended by
time in the

it,

it

is

still

less technical

described by him as being in sense of being with time, that is to

2 say, of being when time is. When, however, eternity is applied to immovable beings, as God or the Intelligence, it of necessity means a negation of temporal relation, for there

can be no time when there

is

no motion.

While Aristotle

himself does not say anything on this subject beyond the statements that the universe, circular motion, the spheres,

and God are

all

eternal, this inference

is

certainly to be

derived from his statements.'


s,
*

37 D.

Physics, IV, 12, 22ia, 9-11.

Crejcas' Critique of Aristotle , pp. 287, 646, n. 21. Cf. also Aristotle's discussion of the meaning of a.i&v in Df Caelo, I, 9, 2793, 22-33.

Cf.

my

DBF. 8]

DURATION, TIME, AND ETERNITY


Plotinus as to Aristotle there
is

361

To

more than one kind of

being which has a beginningless existence, for the process of emanation is continuous and therefore the sphere is as
eternal, in the sense of having no beginning, as the universal soul, as the intelligible world, as the Intelligence, and as the

One

Aristotle he does not apply the term eternity to all of these types of being. Rather like Plato he applies it exclusively to what in his system corres-

or God.

But unlike

to the world of ideas in the system of Plato, to the intelligible world, to the Intelligence and the One. Eternity

ponds

according to him
Intelligence.
ity,

is

identical with

God.

It

is

the

life

of the

It

is

"life consisting in rest, identity,


2

uniform-

The universal soul, however, has no but time, or, as we have preferred to call it, indefieternity nite time or duration, whereas the sphere and everything that is moved with it and through it has definite time. Though
and
infinity/*

time

is

endless to Plotinus,
is

still it is

not eternity, for eternity,

as in Plato,
is

essentially of a different nature than time and an exclusion of any kind of temporal relation.

Among
soul

Jewish and Arabic philosophers, the Aristotelian


Intelligences as well as the Plotinian universal
Intelligences, the

and Plotinian

became the

number of which were

determined by the number of the celestial spheres and which were identified with the angels of the Bible and functioned
as the cause of the motion of the celestial spheres. 3 But with their rejection of the Plotinian emanation and their

acceptance in

its

place of the theory of creation,

God

be-

came the only being who had endless existence and thereby He also became the exclusive possessor of the attribute of eternity. Eternity could then have been used by them as a
1

Enneads,

III, vii,

4 (cd. Creuzer ct Moser, Paris, 1855).


11.

-'

Ibid., 10 (p. 177,

34-35).

Cf. above, p. 218.

362

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

surrogate to God and as an epitome of all His attributes. Still the problem of creation was for them a vital subject of
discussion and in the course of that discussion they had to deal with Aristotle's theory of the eternity of the world and

its

of motion, and this called for the use of the term eternal in Aristotelian sense of infinite time. Thus the term eternity

had

to be used

by them both with reference

to

God and

with

reference to other beings which were supposed by Aristotle to be of endless existence. The result was that the term
eternity

had

for

and the
this

Aristotelian.

them two meanings, again the Platonic On the one hand, it meant the excluit

sion of time; on the other,

meant

infinite time.

Owing

to

double meaning of the term, Jewish philosophers always

God

took great pains to explain that when eternity is applied to it does not mean infinite time but rather freedom from

temporal relations.

We may illustrate this generalization by a brief analysis of the discussion of the attribute of eternity which occurs in the writings of some of the leading Jewish philosophers. It usually takes the form of an explanation of the terms
"first"

and "last," the use of which

is

the Biblical

way

of

1 expressing the eternity of God, that is to say, eternity a pane ante and a parte post. In their explanation of these Biblical terms, Jewish philosophers endeavor to emphasize that these

two terms should not be taken literally to mean beginningless and endless time but should be taken rather as implying
God's exclusion from any kind of temporal relation. Both Bahya and Maimonides insist upon this point and
suggest that the term "first" should be taken as a negation either of God's having anything prior to Him, as Bahya
2

expresses himself,
1

or of His having been created, as Maia

Cf. Isaiah 44, 6.

Robot ha-Lcbabot,

I, 6.

DEF. 8]

DURATION, TIME, AND ETERNITY


1

363

it. Similarly, Judah ha-Levi speaks of God as transcending all relations of time and explains the terms " " and "last" not as affirmations of literal priority and first

monides puts

posteriority but rather as negations of God's having been 2 preceded by anything and of His ever coming to an end.

most interesting passage

for

our purpose
is

is

that of Abra-

ham Ibn Daud where


the attribute 'eternal/

eternity

directly identified with

immovability and immutability.

"When we

ascribe to

we only mean thereby

that

God He was

immovable, that He is immovable, and that He will be immovable. You already know that by motion we mean change from one state to another." 3 Crescas, though on account of
his defining time as duration

no objection
4 tion, follows

to the use of divine attributes

independent of motion he has which imply dura-

Maimonides

in interpreting the
s

term "first"

in

the sense of being "uncreated."

The most

interesting passage for our purpose, however,

is

that of Albo.

"First" and "last," he says, mean absolute

6 independence of any temporal relations. Albo, as we have already seen, distinguishes between two kinds of time: one,

absolute time or duration, which


definite

is infinite,

and the other,

is finite. Eternity as applied to God, 7 according to him, excludes duration as well as definite time. The reason given by him why God alone of all beings is de-

time, which

scribed as eternal

is

that

God

alone of

sary existence by virtue of His own beings have only possible existence by their
1

beings has necesnature, whereas all other


all

own

nature. 8

March Nebukim,

I, 57.

Cuzari, II,

1.

Emunah Ramah,

II,

iii

(pp. 54-55).

Or Adonai^ I, iii, 3 (p. 236). Cf. my "Crescas on the Problem of Divine Attributes" in the Jewish Quarterly Review^ New Series, VII (1916), pp. 181-182. 5 Or Adonai, I, iii, 3 (p. 24b). Cf. my "Crescas on the Problem of Divine Attributes," p. 207, n.
'

in.

6
8

'/0rfV0,
Ibid.

II, 18.

Ibid.

364

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


to

[ETHICS,

Or

put
1

it

in other words, eternity


in

cording to Albo, because


identical.

God

applied to God, acessence and existence are


is

by Albo as idenand immutability, 2 terms which remind us tity, uniformity, of those used by Plotinus as well as Plato in his characterizaEternity
is,

therefore, defined

tion of eternity.

The
per
se y

use of eternity as a description of necessary existence i.e., of the identity of essence and existence, may be

also found in Altabrizi. which he adduces there

Among
is

one which reads that

the four definitions of time "

time exists

in itself, is neither a body nor anything belonging to a body, but is something which has necessary existence by virtue of
I have suggested elsewhere that the last statement was taken from the Plotinian definition of eternity and was

itself."

4 misapplied by Altabrizi to time. In exactly the same sense is the term eternity used in mediaeval Latin philosophic texts. It is applied exclusively

to

God and

it is

relations.

If other beings are

defined as the exclusion from any temporal assumed to have an endless

existence, they are not described as eternal but by some other term. If the same term eternal is applied also to other

beings, then the term when applied to God is said to have a special meaning. In either way, eternal as applied to God means more than the mere negation of beginning and end.

means immovability and necessity of existence. contrast between eternity and time as that between permanence and motion is suggested by Augustine when he speaks of eternity as the "ever-fixed" (semper stantis) and of time as the "never-fixed" (numquam stantis] s or when he says that "time does not exist without some kind of
It

The

Ibid.

ibid.

Altabrizi,

Commentary on Maimonides* Twenty-five


n.

Propositions, Prop. 15.

Cf.
5

my

Crescas' Critique of Aristotle , p. 662, n. 29.

Confessions y XI,

DEF. 8]

DURATION, TIME, AND ETERNITY


*

365

change caused by motion, while in eternity there is no Boethius expresses the distinction between eterchange."
nity and infinite time in the following statement: "Philosophers say that ever (semper) may be applied to the life of the heavens and other immortal bodies. But as applied to God
it

has a different meaning/' 2 Though the world, according to Aristotle, "never began nor were ever to end, and its

did endure with infinite time, yet it is not such that it 3 In order not to confuse eternity ought to be called eternal/'
life

with

infinite

time he suggests two different terms for them.

if we will give things their right names, followPlato, let us say that God is eternal and the world ing

"Wherefore,

perpetual."

of Augustine and Boethius are re-echoed throughout the history of mediaeval philosophic writers. Eternity and time are considered to be of essentially different
natures,

The views

and

in

order to take care of the duration of beings

which can be described by neither eternity nor time, the term aevum is generally used. A list of scholastic views on
5 But for our present purpose eternity is given by Suarez. Suarez' own view on eternity is of significance, for, like Albo, he identifies it with necessary existence per se. He argues

that eternity is not only a negation of God's having been created, or of His having a beginning and end, or of His

being subject to motion and change, but that it has a positive meaning in so far as it expresses the necessity of the existence

of

God by His own


existence.
6
1

essence,

i.e.,

the identity of His essence

and

DC De

Civitatc Dei,

XI,

6.

3 *

Stewart and Rand, pp. 20-21. Consolatio Philosophiae, V, 6, ed. Stewart and Rand, pp. 400-401.
frinitatey IV, ed.
Ibid., pp.

402-403.

5 6

Disputationes Metaphysicac, Disp. L, Sec. III.


Ibid., Disp. L, Sec. Ill, x.

366

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


similar definition also occurs in

[ETHICS,

cabalistic

work

Puerto, del Cielo.

Abraham Herrera's The author quotes Plato,

Plotinus, Boethius,

Torquato Tasso, and Ficino on the mean-

ing of eternity. He himself defines it as his contemporary Suarez and as Albo do, as meaning existence which is neces-

sary by

its

own

ence, for, as he says, 1 per se is eternal/'

nature, or the identity of essence and exist" every essence that is necessary and

Whatever sources Spinoza had consulted about eternity he must have received the following general impression. Eternity as applied to God does not mean merely endless time. It is used as an epitome of the main distinguishing characterdifferentiated from other beings. These distinguishing characteristics are summed up under two headings, both going back to Aristotle. First, God is
istics
is

by which God

immovable, whereas everything


eternity
is

else is

movable, and hence

said to

mean immovability, immutability,


and
all

manence,
with
it.

indivisibility,

Second,

God

perthe other negations that go has necessary existence, whereas other

beings have only possible existence. Accordingly eternity is also said to mean, as in Albo, Suarez, and Herrera, the necessary existence of God or, which is the same thing, the
identity of essence

and existence

in

Him.

Following these

traditional views on eternity, Spinoza gives his tion of the term.

own

defini-

begin with, eternity is not merely beginningless and endless time or duration. "It cannot therefore be explained

To

by duration and time, even

if

duration be conceived without

2 Indeed, in common speech, we speak beginning or end/' of the eternity of the world when we mean its eternal dura-

tion in time, but this


1

is

an erroneous use of the term.

It is

Sha'ar ha-Shamayim y III, 4.


Ethics, I, Def. 8, Expl.

DEF. 8]

DURATION, TIME, AND ETERNITY

367

only because of a defective terminology that "we say that the world has existed from eternity." * As we have seen,

Boethius has already tried to remedy this defect by introducing the use of the term perpetual. An equally defective use of the term eternity, says Spinoza, is when it is used with
reference to things which do not exist, as the essence of things is eternal, although

when we say "that we do not think of

the things as ever existing." 2 The reference in this passage is undoubtedly to the use of the term eternal with reference
to the axiomatic truths

which

exist only as concepts of the

mind, as, for instance, in the expression "eternal truths" used by Descartes. The particular Cartesian passage which
in mind is probably the following: "When we that it is impossible that anything can be formed apprehend of nothing, the proposition ex nihilo nihilfit is not to be con-

Spinoza had

sidered as an existing thing, or the mode of a thing, but as a certain eternal truth which has its seat in our mind, and is
a

common
Thus

notion or axiom."

eternity, like duration

and time,
call

which

exist, or, as

Spinoza would

refers only to things them, real beings. But

inasmuch as
into those

real beings are divided, according to Spinoza,

"whose essence involves existence," i.e., God or Substance, and those "whose essence involves only a possible existence,"
first
4

kind of real being.

eternity, says Spinoza, applies only to the Accordingly Spinoza reverts to a

definition of eternity the like of

which we have found


in Spinoza's

in

Albo, Suarez, and Herrera.

Now,

terminology

the expression essence involving existence has the same meaninfinite in the ing as causa sui or being causeless or infinite
sense of undetermined

by a
2
5

cause. 5

Hence Spinoza

defines

eternity as an "attribute under which


1

we conceive

the inI,

Cogitata Mctaphysica, II, Cogitata Mctaphysica,

I.

Ibid.

Principia Philosophiae,

49.

I, i.

Cf. above, pp. 127, 138.

368

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


of God."
'

CETHICS,
in

finite existence

"

Infinite

"
is

used here

the

sense of causeless, in contrast to "created," which, as


seen,
is

we have

of "caused/*
eternity
is

used by him in his definition of duration in the sense 2 Similarly in a letter to Meyer he says that
the only term which explains the existence of it means "the infinite enjoyment of

substance, and hence


existence, or (in
finite existence

awkward Latin) essendi." Here, too, by inhe means existence undetermined by a cause.
3

The
flects

expression existendi or essendi Jruitio undoubtedly rethe expression plentitudo essendi which is used by
in his definition of eternity.
*

Suarez
is

also to be

found

in his

implication formal definition of eternity in the

The same

Ethics, which reads as follows: "By eternity I understand existence itself (ipsarn existentiarri), so far as it is conceived necessarily to follow from the definition alone of the eternal
5 I take the ipsam in ipsam existentiam not only as thing." a reflexive and emphatic pronoun but in the sense of existen-

tiam per se or per essentiam, the equivalent of the expression ipsius esse per essentiam which occurs in Suarez' definition
of eternity. 6 The existence of
plies differs

God

to

which alone, then, eternity apall


it is

from the existence of

to Spinoza, not only in that

other beings, according identical with His essence


in a different

but also in that

it is

known and demonstrated

manner from that of


are three

the existence of other beings. the


2

There

ways

in

which the existence of a thing

may

be

known,
1

according to Spinoza:
I, 4.

way

of perception, the

Cf. above, p. 351. Cogitata Metaphysica, Epistola 12: "hoc est, infinitam existendi, sive, invita latinitate, essendi

fruitionem."
< Suarez, Disputationes Mctaphysicae y Disp. L, Sec. Ill, x: "Estenim aeternitas duratio ipsius esse per essentiam: unde sicut ille esse est ipsa plentitudo essendi,

ita aeternitas est (ut ita


s

dicam) ipsa plentitudo durandi."

Ethics, I, Def. 8.

Cf. quotation in note 4 above.

DEF. 8]

DURATION, TIME, AND ETERNITY

369

his well-known way of reason, and the way of intuition in the case of all other three stages of knowledge. Now,

beings, their existence is known by the first two kinds of knowledge, either by direct perception or by indirect proof

a posteriori.

The

existence of eternal truths, the axioms and

common
eternity

notions, are perceived directly as intuitions, or


call

what

Descartes would
I

" Spinoza thus says: By understand existence itself, so far as it is conceived

innate ideas.

necessarily to follow from the definition alone of the eternal thing, for such existence, like the essence of the thing, is

conceived as an eternal truth."


eternal truths
is

The comparison with


is

meant
is

to bring out the fact that the exist-

ence of

God which

identical with His essence

known

as the essence of the eternal truths.

But there

intuitively is a

difference between the eternal

God and

the eternal truths.

In the eternal

God

there are both essence and existence,


identical.

though the two are

In the eternal truths there

is

3 only essence; there is no existence in them. In Albo's discussion of the eternity of God, we have seen, not only time but also duration is excluded as an admissible

In scholastic philosophy, however, the admissibility of duration as a fitting attribute of God was a mooted point. Suarez quotes Aureolus as being opposed to
the attribution of duration to God.

attribute of God.

He

himself

is

in

favor

Spinoza likewise raises the question in Cogitata Metaphysica^ II, I, and like Albo and Aureolus he denies the appliof
it.
4

God. The passage in which the discussion is contained, however, seems to refer to certain definite texts which at the present writing I am unable to
cability of duration to
identify.
'

Cf. below, Vol. II, pp. 155

'

ff.

Ethics,

I,

Def.

8,

and Expl.

Cf. above, p. 367, notes 1 and 3. Suarez, op. cit. t Disp. L, Sec. Ill, n.

CHAPTER XI
MODES

XIX to XXXVI, despite their external apof disjointedness and incongruity, have in reality, pearance like all the other groups of propositions we have already treated, a logical order of sequence. They fall into six groups, dealing with the following topics: I. Eternity of God (Props.
PROPOSITIONS

XIX-XX).
XXIII).

II.

III.

and Eternal Modes (Props. XXIThe Nature of Modes in General (Props.


