Module 2 Part 2
Module 2 Part 2
Module 2 Part 2
Frameworks
Immanuel Kant
Towards the end of his most influential work, Critique of Pure Reason(1781/1787), Kant argues
that all philosophy ultimately aims at answering these three questions: “What can I know? What
should I do? What may I hope?” The book appeared at the beginning of the most productive
period of his career, and by the end of his life Kant had worked out systematic, revolutionary,
and often profound answers to these questions.
At the foundation of Kant’s system is the doctrine of “transcendental idealism,” which
emphasizes a distinction between what we can experience (the natural, observable world) and
what we cannot (“supersensible” objects such as God and the soul). Kant argued that we can
only have knowledge of things we can experience. Accordingly, in answer to the question,
“What can I know?” Kant replies that we can know the natural, observable world, but we cannot,
however, have answers to many of the deepest questions of metaphysics.
Kant’s ethics are organized around the notion of a “categorical imperative,” which is a universal
ethical principle stating that one should always respect the humanity in others, and that one
should only act in accordance with rules that could hold for everyone. Kant argued that the moral
law is a truth of reason, and hence that all rational creatures are bound by the same moral law.
Thus in answer to the question, “What should I do?” Kant replies that we should act rationally, in
accordance with a universal moral law.
Kant also argued that his ethical theory requires belief in free will, God, and the immortality of
the soul. Although we cannot have knowledge of these things, reflection on the moral law leads
to a justified belief in them, which amounts to a kind rational faith. Thus in answer to the
question, “What may I hope?” Kant replies that we may hope that our souls are immortal and
that there really is a God who designed the world in accordance with principles of justice.
In addition to these three focal points, Kant also made lasting contributions to nearly all areas of
philosophy. His aesthetic theory remains influential among art critics. His theory of knowledge is
required reading for many branches of analytic philosophy. The cosmopolitanism behind his
political theory colors discourse about globalization and international relations. And some of his
scientific contributions are even considered intellectual precursors to several ideas in
contemporary cosmology.
This article presents an overview of these and other of Kant’s most important philosophical
contributions. It follows standard procedures for citing Kant’s works. Passages from Critique of
Pure Reason are cited by reference to page numbers in both the 1781 and 1787 editions. Thus
“(A805/B833)” refers to page 805 in the 1781 edition and 833 in the 1787 edition. References to
the rest of Kant’s works refer to the volume and page number of the
official Deutsche Akademie editions of Kant’s works. Thus “(5:162)” refers to volume 5, page
162 of those editions.
Table of Contents
1. Life
2. Metaphysics and Epistemology
1. Pre-Critical Thought
2. Dogmatic Slumber, Synthetic A Priori
Knowledge, and the Copernican Shift
3. The Cognitive Faculties and Their
Representations
4. Transcendental Idealism
1. The Ideality of Space and Time
2. Appearances and Things in Themselves
ii. The Deduction of the Categories
iii. Theory of Experience
iv. Critique of Transcendent Metaphysics
1. The Soul (Paralogisms of Pure Reason)
2. The World (Antinomies of Pure Reason)
3. God (Ideal of Pure Reason)
b. Philosophy of Mathematics
c. Natural Science
i. Physics
ii. Other Scientific Contributions
b. Moral Theory
i. The Good Will and Duty
ii. The Categorical Imperative
iii. Postulates of Practical Reason
b. Political Theory and Theory of Human History
i. Human History and the Age of Enlightenment
ii. Political Theory
iii. Perpetual Peace
b. Theory of Art and Beauty
i. The Beautiful and the Sublime
ii. Theory of Art
iii. Relation to Moral Theory
b. Pragmatic Anthropology
c. References and Further Reading
i. Primary Literature
ii. Secondary Literature
1. Life
Kant was born in 1724 in the Prussian city of Königsberg (now Kaliningrad in Russia). His
parents – Johann Georg and Anna Regina – were pietists. Although they raised Kant in this
tradition (an austere offshoot of Lutheranism that emphasized humility and divine grace), he
does not appear ever to have been very sympathetic to this kind of religious devotion. As a
youth, he attended the Collegium Fridericianum in Königsberg, after which he attended the
University of Königsberg. Although he initially focused his studies on the classics, philosophy
soon caught and held his attention. The rationalism of Gottfried Leibniz (1646-1716) and
Christian Wolff (1679-1754) was most influential on him during these early years, but Kant was
also introduced to Isaac Newton’s (1642-1727) writings during this time.
