Ethics, Politics, and Types of Justice: March 2011
Ethics, Politics, and Types of Justice: March 2011
Ethics, Politics, and Types of Justice: March 2011
net/publication/263385968
CITATIONS READS
2 2,350
1 author:
Tim Murphy
32 PUBLICATIONS 138 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
All content following this page was uploaded by Tim Murphy on 20 February 2015.
A review of Michael J Sandel, Justice: What’s the Right Thing to Do? (Farrar,
Straus & Giroux, 2009) 308pp, Hbk ISBN: 978-0374180652.
‘Morality’ and ‘ethics’ are rarely distinguished but, when they are, it is sometimes
said that morality addresses the question, in the context of a set of codified norms,
‘What must I do?’, whereas ethics addresses the broader question, ‘How should I
live?’1 Even in these formulations, which are controversial and expressed differently
in different writers, it is clear that both morality and ethics refer to the domain of
individual deliberation and choice. It is always the individual who faces moral or
ethical questions such as, ‘Should I pay my taxes?’ ‘Should I have an abortion?’
‘Should I torture this prisoner?’ These questions are related to but distinguishable
from questions of political philosophy, which also involve deliberation and choice but
in which the decision-making relates to the collective affairs of the polis: Is the
taxation system just? Should there be an entitlement to choose whether or not to have
Obviously, given that individuals live in society, there is overlap and interdependence
Michael Sandel’s new book, Justice: What’s the Right Thing to Do?, is a primer
justice. The course has also spawned an interactive website and a television series.
1
See eg Roberto Toscano, ‘The Ethics of Modern Diplomacy’ in Jean-Marc Coicaud
and Daniel Warner (eds), Ethics and International Affairs: Extent and Limits (United
Nations University Press, 2001) 42, 43–44.
Given its introductory nature, it is somewhat surprising that the book does not bring
the fundamental distinction between moral and political philosophy into sharper
relief. Indeed, the book’s title—in the currently dominant Western philosophical
tradition in English at least—tends to evoke ideas of ‘social justice’, whereas the sub-
title is a question that, in ordinary English, denotes most commonly a choice facing an
about particular situations and the principles we affirm on reflection’ (28) and he
observes that when moral reflection ‘turns political’ it ‘needs some engagement with
the tumult of the city, with the arguments and incidents that roil the public mind’ (29).
defining element of political reflection, and this means that the moral experience of
appropriate social or political policy. There may even be cases where tensions or
conflicts arise between our individual and our social choices; ‘No, the taxation system
is not just but, yes, I should pay my taxes’ is a common example. Another aspect of
the distinction is that a moral question within the social domain is asked by each
following a vote among members, each member faces the individual moral question
It might be said that one benefit of Sandel’s tendency to conflate the two
domains is that it allows his considerable rhetorical skills freer range. Justice is
written in an extremely accessible style; typically, the author draws the reader in by
presenting vivid stories— often well-known ‘issues of the day’ but also fictional
refers to the trading of baseball cards between his two sons when they were young; to
$50,000 plumbing bill for the repair of a leaky toilet. Many of the examples that bring
this book to life are decidedly ethical dilemmas. Should one allow, for example, a
runaway trolley to kill five workers on a railway track, or divert it onto another track
where it would kill only one person? Other dilemmas introduced by Sandel raise
issues with a definite social or political remit. Should United States citizenship be
available for sale, for example, or should the law mandate affirmative action
programs?
One of the effects of Sandel’s blurring of the distinction between the ethical and
the political is occasionally to muddy the waters regarding precisely what type of
‘justice’ forms the subject of the book taken as a whole. Political philosophy, and in
Sandel observes that a just society distributes valued goods such as income and
wealth, duties and rights, powers and opportunities, and offices and honours, ‘in the
right way; it gives each person his or her due’, but, he notes, the ‘hard questions’
begin ‘when we ask what people are due, and why’ (19). The book’s aim, ostensibly
broadly on welfare, freedom, and virtue—and examine their responses to these ‘hard
writes, it can ‘give shape to the arguments we have, and bring moral clarity to the
to critical examination—to figure out what they think, and why’ (30). Justice
certainly succeeds, and in some ways admirably, in encouraging and facilitating this
type of reflection, but it is not neutral with regard to the three approaches. It seeks to
theories of justice based on freedom, rights and fairness; the reader is thus led
he writes, ‘I prefer a version of the third approach’ (260)—that is, theories that see
Sandel rejects utilitarian justice in brief and familiar terms: Bentham’s approach
is defective because it makes justice a matter of calculation rather than principle, and
because, ‘by trying to translate all human goods into a single, uniform measure of
value, it flattens them, and takes no account of the qualitative differences among
them’ (260); Mill’s philosophy can save utilitarianism from the charge that it reduces
everything to a crude calculus, but ‘only by invoking a moral ideal of human dignity
and personality independent of utility itself ’ (56). Theories of justice such as those of
Nozick, Kant and Rawls adopt a principled approach but ultimately, according to
Sandel’s account, they too fall down because they ‘don’t require us to question or
challenge the preferences and desires we bring to public life’ (261). This
most obviously, the fundamental orientation in Kant that one ought to act taking
account of others.