Infinite

XXIV-XXVII). IV. Finite Modes (Props. XXVIIIXXIX). V. Intellect, Will, and Power (Props. XXXXXXV). VI. Purposelessness (Prop. XXXVI and AppenAll these six topics may be subsumed under one dix).
general topic which, like that of the preceding group of propositions (Props. XV- XVIII), is the causality of God,

XXXVI

Propositions XIX-XXIX dealing with the effects of God's causality, that is to say, modes, and Propositions and Appendix dealing with the necessary and pur-

XXX-

poseless nature of God's causality. Furthermore, not only are the propositions under each of these topics logically coherent in themselves, but there is also a logical transition

from one topic to another.

The subject of Propositions XIX-XXIX is the description of the modal system of the universe. Having already dealt with the nature of God and His attributes, His existence and
His causality, Spinoza now undertakes to present a complete and systematic view of his conception of the modes. If we

may

use here Spinoza's own expressions which we have already discussed previously but which in the Ethics are not

PROPS. 19-29]

MODES
may

371

introduced by Spinoza until later in the course of the propositions

under consideration, we

say that the Ethics so


it

far has dealt with natura naturans\

from now on

will deal

with natura naturata.

In our chapter on Extension and

Thought we have already discussed quite fully Spinoza's system of modes as they are treated by him in his writings outside the Ethics. That chapter may serve us now as a general introduction to the subject. In this chapter we shall draw upon it only in so far as it will be necessary for us to explain the order and the meaning of the propositions before us, but we shall give fuller consideration to those phases
of the problem which appear for the
propositions. To describe the
first

time

in

these

simpler language, the world as it is seen, perceived, and thought of by us, the most natural method for Spinoza would have

modal system of the universe

or, in

been to start with that which we ordinarily think of as directly

known

to us, namely, individual things,

and work up gradu-

ally to that

indirectly.

which we ordinarily think of as known to us only He could have done so without the sacrifice of

the use of his

own

terminology.

He

could have started with

an enumeration and classification of individual things or finite modes and then reduced them to two classes, extended
things and thinking things. He could have then considered the totality of these individual things as constituting the infinite physical universe and called it by his own expression " " the face of the whole universe and described it in his own

way

as a mediate infinite

and eternal mode. He could have

then explained the behavior of the finite modes within the totality of the universe on the basis of two principles, motion-

and understanding, on the other, and described these again in his own way as immediate infinite and eternal modes. Then he could have gone further

and-rest, on the one hand,

372

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

and shown how these two activities are the expressions of two aspects of a single self-subsistent whole transcending the
aggregate totality of the individual modes and called that transcendent whole substance and the two aspects, of which

and understanding are expressions, the To have done so attributes of extension and thought. would have followed the a posteriori method used by Spinoza
motion-and-rest
adherents in the Middle Ages. But Spinoza considered himself bound by the self-imposed a Substance is priori reasoning of his geometrical method.
Aristotle

and by

his

more immediately known

to us, according to him, than the

individual things, and the source of knowledge by which it From the definition of is known to us is the most reliable.

substance the nature of the entire universe follows by necessity as the properties of a triangle follow from the definition
of a triangle. Spinoza, therefore, preferred to start with substance or God and to work gradually downward to individual things. Spinoza is reported to have remarked to Tschirnhaus that while most philosophers begin with creal a remark which, it must be said, tures he began with God describes only his method of exposition but not necessarily

manner in which he has arrived at his scheme. But departing though he did from most philosophers, Spinoza was not altogether without a model.
the

His model
as a

is

emanation with

its initial

the theory of emanation. This theory of monism is not only taken by him

model
is

for his

own system

in preference to the

dualism

which

co-existence of the universe with God, but, as

implied in the Aristotelian theory of the eternal we have seen


it is

on several occasions,
1

also used

by him

as the

main

target

Gerhardt, "Leibniz und Spinoza," in Sitzungsberic hte der koniglich prcussischcn Akademie der Wissemchajten zu Berlin, 1889, p. 1077. Cf. below, See K.
I.

Vol. II, p. 4.

PROPS. 19-29]

MODES
There

373

of his criticism.

are, of course, fundamental differ-

which

ences between the prototype and the copy, chief among is the nature of God, which is pure thought according

to the emanationists but

according to Spinoza.

both thought and extension Barring this fundamental difference


is

between them, the respective schemes in both systems are parallel to each other. There is God as the starting point of
both systems. The two immediate
in Spinoza,

and eternal modes namely, the absolutely infinite intellect and motion-and-rest, correspond respectively to the Intelligences and
infinite

the circular motion of the spheres in emanation. Spinoza's "face of the whole universe" corresponds to the outermost celestial sphere which encloses the totality of the physical

universe according to the emanationists, with the difference that the former was considered as infinite whereas the latter

was considered

as finite.

And

then, within the universes of

both these systems there are individual things. Another important element of emanation retained by Spinoza is its terminology. When choosing his terms carehe always speaks of things as following (sequi) from the nature of God or from His attributes. This reflects the terms
fully,
1

"proceeding" generally used

and "following by necessity"


in

which are
uses

Hebrew

philosophic literature in connec-

tion with the process of emanation.

Even when he
3

some

other term, such as that

God "acts"

(agit)

or "to be pro-

duced" (product) by God, 4 it is to be understood in the sense that it follows by necessity from the nature of God. The term cause which Spinoza applies to God is likewise to be understood in the logical and geometrical sense, that is to
1

N2T.

Cf.

Emunah Ramah,
Cf.

II, iv, 3.
II, 22.

3"nrV, fjL.
Ethics,
I,

March Nebukim,

Prop. 17; IV, Praef.

Ibid., I, Prop. 28, Schol.

374

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETJHCS,

say, in the sense in

which the premise of a syllogism is said to be the cause of its conclusion and the definition of a triangle is said to be the cause of its properties. The term
1

"cause" (causa)
"reason*
(ratio),

to Spinoza means the same as the term which two terms are sometimes connected
I

by him by the co-ordinating conjunction "or/' so that the causality he affirms of God is not meant to be understood as
2 In this respect, indeed, his implying temporal sequence. of God's causality corresponds exactly to that conception of the emanationists as it is characterized by Maimonides

in the following passage:

"It

is

clear that

when

Aristotle

says that the first Intelligence necessarily follows from God, that the second necessarily follows from the first, and the
third from the second

was

first in

existence

a necessary result.

... he does not mean that one thing it came the second as ... By the expression 'it necessarily
and then out of

follows' he merely refers to the causal relation; he

means

to

say that the first Intelligence is the cause of the existence of the second, the second of the third, and so on .; but none of these things preceded another, or has been in exist. .

ence, according to him, without the existence of that other.

one should say, for example, that from the primary qualities there follow by necessity roughness, smoothness, hardness, softness, porosity, and solidity, in which case no
It
is

as

if

person would doubt that though ... the secondary qualities follow necessarily from the four primary qualities, it is
impossible that there should exist a body which, having the primary qualities, should be denuded of the secondary ones." 3

The same
1

idea,

it

may

be added,

is

reflected in Spinoza's use


1.

Ibid., I, Prop,

n, Demonst.
26).

2 (Opera, II, p. 52,

31 et pass.};
n.

IV, Praef.

(Opera, II, p. 206,


a
3

1.

Cf. Joachim,

Study of the Ethics of Spinoza, p. 54,


II, 21.

Moreh Nebukim,

PROPS. 19-29]

MODES
l

375
2

of the expression prior in nature he applies to God.

or prior in causality
his

which

But whatever the

differences

between

God and

the

God

of tradition, Spinoza seems to say at the beginning of this new chapter in the Ethics that his God does not differ from
the traditional God in the matter of eternity. "God is eternal," or, since God's attributes are nothing but certain 3 aspects of His essence, "all His attributes are eternal/'

Now,

meant three

eternity in the history of philosophy, as we have shown, things. In the first place, it meant necessary

existence per se y or the identity of essence and existence. In the second place, it meant immutability. Then, in the third
place, it meant, at least in Spinoza's assertions that the eternal existence of God is an eternal truth, to be immediately

known as an intuition. 4 In the first two propositions of this new chapter in the Ethics, therefore, Spinoza reiterates these
it

three implications of the term eternity. In the first place, means necessary existence per se y or the identity of essence

and

existence,

"for

God

is

substance, which necessarily


it

exists, that is to

say a substance to whose nature

pertains

and furthermore, "the existence of God and His essence are one and the same thing." 6 In the second place, eternity means immutability, hence "it follows that God is immutable, or (which is the same thing) all His attributes
to exist,"
5

are immutable."

In the third place, the eternal existence


it is

of God
ately

may

be called an eternal truth in so far as


as an intuition, for
is
8

immedilike

known

"the existence of God,


It
is

His essence,
1

an eternal truth."
i.

in this respect only,

Ethics,
2

I,

Prop.

Cf. above, p. 77.

*
s

Ibid., I, Prop. 17, Schol. (Opera, II, p. 63, 1. 7): "prior causalitate." Cf. above, p. 369. Ibid., I, Prop. 19.

Ethics,

I,

Ibid., I,
8

Prop. 19, Demonst. Prop. 20.

Ibid., Corel. 2.
I.

Ibid., I, Prop. 19, Schol.;

Prop. 20, Corol.

376

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


in respect

[ETHICS,

and not

of lack of reality, that Spinoza calls the


eternal truth.
l

existence of

God an

Again, preserving the vocabulary of emanation, Spinoza speaks of his modes as things which follow from God. But

inasmuch as unlike the emanationists Spinoza does not take to be pure thought but rather as possessing an infinite number of attributes of which the two known ones are

God

thought and extension, he does not speak of a single mode following from God but rather of various modes following respectively from the various attributes. Still like the emanationists

he

must be
istics

insists that each mode following from an attribute similar to the attribute from which it follows in

certain essential characteristics.

These

essential characterinfinite.

he sums up

in

two terms, eternal and

By

the

term eternal

in its application to

modes, however, he does not

eternity in all the three senses which it has in its application to God. For one thing, it cannot mean necessary existence per se or the identity of essence and existence, for the

mean

existence per se and their existence For another thing, it is not identical with their essence. cannot mean the immediate perception of the modes as an
eternal truth, for they are known only through their cause. " " Eternal in this case means only to be immutable, or to exist
forever, as Spinoza directly expresses himself in Proposition

modes have no necessary

XXI,
tion

or to have indeterminate existence or duration, as he

Demonstration of Proposiwhere he describes the opposite of it to have "determinate existence or duration/' Similarly by the term infinite which he applies to this mode he does not mean inindirectly expresses himself in the

XXI

finity in the sense

as their cause.
perfect, the
1

"Infinite" in this case

of causelessness, for the modes have God means to be the most


its

most complete and the greatest of

kind, that

Cf. above, pp. 367, 369.

PROPS. 19-29]
is

MODES

377

to say, that which cannot be limited by another thing of the same nature, or what Spinoza elsewhere describes as the

"infinite in its

own

kind."

That

this is

what Spinoza means

by the term infinite as applied to modes may be gathered from the first part of the Demonstration of Proposition XXI. It is in the light of these remarks, therefore, that we may
full meaning of Proposition XXI: "All which follow from the absolute nature of any attribute things of God must forever exist, and must be in finite that is to

understand the

say, through that


finite."

same attribute they are What he means to say is this: They

eternal

and

in-

are eternal only

in the sense of existing forever or of

being immutable, and

they are also infinite only in the sense of being unlimited by another thing of the same attribute.

by eternal and infinite when immediate modes Spinoza does not mean the same as when these terms are applied to God, he could just as well have said in Proposition XXI that all things which
It
is

true, of course, that since

applied to the

follow from

cannot be eternal and

the absolute nature of any attribute of God infinite. But he chose to phrase his

proposition in positive terms evidently because he wanted to emphasize the ever-existence and the infinite perfection of
these immediate modes, for
it is

in these respects that

he

will

want

later to differentiate

them from individual things or finite

modes. Another plausible reason for his choosing to phrase the proposition in positive terms is that by affirming that the modes

who contended
possible, for,

are infinite in perfection he indirectly hit at the mediaevals " that the existence of an infinite effect is im-

were

it

to exist,

it

would be

like its cause."

The Demonstration of Proposition XXI follows Spinoza's favorite method of demonstration by proving the impossibil1

Ibid., I, Def. 6, Expl.

Cf. above, p. 136.


12.

Abraham Herrera, Sha'ar ha-Shamayim> V,

378

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


namely, the impossibility
\sfinite

[ETHICS,

ity of the opposite/

"

that in

some

attribute of

God something which

and has a determi-

nate existence or duration follows from the absolute nature

of that attribute/* For the purpose of his discussion he takes up the mode of the attribute of thought, which he designates
(idea Dei) but by which he means the same as by what he describes elsewhere 2 and asks the reader as the "absolutely infinite intellect,"

here by the

name

of the "idea of

God"

to observe that the

same reasoning

is

true of the other im-

mediate modes, such, for instance, as motion-and-rest in the


attribute of extension.
stration
to the
is

constructed. It

But note how carefully this demonfalls into two parts, corresponding
in the proposition,

two terms used


In the

namely,

infinite

and

eternal.

first

part he
finite.

tries to

show that the im-

mediate modes cannot be

In the second part he tries to show that they cannot have a "determinate duration."

The immediate modes which in Proposition XXI Spinoza has shown to be eternal and infinite are designated by him n Proposition XXII as the modification (modificatio} by
which attributes are modified, and he tries to show also that the mediate mode, which he elsewhere designates by the

name

of the "face of the whole universe,"

must

likewise

of course, in as we have seen, he uses these terms with reference to which, modes. But instead of the term eternal which we should
infinite, in the particular sense,

be eternal and

expect here he uses

the expression to exist necessarily (necessario existere), by which, however, he means the same thing. Evidence that by the expression to exist necessarily

now

he means the same as by the term eternal preceding proposition may be found in the following passage in the demonstration of the next proposition: "If
in this proposition
in the
1 *

Cf. above, pp. 97, 183. Cf. above, p. 344.

Cf. above, pp. 238

ff.

PROPS. 19-29]

MODES

379

a mode, therefore, be conceived to exist necessarily and to be infinite, its necessary existence and infinitude must be con-

God or perceived through it, conceived to express infinitude and necessity of existence, that is to say, eternity." x In the light of these " Whatever remarks, we may now read Proposition XXII:
cluded from some attribute of
is

in so far as it

follows from

any attribute of God,


infinitely,

in so far as it is

modified

by

a modification which through the

same

attribute exists

necessarily

and

must

also exist necessarily

and

infinitely." What he means to say is this: The modes which follow from the immediate modes must be eternal and in-

immediate modes themselves. Thus there are two kinds of eternal and infinite modes, namely, immediate and mediate. In our discussion of the preceding two propositions, for the sake of clearness and in view of the fact that we have
finite like the

already given a complete discussion of the subject in a previous chapter, we have used the terms immediate modes and mediate modes. Spinoza himself, however, has so far used
neither of these terms.

In fact, in none of the propositions

proper of the Ethics has he so far used the term mode. He has always spoken generally of things following from God or from the nature of any of God's attributes, though the term
affection (ajfectio) in the sense of
in a proposition.
2

To

introduce the term

mode has been used by him mode and to distin-

guish among modes which are infinite and eternal between those which are immediate and those which are mediate is the

purpose of Proposition XXIII. In this proposition, dealing again with the infinite and eternal modes and using again the

term "to exist necessarily" for "eternal," he introduces for the first time the term "mode": "Every mode which exists
1

Ethics,
a

I,

Prop. 23, Demonst.

Ibid., I, Prop, i; cf. Prop. 4,

Demonst,

380
necessarily

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


and
infinitely

[ETHICS,

must necessarily follow either from the absolute nature of some attribute of God, or from some attribute modified by a modification which exists necessarily and infinitely/' which the Demonstration explains to mean "either immediately or mediately" and refers in connection with the former to Proposition XXI and in connection with the latter to Proposition XXII. These two
references

make

it

clear that Proposition

XXI

deals with

immediate

XXII

and eternal modes whereas Proposition deals with mediate infinite and eternal modes.
infinite in these three propositions

Thus

we have an

outline of

Spinoza's theory of infinite and eternal modes and of their classification into immediate and mediate. But the names of
these

modes

name

are not given by him. He mentions here the of only one of these immediate infinite and eternal
this, too,

modes, and
in thought.

only indirectly, namely, the idea of God

Another name
as well as
all

eternal

mode

and eternal modes is seen, in one of his letters.

immediate infinite and names of the other infinite supplied by Spinoza, as we have already
for this

the

In our statement that the term eternal

modes does not mean the same

as the term eternal

when applied to when ap-

plied to God, especially in so far as in the later case the term means the necessary existence per se or the identity of es-

sence

and

existence,
It
is

we have anticipated Propositions

XXIV-XXVII.

evidently because in the preceding has given no hint of this changed meanpropositions Spinoza ing of the term except only, as we have suggested, indirectly

when he speaks

in Proposition

XXI

of existing forever as

an alternative of eternal, or when he speaks in the Demonstration of the same proposition of "determinate existence
or duration" as the opposite of eternity, that he
1

now

feels

Cf. above, p. 216.