His mother had died in 1737, and after his father’s death in 1746 Kant left the University to work
as a private tutor for several families in the countryside around the city. He returned to the
University in 1754 to teach as a Privatdozent, which meant that he was paid directly by
individual students, rather than by the University. He supported himself in this way until 1770.
Kant published many essays and other short works during this period. He made minor scientific
contributions in astronomy, physics, and earth science, and wrote philosophical treatises
engaging with the Leibnizian-Wolffian traditions of the day (many of these are discussed below).
Kant’s primary professional goal during this period was to eventually attain the position of
Professor of Logic and Metaphysics at Königsberg. He finally succeeded in 1770 (at the age of
46) when he completed his second dissertation (the first had been published in 1755), which is
now referred to as the Inaugural Dissertation.
Commentators divide Kant’s career into the “pre-critical” period before 1770 and the “critical”
period after. After the publication of the Inaugural Dissertation, Kant published hardly anything
for more than a decade (this period is referred to as his “silent decade”). However, this was
anything but a fallow period for Kant. After discovering and being shaken by the radical
skepticism of Hume’s empiricism in the early 1770s, Kant undertook a massive project to
respond to Hume. He realized that this response would require a complete reorientation of the
most fundamental approaches to metaphysics and epistemology. Although it took much longer
than initially planned, his project came to fruition in 1781 with the publication of the first edition
of Critique of Pure Reason
The 1780s would be the most productive years of Kant’s career. In addition to writing
the Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics (1783) as a sort of introduction to the Critique,
Kant wrote important works in ethics (Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, 1785,
and Critique of Practical Reason, 1788), he applied his theoretical philosophy to Newtonian
physical theory (Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science, 1786), and he substantially
revised the Critique of Pure Reason in 1787. Kant capped the decade with the publication of the
third and final critique, Critique of the Power of Judgment (1790).
Although the products of the 1780s are the works for which Kant is best known, he continued to
publish philosophical writings through the 1790s as well. Of note during this period are Religion
within the Bounds of Mere Reason (1793), Towards Perpetual Peace (1795), Metaphysics of
Morals (1797), and Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View (1798). The Religion was
attended with some controversy, and Kant was ultimately led to promise the King of Prussia
(Friedrich Wilhelm II) not to publish anything else on religion. (Kant considered the promise
null and void after the king died in 1797.) During his final years, he devoted himself to
completing the critical project with one final bridge to physical science. Unfortunately, the
encroaching dementia of Kant’s final years prevented him from completing this book (partial
drafts are published under the title Opus Postumum).
Kant never married and there are many stories that paint him as a quirky but dour eccentric.
These stories do not do him justice. He was beloved by his friends and colleagues. He was
consistently generous to all those around him, including his servants. He was universally
considered a lively and engaging dinner guest and (later in life) host. And he was a devoted and
popular teacher throughout the five decades he spent in the classroom. Although he had hoped
for a small, private ceremony, when he died in 1804, age 79, his funeral was attended by the
thousands who wished to pay their respects to “the sage of Königsberg.”
a. Pre-Critical Thought
Critique of Pure Reason, the book that would alter the course of western philosophy, was written
by a man already far into his career. Unlike the later “critical period” Kant, the philosophical
output of the early Kant was fully enmeshed in the German rationalist tradition, which was
dominated at the time by the writings of Gottfried Leibniz (1646-1716) and Christian Wolff
(1679-1754). Nevertheless, many of Kant’s concerns during the pre-critical period anticipate
important aspects of his mature thought.