Charles Taylor and—particularly in his 1982 book, Liberalism and the Limits of
Justice2 —Sandel himself. One of the main targets of the communitarian critique was
the atomistic individualism associated with thinkers like Rawls, to whom Sandel
contractarianism because, for Sandel and the communitarians, the self is the
personhood that shapes our identity as moral agents and, as such, it cannot be
abstracted from our individual sense of values: ‘A just society can’t be achieved
society we have to reason together about the meaning of the good life ... Justice is not
only about the right way to distribute things. It is also about the right way to value
things’ (261).
of human life. Sandel remarks that for Aristotle the highest end of political
association is to cultivate the virtue of citizens and he suggests that arguments about
justice are, ‘unavoidably, arguments about the good life’ (215). Sandel’s positive
proposal is a set of themes for a ‘new politics of the common good’ (263). One theme
includes finding ‘a way to cultivate in citizens a concern for the whole, a dedication to
the common good’; he instances positively the scheme whereby students receive help
with college tuition in exchange for hours of public service and is favourably disposed
operation of for-profit prison companies and proposals to sell citizenship; these, says
Sandel, ‘may corrupt or degrade the norms that define them’ and therefore ‘we need
to ask what non-market norms we want to protect from market intrusion’ (265). He
2
Cambridge University Press.
also makes the often-overlooked point, while advancing the theme of ‘inequality,
solidarity, and civic virtue’, that focusing on the civic consequences of inequality, and
ways of reversing them, ‘might find political traction that arguments about income
Sandel is short on detail in relation to these themes, but more significant is the
deep conceptual flaw in his analysis of the common good. Like many
goal that can and should be common to everyone. In fact no social outcome—that is,
no particular configuration of the social order—is an aim or goal common to all. The
common good is best thought of as a framework that allows people to pursue their
Aristotelian tradition, the common good is simply the maintenance of peaceful and
civil society in which humans can, for the most part, live their lives in peace and
mutual respect. This sensible and realistic view of the common good is found in other
law’s function in maintaining a peaceful social order that is, perhaps surprisingly,
similar to that of St Thomas. Hobbes suggested that humans were motivated to seek
such order by the ‘Feare of Death; Desire of such things as are necessary to
commodious living; and a Hope by their means to obtain them’.3 On this view, the
desire for what allows a good life and the hope of being able to live it are the desire
3
Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, CB Macpherson (ed) (Penguin, 1968 [1651]) 188.
4
Garrett Barden and Tim Murphy, ‘Law’s Function in Leviathan and De Cive—A
Re-Appraisal of the Jurisprudence of Thomas Hobbes’ (2007) 29 Dublin University
Law Journal 231.
Sandel’s communitarianism is a substantive vision of the common good that has
strong patriotic and emotional elements, captured for example in his invocation of the
memory of Robert Kennedy and the spirit of Barack Obama’s presidential campaign
to preface his core common good argument, and by his suggestion that forms of
mandatory national service should replace the public school and the military as a ‘site
the common good’ (263–4). This theory is built in and for the discrete polis that is the
United States; indeed, the references and examples that are chosen occasionally make
Justice read more like a book about the US than about justice theory. Communitarians
have argued traditionally that the standards of justice must be found in particular
forms of communal life and tradition, but some have engaged constructively with
inter-communal and transnational justice debates. Charles Taylor, for example, in the
debate about cultural differences and human rights, proposed a cross-cultural dialogue
communal conception of virtue, is left without a viable foundation for his purportedly
In 2005 Luttrell was part of a United States Navy SEAL unit operating behind enemy
lines in Afghanistan that came across some unarmed goatherds. Luttrell and three
colleagues were faced with the dilemma as to whether or not they should kill the
5
Charles Taylor, ‘Conditions of an Unforced Consensus on Human Rights’ in Joanne
R Bauer and Daniel Bell (eds), The East Asian Challenge for Human Rights
(Cambridge University Press, 1999).