Cf. pp. 238, 242, 244.

PROPS. 19-29]

MODES

381

that an explanation of the term eternal as applied to modes is due. And so immediately after he has completed his outline of his theory of the infinite and eternal modes he proceeds to say that these modes, though called eternal, have no necessity at all of their own nature but that in every-

thing they are and in everything they do they are to be considered as having been determined by God as their cause.
the causality of God, it may be recalled, has been described by Spinoza by seven characteristic terms, among which he mentions the following three, namely, that God

Now,

is

(i)

an

efficient cause, (2)

free cause. 1

spects the
tions

an immanent cause, and (3) a As distinguished from God in these three remodes are now shown by Spinoza in Proposi-

XXIV, XXV, and XXVI

as their efficient
free cause.

dependent upon Him cause, their immanent cause, and their


to be

In the
efficient

first place, he says in Proposition XXIV, God is the cause of the modes. But before we go further with

the proposition, we must point out the relation between Spinoza's use of the term efficient cause and the use of the

same term by

the mediaevals.

In Maimonides, for instance,

means primarily the cause that into being, and is distinguished by him from brings things the term formal cause which means the cause that preserves the existence of things after their having come into being. God is, however, according to him both the efficient and the
the term efficient cause

cause of the

formal cause of the universe, inasmuch as God is both the commencement of the existence of things and the

cause of the continuance of the existence of things. Thus arguing against those who maintained that the world could continue to exist even without God once it had been produced by " God, he says that they would be right, if God were only the
1

Cf. above, pp. 304

ff.

382
efficient

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


cause and
if
.

[ETHICS,

the continuance of the existence of the


. .

God, produced thing were not dependent upon Him. however, is himself the form of the universe, as we have already shown, and it is He who causes its continuance and
x

permanence."

The same

idea that

God

is

both the cause of

the creation and the cause of the permanence of the universe

runs throughout scholastic philosophy, though a different terminology is used. In Thomas Aquinas the cause of the

permanence of the universe

is

called causa essendi, whereas


is

the cause of the creation of the universe

called causa

fiendi* In Duns Scotus both these causes, which he calls causa conservans and causa produc en s respectively, are said to

be subdivisions of the efficient cause. 3

Similarly Descartes

speaks of God not only as the cause of the creation of the world but also as the cause of its conservation. 4
Reflecting this historical background and using, like Duns Scotus, the term efficient cause to include both the cause of
creation

and the cause of conservation, Spinoza says that

are dependent upon God as their efficient cause, for inasmuch as "the essence of things produced by God does

modes

not involve existence," 5 "God is the cause not only of the commencement of the existence of things, but also of their

continuance

in existence."

In the course of his discussion

Spinoza refers to the scholastic expression causa essendi, mentioned by us before, as a description of the continuance
of the existence of things. Essendi, in the scholastic use of the term, means existendi, as has been pointed out by Spinoza

himself in a letter to Meyer, 7 and


1

is

therefore to be translated

Moreh Nebukim,

I,

69.

^heologica, Pars I, Quaest. 104, Art. I, Conclusio and ad 2. In Octo Libros Physicorum Aristotelis Quaestiones, Lib. II, Quaest. 8, Mcditationes, III (Oeuvres, VII, p. 49, 11. 12 ff.).
Ethics, I, Prop. 24.
6
1.

Summa

No.

5.

* 7

Ibid., Corol.

Epistola 12 (Opera, IV, p. 55,

3).

Cf. above, p. 108, n. 4,

and

p. 141, n. 4.

PROPS. 19-29]

MODES

383

by "existence" rather than by "essence/* though the latter resembles it more closely etymologically.
In the second place, Spinoza wants to say, the modes are dependent upon God as their immanent cause. He does not,

however, say so in these very words. What he says reads that "God is the efficient cause not only of the existence of
x things, but also of their essence/* how in Spinoza's mind to say that

But we

shall try to

show
is

God

is

the cause of the

essence of things was the equivalent of saying that the immanent cause of things.

God

essence of things in Aristotle and throughout the subsequent history of philosophy meant the concept of things as it is formed by its definition. Thus the essence of man is

The

animality and rationality, inasmuch as man is defined as a rational animal. But animality, which is the genus of man, is considered by Aristotle as the cause of man, and that kind
of cause, as we have shown, is called an immanent cause in the sense that the effect resides in it. 2 Consequently, if the
Aristotelian theory of definition is followed, namely, that a thing is defined by its genus, it may be said that the genus is the cause of the essence of the species, or, to express it
differently, the essence of the species
is

dependent upon the


rejects this

genus as its

immanent

cause.

Now, Spinoza

Aristotelian theory of definition, "although," he says, "all the logicians admit this," 3 and sets up in its place a new
exist

theory according to which modes or things "which do not 4 5 through themselves" or which are "created" are

be defined "only through the attributes whose modes they are, and through which, as their genus, they must be
to
1

Ethics, I, Prop. 25.


3
<

Cf. above, pp. 323

ff.

Short treatise,
Ibid.,
10.

I, 7,

9.

Tractates de Intellects Emendation e ,

96 (Opera,

II, p. 35,

1.

12).

Cf. above,

PP- 35<>-35

384

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


r

[ETHICS,

understood/'
"
"

or,
2

as

he

proximate

or

theory, man is as a combination of the


sion

According to this not defined as a rational animal but rather


efficient

"

sometimes says, through their


"
3

cause.

modes of God's

and thought,
4

or, as Spinoza himself says,

attributes of exten" the essence of

man

consists of certain modifications of the attributes of


Still,

God."
to the

while Spinoza differs from his predecessors as

to the nature of a definition, he does not differ

from them as

meaning of the term essence. The essence of a thing is still to him the concept of a thing attained by what he considers to be the definition of a thing, namely, the attributes
of which the thing
5

is

a mode, for

"a
said

definition, if

it is

to be

perfect," he says, "must explain the innermost essence of a

thing."
as its

But the attributes are


cause.
6

be related to the definiendum as

its
is

by Spinoza himself to genus and consequently

immanent

Spinoza

thus enabled to speak of

the attributes or of substance or of God, just as his predecessors speak of the genus, as the cause of the essence of the

definiendum y
definiendum.
7

or,

rather,

as

the

immanent cause of

the

But still, unlike the Aristotelian definition which merely states what a thing is but does not affirm that
exists,

it

definition affirms

Spinoza's theory of definition maintains that a what a thing is as well as that it exists, for

"given the definition of a thing, there should be no possibil8 ity of questioning whether it exists." Though he says else-

where that

"

involve existence,"
1

the essence of things produced by God does not 9 he does not mean that there is a possiI,

Short Treatise,

7,

10.
',

Tractatus de Intellectus Emendations

96 (Opera ,

II, p. 35,

1.

13).

Epistola 60 (Opera , IV, p. 270, Ethics, II, Prop. 10, Corol.

1.

22).

Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione,


Cf. above, pp. 324, 328. Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione,
9

95 (Opera,
7

II, p. 34, 1. 29). Cf. above, p. 124. II, p. 35,


11.

97 (Opera,

31-32).

Ettiics, I,

Prop. 24.

PROPS. 19-29]

MODES

385

bility of questioning whether they exist; he only means that their existence is not determined by their own nature but by

their cause.

Consequently, unlike the genus in the Aristote-

lian definition, the attributes, or substance, or

God, or the

proximate or the efficient cause in Spinoza's definition are the causes of both the existence and the essence of the thing
defined.

Hence

in

wishing to say that the modes are dependis

ent upon
tion

God

as their efficient cause Spinoza says in Proposi-

XXV

that

"God

the efficient cause not only of the

existence of things, but also of their essence."

In the third place, says Spinoza, modes are dependent

upon God as their only free cause. We already know that by the term free cause Spinoza means that "which exists from the necessity of its own nature alone, and is determined to action by itself alone," and that when he speaks of God 2 he means that God alone as being the only free cause "acts from the laws of His own nature only, and is com3 The modes, on the other hand, not being pelled by no one." are determined in their action by some cause. This free, conclusion with regard to modes is summed up by Spinoza in two statements in Proposition XXVI, first, in a positive statement, "a thing which has been determined to any action was necessarily so determined by God," and second, in a negative statement, "that which has not been thus
J

determined by

God

cannot determine

itself to action."

Now this proposition, both in its positive and in its negative statements, would on the whole have been admitted by
Talmudic
the mediaeval Jewish theologians and philosophers. In the literature there occur such sayings as "everys is in the control of God," 4 "everything is foreseen," thing
'

Ibid., I, Def. 7.

Ibid., I, Prop. 17, Corol. 2.

Ibid. y I, Prop. 17.

Eerakot 33 b, and parallels.


ty

III, 15.

386

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


"

[ETHICS,
it is

and

no one on earth bruises


x

his finger, unless

decreed in

heaven."

In the philosophic literature it is generally maintained that everything has a cause which ultimately goes back to God as the first cause. Thus Judah ha-Levi sums

up the position of Jewish philosophers by saying that whatever one may think of freedom of the will, it is generally admitted that nothing happens which does not come either directly or indirectly under the decree or determination of
God. 2
Similarly

Maimonides maintains "that God

is

the

efficient cause of the particular events that take place in the world, just as He is the efficient cause of the universe as a

But still, while they would have admitted both these parts of the proposition, they would have insisted that man has freedom of the will. The Talwhole as
it

now

exists."

mudic statement that "everything is in the control of God" adds "except the fear of God," 4 and the statement that "everything is foreseen" adds "yet freedom of choice is
s Similarly in the philosophic literature the principle given." of freedom of the will is maintained. Now this freedom of the

will,

niscience

according to its protagonists, does not exclude the omand hence the foreknowledge of God. How these

two can be reconciled constitutes the problem of the freedom of the will. Various solutions of this problem are offered. It is sometimes said that while God has foreknowledge of
man's choice
is
it

knowledge no foreknowledge of man's choice, but it is argued that such a lack of foreknowledge is no defect in God. 7 Sometimes it
is
1

not causative. 6 Or

does not determine that choice, for God's it is admitted that God has

argued that while indeed both the principle of man's


Hullin jb.
a 4

&

Moreh Nebukim, Abot> HI, 15.

I,

69.

Cuzari t V, 20. Berakot 3jb.

6
7

Emunot

Emunah Ramah,

wf-De'of, IV, 4; Cuzari, V, 20. II, vi, 2 (p. 96).

PROPS. 19-29]

MODES

387

freedom and the principle of God's foreknowledge are to be admitted, there is no contradiction between them, for God's

knowledge is a homonymous term and is absolutely unlike human knowledge. Now, all these, Spinoza must have
1

mind, are a sort of specious reasoning and special pleading which do not really remove the essential difficulty. To say that God's knowledge is not causative or
argued
in his

that God has no foreknowledge is to deny God's omnipotence and omniscience, and to say that God's knowledge is different from ours is tantamount to an admission that the problem is unsolvable. If God's omnipotence and omniscience
are to be maintained, then

God must be
also

the cause of every

future event and


event.

He must
it is

If despite this
will,

have foreknowledge of that maintained that man has freedom

of the

then

it

means that man can render indeterminate

that which has been determined by God. It is this pointed argument against the mediaeval position on the freedom of

the

human
to

will that

Proposition XXVII

that

Spinoza had in mind when he said in " a thing which has been determined
itself

by God

any action cannot render

indeterminate."
infinite

Spinoza has thus explained the two sets of


eternal modes, those which
attributes of
in so far as

and

God and

immediately follow from the those which follow from His attributes

modes.

they are modified already by the immediate But the world which Spinoza has undertaken to

describe does not consist wholly of infinite and eternal modes. The modes which come directly under our observation are

what Spinoza

things (res singulares)^ and these are neither infinite in the perfection of their nature nor
calls individual

eternal in the duration of their existence.

They

are rather

imperfect and transient things. Consequently, after having shown in Proposition XXV that God is the efficient cause not
1

Moreh Nebukim,

III, ao.

388

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

only of the existence of the infinite and eternal modes but also of their essence, he derives therefrom in the Corollary
of the same proposition that "individual things are nothing but affections or modes of God's attributes, expressing those
attributes in a certain

and determinate manner." The impliis

cation of this statement


existence

that

God

is

also the cause of the

and of the essence of

finite

modes.

When

in the

next proposition he states in a general way that God is the cause of the action of a thing, he similarly means to assert
that

God

is

the cause of the action of the infinite and eternal

modes

as well as of the finite

and transient modes.

Thus

individual things, like the infinite and eternal modes, follow from God and are determined by God in their existence,
essence,

and

action.

But

if

individual things follow from God, then, since

God
be

is infinite,

where does
rise

their finiteness

come from?

It will

recalled that both in his criticism of the emanationist ex-

planation of the

of matter out of an immaterial


for the infinity
2

God

and

in his

own argument

and eternity of

Spinoza insisted upon adherence to the principle of necessary causality, namely, that the effect must be like the cause, so that cause
strict

the immediate and mediate

modes

mutually implicative concepts and one can be known by the other. 3 How then on the basis of this principle can Spinoza assert that finite things follow from

and

effect are

the infinite

God? Spinoza

is

thus

same problem

as the emanationists

now confronted with the when these latter found

themselves called upon to explain the rise of matter the which Spinoza thought he had solved for good problem when he endowed God with the attribute of extension. The
1

Cf. above, Chapter IV. Cf. above, pp. 377~378. Ethics, I, Def. 4. Cf. above, p. 90.

PROPS. 19-29]

MODES
returns to

389

problem now

him not

in the

form of how material

things arose from an immaterial cause but rather in the form of how finite things arose from an infinite cause.

That Spinoza was conscious of


dent.
it

this problem is quite eviIn the Second Dialogue in the Short Treatise he puts " in the mouth of Erasmus, who asks, if the effect of the
.

inner cause cannot perish so long as its cause lasts; then can God be the cause of all things, seeing that
.

how

many

again stated by him, not indeed directly in the form of a question but rather indirectly in the form of a positive statement, in the Demonthings perish?"
is

The same problem

finite

stration of Proposition XXVIII in Ethics ^ I: "That which is and which has a determinate existence could not be

produced by the absolute nature of any attribute of God, for whatever follows from the absolute nature of any attriIn both these places is infinite and eternal." solution for the problem is offered. In the Second Dialogue of the Short Treatise^ Erasmus, speaking for Spinoza, says that "God is really a cause of the effects which

bute of

God

the

same

He

tions except His attributes alone;

has produced immediately, without any other condiand that these cannot

perish so long as their cause endures; but that you cannot call God an inner cause of the effects whose existence does

immediately, but which have come into some other thing, except in so far as their being through causes do not operate, and cannot operate, without God, nor also outside Him, and that for this reason also, since
not depend on

Him

The same explanation


Treatise, I, 8,

they are not produced immediately by God, they can perish." is given by Spinoza himself in Short

where he says that the individual things are the "general mode," which expression is used produced by by him there to include both the immediate and mediate
infinite

modes, though he mentions there only the immedi-

390

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

ate modes. 1 Similarly in the Scholium to Proposition XXVIII of Ethics, I, Spinoza maintains that God is the absolutely

proximate cause (causa absolute proximo) of the immediate modes, that He is only the proximate cause in its own kind (causa proxima in suo genere) of the mediate ininfinite
finite

the literal sense of the term,

modes, but that in distinction to these, though not in He is the remote cause (causa
2

remota) of the individual things.


also says in Proposition

In addition to
as follows:

all this,

he

XXVIII

"An

individual

thing, or a thing which is finite and which has a determinate existence, cannot exist nor be determined to action unless
it

which

be determined to existence and action by another cause is also finite and has a determinate existence, and

again, this cause cannot exist nor be determined to action unless by another cause which is also finite and determined
to existence

and

action,

and so on ad infinitum" Taking

all

these passages together

we may

tion of the rise of finite things as follows:

restate Spinoza's explanaFinite things folinfinite


effects.

in

low directly from finite causes. These finite causes are number and form an infinite series of causes and
infinite series of finite causes follows

This

from the mediate


follows from the
turn,

infinite

mode. This mediate

infinite

mode
in

immediate infinite modes, which, directly from God.


1

their

follow

Cf. above, pp. 216, 249. From the reading of the opening lines of the Scholium as given in Gebhardt's

edition (Opera, II, p. 70, 11. 2-4; cf. editor's discussion on p. 352), it is clear that "quaedam a Deo immediate produci debuerunt" (1. 2) refers to the immediate
infinite

modes and that "et


infinite

alia

mediantibus his primis"

(11.

3-4) refers to the

mediate

modes.