Kant’s first purely philosophical work was the New Elucidation of the First Principles of
Metaphysical Cognition (1755). The first parts of this long essay present criticisms and revisions
of the Wolffian understanding of the basic principles of metaphysics, especially the Principles of
Identity (whatever is, is, and whatever is not, is not), of Contradiction (nothing can both be and
not be), and of Sufficient Reason (nothing is true without a reason why it is true). In the final
part, Kant defends two original principles of metaphysics. According to the “Principle of
Succession,” all change in objects requires the mutual interaction of a plurality of substances.
This principle is a metaphysical analogue of Newton’s principle of action and reaction, and it
anticipates Kant’s argument in the Third Analogy of Experience from Critique of Pure
Reason (see 2f below). According to the “Principle of Coexistence,” multiple substances can
only be said to coexist within the same world if the unity of that world is grounded in the
intellect of God. Although Kant would later claim that we can never have metaphysical cognition
of this sort of relation between God and the world (not least of all because we can’t even know
that God exists), he would nonetheless continue to be occupied with the question of how multiple
distinct substances can constitute a single, unified world.
The final publication of Kant’s pre-critical period was On the Form and Principles of the
Sensible and the Intelligible World, also referred to as the Inaugural Dissertation (1770), since it
marked Kant’s appointment as Königsberg’s Professor of Logic and Metaphysics. Although
Kant had not yet had the final crucial insights that would lead to the development of
transcendental idealism, many of the important elements of his mature metaphysics are
prefigured here. Two aspects of the Inaugural Dissertation are especially worth noting. First, in
a break from his predecessors, Kant distinguishes two fundamental faculties of the mind:
sensibility, which represents the world through singular “intuitions,” and understanding, which
represents the world through general “concepts.” In the Inaugural Dissertation, Kant argues that
sensibility represents the sensible world of “phenomena” while the understanding represents an
intelligible world of “noumena.” The critical period Kant will deny that we can have any
determinate knowledge of noumena, and that knowledge of phenomena requires the cooperation
of sensibility and understanding together. Second, in describing the “form” of the sensible world,
Kant argues that space and time are “not something objective and real,” but are rather “subjective
and ideal” (2:403). The claim that space and time pertain to things only as they appear, not as
they are in themselves, will be one of the central theses of Kant’s mature transcendental
idealism.
The solution to Hume’s skepticism, which would form the basis of the critical philosophy, was
twofold. The first part of Kant’s solution was to agree with Hume that metaphysical knowledge
(such as knowledge of causation) is neither given through the senses, nor is it known a
priori through conceptual analysis. Kant argued, however, that there is a third kind of knowledge
which is a priori, yet which is not known simply by analyzing concepts. He referred to this as
“synthetic a priori knowledge.” Where analytic judgments are justified by the semantic relations
between the concepts they mention (for example, “all bachelors are unmarried”), synthetic
judgments are justified by their conformity to the given object that they describe (for example,
“this ball right here is red”). The puzzle posed by the notion of synthetic a priori knowledge is
that it would require that an object be presented to the mind, but not be given in sensory
experience.
The second part of Kant’s solution is to explain how synthetic a priori knowledge could be
possible. He describes his key insight on this matter as a “Copernican” shift in his thinking about
the epistemic relation between the mind and the world. Copernicus had realized that it
only appeared as though the sun and stars revolved around us, and that we could have
knowledge of the way the solar system really was if we took into account the fact that the sky
looks the way it does because we perceivers are moving. Analogously, Kant realized that we
must reject the belief that the way things appear corresponds to the way things are in themselves.