6
Marcus Luttrell, with Patrick Robinson, Lone Survivor: The Eyewitness Account of
Operation Redwing and the Lost Heroes of SEAL Team 10 (Little, Brown, 2007).
goatherds, even though they had not done anything hostile, or let them go and take the
risk that they would warn the Taliban. After one colleague abstained Luttrell cast a
deciding vote to release the goatherds. The Taliban subsequently killed all three of
team. Looking back, Luttrell suggests that he should have killed the goatherds; Sandel
finds it difficult to disagree and observes that the case for killing them is strong
but Taliban sympathizers’ (26). Sandel’s justice theory interprets this case as solely a
matter of partisan military ethics and ignores the range of political issues raised by the
very presence of United States military forces in Afghanistan; when Sandel does
consider the wars in Afghanistan and Iraq directly he does so only in the context of
In this work there are underlying assumptions about the role of ‘a strong sense
of community’ (263) in justice theory that leave no space for questions of justice
beyond borders. This may mean that Sandelian justice can be transnational only in the
limited sense of a comparative tradition, but when this shortcoming is combined with
a blurring of the divide between the ethical and the political domains, we are left with
quite a myopic as well as an ethnocentric justice theory. For example, ethics and
estrangement,7 and in his discussion of the ethics of such mediation, Robert Toscano
notes that the ‘specific profile’ of diplomacy is as ‘choice and action’ by ‘professional
7
James Der Derian, On Diplomacy: A Genealogy of Western Estrangement (Basil
Blackwell, 1987).
mediators of international otherness’.8 Sandel’s community-bound perspective leads
only to confusion regarding the role of justice in such choice and action: it would
seem to permit, for example, Margaret Thatcher to take tea with a torturer and fight
for releasing that torturer from the United Kingdom justice system because he helped
in the Falklands war. Indeed, given his perspective on the case of the Afghan
goatherds, Sandel may empathise with those who propose that state-sponsored
The management (to use that term loosely) of globalisation requires, amongst
clear and concrete visions of transnational justice.10 Justice theory can be an essential
part of such an agenda, as is evident from the approach of the Indian economist and
philosopher, Amartya Sen, whose book on justice, The Idea of Justice, was published
shortly before Justice. Sandel’s approach might be said to overlap with Sen’s—they
both take Rawls as a primary reference point from which they diverge, and Sandel’s
methodology fits with Sen’s approval of the Enlightenment tradition that sought to
advance the cause of justice rather than seek theoretical perfection—but Sen’s
8
Toscano (n 1) 44–45.
9
Noemi Gal-Or, ‘State-Sponsored Terrorism: A Mode of Diplomacy?’ (1993) 13
Journal of Conflict Studies 7–23, 19. In her discussion of the possibility of a
diplomatic regime in which limited political violence is at least tolerable, if not to
some degree legitimate, Gal-Or suggests the term ‘terrorist diplomacy’.
10
Mark Malloch-Brown, The Unfinished Global Revolution: The Limits of Nations
and The Pursuit of a New Politics (Allen Lane, 2011).
neighbourhood that is constructed by our relations with distant people ‘has pervasive
Sandel, Sen observes that the ‘global presence’ of non-Western thought is ‘often
discourse’.13
how we can understand and address issues of social or distributive injustice in the
global context. Whereas for Sandel the moral life aims at happiness, understood as ‘a
way of being’ (197) in accordance with a communal conception of virtue, Sen’s idea
capabilities that people actually enjoy. Sen’s ‘capability approach’ to economics is the
current paradigm for policy debate in human development discourse and the basis for
policy responses to famine and illiteracy are possible, he suggests, ‘even if we are
unable to identify the perfectly just’.14 One of the central motifs of The Idea of Justice
is the distinction between two classical Sanskrit words denoting justice: niti and
nyaya stands for a comprehensive concept of realised justice that is linked not to rules
or institutions but rather, in line with Sen’s thought, to ‘the world that actually
11
Amartya Sen, The Idea of Justice (Allen Lane, 2009) x.
12
Ibid, 172.