When,

therefore, Spinoza says later "that of things im-

mediately produced by

own kind"

(11.

5-7),

it

the proximate cause in of proximate cause is found in Heereboord's Mclttcmata Philosophica, Disputationes

God He is the proximate cause absolutely, and not in their may be inferred that of the mediate infinite modes God is their own kind. The distinction between these two senses
XXII.
Cf. also above, p. 308.

ex Philosophia Selectae t Vol. II, Disp.

PROPS. 19-29]

MODES

391

The analogy between

this explanation of the rise of finite

things in the system of Spinoza and the explanation for the rise of material things in the system of emanation is quite

complete. Just as the emanationists speak of material things " " " as proceeding or as "following by necessity from God, so also Spinoza speaks of finite things as "following" from

God.

Just as the emanationists start out with the principle that "the direct emanation from God must be one simple

and nothing else," 2 so also Spinoza starts out with the principle that "whatever follows from the absolute
Intelligence,

nature of any attribute of God is infinite and eternal." 3 Just as the emanationists account for the rise of material
things by interposing immaterial Intelligences between God and matter, so also Spinoza accounts for the rise of finite

things by interposing infinite modes between God and finite modes. Finally, just as the emanationists arrange all the

sublunar existences, in a series of causes and

material things, from the celestial spheres to the lowest of effects, so also
all

Spinoza arranges

the finite modes in a series of causes


difference between

and

effects.

The only

them
4

is

that accord-

ing to the emanationists,

who

follow Aristotle in his denial


effects,

of an infinite series of causes and

this series is finite,

whereas according to Spinoza, who, by his own statement, 5 admits with Crescas the possibility of an infinite series of
causes and effects, 6 this series is infinite. The gist of both these explanations is that material things and finite things

which cannot be conceived to follow directly from God can


be conceived to follow indirectly from
1

Him

if

we only
II, 22.

inter-

Cf. above, p. 373.


Ethics, I, Prop. 28,

Moreh Nebukim,

*
<

Demonst.

II, I, 993a, 30 ff. Epistola 12. Cf. above, pp. 195 ff. Cf. my Crescas' Critique of Aristotle, pp. 68-69; 225-229; 490, n. 13; 496,

Metaphysics,

392

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


finite things

[ETHICS,

pose between these material or of intermediate causes.

and God a buffer

But

still

it

is

hard to see how a buffer of intermediate

For, truly speaking, any exoffered in solution of the problem of the rise of planation finitude in Spinoza or of the rise of matter in emanation must

causes can solve the problem.

from the

not only show that finitude or matter does not come directly infinite or the immaterial cause but it must also
either one of these can

show how
all

come

at

all,

seeing that

things, according to both these systems,


infinite or the

must ultimately
as their

be traced to the
cause.

immaterial
1

God
is

prime

This

is

the very reasoning employed

by Maimonides
also the very

in rejecting necessary

emanation, and this

reasoning by which Spinoza was forced to the conclusion that God is material. 2 The absence of any attempt on the
it

part of Spinoza to explain his position on this point, or, as may be phrased, the absence of any explicit statement of

a principle of individuation (principium individuationis] in the philosophy of Spinoza, makes one wonder whether this
failure of his to offer

fact that he did not think

any explanation was not due to the it was necessary for him to do so.

He may

have

felt

explanation for either

quite justified in dispensing with such an one of the following two reasons

either because he relied

upon

his readers to be able to find

among

the several solutions evolved in the course of the his-

tory of philosophy by the various monistic systems, in explanation of their common difficulty as to how the many

arose from the one, a solution which would apply to his own particular problem as to how the finite arose from the infinite,
or because he relied

upon them
between

to discover for themselves


his

some
1

essential difference
II, 12.

own

particular kind of

Moreh Ncbukim,

Cf. above, p. 106.

Cf. above, Chapter IV.

PROPS. 19-29]

MODES
the other kinds of

393
the former

monism and

monism by which

to the difficulty which required a shall, special principle of individuation for its solution. therefore, first canvass the various solutions of the common

was rendered immune

We

systems to see if any of them could be used by Spinoza, and then, in the event of our failure to find any solution which could be suitably used by him, we
difficulty of monistic
is not something about Spinoza's conof God which disposes of that common difficulty of ception monistic systems without any recourse to a special principle

shall try to see if there

of individuation.
of the explanations of the origin of the many which to monistic systems in the history of philosophy to regard the many as unreal and as having only an illusory

One

is
is

common

existence.

In European philosophy this tendency appears with the Eleatics and recurs under different forms in the

various idealistic systems. Some interpreters of Spinoza x finite modes to be of a similar nature. But passages " in which Spinoza couples affections" with "substance" as the two things which exist outside the mind, in contrast to

take his

attributes which he uses as an alternative term for substance,


clearly indicate that he considered the

modes

as

something

having reality outside the mind like substance itself, and as being unlike the attributes, which he considered only as aspects under which substance appears to our mind.

The only

difference that Spinoza finds between the reality of substance and the reality of modes is that the former is due to the

necessity of its own nature whereas the latter is due to the existence of substance. The finite modes are no less real to

him than the infinite and eternal modes. Another explanation which occurs in the history of philosophy in answer to the problem of how the many arose from
1

Ethics,

I,

Prop. 4, Demonst.; Prop. 28, Demonst.

394

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

the one or the individual from the general consists in an attempt to accredit all these to matter. According to this

explanation, all that is necessary is to account for the origin of matter, but once matter is accounted for, either by the theory of its co-eternal existence with God or by the process of emanation or by the belief in a special act of creation ex nihihy there
tibility,
is

a ready explanation for

all

divisibility, individuality,

and

in

the change, corrupfact for all the

changing phenomena of the visible world. It is thus that mediaeval philosophers speak for Aristotle and for themselves of matter as the principle of individuation. Spinoza, however, could not offer matter as his principle of finitude, for if matter is taken as a principle of individuation it is only

because
is

it is

considered as something which by

its

very nature

potential, passive, imperfect, and is consequently the cause of divisibility and corruptibility. But Spinoza's matter, being extension and an infinite attribute of God, is none of
1

these,

and cannot therefore out of

its

own nature become

the principle of finitude.

another explanation occurs in the history of philosophy which has a direct bearing upon Spinoza's problem here,
Still

for the
is

problem which the explanation was meant to solve formulated as here by Spinoza in terms of the rise of the

This explanation may be designated by the Cabalistic Hebrew term Zimzum,* i.e., contraction. The theory of Zimzum has a long history and is susceptible
finite
infinite.

from the

of various philosophic rationalizations, but we shall quote here a brief statement of its original and unadulterated

meaning from Abraham Herrera's Puerto, del Cielo. Starting with the statement that "from an infinite power, it would seem, an infinite effect would necessarily have to follow/'
Herrera proceeds to say with the Cabalists that "in a certain
1

Cf. above pp. 237, 257.

PROPS. 19-29]

MODES
active force
It
finite effects/*
x

395

manner God had contracted His


order to produce

reference to this problem of the rise infinite that Solomon Maimon made in one of his works the

and power in must have been with of the finite from the

cryptic remark that the view of Spinoza "agrees with the 2 In his opinion of the Cabalists on the subject of Zimzum. autobiography, Solomon Maimon similarly calls attention to
1 '

Zimzum

the analogy between Spinoza and the Cabalistic principle of in the following passage: "In fact, the Cabala is

nothing but an expanded Spinozism, in which not only is the origin of the world explained by the contraction (Einschrdn-

kung

Zimzum) of the divine


its

ery kind of being, and

being, but also the origin of evrelation to the rest, are derived from

a special (besonderri) attribute of God." 3 However, Spinoza could have made no use of this theory of contraction in the
solution of his problem of the rise of the finite from the infinite, for Zimzum as a solution of the problem implies that the infinite cause is an intelligent agent, and it is in this sense

that

it is

who

insists

generally used among the Cabalists, but to Spinoza, upon the necessary nature of the divine causality,

such an assumption is entirely inadmissible. To quote again from Herrera: "The second reason on account of which it
is

manner contracted and

possible for us to maintain that the Infinite had in some limited himself in order to enable

himself to produce finite and limited emanations is that the act of contraction is an act by means of His intelligence and

His

will."

Finally,
1

among

the various formulations of the theory of

Sha'ar ha-Shamayim^ V, 12.


Cf.

Solomon
I,

Maimon's Hebrew commentary

Gib'at

ha-Moreh on Morch
Ch.

Nfbtikim^
3

74.
I,

(1792), p. 146.
*

Salomon Maimon' s Lcbcnsgeschichte von ihm sclbst beschricben, Part English translation by J. C. Murray, Boston, 1888.

XIV

Sha'ar ha-Shamayim t V, 12.

396

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

emanation which are advanced as explanations of the problem of the origin of matter there is one which, by analogy with one of the present-day solutions of the problem of the
origin of
life

known

as
1

"emergent evolution," we

may

call

"emergent emanation/' It assumes indeed, as do all theories of emanation, that God is immaterial and that matter does not therefore arise directly from God. Still it does not arise
from anything external to God. Nor does it arise by the will of God. It arises because in the process of emanation a new cause inevitably makes its appearance. This new cause does
is

not proceed from God nor does it come from without, but the necessary concomitant of a new relation which, not
its

present in God, appears in the

nature of

first Intelligence by the very an emanation and hence, unlike God, being having only possible existence. This theory says in effect that matter is not the resultant of spiritual causes, but rather an

emergent, arising as something unpredictable out of a new relation which makes its appearance in the emanated Intelligence.

Now

such an unpredictable new relation appears also

in Spinoza's

immediate

infinite

modes, and

it

appears in them

by the very circumstance that their existence is dependent upon God as their cause, and hence, unlike God, they have
only possible existence. Out of this new relation or condition, not present in God but present in the immediate infinite

modes, Spinoza might say, there arise the finite modes. Logically this would be a tenable explanation. But if we assume this explanation to have been satisfactory to Spinoza
to account for the rise of finite

modes from an

infinite

God,

why should he not have accepted it also as satisfactory to account for the rise of material things from an immaterial
1 Cf. my paper "The Problem of the Origin of Matter in Mediaeval Jewish Philosophy and its Analogy to the Modern Problem of the Origin of Life" in Proceedings of the Sixth International Congress of Philosophy (1926), pp. 602 ff.

PROPS. 19-29]

MODES

397
against the

God? What then becomes of his main argument immateriality of God? If Spinoza did refuse to

accept this

sort of reasoning as an explanation of the rise of matter

out of an immaterial cause, we must assume that he would also refuse to accept it as an explanation of the rise of finite

modes out of an infinite cause. Inasmuch as none of these

historical solutions could

be

fittingly used by Spinoza, let us now look for some difference a difference that between Spinoza and the emanationists

would be sufficiently valid to dispose of the difficulty with which we are now contending. Such a difference can be found if we only free Spinoza from the encumbrance of the traditional terminology which he
affects, for, in

truth, while he uses emanationist terms he

does not

When
from
really

exactly what the emanationists mean. " " the emanationists speak of things as proceeding
or as

mean by them
"

God

mean

following by necessity" from God, they that there is an actual egression of something
1

from within
in

God which on

its

departure from

God assumes

Though that departure is not time nor in space, still logically the world follows from God in some order of succession and is outside of God. The Intelligences are thus conceived as proceeding

a nature unlike that of God.

from

God and

from the Intelligences, and within the spheres appears matter which is not contained in God. In such a conception of succession, the appearance of matthe spheres as proceeding
ter,

indeed, has to be accounted

for.

When Spinoza,

however,

as following (sequi) from God or as being produced (froduci) by God, or when he speaks of God as acting (agif) or as a cause, all these expressions, as we have shown above, 2 mean nothing but that the modes are con-

describes the

modes

tained in the substance as the conclusion of a syllogism


1

is

Cf. above, p. 373.

Cf. above, p. 373.

398

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


its

[ETHICS,

contained in

are contained in its definition.

premises and as the properties of a triangle 1 There is no such thing as

the procession of the finite from the infinite in Spinoza. God or substance is to him an infinite logical crust which holds

together the crumbs of the infinite number of the finite modes, and that crust is never broken through to allow the

crumbs to escape or to emanate. Infinite substance by its very nature contains within itself immediate infinite modes, and the immediate infinite modes contain within themselves
mediate
infinite

modes, and the mediate

infinite

modes con-

tain within themselves the infinite

number

of finite modes,

last are arranged as a series of causes and effects. In such a conception of an all-containing substance there can be no question as to how the finite came into existence out of an

which

infinite

any more than there can be a question as

to

how

subits

stance

came
is

into existence.
it

Substance

is

causa sui y and

nature

such that

involves within itself three orders of

immediate infinite, mediate infinite, and finite. modes The question as to how things come into existence can logically appear only within the finite modes, and the answer to this, as given by Spinoza, is that each finite mode comes into existence by another finite mode, and so on to infinity, but
is ultimately contained in God, who causa sui, through the mediate and immediate infinite modes. Things are finite by the very fact that they are parts

the entire infinite series

is

of a whole which

is infinite.

Spinoza has thus proved that both the infinite modes and the individual things are determined by God in three respects, viz., in their existence, in their essence, and in their action. As a result of this he concludes in Proposition

XXIX

things are determined from the necessity of the divine nature to


1

that "in nature there

is

nothing contingent, but

all

Cf. Ethics,

I,

Prop. 17, Schol., and above, p. 90.

PROPS. 19-29]

MODES
in a certain

399

exist

and act

manner." Three statements are

contained in this proposition. In the first place, it denies contingency, or, as he calls it elsewhere, the existence of
"accidental things," which are defined by him as those 1 or of which, through "a things which have "no cause"
the order of causes is condeficiency in our knowledge cealed from us." * Accidental things are similarly defined by Aristotle as those things which have no determinate
.
. .

cause. 3

In the second place, since there are no accidental things in nature but everything in nature is determined in
existence and action
if

its

by

a cause, there

is

no freedom

in

nature, by freedom is meant, as it is defined by Spinoza, that which exists and acts by its own nature and without
4 any other cause. In the third place, all the causes in nature are traceable to one cause, which is the necessity of the divine

nature.

This concludes Spinoza's treatment of the modes.


all

Taking now
infinite,

the

modes

together, the finite as well as the

he contrasts them with substance and attributes, the former natura naturata and the latter natura calling naturans. 3 Similarly in the Short 'Treatise he makes the same
classification at the beginning of his

treatment of the modes. 6

But we have already discussed

this

matter quite
7

fully in the

chapter on Extension and Thought.


1

Short Treatise
Ethics ,
I,

-,

I, 6,

2.

2 3

Prop. 33, Schol.

Cf. above, p. 318. i. Cf. Cogitata Metaphysica,

I, 3,

and above,

p. 189.

*
5

Metaphysics, V, 30, 10253, 24. Cf. Ethics, I, Def. 7.


Ibid.,
I,

Prop. 29, Schol.


I, 8.
ff.

Cf. above, p. 390, n.

i.

6
7

Short Treatise,

Cf. above, pp. 253

CHAPTER

XII

NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS


I.

INTELLECT, WILL, AND


in Proposition
in nature, that

POWER
that there
is is

THE

statement

XXIX

noth-

determined by everything ing contingent a cause, and that the causes are traceable to God reflects on
the whole the mediaeval philosophic position. When Crescas raises the question whether pure possibility exists in nature,

he sums up the case for the negative by the statement that

"in the case of


causes

all

corruption, their existence


.
. .

things that are subject to generation and is necessarily preceded by four

and when we inquire again into the existence of these causes, it is also found that they must necessarily be and when we look for other preceded by other causes
. . .

causes for these causes, the same conclusion follows, until the series of causes terminate at the Prime Being who is x Similarly Maimonides states that necessary of existence."

"when we have found for any existing thing those four causes which are in immediate connection with it, we find
for

them again

causes,

and

for these again other causes,

and

so on until
at

we

arrive at the first causes/'

and then

finally

God. 2 But the mediaevals, after having asserted the existence of this causal nexus, try to break the nexus at two
points,
ity of

by introducing a certain kind of design


a certain

in the causal-

God and

amount of freedom

in the action

of

man. Spinoza will therefore now try to eliminate both design in God and freedom in man and will insist upon an un1

Or Adonai> II, v, 2. Cf, above, Moreh Nebukim, I, 69.

p. 309.

PROPS. 30-36]

NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS

401

interrupted sequence of causal continuity. Here in the last seven propositions and Appendix of the First Part of the
Ethics^

which deals with God, he

tries

primarily to eliminate

two propositions of the Second Part, which deals with man, he tries to eliminate freedom in man.
design in

God;

later in the last

The

tion, is expressed

design in God's actions, especially in the act of creaby the mediaevals in terms of certain

creation.

attributes which they find to be implied in the divine act of Thus Saadia derives from the fact of creation that

God

1 power, and knowledge. Judah ha-Levi derives from the same fact that God has knowledge, power, life, and 2 will. Maimonides insists that creation must be an act of

has

life,

and design, 3 which, according to his own statements, 4 imply also life, knowledge, and power. These four attributes then are what according to the mediaevals raise the
will

actions of

God above

His causality the result of

mere mechanical process and make will, intelligence, and purpose.