Furthermore, he argued that the objects of knowledge can only ever be things as they appear, not
as they are in themselves. Appealing to this new approach to metaphysics and epistemology,
Kant argued that we must investigate the most basic structures of experience (that is, the
structures of the way things appear to us), because the basic structures of experience will
coincide with the basic structures of any objects that could possibly be experienced. In other
words, if it is only possible to have experience of an object if the object conforms to the
conditions of experience, then knowing the conditions of experience will give us knowledge –
synthetic a priori knowledge in fact – of every possible object of experience. Kant overcomes
Hume’s skepticism by showing that we can have synthetic a priori knowledge of objects in
general when we take as the object of our investigation the very form of a possible object of
experience. Critique of Pure Reason is an attempt to work through all of the important details of
this basic philosophical strategy.
The most basic type of representation of understanding is the “concept.” Unlike an intuition, a
concept is a representation that refers generally to indefinitely many objects. (For instance, the
concept ‘cat’ on its own could refer to any and all cats, but not to any one in particular.)
Concepts refer to their objects only indirectly because they depend on intuitions for reference to
particular objects. As with intuitions, there are two basic types of concepts. Pure concepts are a
priori representations and they characterize the most basic logical structure of the mind. Kant
calls these concepts “categories.” Empirical concepts are a posteriori representations, and they
are formed on the basis of sensory experience with the world. Concepts are combined by the
understanding into “judgments,” which are the smallest units of knowledge. I can only have full
cognition of an object in the world once I have, first, had an empirical intuition of the object,
second, conceptualized this object in some way, and third, formed my conceptualization of the
intuited object into a judgment. This means that both sensibility and understanding must work in
cooperation for knowledge to be possible. As Kant expresses it, “Thoughts without content are
empty, intuitions without concepts are blind” (A51/B75).
There are two other important cognitive faculties that must be mentioned. The first is
transcendental “imagination,” which mediates between sensibility and understanding. Kant calls
this faculty “blind” because we do not have introspective access to its operations. Kant says that
we can at least know that it is responsible for forming intuitions in such a way that it is possible
for the understanding to apply concepts to them. The other is “reason,” which operates in a way
similar to the understanding, but which operates independently of the senses. While
understanding combines the data of the senses into judgments, reason combines understanding’s
judgments together into one coherent, unified, systematic whole. Reason is not satisfied with
mere disconnected bits of knowledge. Reason wants all knowledge to form a system of
knowledge. Reason is also the faculty responsible for the “illusions” of transcendent metaphysics
(see 2g below).
d. Transcendental Idealism
Transcendental idealism is a theory about the relation between the mind and its objects. Three
fundamental theses make up this theory: first, there is a distinction between appearances (things
as they appear) and things as they are in themselves. Second, space and time are a priori,
subjective conditions on the possibility of experience, and hence they pertain only to
appearances, not to things in themselves. Third, we can have determinate cognition of only of
things that can be experienced, hence only of appearances, not things in themselves.
A quick remark on the term “transcendental idealism” is in order. Kant typically uses the term
“transcendental” when he wants to emphasize that something is a condition on the possibility of
experience. So for instance, the chapter titled “Transcendental Analytic of Concepts” deals with
the concepts without which cognition of an object would be impossible. Kant uses the term
“idealism” to indicate that the objects of experience are mind-dependent (although the precise
sense of this mind-dependence is controversial; see 2d2 below). Hence, transcendental idealism
is the theory that it is a condition on the possibility of experience that the objects of experience
be in some sense mind-dependent.
One argument has to do with the relation between sensations and space. Kant argues that
sensations on their own are not spatial, but that they (or arguably the objects they correspond to)
are represented in space, “outside and next to one another” (A23/B34). Hence, the ability to
sense objects in space presupposes the a priori representation of space, which entails that space
is merely ideal, hence not a property of things in themselves.
Another argument that Kant makes repeatedly during the critical period can be called the
“argument from geometry.” Its two premises are, first, that the truths of geometry are necessary
truths, and thus a priori truths, and second, that the truths of geometry are synthetic (because
these truths cannot be derived from an analysis of the meanings of geometrical concepts). If
geometry, which is the study of the structure of space, is synthetic a priori, then its object –
space – must be a mere a priori representation and not something that pertains to things in
themselves. (Kant’s theory of mathematical cognition is discussed further in 3b below.)