13
Ibid, xiv.
14
Ibid, 400.
emerges’.15
At the heart of The Idea of Justice is the conjoining of capability theory with the
social choice tradition associated with Borda, Condorcet and Kenneth Arrow, but Sen
accepts the ‘possible sustainability of plural and competing reasons for justice, all of
which have claims to impartiality and which nevertheless differ from—and rival—
each other’.16 Whilst acknowledging that no form of reason can settle all practical or
theoretical issues of justice, Sen insists that different and competing positions, each of
which can be well defended, can be absorbed into his justice theory. This claim will
not be accepted universally. The trading order, for example, is part of an all-
encompassing social order and its intrinsic fluidity and variability impedes the
ranking capacity of even refined versions of social choice theory. Another difficulty is
maximizers’, in the sense of choosing what seems good and preferable to us at the
time, is not what we choose to be, it is what we inescapably are. However, not all of
the theoretical consequences typically (and often lazily) associated with this latter
comprehensively the principle of pluralism in social justice theory, Sen may yet have
From the perspective of justice theory generally, there remains the shared
limitation in Sandel and Sen that they are both preoccupied unduly, and from a
15
Ibid, 20.
16
Ibid, 12.
17
Garrett Barden and Tim Murphy, Law and Justice in Community (Oxford
University Press, 2010) ch 5.
methodological point of view unsoundly, with social or distributive justice. When
Sandel states that a just society distributes goods ‘in the right way; it gives each
person his or her due’ (19), he does not remark that this description of a just society
reflects the Roman law definition of justice in Justinian’s Institutes: ‘Iustitia est
constans et perpetua voluntas ius suum cuique tribuens’—‘The virtue of justice is the
constant and enduring will to render to each what is due’. And although Sandel’s
law definition indicates, justice is itself a virtue. The Roman idea that justice is the
that does not indicate what is due to whom; what is due to whom must be discovered
this approach justice is also about ‘the right way to value things’, but such valuation
justice.
Aristotle (who, it may be argued, presupposed what later became the Roman
definition of justice) and St Thomas Aquinas (who, effectively, adopted the Roman
situation or case. The search for what is intrinsic to the situation or case discovers that
pacta sunt servanda is intrinsic to promise-making, for example, and that it is intrinsic
18
Michel Villey (1914–88) is the leading modern thinker in this tradition. For a
succinct account of the Roman invention of law understood as a method of dealing
with questions of justice, see his Le droit et les droits de l’homme (Presses
Universitaires de France, 1983) 33–35. See also Garrett Barden, Essays on a
Philosophical Interpretation of Justice: The Virtue of Justice (Mellen, 1999).
to ownership and the practice of borrowing and lending that what is borrowed ought
agreement. The fundamentals of contract law express what is naturally just, but many
agreement, in order to be a valid contract, must be written or not). The same can be
said for the rule a library lays down as to when a borrowed book must be returned: it
is natural that the book be returned, but loan periods vary from book to book and from
Sandel does not analyse (and nor does Sen) the distinction between natural and
seems to think, for example, that the scheme whereby students receive help with
college tuition in return for hours of public service is a matter of social or distributive
shortcoming of many a justice theory; in Sandel’s case its most negative effect is the
way it allows ‘ethics’, ‘politics’ and ‘the common good’ to all collapse into a vaguely
defined but partisan sense of communal ‘virtue’ that somehow represents ‘justice’.
19
For an analysis that interprets this Aristotelian classification of justice as tripartite,
see Barden and Murphy (n17) chs 4 and 5.
Overall, and despite its many flaws, Sandel’s Justice contributes to
Sandel calls for a ‘more robust public engagement with our moral disagreements’
(268), he echoes Ronald Dworkin’s concern at the absence in the US of ‘even the
beginnings of a decent public argument about [human rights, religion, and taxes,
among many other issues]’.20 Perhaps the greatest contribution Justice makes is to
encourage such a ‘robust’ public culture, such a ‘decent’ public argument, in the
self-imposed confines it encourages and facilitates dialogue about what sort of society
people want to live in. This is not a complex book, and the combination of Sandel’s
clear, accessible style and his scholarly insight will provoke, constructively and
20
Ronald Dworkin, Is Democracy Possible Here? (Princeton University Press, 2006)
127. Dworkin’s book is as ethnocentric as Sandel’s but in Dworkin’s case this is
emphasised and compounded by the dreadful title.