In desiring to show that the causality of

God

is

a neces-

sary process Spinoza subjects these attributes to a critical examination with a view to finding out what they may actually mean when applied to God. He does this in two

ways.

First,

he

tries to

prove that on the showing of the

understanding of the meaning of the attributes of intellect, life, and power by the mediaevals themselves God's action

must be a necessary
lowed above
in the

action. This

method of attack he has

fol-

Second, of these attributes of intellect, will, and power, he again tries to show that God's action is a
unfolding his

Scholium to Proposition XVII.

own conception
This
is

necessary action.
Propositions
1

what he

is

proposing to do

now

in

XXX-XXXIV
y

before us.
3

Emunot we-De'ot Morth Nebukim^

II, 4.

Cuzari, V, 18, 7-9.


7*V/., II, 19; I, 53.

II, 19

and

21.

402

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

In both these places, it will be noticed, Spinoza deals only with three out of the four attributes enumerated by the mediaevals, mentioning only intellect, will, and power, leaving out life. The reason for his not mentioning life

but
"

may
the

perhaps be found

in the fact that

Spinoza defines

life

as

power (vim) through which things persevere in their existence," and "moreover, the power by which God perseveres in His existence is nothing else than His essence." Now,
r

the "ability to exist"

is

defined by Spinoza himself as


life

"power"

(potentia)*
is

Consequently,
(potentid).
It

(vita) y

according

to Spinoza,

power

may

therefore be conlife

cluded that the omission of the attribute of


in the propositions before us
is

by Spinoza

due to the

fact that he has

under the attribute of power. In his first kind of argument in the Scholium to Proposition XVII, as we have already seen, Spinoza has arrived
included
it

believe that intellect, will,

at the conclusion that, from the point of view of those who and power pertain to the nature
it

of God,

would have

to follow that

"God's

intellect, will,

and power are one and the same thing." On the whole, this represents exactly the views of Saadia, Maimonides, and the
other Jewish philosophers, all of whom maintain that these attributes are one and the same in God. To quote a short

passage from Maimonides:


[i.e.,

"You must know

that

wisdom

[and for that matter also will and in reference to God are not different from each other." 3 power] Similar statements as to the identity of intellect, will, and
intellect]

and

life

power in God are made by Spinoza in his Cogitata Metaphysicaf and there, too, he is merely repeating the common mediaeval view. In the Scholium to Proposition XVII,
1

3
*

Moreh Nebukim,

Ethics, I, Prop, n, Demonst. 3. Cogitata Metaphysica, II, 6. I, 53. Cf. quotations from Saadia and Albo above, p. 155.

Cogitata Metaphysica, II, 7, note,

and

8.

PROPS. 30^36]

NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS


tries to establish the necessity

403

therefore, he

of God's causality

this commonly accepted mediaeval view and contending that if intellect and will pertain to the essence of God and are one, then these attributes must be homonymous terms, and hence meaningless terms, and consequently

by arguing from

to say that God acts by intelligence and will to saying that God acts by necessity. 1
to establish this necessary causality of

is

tantamount
tries

But here in these Propositions XXX-XXXI V Spinoza

not by arguing from the generally accepted mediaeval view but by arguing against it. In the first place, he seems to say, the three

God

by which the mediaevals try to characterize the of God are not of the same order. Indeed, "the causality 2 power of God is His essence itself," but as for intellect and
attributes

they do not pertain to the essence of God. Intellect and will, which are the same, 3 are nothing but modes of
will,

God.

What

kind of

mode

the intellect, or, rather, the ab-

solutely infinite intellect,

Spinoza.

It is the

has already been explained by immediate mode of thought correspondis,

ing to motion ar\d rest, which are the immediate extension. 4 So is also will an immediate mode of

mode

of

thought. Consequently, "will and intellect are related to the nature

of

God

as

motion and

rest/'

are the immediate

mode

except that will and intellect of the attribute of thought whereas

motion and
extension.

rest are the

immediate mode of the attribute of

Now, the attribute of thought in its self-conscious has as the direct object of its knowledge the essence activity 6 of God himself and through God's essence also the modes.
1

Cf. above, p. 317.


11.

Cf. also Bruno,


a

De

I'

infinite untvcrso et

Mondi, Dial.

I,

p. 316,
*

21-31 (ed. Lagarde).

Ethics, I, Prop. 34.

Cf. Prop. 17, Schol.

Ethics, II, Prop. 49, Corol.;


11.

p. 62,
s

28-29).
I,

Tractatus 'Theologico-Politicus, Ch. 4 (Opera, III, Cf. above, p. 216.


-i

Ethics,

Prop. 32, Corol.

2.

Cf. below, Vol. II, p. 17.

404

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


intellect,

[ETHICS,

The

however, not pertaining to the essence of God and being only a mode of thought, cannot have the essence of God as the object of its knowledge. But still, the object of
tellect itself.

its

knowledge must be something that exists outside the inSince, however, outside the intellect there is

nothing but God or (which is the same thing by Def. IV) His attributes and their modes, 1 and since furthermore the
intellect

the object of

cannot comprehend the essence of God himself, its knowledge must be the attributes of God

and their affections, not only the attribute of thought, of which it is itself a mode, and the modes of thought, but also the attribute and modes of extension. 2 This is what is meant by Proposition XXX: "The actual intellect, whether finite or infinite/' that is to say, whether the human intellect or
tributes of

the absolutely infinite intellect, "must comprehend the atGod and the affections of God, and nothing else/'

The terms "actual


tial

intellect'* (intellectus actu)

and "poten-

intellect" (intellectus potentid) used by Spinoza in this proposition are a mediaeval heritage, and are to be found in

Arabic, Hebrew,

back to
neLy

Aristotle's vovs tvtpydq. (or e^reXexti^t)

and Latin philosophy, but ultimately go and vovs dvvafrom the terms
"
active

and these are

to be distinguished

and "passive intellect" (intellectus passivus) which go back to the Greek *>oDs 7rou)Ti/c6s and vovs 7ra0r;Tt/c6s. 4 The terms "actual" and "potential" describe two states of the intellect, one before the act of thinking, when the intellect is a mere capacity, and the other
intellect" (intellectus agens)
1

Ethics y

I,

Prop. 4, Demonst.
are:
(i)

Cf. above, pp. 142

f.

The Hebrew and Arabic terms

^yisn ^OPH, J*AJU

JiJl;

(2)
4

ran

fen

-JiJU

jaJl.
are:
(i)

The corresponding Hebrew and Arabic terms


jsJl;
( 2)

7yi3n 7DBH,

JUJl

7y>n

7Dtpn,

J.AJLJI

Cf. below, Vol. II, p. 14.

PROPS. 30-36]

NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS

405

in the act of thinking,

when

the intellect

is

an actuality. The
is

nature of these two states of the intellect


Aristotle in

discussed by
in

De Anima^

III, 4, the

most pregnant passage

which
it

is

tially all

the following: "The intellect is in a manner potenobjects of thought, but is actually none of them until
'

thinks/*

An elaborate
in

discussion of this distinction


in a

is

also

to be

found

Maimonides

chapter which has been

several occasions. 2 But, as " " himself says, he uses the expression actual intellect Spinoza not because he agrees with Aristotle and the mediaevals that

drawn upon by Spinoza on

there is a "potential intellect" but rather for the purpose of emphasizing the fact that the intellect is to him always that which Aristotle and the mediaevals would describe as actual,
"

that

is

to say, the act of understanding itself (ipsa scilicet


3

intellectione) ."

modes whereas power is intellect and will belong

Furthermore, says Spinoza, since intellect and will are identical with the essence of God,

to natura naturata^ whereas power, be said to belong to natura naturans* by implication, may Hence the significance of Proposition XXXI, that "the

actual intellect, whether


will, desire, love, etc.,

it

be

finite or infinite,

together with

must be

referred to the natura naturata

and not

to the natura

naturans" The mention of desire and

love in this proposition together with will and intellect is in accordance with Spinoza's habit of referring to desire and

love as
lect, it

modes

may

or of thought. 5 Will and intelbe recalled, are considered by Spinoza as modes


either of will
4

of thought and as identical with each other. Spinoza's denial of will as pertaining to the essence of God

and
1

his relegation of
68.

it

to the realm of

modes

leads

him

De Anima,
Ethics,
I,

III, 4, 429!), 30-31.


I,

Moreh Nebukim,

Cf. above, pp. 238-239; below, Vol. II. pp. 24, 45.

Prop. 31, Schol.


4,

Short Treatise, II, 2,

and

16,

8.

Ethics, II, Ax. 3.

406

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

directly to a denial of the mediaeval attribution of freedom of the will to God. As a prelude to what the mediaevals

meant by attributing freedom of will to God, we may first make clear what they meant by will and by freedom of the will in general. The best definition of will for our present
purpose
the will
is
is

the

same

that given by Maimonides. "The true essence of the ability to will and not to will.'' * Practically definition is also given by Descartes: "The faculty

of will consists alone in our having the power of choosing to do a thing or choosing not to do it (that is, to affirm or deny,
2 to pursue or to shun it)." Spinoza, as we shall show on a later occasion, reproduces this definition when he says that

"by will I understand a faculty of affirming or denying/' The implication of this definition is that there is no will unless
that possibility of choice between willing and not willing. An eternal and immutable will, therefore, is a contradiction in terms, according to Maimonides. 4 As a result
there
is

of this definition, no act of the will can be an eternal and immutable act; it must have a beginning and end or it must

Now, proceed the mediaevals, if the changes which by definition must occur in any act of the will are brought about by external causes the will is said to
be not
the will
free.

be an intermittent act.

But

if

ternal causes but


is

they are brought about without any exby the very nature of the will itself, then

"Free will/' says Judah ha-Levi, "qua no compulsory cause." s Similarly Crescas de" to will and not to will fines absolutely free will as the ability 6 without an external cause/' These definitions, in fact, corcalled free.
free will, has
1

Moreh Nebukim, Meditationes, IV


p. 167.

II, 18,

Second Method.
11. 21-23). Short Treatise, II, 16,

(Ocuvrc, VII, p. 57,

Ethics, II, Prop. 48, Schol.;

2.

Cf. below, Vol. II,

* s

Moreh Nebukim,
Cuzari, V, 20.

II, 21.

Or Adonai,

II, v, 3 (p.

4 8b).

PROPS. 30-36]

NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS

407

respond to Spinoza's
is

own

1 definition of freedom.

But while

in nature in general, it is

no such

free will,

and while

admitted by the mediaevals, there in the case of man the question

of freedom constitutes one of their major problems of philosophy, with reference to God, they all maintain that He acts

from the freedom of His

will.

Says again Maimonides: "If

this will pertained to a material thing, so that the object

sought after by means of that will was something outside the thing, there would then be a will which would change according to obstacles and newly arising circumstances. But the will of an immaterial being, which in no sense has for its

object any other thing,


it

is unchangeable, and the fact that one thing and tomorrow it wills another thing does not constitute a change in the essence of the being nor

now

wills

does

it

lead to the assumption of the existence of another

cause [external to it]." 2 As against this the position taken by Spinoza may be summed up as follows: Granted that God
is free,

that freedom cannot be called freedom of the will; for


for the inadmissibility of will in

will,

he maintains, cannot pertain to the essence of God.

The argument

God

is

given in Proposition

XXXII.

pertain to the essence of God. identical with the infinite intellect, following immediately from the attribute of thought. Being a mode of thought, it

Will, says Spinoza, cannot It is only an infinite mode,

determined by thought as its cause, just as the finite will is determined by a series of causes, which series is infinite, according to Spinoza himself, or
is

of any individual being

3 according to the mediaevals. Having a cause, will can no longer be called free. Hence, "the will cannot be

finite,

called a free cause, but can only be called necessary."


1

Ethics, I, Def. 7.

Cf. above, p. 311.

Moreh Nebukim,

II, 18.

*
*

Cf. above, p. 196.


Ethics,
I,

Prop. 32, and Demonst.

4o8

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


it

[ETHICS,

Furthermore,

follows "that
x

God

does not act from free-

dom

of the will,"

for will does not pertain to

His essence

but is only a mode which by its very nature must have a cause and cannot therefore be free. To say that God acts

God

will has no more meaning than to say that from freedom of motion, since both are modes 2 respectively of the attributes of thought and extension. One of the implications of the mediaeval view that God

from freedom of
acts

acts from freedom of will

is

that the world could have been

produced by God
than that in which
of this view
is

in
it

another manner and in another order

has been produced. A brief statement to be found in Herrera's Puerto, del Cielo.

In his fourth argument in proof that God acts from freedom of the will he says that "such free action was the beginning of all the things which were produced and caused by God

when

it

was so decreed by His

will,

and by the same token

God could have omitted to bring them into existence or He could have brought other things into existence, and even now after having brought these things into existence, He can still change them, destroy them, and then bring
them back
into existence,
all

according to His free choice

and will/' 3 But perhaps


are

more pertinent for our present purpose the statements made by Maimonides, in which he constill

trasts Aristotle's theory of necessity with his own theory of creation by will and design, for in these statements we shall find the background not only of the view which Spinoza re-

jects but also the view which he adopts as his own. Restating Aristotle's view, Maimonides says that "it is the view

of Aristotle that this universe proceeded from the Creator by way of necessity, that God is the cause and the world is the
1

Ibid., Corol.

i.

Ibid., Corel. 2.

Sha'ar ha-Shamayim y III,

6.

PROPS.

3036]

NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS


this effect is a necessary one;

409
it

effect,

and that

and just as

cannot be explained

why God

exists or

how He

exists in this

particular manner, namely, being one and incorporeal, so it cannot be asked concerning the whole universe why it
exists or

how

it

exists in this particular


i.e.,

manner.

For

it is

necessary that the whole,

the cause as well as the effect,

should exist in this particular manner; it is impossible for them not to exist, or to be different from what they actually are. This leads to the conclusion that the nature of everything remains constant, and that nothing changes
in
l

its

nature

Maimonides maintains as any way/' own view that "we who believe in creation must admit that God could have created the universe in a different manner as regards the causes and effects contained in it." 2 Or
against this
his

As

again: "We, however, hold that all things in the universe are the result of design, and not merely of necessity. It is possible that He who designed them may change them and

conceive another design.

Not every

design, however,

is

subject to change, for there are things which are impossible 3 by their nature and cannot be altered, as will be explained/*

The

exceptions referred to here by Maimonides are those things which he himself and other mediaevals consider as

impossible on account of their involving a contradiction in their definition, such as, e.g., a square the triangle of which
is

equal to

its side. 4

With
view
in

this as his

background Spinoza formulates

his

own

Proposition XXXIII, aligning himself with Aristotle as against Maimonides: "Things could have been produced

by God
in

in

no other manner and

in

no other order than that

which they have been produced/* Direct references to controversies on this point are made by him in his Short
1

Moreh Nebukim,
Ibid., II, 19.

II, 19.

Ibid. y III, 13.

Cf. 17.

Cf. above, p. 312, n, 5.

4 io
freatise.
1

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


-,

[ETHICS,

In the Short Treatise furthermore, there is a passage 2 Here in parallel to the demonstration of this proposition. the Ethics the most important part of the discussion is given
In the first Scholium Spinoza explains the " of the terms "necessary/* impossible/' "possible/' meaning " and contingent/' which we have already discussed on several occasions. 3 But the introduction of these terms right after
in

two

Scholia.

the proposition, which

is

undoubtedly directed against the

passage we have quoted above from Maimonides, is significant, for in that passage of Maimonides, as we have seen, reference is also made to the nature of the impossible.

Spinoza seems to challenge Maimonides as follows: You say that while indeed in nature there are certain things which
absolutely necessary, but everything in it is possible or contingent, inasmuch as everything in nature, according to you, can be
are impossible, there
is

nothing in

it

which

is

changed or come into existence without any previous cause but by the mere will of God. As against you I say that in
nature there are only things impossible and things necessary, but nothing that is absolutely possible or contingent.

The second Scholium falls into three parts, as follows: (i) From the beginning of the Scholium to "Neither is
should here repeat those things which are said in the Scholium to Proposition XVII" (Opera, II,
there

any need that


1.

p. 74,

2o-p. 75,

1.

3).

(2)

From

"

But

for the sake of those


.
. .

who
and

differ
will
.
.

from me*' to "and hence


.

God's
is

intellect

must have been

different,

which

absurd"

(Opera, II, p. 75, 1. 3~p. 76, 1. 3). (3) From "Since, therefore, things could have been produced by God in no other manner or order" to the end of the Scholium (Opera, II,
p. 76,
1

1.

