Lesson 10: Understanding and Responding To Moral Pluralism
Lesson 10: Understanding and Responding To Moral Pluralism
Lesson 10: Understanding and Responding To Moral Pluralism
Who is Responsible?
• Does someone have role-related responsibilities (RRR) with regard to the person or subject of moral
worth that might be harmed? If so, what are those responsibilities and how do they relate to the
causing of the harm?
• If the harm caused is not a violation of a person’s RRR, could the harm have been predicted and avoided
in achieving some legitimate goal? If the goal is not legitimate, then causing harm is rarely justified.
Some Tips for Conceptualizing and Justifying
Complete explanation of moral rule violations can be found in the works of Bernard Gert, listed on
the resources page, but here I include some tips that students unfamiliar with Gert’s work have
found helpful.
Any ethically questionable action toward a human being can be reduced to one or more of these 10
moral rule violations:
• Do not kill.
• Do not cause pain.
• Do not disable.
• Do not deprive of freedom.
• Do not deprive of pleasure.
• Do not deceive.
• Keep your promises.
• Do not cheat.
• Obey the law.
• Do your duty
Close Analysis of Deception, Cheating, and Promise-Breaking
Deception, cheating, and promise-breaking are common moral rule violations in personal, public, and professional
life. Because these are common acts and are often denied or misunderstood, complete descriptions for
conceptualization and justification of these moral rule violations follow.
• Deception
• Conceptualization
• Deception is the correct label for any action or non-action that is intended to lead others to a false conclusion.
• Paternalistic Deception is deception that is done with the intent of acting in the best interest of the person
deceived.
• Non-paternalistic Deception is deception that is not done with the intent of acting in the best interest of the
person deceived.
• Lying by speech or action is ethically questionable and requires justification. (If I dress like a physician to gain
entrance to a patient’s hospital room, I have ‘lied’ by how I dressed.)
• Failing to disclose information only sometimes counts as deception. Failing to disclose information is an act of
deception only if the failure to disclose also:
• breaks a promise, or
• cheats, or
• is illegal, or
• neglects one’s duty.
• Misleading people by using accurate statements also counts as deception as it is failing to
disclose one’s true intentions and involves cheating. It is an act of cheating because using
accurate statements to mislead violates general rules of how people use language.
• Justification
• Paternalistic Deception is justified by how likely the deceived person would be to consent to
the deception:
• If the person deceived is a rational, competent adult, it is justified only if the person gave
consent or would consent to the deception. For example, if a patient with advanced illness
requests that his doctor NOT tell him when he is likely to die, it is justified deception for the
doctor to fail to provide this information (that would otherwise be the doctor’s duty to
provide).
• If the person deceived is a child or non-competent adult, paternalistic deception is justified if it
• advances this person’s growth or autonomy, or
• protects him or her in a way that he or she would wish to be protected if it were possible for him or her to
give consent.
• Non-paternalistic Deception is justified if both of the following conditions are met:
• The harm caused by the deception is significantly less than the harm caused if the deception
does not occur, and
• The deceiver is willing to publicly advocate that deception be ethically permitted
• in all cases of this kind (even if he or she were the person deceived).
Cheating
I. Conceptualization
• Cheating is different from deception. Cheating violates rules or standards that everyone is
reasonably expected to follow. One can cheat by action or non-action. It is reasonable for my
students to expect me to show up on time to teach class. If I fail to do so, I have cheated the
students.
• It is possible to deceive without cheating and it is possible to cheat without deceiving. For
example, if I lie to Federal investigators about how I got that investment tip, I haven’t “cheated”
in telling the lie, but I’ll be likely to go to prison anyway. I have acted deceptively.
• On the other hand, if I move my ball from the sand trap to the fairway when my subordinates
are playing golf with me, I have cheated, even if everyone puts up with it because I’m the boss.
I haven’t deceived anyone, I have just taken advantage of my position in violating a standard or
rule that everyone can be reasonably expected to follow. I cheated.
II. Justification
• Cheating is justified if the following two conditions are both satisfied:
• The cheating is a public act that can be known to all involved or the cheating is a significantly smaller rule
violation than the one being prevented by the act, and
• The cheating does not involve misuse of power, objectification or exploitation of another.
Promise Breaking
I. Conceptualization
• Making a promise turns an act that is morally neutral into one that is morally required.
Promising is a performative – just the act of saying “I promise” or “I certainly will” gives
the person responsibilities that she or he didn’t have before saying those words. A
promise is binding only if the act is voluntary.
II. Justification
• Breaking a promise is justified if all of the following conditions are met:
• The harm caused by keeping the promise is greater than the harm caused by breaking the promise,
and
• The harm vs. harm balance is done with every person directly affected being
• considered and the consideration favors the most vulnerable, and
• The promise-breaker acknowledges to all parties involved that the promise is being broken and
provides reasons for that.
Life of an Ethical Person
Excuses, rationalizations, and explanations are all methods that people use to deny their moral responsibility. Even
though there might be justification for breaking a moral rule, it is necessary to admit the moral rule violation. Here
are the common ways that people deny their ethically questionable acts. They say to themselves (or others):
•As the activities in this book have shown, justifying an ethically questionable act takes careful and honest
consideration. Here’s what is wrong with these common excuses:
•Other people do it. The fact that other people do unethical things does not justify me doing the same thing. If the
action is ethically prohibited, it is wrong no matter how many people are doing it.
•(Some authority) told me to do it. Competent, rational adults cannot pass their moral responsibility off to another. I
might choose to stay in a job that requires me to act unethically, but that is an economic choice, not an ethically
sound decision.
•I didn’t intend to hurt anybody. Most of the interesting ethical issues arise when good people are trying hard to do
the right thing. The fact that causing harm was unintentional might mitigate the level of moral responsibility, but
doesn’t change the fact that harm was caused.
•No one knew that I did it. When I do something unethical, I know it. I am the person to whom knowledge of my act
matters most.
Thank You!