Many commentators have found these arguments less than satisfying because they depend on the
questionable assumption that if the representations of space and time are a priori they thereby
cannot be properties of things in themselves. “Why can’t it be both?” many want to ask. A
stronger argument appears in Kant’s discussion of the First and Second Antinomies of Pure
Reason (discussed below, 2g2). There Kant argues that if space and time were things in
themselves or even properties of things in themselves, then one could prove that space and time
both are and are not infinitely large, and that matter in space both is and is not infinitely
divisible. In other words, the assumption that space and time are transcendentally real instead
of transcendentally ideal leads to a contradiction, and thus space and time must be
transcendentally ideal.
ii. Appearances and Things in Themselves
How Kant’s distinction between appearances and things in themselves should be understood is
one of the most controversial topics in the literature. It is a question of central importance
because how one understands this distinction determines how one will understand the entire
nature of Kantian idealism. The following briefly summarizes the main interpretive options, but
it does not take a stand on which is correct.
A common objection against two-world interpretations is that they may make Kant’s theory too
similar to Berkeley’s immaterialist idealism (an association from which Kant vehemently tried to
distance himself), and they seem to ignore Kant’s frequent characterization of the
appearance/thing in itself distinction in terms of different epistemic standpoints. And a common
objection against one-world interpretations is that they may trivialize some of the otherwise
revolutionary aspects of Kant’s theory, and they seem to ignore Kant’s frequent characterization
of the appearance/thing in itself distinction in seemingly metaphysical terms. There have been
attempts at interpretations that are intermediate between these two options. For instance, some
have argued that Kant only acknowledges one world, but that the appearance/thing in itself
distinction is nevertheless metaphysical, not merely epistemological.
There are twelve categories in total, and they fall into four groups of three:
The task of the chapter titled “Transcendental Deduction of the Categories” is to show that these
categories can and must be applied in some way to any object that could possibly be an object of
experience. The argument of the Transcendental Deduction is one of the most important
moments in the Critique, but it is also one of the most difficult, complex, and controversial
arguments in the book. Hence, it will not be possible to reconstruct the argument in any detail
here. Instead, Kant’s most important claims and moves in the Deduction are described.
Kant’s argument in the Deduction is a “transcendental argument”: Kant begins with a premise
accepted by everyone, but then asks what conditions must have been met in order for this
premise to be true. Kant assumed that we have a unified experience of the many objects
populating the world. This unified experience depends on the unity of apperception. The unity of
apperception enables the subject to distinguish between subjective and objective elements in
experience. This ability, in turn, depends on representing objects in accordance with rules, and
the rules in question are the categories. Hence, the only way we can explain the fact that we have
experience at all is by appeal to the fact that the categories apply to the objects of experience.
It is worth emphasizing how truly radical the conclusion of the Transcendental Deduction is.
Kant takes himself to have shown that all of nature is subject to the rules laid down by the
categories. But these categories are a priori: they originate in the mind. This means that the order
and regularity we encounter in the natural world is made possible by the mind’s own
construction of nature and its order. Thus the conclusion of the Transcendental Deduction
parallels the conclusion of the Transcendental Aesthetic: where the latter had shown that the
forms of sensibility (space and time) originate in the mind and are imposed on the world, the
former shows that the forms of understanding (the categories) also originate in the mind and are
imposed on the world.
f. Theory of Experience
The Transcendental Deduction showed that it is necessary for us to make use of the categories in
experience, but also that we are justified in making use of them. In the following series of
chapters (together labeled the Analytic of Principles) Kant attempts to leverage the results of the
Deduction and prove that there are transcendentally necessary laws that every possible object of
experience must obey. He refers to these as “principles of pure understanding.” These principles
are synthetic a priori in the sense defined above (see 2b), and they are transcendental conditions
on the possibility of experience.