4-1. 34).
I,

Short Treatise,
Ibid.,

4,
11.

3 and

7 (Opera,

I, p.

37,
3

(p. 38,

33

ff.).

11. 16 ff., p. 38, 11. 30 Cf. above, pp. 188 ff.

ff.).

PROPS. 30-36]

NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS

411

part Spinoza deals with a problem which he has already dealt with before in the Scholium to Proposition XVII, but he restates it here in a different form. On

In the

first

the previous occasion the problem was presented by him in the form of a question as to whether God has produced all the things which are actually in His intellect. Here the

problem is presented by him in the form of a question as to whether God has produced all the things in as high a degree of perfection as they are actually in His intellect. In a some-

what

similar

physica: could be given He necessarily diminished His own power." Both these phases of the problem, however, are combined by
'

way "If God

the problem is stated in the Cogitata Metacreated a duration so great that no greater

says: "But now, again, there is the controversy whether, namely, of all that is in His idea, and which He can realize so perfectly, whether, I

him

into one in the Short Treatise

when he

say, He could omit to realize anything, and whether such an omission would be a perfection in Him/' 2 In the passage from Herrera, which I have quoted as the literary back-

ground of Spinoza's discussion

in the

XVII, 3

it

may

also be noticed that the

Scholium to Proposition two phases of the prob-

Not only does Herrera say that only a those things which are in the intellect of limited God have been produced by Him, but he also maintains that
lem are combined.

number of

number of things produced are not of the highest of perfection, for God, according to him, can still prodegree duce things of higher perfection. In his argument in the first
this limited

part of the Scholium here Spinoza repeats in the main the arguments employed by him in the first part of the Scholium
to Proposition

XVII; he only changes


2

for perfection. His opponents say, he argues here, that


1

the term omnipotence if the


I, 4,

Cogitata Metaphysica, II, 10. Cf. above, pp. 314 ff.

Short Treatise,

3.

4 I2

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

things produced by God are of the highest perfection, then God could no longer produce things which are more perfect,

and if He could not do so, it would be an imperfection in Him. As against this Spinoza contends, in effect, that, quite the contrary, it is the perfection of God that must lead one to
say that the things already produced by Him are of the highest perfection, for if He could have produced more perfect
things and did not produce them, then His failure to produce them would have to be accounted for by some imperfection in

His nature, the imperfection either of incompetency or of

A similar argument is put in the mouth of Aristotle Maimonides in the following passage: "For, according by to this theory, God, whom every thinking person recognizes to be endowed with all the kinds of perfections, is in such a relation to the existing beings that He cannot change in them
ill-will.

anything.
will

make any change, and

Aristotle says that God does not try to that it is impossible that He should

anything to be otherwise from what it is. If it were possible, it would not constitute in Him greater perfection; it
might, on the contrary, from some point of view, be an
'

imperfection." In the second part of the Scholium here Spinoza takes up again the main proposition, namely, "that things could be

created in no other
it

against his

mode or order by Him," and tries to prove opponents from their own admission "that
God's essence." Now, the main point
his
in this

will pertains to

premise admitted by
as
its

opponents,

if

we take Maimonides
is

chief exponent, is that while the will of God eternal with God, the world is not eternal, for will

coits

by

very nature means the ability to will to do a thing at one time and not to will to do it at another time, 2 and to adopt
1

Moreh Nebukim^
11.

II, 22.

Cf. Bruno,

De
3

I'infnito univcrso et
Ibid., II, 18.

Mondi

Dial. I,

p. 317,

I ff.

(cd.

Lagardc).

PROPS. 30-36]

NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS

413

one course or the other by an act of decree or decision; but, they contend, inasmuch as in the case of God the decree or
decision
it

is

entirely independent of anything external to

Him,

does not produce any change in His essence.

Spinoza raises the following question: (decretumY of God to make things in the manner and order in which they are, when did it take place? There are three
this

against This decree

As

possible assumptions:
before the things

(i) It

could have taken place shortly

were produced by God. (2) It could have co-existed with God from eternity, without any possibility
its

being changed even by the will of God. (3) It could have co-existed with God from eternity, but with the possiof

being subject to change by the will of God prior His having produced the things. Spinoza, in the course of his discussion, examines all these three assumptions and
bility of its

to

tries to

show

either that they are untenable or that they


set

prove just the opposite of what his opponents have


to prove.

out

begin with, the first assumption is untenable even according to the mediaevals themselves, for, according to Maimonides and others, prior to creation there was no time;

To

what there was then may be or, if you choose, eternity,


2

called an "imagination of
in

time"

which there

is

no

before nor

after. Spinoza thus says: "But since in eternity there is no when nor before nor after, it follows God that
.

had not existed before His decrees, and could never


without them."
3

exist

Then, proceeds Spinoza, if the second assumption be true, it will prove his own contention against his opponents.
1

Hebrew and Arabic


III, 17).
'

equivalent:

n"VH

J-Vi,

U**.

(Cnzari, V, 19;

March

Nebukim,
J
J

I^ariniy
Ethics,
I,

Cf. above, p. 339. II, 18. Prop. 33, Schol. 2 (Opera, II, p. 75,

11.

12-15).

4 i4
If things

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


it

[ETHICS,

which

have come into existence exactly in the manner in had been decreed by God from eternity and if God
"

could not have changed that decree, then things could have been produced by God in no other manner and in no other

This order than that in which they have been produced/' to reflect the second assumption, it may be remarked, seems
following statement in Heereboord:
"

What God

does in time

But Spinoza seems to differ has decreed from eternity." from Heereboord as to the meaning of this statement. According to Heereboord, this statement does not mean that "God accomplishes things in time in the order in which He
has decreed them from eternity"; 3 it only means that "God produces in time the things which He has decreed from
as He has decreed to produce According to Spinoza, the order as well as the nature of things has been decreed from eternity. In Proposition

He

eternity

and He produces them

them."

XXXIII

he speaks of the unchangeability of the manner (modus) and order (ordo) in which things have been produced, and in Scholium II, evidently in direct opposition to Heereboord, he speaks of both the nature of things (rerum naturd) and their order (ordo) 5 as having been decreed by God from

eternity.

There

is

nothing

left

therefore for his opponents but to

adopt the third assumption, namely, that God himself could have changed His eternal decree prior to the creation of
the world so that the world could have been created other-

wise than the


1

way

it

had been decreed from

eternity.

As

Ibid., II, Prop. 33. Meletemata Philosophica, Disptitationcs ex Philosophia ^e/ectaf, Vol. XXIV, ix: "Uti quid Deus facit in tempore, ita ab aeterno decrevit."
2

II,

Disp.

J
4

Ibid.-.

"Quo

Ibid.:

"Quas
facit."

ordine res Deus decrevit ab aeterno, eo in tempore exequitur." res decrevit ab aeterno et quales decrevit faccre, eas et tales
16-17, 20.

in

tempore
3

Optra,

II, p. 75,

II.

PROPS. 30-36]

NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS


raises four objections, which, it

415

against this, Spinoza


selves.

must

be said, have not passed unnoticed by the mediaevals themFirst,


it

implies that prior to creation there could have

been a change in God's will and hence also in His intellect with which His will is identical. Maimonides himself has
discussed this problem and admits that such a change in
will is possible inasmuch as it is not determined by external cause. 1 any Second, if such a change in God's will was possible before creation, why should it not be possible now after creation?

God's

Here, too, Maimonides would say that if God willed it and if it served any purpose He could change the order of nature even after its creation, except in things which are impossible

by

their

own nature and would


2

involve a contradiction in

their definition.

Third, Maimonides as well as


"
that

all

God
is

is

an

intellect

which always

other philosophers agrees is in action, and that


3

But to say that potentiality at all." God changes His will or intellect implies a change from potentiality to actuality, which is contrary to their own premthere
in
ise.

Him no

who

This argument, too, has been discussed by Maimonides, tries to show that in an incorporeal agent a change from non-action to action does not imply a transition from

potentiality to actuality. taken as an illustration.

"The ... It

active intellect
is

may

be

an evident fact that


.

the active intellect does not act continually

and yet

Aristotle does not say that the active intellect is changeable, or passes from a state of potentiality to that of actuality,

although
1

it

produces at one time something which


II, 18.

it

has not

Moreh Ncbukim,
Ibid., It, 19;

Cf. above, pp. 101

ff.

III, 25.

Cf. above, p. 312.

'

Ibid., I, 68.

Cf. above, p. 239.

4l 6

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


x

[ETHICS,

In fact, Spinoza himself makes use of produced before." this statement of Maimonides in the Short Treatise. "Furthermore, of such an agent who acts in himself it can never
is

be said that he has the imperfection of a patient, because he not affected by another; such, for instance, is the case
2

with the intellect/'

Fourth, Maimonides and

all

the other mediaevals admit

that God's will and intellect are identical with His essence. 3

To

say therefore that His will could change would imply


This, too,
is

that His essence could also change.

answered

by Maimonides. "Similarly it has been shown by us that if a being [like God] acted at one time and did not act at another, this would not involve a change in the being itself." 4
In the third part of the Scholium Spinoza combines all the three phases of the problem and asserts (i) that "things
order," (2) that
intellect,"

could have been produced by God in no other manner or God created "all things which are in His

and (3) that the things created were created "with the same perfection as that in which they exist in His intellect." All these three principles are included in what Spinoza
calls necessity, by which he means that things cannot be otherwise than what they are, that they cannot be more than they are, and that they cannot be more perfect than

are in opposition to of necessity are divided by conception Spinoza into two classes. The first class is characterized by him as the view which makes everything dependent upon " the will of God

they

are.

The mediaeval views which

this

alone" (Dei tantum voluntas) or upon "a certain indifferent

God's will" (indiferens quaedam Dei voluntas) or upon God's

"good pleasure"
1

(ipsius beneplacitum).
Method.

According to

this

Ibid., II,
1
3

8, First

Short Treatise,

I, 2,

Moreh Ncbukim,
Ibid., II,
1

I,

24 (Opera, I, p. 26, 11. 23-26). 53 and 68. Cf. above, pp. 155, 317, 402.

8,

Second Method.

PROPS. 30-36]

NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS

417

view not only are things in themselves neither perfect nor imperfect, but they are also neither good nor evil. They are so only by the will of God alone, and therefore if God had
willed
is

He could have made them otherwise. The

second class
1

characterized by him as the view of those "who affirm that God does everything for the sake of the good/ Spinoza's characterization of these two mediaeval views reflects again

Maimonides' discussion of the difference between the view


of the

Mohammedan

to the Ashariya everything

Ashariya and his own view. According is the result of God's will alone;
it is

and two views wisdom. The essential difference between these is the question whether the things created by God and the commandments revealed by Him are the work of an arbitrary will of whether they are created and revealed for the sake of some purpose. "Purpose" is another word used by Maiaccording to Maimonides,
the result of both will
1

for what Spinoza calls here "the good/' for, as says Maimonides, "we call 'good' that which is in accordance with the object we seek." 2 Similarly Heereboord says that

monides

"the good is the formal reason of the final cause." 3 All " that these go back to Aristotle's definition of the good as

which

all

4 things aim at."

In Maimonides'

own words

the

Asharian view

is

de-

scribed as the view of those thinkers

"who assume

that

God

does not produce one thing for the sake of another, that there are no causes and effects, but that all His actions are
the direct result of the will of God, and no purpose can be for them, nor can it be asked why He has made this
for He does what pleases Him, and it is not to be considered as the result of some kind of wisdom." s
* *

found

and not that;

Ibid., Ill, 25 and 26. Ibid., Ill, 13. Meletemata Philosophica, Disputationes ex Philosophia Stlectae, Vol. XXIII, ii: "Bonitas ergo formalis ratio est causae finalis."
*

II,

Disp.

Nicomachean Ethics,

I, I,

iO94a, 3.

Moreh Nebukim,

III, 25.

41 8

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


is

[ETHICS,

His own view

which

God

wills to

described by him as follows: "The things do are necessarily done; there is nothing

that could prevent the realization of His will. God, however, wills only that which is possible; not indeed everything
that
is

possible, but only such things as


l

His wisdom decrees

upon." only question to be asked," says Maimonides in another place, "is this: What is the cause of this design?

"The

The answer
a purpose

to this question
is

is

that

all this
2

has been

made

for

which

unknown

to us."

In criticizing both these views, Spinoza dismisses the first one by summarizing his previous contention that a change in God's will is unthinkable. Still, though he is opposed to
this view, he considers
it

nevertheless "at a less distance

from the truth" than the second view, which he proceeds to refute in the following statement. "For these seem to place
something outside of God which is independent of Him, to which He looks while He is at work as to a model, or at which He aims as if at a certain mark. This is indeed nothing else than to subject God to fate, the most absurd thing which can be affirmed of Him. Therefore it is not
. . .

worth while that


surdity."

should waste time in refuting this ab-

There
it

is

seems to

more hidden away in this statement than what convey to the mind of the casual reader. We may

all its implications by making Spinoza address Maimonides directly and speak out all that was in the back of his mind when he gave utterance to this statement. Spinoza seems to address Maimonides as follows: You say that things do not depend upon an arbitrary will

try to unfold

of

God

but upon a rational

will,

which you

call

wisdom, so

that everything created by is guided by a purpose or


1

God
*

has a purpose. God, then, His Wisdom, the nature of by


Ibid., II, 19.

Ibid.

PROPS. 30-36]

NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS


is

419
is

which you say

unknown

to us, but

which you maintain

not external to Him.

It is well for

you

to seek refuge out of

But those predecessors of the rabbis, aye, and the philosophers, too, whose trayours, ditional teachings, from which you refuse to depart, are responsible for
to
all

the difficulties into which your leads you by pleading ignorance.

own philosophy

so often

know what
all

your philosophical difficulties, did confess that divine Wisdom was and the purpose for

which

things were created. They say that the Wisdom, in person in the eight chapter of the Book of Proverbs, is the Torah, or the Law of Moses, and it is the

which speaks

Torah which is regarded by them as the purpose for which the world was created. Furthermore, this Torah, though
1

not considered in Judaism to be eternal, existed, according to its beliefs, before the creation of the world, and it is said that

God

consulted

it

2 as to the creation of the world,

and that

it

model according to which the world was created; as the rabbis say: "God looked into the Torah " and created the world. 3 Not only your rabbis but also
served
as a sort of
in the

Him

your philosopher Philo speaks of Wisdom and of the Logos same way as the rabbis speak of the Torah, namely,

you yourself insist upon Wisdom with the essence of God. But it is these identifying
course,

as divine instruments of creation. 4

Of

do not take these statements


traditional utterances about

literally.

You

Wisdom

in

the sense of the

Torah that

behind your statements that things were created for some unknown purpose and by some unreally
lie

Or Adonai

II, vi, 4,

D'DP
however,
exist."
3

1D"pri3

N7 (Pesahim

quoting as proof-text the rabbinic dictum mill 68b), which he evidently takes to mean "but for

the Torah, heaven and earth would not have come into existence." The dictum, may mean "but for the Torah, heaven and earth would not continue to
*

Pirke de-Rabbi Eliezer, Ch.


Sit y

3.

and parallels. De Eo: Quis Rerum Divinarum Herts


Genesis Kabbah,
I, i,

XLI,

199;

De Cherubim

et

Flam-

meo Gladio y

XXXV,

ii4.fi.

Cf.

Drummond,

Philo Judaeus, II, pp. 205-206.

4 20

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


divine wisdom.

[ETHICS,

Stripped of this metaphysical garb with which you have clothed these ancient utterances, your own statements "seem to place something outside of God
is independent of Him, to which He looks while He work as to a model, or at which He aims as if at a certain mark/* But furthermore, Spinoza seems to say to Maimonides, if the Torah is that which God consulted and by which God was guided in creating things, then your God is governed by a Torah or Wisdom or Logos just as some philosophers,

known

which
is

at

say the Stoics, maintain that the world is governed by fate (fatum, 17 cijuapjLte^r/). "This indeed is nothing else than
to subject

God
in
it.

to fate."

statement

intelligible

makes Spinoza's enough. But there may be even more


This by
itself

than that

the universe. 1

Stoics speak of fate as the Logos of Similarly Philo refers to the Logos as that
call

The

"which most men


therefore

fortune (rux??),"

fortune probably

3 being here an interchangeable term with fate.

What Spinoza

would seem to say to Maimonides is this: Since the Stoic and the Philonic Logos, which is sometimes used
as the equivalent of
is
is

when God
Logos,
nella

or your Torah, is called fate, said to be ruled by the Torah or Wisdom or the
really said to be ruled

Wisdom

He

combines the terms

"

by fate. In fact Campa" " " wisdom and fate when he

speaks of the maintenance of things by the power of


necessity, by His wisdom or fate
(faturri),

God

or

and

finally

by His

love or ordinance. 4
1

Cf. Zeller, Philosophic der Griechen, III,


Stoics , Epicureans,

I, p.

161, n, 2 (4th ed.).

English

translation:
a
3

and

Sceptics, p. 161, n. 3.

$uod Deus

$it Immutabilis,

XXXVI,

176.
>

Vol.
4

De Augmentis Scientiarum, III, 4 (Works London, I, p. 569): "quas uno nomine Fatum aut Fortunam vocabant." Reproduced by Erdmann, Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie, I,
Cf. Francis Bacon,

1857,

246.

4,

based upon Campanella's Philosophia Universality VI, Proem.

PROPS. 30-36]

NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS

421

Spinoza would not shrink from the use of the term " "fate in its strictly Stoic sense of a universal and inscrutable law that governs
6,
all

Now

things.

In fact in Short Treatise^

I,

he practically uses the term "fate" when he describes the contents of the chapter in which he denies the existence of any

by the title "On Divine Predestination." But what he insists upon saying here is that while all things and all actions, in so far as they follow with inevitable necesaccidental things
sity

from the nature of God,


fatalistic necessity,

have a

may be said in a certain sense to God himself must be conceived

and as not being subject to any fate. This was difficult to be grasped by his corand on several occasions in letters to Ostens respondents, and Oldenburg Spinoza felt called upon to explain himself. To quote a few characteristic passages from these letters:
as absolutely free

distinction evidently

"The

basis of his

away God's
tirely false.

argument is this, that he thinks that liberty, and subject Him to fate. This For I assert that all things follow with

take
en-

is

inevi-

table necessity from the nature of God, just as all assert that it follows from the nature of God that He understands himself."
I

Again: "I want to explain here briefly in what sense maintain the fatalistic necessity of all things and of all
*

For I do in no way subject God to fate, but I conceive that evervthing follows with inevitable necessity from the nature of God, just as all conceive that it follows from
actions.

the nature of
self."
*

God

himself that

He

should understand him-

which do not pertain to God, power, as we have already pointed out, is admitted by Spinoza to pertain to the essence of God and to be identical with His essence. Hence Proposition XXXIV: "The power
will,

Unlike intellect and

of
1

God

is

His essence

itself."
a

Power, as we have elsewhere


Epistola 75.

Epistola 43.

422

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


1

[ETHICS,

remarked, means to Spinoza the ability to exist and the

Hence Spinoza defines God's power here in the demonstration of the proposition as that "by which He himself and all things are and act/'
ability to bring things into existence.

identity with the essence of God Spinoza tries to solve again the problem which he has discussed in Scholium II to Proposition XVII and
its

From

this definition of

power and from

in the third part of the

Scholium to Proposition XXXIII,

namely, whether God created all things which are in His intellect. His answer is in the affirmative. Hence Proposition

XXXV:

"Whatever we conceive
In the Short

to be in

God's power

necessarily exists."

same view by saying: do what He does." 2


II.

"We

he expresses the that God cannot omit to deny


^Treatise

FINAL CAUSES

It

may

"cause"

to

be recalled that the mediaevals apply the term God in three out of its four Aristotelian senses.

God

is to them the efficient, formal, and final cause, but not the material cause, of the world. 3 In opposition to them, Spinoza made God also the material cause of the world, and

by further reducing the formal


throughout
Proposition
his discussion

XV

to the efficient cause, he has of the causality of God, from to XXXV, elaborated in great detail his

conception of the efficient causation of God. In the course of his discussion he has also refuted the views of those who,

having denied the principle of causality altogether, attributed the succession and change of things either to chance 4
or to the direct intervention of God's arbitrary will. 5 The latter view, which is discussed by him in the last part of
1

Cf. above, pp. 204-205. Cf. above, p. 302.


Cf. above, pp. 416
ff.

Short treatise,

I, 4,

I.

Cf. above, p. 318.

PROPS. 30-36]

NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS

423

Scholium

II to Proposition

XXXIII,

led

him

to touch

upon

the problem of final causation, without, however, going into a full discussion of the problem. Now, at the conclusion of the
first

Part of the Ethics, Spinoza wanted to come out with

a formal denial of the mediaeval view as to the existence of


final

But following his general custom in the propositions of the Ethics, instead of directly opposing the mediaevals, he states his own position in positive terms, but in such a manner as to contain an indirect denial of the
causes.

causes in nature. 1

commonly accepted belief in final The oppositional views in the


final

history of philosophy to

causes

may

be

the view that everything

God, which, as we

headings. First, the result of the arbitrary will of have seen, Maimonides attributes to the
is

summed up under two

Mohammedan
is

Ashariya. Second, the view that everything the result of chance and accident, which, again, Maimon2 ides attributes to the Epicureans. Spinoza, as we have seen,

has discussed both these views and rejected them. 3 The method by which he now tries in Proposition XXXVI to
reject final causes altogether
is

by reducing every

final

cause

events constantly and resucceed one another, he seems to say, it is not to peatedly be explained in terms of final causes, namely, that the first
to an efficient cause.

When two

event aims

at,

or

is

made

to serve, the second event as its

to be explained rather solely in terms of efficient causes, namely, that the second event follows by

purpose, but

it is

necessity from the nature of the

from whose method of eliminating


exists
1

event, for "nothing nature an effect does not follow/' This


first

final

causes by reducing

them

to

On

Brunner, Probleme der


(Heidelberg, 1928).
a *

the general problem of final causes in the philosophy of Spinoza, see Peter 'Tcleologic bei Maimonides y Thomas von Aquin und Spinoza
Cf. above, p. 318.

Moreh Nebukim,

II, 13.
ff.

Cf. above, pp. 416

4 24
efficient

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


causes
is

[ETHICS,

already indicated in the Cogitata Metaphysica: "Second, I say that in creation no causes concur except the efficient one. I might have said that creation
x A still negates or excludes all causes except the efficient." clearer statement to the same effect occurs in the Preface

to Ethics, IV:

"A

final cause, as it is called, is nothing,

therefore,

but

human

desire.

house to live

in, in

so far as

it is

Therefore, having a considered a final cause, is


.

merely
cause/'

this particular desire,


2

which

is

really

an

efficient

This

in fact is

Aristotle's

own

nothing but a logical corollary from denial of design and purpose in God's causal-

ity, which Spinoza seems to be stressing in this proposition against Aristotle. For Aristotle, though he denies design

and purpose

in the causality of

God,

still

maintains that

there are final causes in nature, a logical inconsistency which Maimonides makes much of in his defence of the belief in
creation. 3

Thus both Maimonides and Spinoza


to

see the in-

attempt uphold the existence of final causes in nature while denying at the same time the
consistency in Aristotle's
existence of design in God, but as they are in disagreement as to which of these two premises is correct, they arrive at

two diametrically opposite conclusions.

Maimonides

starts

with the Aristotelian premise that there are final causes in nature and therefore argues, as against Aristotle, that there must be design in the causality of God. Spinoza, on the other

hand, starts with the Aristotelian premise that there


design in the causality of

is

no

therefore argues, also against Aristotle, that there cannot be final causes in nature. This denial of final causes by Spinoza re-echoes, on the

God and

whole, Francis Bacon's condemnation of the search of final


1

Cogitata Metaphysica y II, 10.

Opera,
3

II, p. 207,

11.

Moreh Nebukim,

II,

2-4 and 9-11. 20 ff.

APPENDIX]

NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS

425

1 causes in the realm of physics. But unlike Bacon, who ad" mits that final causes are true and worthy to be inquired in 2 metaphysical speculations'* and that they are perfectly com-

patible with efficient or physical causes, "except that one declares an intention, the other a consequence only," 3 Spinoza eliminates them even from metaphysical speculations.
If this
is

Appendix

to Part I,
is,

the meaning of the last proposition, then the which deals exclusively with the problem

with the exception of the introductory a scholium to the last proposition of paragraph, really Part I. In the Appendix, Spinoza starts out with a restateof final causes,

which men commonly suppose" with regard to The passage which follows falls into two parts and betrays the influence of two different sources. The first part restates the view of those who hold "that all things in nature, like men, work for (propter) some end; and indeed

ment of that
final causes.

"

it

thought to be certain that God himself directs all things to some sure end (ad cerium aliquem finem)" The
is

immediate source of this view is the following passage in Heereboord: "All natural things work for (propter) some end,
or, rather,

by God

they work to some end, since they are directed to an end pre-determined for each thing (ad finem
4

The second part of the passage adds singulis praefixum)." " for it is said that God has made all things for man, and man
worship God." The immediate source of this statement seems to be a combination of the following pasthat he

may

sages in Saadia and Maimonides.


as follows:
1

"Should

it

Saadia's passage reads occur to one to ask for what reason

Df Augmentis
Ibid., Ill, 4

Scientiarum, III, 4.
I,

(Works, London, 1857, Vol.

p. 570; Vol. IV, p. 364).

Ibid.
4

XXIV,

Melctemata Philosophica^ Disputationcs ex Philosophia Selectae, Vol. II, Disp. i: "Res omnes naturales agunt propter finem, aut potius agunturad II,

finem, quatenus a

Deo

diriguntur ad finem singulis praefixum."

426
did
.
.

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


God
.

[ETHICS,

create

The

these things, three answers may be given. third answer is that He created the beings for their
all

own

direct them in that benefit and In another place Saadia states Him/' they might worship " that although we observe that the created beings are many the end of all of them is man/'- Maimonides' passage,

benefit so that

He might
l

which there seems to be an allusion to the statements quoted from Saadia, reads as follows: "But of those who
in

accept our theory that the whole universe has been created from nothing, some hold that the inquiry after the purpose
is necessary, and assume that the universe was created for the sake of man's existence, that he might only 3 It must, however, be remarked that, conworship God."

of creation

trary to what may be inferred from Spinoza's statement here, neither Saadia nor Maimonides is in the least dog-

matic about this view.


exists for the

Maimonides
for

definitely rejects the

view that the universe exists

man's sake and that

man

own

purpose of worshipping God, and gives as his view that "we must in continuing the inquiry as to the

purpose of creation at last arrive at the answer that it was the will of God or that His wisdom decreed it." 4 Even Saadia
gives as his first answer to the question as to the purpose of " creation the view that God created things for no purpose at
all

...

for
5

God

is

above any consideration of external

purpose."

Spinoza's own discussion of the problem is divided by himself into three parts. First, how man came to the idea

of final causes.
final causes.

Second, arguments against the existence of Third, certain erroneous conceptions to which
rise.

the idea of final causes gave


1

Emunot wf-De'ot, I, 4. March Nebuktm, III, 13. Emunot we-De'ot, I, 4.

Ibid.> IV, Introduction.

Ibid.

APPENDIX]

NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS


final

427

In his account of the origin of the belief in

causes

and

his explanation of the question

"why

all

are so naturally

inclined to

embrace it," Spinoza does nothing more than transform the reasons which his predecessors had used as
for the existence of final causes into

arguments
so-called

motives for

their belief in final causes.

He

seems to say to them: Your

arguments

for the existence of final causes are

nothing but the expressions of your desires and wishes which you put in the form of logical arguments. Or to put it in other words, Spinoza tries to show that what the mediaevals call reasons are only different forms of rationalization.

Take

the conception of final causes in

human

actions,

Spinoza seems to argue, and you will find that even there, where final causes are generally assumed to exist beyond

any shadow of a doubt, their existence may be questioned. For what basis is there for this general belief that man does
everything for an end, if not the belief that man is free to choose from two alternatives that which is profitable to him.

Let us then consider what

is

meant by

this

freedom of choice.

The

best description, Spinoza would seem to argue, is to be found in Saadia, who says that it is a matter of common ob-

servation that

seize or set loose,

that he can speak or remain silent, this without being conscious of any and "r force that could restrain him from carrying out his desire.
feels
all

"man

is that feeling of being able to choose without conscious of any compulsion to make the choice. being This choice, furthermore, is supposed to be made in considera-

Freedom then

end which man has in view, and it is this of an end which is generally taken to establish supposition the existence of final causes in human action. But, says
tion of a certain

Spinoza,
1

is it

not possible that the consciousness of freedom

ibid., IV, 4 .

428
is

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

only a delusion based upon the ignorance of the true causes that really determine one's action, and therefore the
belief that also a delusion based

one acts for a certain purpose or final cause is upon an ignorance of the real causes,

which are always efficient causes, that really necessitate one's action? "It will be sufficient/' says Spinoza, "if I take here
as an

that

man

axiom that which no one ought to dispute, namely, is born ignorant of the causes of things, and that he

has a desire, of which he is conscious, to seek that which is profitable to him. From this it follows, firstly, that he thinks
himself free and, secondly, it follows that man does everything for an end." It must, however, be remarked that Spinoza had been anticipated by Crescas in the suggestion that the conscious. . .

ness of freedom

may

be a delusion.

ment

for

freedom from the fact that

In discussing the arguman is not conscious

of any compulsion in making a decision, Crescas says that in making a choice, is unconscious of "though man,

any

compulsion and restraint, it is quite possible that, were it not for some cause that compels him to choose one of the
alternatives, he

would

desire both alternatives alike."

Spinoza continues with the same method of argument with which he had started. Taking the traditional
philo-

sophic evidences for design in nature from which the mediaevals tried to prove creation and the existence of an intelligent

them into psychological motives which have induced man to attribute the delusions of his own freedom and of the purposiveness of his own actions to nature
deity, he transforms

and God. The traditional philosophic view is summed up by Maimonides in the following passage: "Aristotle repeat2 edly says that nature produces nothing in vain, that
1

is

to

Or Adonai,

II, v, 3.

Dt

Caelo,

I,

4, 2713, 33;

De Anima,

III, 9, 432*), 21.

APPENDIX]

NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS

429

say, every natural action must necessarily have a certain object. Thus, Aristotle says that plants were created for

the sake of animals; and similarly he shows in the case of some other things that one exists for the sake of the other. This is still more obvious in the case of the organs of animals.

Know

that the existence of such a final cause in the various

parts of nature has compelled philosophers to assume the existence of a primal cause apart from nature, namely, that which Aristotle calls the intelligent or divine principle, which
divine principle creates one thing for the purpose of another. And know also that to those who acknowledge the truth,

the greatest of all arguments for the creation of the world is that which has been demonstrated with regard to natural things, namely, that every one of them has a certain purpose

and that one thing

exists for the sake of another."

All this,

says Spinoza, is simply a projection of man's own purposes into the actions of other human beings and into nature, for

"by
and

" necessarily judges that of another thus also "it comes to pass that all natural objects are
his

own mind he
as

considered

means

for

Furthermore, since
as

man

obtaining what is profitable." has falsely considered these things

some end, he thought "it was impossible to had created themselves," and so again by an analogy of his own experience he inferred "that some ruler or rulers of nature exist, endowed with human liberty, who have taken care of all things for him, and have made all

means

to

believe that they

things for his use."

The

allusions in this passage to the pas-

sages quoted from Maimonides are quite apparent. Spinoza finally concludes his argument with a condemnation of the

by Maimonides, namely, that "nature does nothing in vain," as an attempt to show "that nature, the gods, and man are alike mad."
Aristotelian principle quoted
x

Moreh Ncbukim,

III, 13.

430

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA

[ETHICS,

naturally expect that in discussing design in nature Spinoza would resuscitate the old problem of evil

One would

which philosophers before him had found at variance with the assumption of design and providence in nature. Spinoza introduces this problem with an enumeration of the so-called
physical evils which are similarly discussed by Maimonides 1 in connection with the problem of final causes and design, 2 and in connection with the problem of divine knowledge. " The evils which Spinoza happens to mention, storms, earthquakes, diseases/' are reminiscent of the list of evils
arise

earthquakes, 3 But when Spinoza pretends to restorm, and lightning/' produce the mediaeval explanation of evil by saying that "it was affirmed that these things happened because the
[i.e.,
.

mentioned by Gersonides, "from the mixture

in

which are included


diseases]
.
.

evils

which

gods were angry either because of wrongs which had been inflicted on them by man, or because of sins committed in the

method of worshipping them," he does not do justice to their case. Maimonides, Gersonides, and others had more
subtle solutions for the problem of evil. This explanation that physical evil is a divine retribution

which Spinoza rightly or wrongly reproduces as the only or the chief explanation that had been advanced for the problem, leads him to revive the old quesfor

moral

evil or sin,

tion, already raised in the Bible, especially in the

Book of
religious

Job, and repeated throughout the history of Jewish


literature

the literature of other religions, namely, that our observation does not confirm the belief that physical evil is proportionate to moral evil, for "experias well as in

ence/* says Spinoza, "daily contradicted this, and showed


1

Ibid., Ill, 12.

'

Ibid., Ill, 16, end.

Milhamot Adonai, IV, 3 (pp. 160-161);

Introduction to his

Commentary

on Job.

APPENDIX]

NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS

431

infinity of examples that both the beneficial and the injurious were indiscriminately bestowed on the pious and

by an

the impious." Parallel passages in which the problem is stated in similar terms can be picked up at random in almost

any mediaeval work dealing with

this

problem.

But

I shall

quote here only the following passage from Crescas: "The great difficulty which cannot be solved completely ... is the ill-order which is believed to exist in the world from
the fact of our observation that
like the

many worthy people are dust at the feet of unworthy ones, and, in general,
why
there
is

the question

a righteous

man who

fares

badly
r

and a wicked man who fares well, a question by which prophets and philosophers have been perplexed unto this day."
solutions are offered for this problem. Maimonides, for instance, enumerates four theories, the Aristotelian, the

Many

finds that

Scriptural or his own, the Mutazilite, and the Asharian, and Job and his three friends, Eliphaz the Temanite,

Bildad the Shuite, and Zophar the Naamathite, are respec2 tively the spokesmen of these four views. Spinoza seems
to

sum up

all

the solutions of the problem in the following

general statement: "Hence it was looked upon as indisputable that the judgments of the gods far surpass our comprehension." It is quite possible that this is all that the

various solutions ultimately amount to. Strictly speaking, however, the solution mentioned here by Spinoza as typical

of

the solutions would, according to Maimonides, represent only the view of Zophar the Naamathite or of the
all

Ashariya. In the second part of the Appendix

we may

discern four

arguments
1

against final causes.


II,
ii,

Or Adonaiy IV, 2 (p. I 5 6).


3

i (p. 35b).

Cf.

Moreh Nebukim y

III, 19;

Milhamot Adonai y

Moreh Nebukim^

III, 17

and

23.

43*

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


first

[ETHICS,

two arguments seem to be directed against two statements made by Heereboord. First, "the end is prior in works in intention to the means." Second, "God
*
. .

The

a most eminent

himself
.
.

an end, not one which way God has done all things for His
for

is

outside

own sake

not that
.
. .

made

stood in need of those things which which view the scholastics explain in the

He

He
fol-

lowing manner: God has done all things for an end, not of want but of assimilation/' that is to say "in order to benefit other things which are outside himself," 2 by assimilating

them

to himself,

i.e.,

by making them

like himself.

Metaphysica> where Spinoza does not choose to enter into controversy with those "who ask

Now,

in the Cogitata

whether

God had

not determined for himself beforehand

an end for the sake of which


is

He had

created the world," he

quite willing to say that "a created object is one which presupposes for its existence nothing except God," and to

statement by the explanation that "if God had predetermined for himself some end, it evidently was

supplement

this

God by which He was

not independent of God, for there is nothing apart from influenced to action." 3 But here in
if it

the Ethics he rejects any conception of end, even

be

nothing apart from God himself. Heereboord's first statement which declares the priority of the end to the means
characterized by Spinoza as one which "altogether turns nature upside down," for it makes the things which are imis
1

XXIV,
3

Meletemata Philosophica^ Disputationts ex Philosophia Selectae y Vol. vni: "Finis est prior in intentione quam media."

II,

Disp.

non quod istis, propter se quod Scholastici enunciarunt hoc modo; Deus omnia quae fecit, indigeret fecit propter finem, non indigentiae, sed assimilationis, . ut bene aliis faciat, quae sunt extra se, rebus." Cf. Baensch's note to this passage in his translation
fecit
.
. . . .

Ibid., Disp. XXIV, vi-vn: finem, non qui extra se sit. . . .


.

"Deus

modo eminentissimo

agit propter

Deus omnia

of the Ethics.
*

Cogitata Mttaphysica, II, 10.

APPENDIX]

NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS

433

mediately produced by God to exist for the sake of things produced by Him last. The second statement is simply
dismissed by him as a verbal quibble and he insists that "if

God works to obtain an end, He necessarily seeks something of which He stands in need/' and thus "this doctrine does
away with God's perfection." The third argument deals with
the concurrence of

the scholastic theory of


is

God

(concursus Dei), of which there

an

elaborate discussion in Heereboord. 1

This theory, which is stated by Descartes in several different connecrepeatedly 2 tions, is explained in Spinoza's restatement of Descartes
to

mean

that "each single

moment God

continually creates

things as if

anew," from which it follows "that things in themselves have no power to do anything or to determine
is

themselves to any action."


cartes' principle

A similar explanation of Desgiven by Blyenbergh in a letter to Spinoza:


3

"Following your assertion, creation and preservation are one and the same thing, and God makes not things only,
but also the motions and modes of things, to continue in their own state, that is, concurs in them." From this Blyenbergh infers "that nothing can happen against the will of in the Ethics he illustrates the theory of concurrence by the following example: "For, by way of example, if a stone has fallen from some roof on somebody's

God." 4 Here

head and
did not
so
1

killed

him, they

will

demonstrate
kill

in this

manner
For
if it

that the stone has fallen in order to


fall for

the man.

that purpose by the will of God,

how

could

many

circumstances concur through chance (and a

numDisps.

Meletemata Philosophica> Disputationes ex Philosophia Sclcctae^ Vol.

I,

VI1-XII.
a Principia Philosophiac, II, 36. For other references to Descartes and parallel passages in scholastic authors, see Gilson, Index Schofastico-Carttsicn, 81, and cf. IIO-II2.

Cogitata Mctaphysica, II, 11.

Epistola 20.

434

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


1

[ETHICS,

He concludes by her often simultaneously do concur)?" characterizing the exponents of this view in the following words: "And so they all fly to God, the refuge for ignorance/'
a

similar description of the Asharian view that

every occurrence is determined by the direct intervention of God's absolute will is given by Maimonides in the following passages: "For example, when a storm or gale blows, it causes undoubtedly some leaves of a tree to drop, breaks off some branches of another tree, tears away a stone from a

heap of stones,
stirs

them, and up the sea so that a ship goes down with the whole or
raises dust over herbs spoils

and

3 Now the Mohammedan Ashariya part of her contents." "admit that Aristotle is correct in assuming one and the same

cause [the wind] for the fall of leaves [from the tree] and for the death of a man [drowned in the sea]. But they hold at the same time that the wind did not blow by chance; it is

God

that caused

it

to

move;
fall;

it

is

not therefore the wind


fell

that caused the leaves to

each leaf
caused
it

according to

the divine decree;

it is

God who

to fall at a certain

time and in a certain place; it could not have fallen before or after that time or in another place, as this had previously

been decreed."

fourth argument 5 is directed against the alleged evidence of design that may be discerned in the structure of the

The

yet more easily comprehend that the world was given by the immortal gods to men, if we examine thoroughly into the structure of the body and the form and
perfection of
1

human body. "But we may

Cicero makes use of this sort of evidence.

human
1.

nature."
1.

Among
a

the several examples


11.

Opera,
3

II, p. 80,

35~p. 81,

2.

Ibid., p. 81,

10-11.

Moreh Nebukim,
Ibid.,

III, 17,

Second Theory.

Third Theory.
II, p. 81,
11.

Opera,

ff.

De Natura Deorum,

II, 54,

133.

APPENDIX]

NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS

435

which indicate design in the structure of the human body he mentions the delicate structure of the eye, which he deThe same evidence is used also by scribes in some detail.
1

Maimonides. Like Cicero, he

illustrates

it

by a description

of the structure of the eye, and then concludes: "In short, considering the humor of the eye, its membranes and nerves,

with their well-known functions, and their adaptation to the purpose of sight, can any intelligent person imagine that all
this is

to our

due to chance? Certainly not view the result of the action of an


.

but

is

according
2

intelligent being/'

Spinoza's answer to this alleged evidence of design is that it is based on ignorance, for "when they behold the structure

they are amazed; and because they are of the causes of such art, they conclude that the ignorant body was made not by mechanical but by divine or superof the
natural art/'

human body,

Note the

difference between

Maimonides'

passage and Spinoza's passage

in the choice of an oppositional

term to "intelligent being" or "divine art." In Maimonides the oppositional term is "chance," i.e., without any cause;
in

Spinoza

it

is

"mechanical art,"

i.e.,

necessary efficient

Maimonides, however, was not ignorant of "mechanical art" as a possible alternative for "chance" in opcausation.
position to "intelligent being," for between his premise that the structure of the eye could not be the work of chance and
his conclusion that
it

must be the work of an


"

intelligent

agent he inserts the statements that this is an artistic organ" " ization and that nature has no intelligence and no organizing faculty, as has been accepted by all philosophers," and it is in consequence of this that we must assume that it is

the

work of an

intelligent

agent.

maintains that the


'

artistic organization

In short, Maimonides of the structure of

Ibid., II, 57,


a

142.
III, 19.

Moreh Nebukim,

436

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


"

[ETHICS,

chance the eye eliminates not only the assumption of of a "mechanical art/' and points but also the assumption
to a "divine art" as its only possible explanation. In the third part of the Appendix Spinoza shows how from

"

the conception of final causes and from the belief that all things are made for man there has been formed the conception of good, evil, order, confusion, heat, cold, beauty, and deformity. Here, too, Spinoza is transforming a statement

used by those
into an

who

believe in the existence of final causes

argument against them. The statement which must have given rise to Spinoza's argument here is found in Heereboord. He says: "The end produces the means; not only

does it produce them, but it also endows them with goodness, l In his criticism of this statement measure, and order/'

Spinoza

is

evil in all their variety of

trying to establish the principle that good and forms are only relative to man

"they do not reveal the nature of anything in itself, but only the constitution of the imagination." This is not an especially new view. Maimonides has fully developed it, and the following are a few characteristic expressions used by him:
All "Evils are evils only in relation to a certain thing. evils are privations. ... It cannot be said of God that He
.

His works are all perfectly good." directly creates evil. In letters to Blyenbergh Spinoza uses almost the same ex. .

pressions as Maimonides: "But I for my part cannot admit for the evil in that sin and evil are something positive
. . .

it [Adam's disobedience] was no more than a privation of a more perfect state which Adam had to lose through that action." 3 "I think that I have sufficiently shown that that which gives its form to evil, error, or crimes does not con1

Meletemata Philosophica, Disputationes ex Philosophia Selectae^ Vol.

II,

Disp.

XXIII, vn: "Finis causat media, nee causat solummodo, sed dat illis bonitatem, a March Nebukim, III, 10. mensuram, et ordinem."
a

Epistola 19 (Opera, IV, p. 88,

11.

10-11; p. 91,

11.

4-6).

APPENDIX]
sist

NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS


l

437

anything which expresses essence, and that thereSimifore it cannot be said that God is the cause thereof/' in Cogitata Metaphysica he repeats the words of Mailarly
in

monides

in saying that "a thing considered in itself is called neither good nor evil, but only in respect to another being, which it helps to acquire what is desired, or the contrary/' 2

The direct influence of Maimonides upon Spinoza's treatment of evil is evident beyond any doubt in Short 'Treatise,
I, 4.

Spinoza raises there the question how it is possible for a perfect God to permit confusion to be seen everywhere in

nature. The term "confusion" reflects the expression "absence of order" used by Maimonides 3 and its similar expression "ill-order" which occurs frequently in Gersonides

and Crescas. 4 Spinoza denies that there


nature.

is

real confusion in

What we

call

confusion

certain general ideas which


perfection.

we

simply a deviation from have set up as exemplars of


is

then dismisses the existence of general ideas, referring in the course of his discussion to those who say that "God has no knowledge of particular and transient

He

which in their opinion are and concludes that "God then is the cause imperishable," Now, of, and providence over, particular things only."
things, but only of the general,

Maimonides, in a similar way, after discussing the problem whether Providence extends only to the species or also to
the individuals, 5 proceeds to say that "species and other general ideas are only things of reason, whilst everything

that exists outside the

mind

is

an individual object, or an

aggregate of individual objects. This being granted, it must be further admitted that the divine influence, which exists
1

Epistola 23.
3
y

Cogitata Metaphysica ,
1

I, 6.

MorehNebukim,ll\ 19: 1HD Tiyn, fUi^ ^ac. Milhamot Adonai> IV, 2 (p. 156); Or Adonai y II, ii, 2 (p. 35b): "ttlDH March Nebukim, III, 17.

JJV1.

438
in

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


human
species, that
is,

[ETHICS,

union with the


that

the

human

intel-

lect, is

that which exists in union with the individual intelis

lects,

to say, that
x

which emanates

in

Reuben, Simeon,

Levi, and Judah."

More

that these things of reason/' would seem to are not real things, only things draw upon Maimonides* statement "that species and other
those

"

especially, Spinoza's reference to

who

follow Aristotle/'

who "say

general ideas are only things of reason." This conception of the relativity of good and evil
in the Short Treatise

is

ex-

pressed by Spinoza that they are "entities of reason" (entia rationis) as opposed to "real entities" (entia rea/ia), for among the entities of
evil

by the statement

reason, he says, are included all relations, and "good and 2 are only relations." Here in the Ethics^ however,

Spinoza goes still further and calls good and evil "entities (entia) not of the reason (rationis) but of the imagination
"
(imaginationis)

The Appendix is concluded by Spinoza with the question "'why God has not created all men in such a manner that
3 they might be controlled by the dictates of reason alone." The question is an old one. Judah ha-Levi, for instance, puts

way: "Would it not have been better or more commensurate with divine wisdom, if all mankind had been
it

in this

4 Descartes, too, has raised it. guided in the true path?" "And, finally, I must also not complain that God concurs

with
in

me

in
I

which

forming the acts of the will, that is the judgment 5 But "I nevertheless perceive that go astray."

God
1

could easily have created


I
still

me

so that

never could

err,

although
Ibid.
2

remained

free

and endowed with a limited

Short Treatise

',

I, 10.
11.

Cf. above, pp. 161-162.

Opera,
Cuzari,

II, p. 83,
I,

26-27.
26-28).

*
s

102.

Mcditationes,

IV

(Ocuvrcs, VII, p. 60,

11.

APPENDIX]

NECESSITY AND PURPOSELESSNESS


x

439

knowledge/'
is it

Spinoza has raised the same question also

"Against all this others object: how that God, who is said to be supremely perfect, possible and the sole cause, disposer, and provider of all, nevertheless permits such confusion to be seen everywhere in nature? " 2 Also, why has He not made man so as not to be able to sin ?
in the Short Treatise:

The

question was also addressed to Spinoza in a letter by


3

Blyenbergh. Two answers to this question given by Descartes are use of by Spinoza.
First,

made

Descartes denies that acts of error and sin have any " these acts are positive existence with reference to God, for
entirely true

and good, inasmuch


is

as they

4 depend on God."

This answer
Ethics.
6

in his letter to Blyenbergh, 5

followed by Spinoza in the Short Treatise, and in the Second Part of the
"

As regards the other quote the Short Treatise: God has not made mankind so that they [objection], why should not sin, to this it may serve [as an answer], that whatever
is

To

7 only said with reference to us." Second, Descartes maintains that error and sin were made possible by God for the special purpose of adding to the per-

said about sin

is

And it is easy for me to understand that, in so far as I consider myself alone, and as if there were only myself in the world, I should have been much more perfect than I am, if God had created me so that
fection of the universe as a whole.
I

"

could never
it is

err.

Nevertheless

cannot deny that

in

some

sense

a greater perfection in the whole universe that cer-

ibid. (p. 61,11.9-11).

Short Treatise, I, 6, 6. Epistola 22 (Opera, IV, p. 142,


Meditationes,

11.

26

ff.).
11.

IV

(Oeuvres, VII, p. 60,

28-29).

Epistola 23 (Opera, IV, p. 147, 11. i ff.). Props. 33 and 35. Cf. below, Vol. II, pp.
7

in

ff.

Short Treatise,

I, 6,

8.

440

THE PHILOSOPHY OF SPINOZA


exempt from error
all

[ETHICS,

tain parts should not be

as others are than


'

that

parts should be exactly similar."


it is

This answer in

given by Descartes is not reproduced and he did not reproduce it for the self-evident by Spinoza, reason that he did not believe that anything was created by

the form in which

God
close

for

as a whole.

any purpose, even for the perfection of the universe But there is in Spinoza an answer which upon a examination appears to be only a revised form of this
Error and sin exist in the world, he because they are to contribute to the

answer of Descartes.
argues in effect, not

perfection of the whole universe but because their exclusion from the world would be contradictory to the conception of
as infinitely great and powerful. Given a God whose greatness and power are infinite, he seems to argue, such a

God

God must

be able to produce by the necessity of His nature everything conceivable, and that includes also sin. This is
the meaning of the following concluding

passage in

the

Appendix: "I give but one answer: Because to Him material was not wanting for the creation of everything, from
the highest down to the very lowest grade of perfection; or> to speak more properly, because the laws of His nature were so ample that they sufficed for the production of everything

which can be conceived by an


1

infinite intellect.
11.

"

Meditationes,

IV

(Oeuvres, VII, p. 61,


11.

17-23).

'

Opera, II, p. 83,

27-32.

You might also like