The first two principles correspond to the categories of quantity and quality. First, Kant argues
that every object of experience must have a determinate spatial shape and size and a determinate
temporal duration (except mental objects, which have no spatial determinations). Second, Kant
argues that every object of experience must contain a “matter” that fills out the object’s extensive
magnitude. This matter must be describable as an “intensive magnitude.” Extensive magnitudes
are represented through the intuition of the object (the form of the representation) and intensive
magnitudes are represented by the sensations that fill out the intuition (the matter of the
representation).
The next three principles are discussed in an important, lengthy chapter called the Analogies of
Experience. They derive from the relational categories: substance, causality, and community.
According to the First Analogy, experience will always involve objects that must be represented
as substances. “Substance” here is to be understood in terms of an object that persists
permanently as a “substratum” and which is the bearer of impermanent “accidents.” According
to the Second Analogy, every event must have a cause. One event is said to be the cause of
another when the second event follows the first in accordance with a rule. And according to the
Third Analogy (which presupposes the first two), all substances stand in relations of reciprocal
interaction with each other. That is, any two pieces of material substance will effect some degree
of causal influence on each other, even if they are far apart.
The principles of the Analogies of Experience are important metaphysical principles, and if
Kant’s arguments for them are successful, they mark significant advances in the metaphysical
investigation of nature. The First Analogy is a form of the principle of the conservation of
matter: it shows that matter can never be created or annihilated by natural means, it can only be
altered. The Second Analogy is a version of the principle of sufficient reason applied to
experience (causes being sufficient reasons for their effects), and it represents Kant’s refutation
of Hume’s skepticism regarding causation. Hume had argued that we can never have knowledge
of necessary connections between events; rather, we can only perceive certain types of events to
be constantly conjoined with other types of events. In arguing that events follow each other in
accordance with rules, Kant has shown how we can have knowledge of necessary connections
between events above and beyond their mere constant conjunction. Lastly, Kant probably
intended the Third Analogy to establish a transcendental, a priori basis for something like
Newton’s law of universal gravitation, which says that no matter how far apart two objects are
they will exert some degree of gravitational influence on each other.
The Postulates of Empirical Thinking in General contains the final set of principles of pure
understanding and they derive from the modal categories (possibility, actuality, necessity). The
Postulates define the different ways to represent the modal status of objects, that is, what it is for
an object of experience to be possible, actual, or necessary.
The most important passage from the Postulates chapter is the Refutation of Idealism, which is a
refutation of external world skepticism that Kant added to the 1787 edition of the Critique. Kant
had been annoyed by reviews of the first edition that unfavorably compared his transcendental
idealism with Berkeley’s immaterialist idealism. In the Refutation, Kant argues that his system
entails not just that an external (that is, spatial) world is possible (which Berkeley denied), but
that we can know it is real (which Descartes and others questioned). Kant’s argumentative
strategy in the Refutation is ingenious but controversial. Where the skeptics assume that we have
knowledge of the states of our own minds, but say that we cannot be certain that an external
world corresponds to these states, Kant turns the tables and argues that we would not have
knowledge of the states of our own minds (specifically, the temporal order in which our ideas
occur) if we were not simultaneously aware of permanent substances in space, outside of the
mind. The precise structure of Kant’s argument, as well as the question how successful it is,
continues to be a matter of heated debate in the literature.
Kant calls the basic concepts of metaphysical inquiry “ideas.” Unlike concepts of the
understanding, which correspond to possible objects that can be given in experience, ideas are
concepts of reason, and they do not correspond to possible objects of experience. The three most
important ideas with which Kant is concerned in the Transcendental Dialectic are the soul, the
world (considered as a totality), and God. The peculiar thing about these ideas of reason is that
reason is led by its very structure to posit objects corresponding to these ideas. It cannot help but
do this because reason’s job is to unify cognitions into a systematic whole, and it finds that it
needs these ideas of the soul, the world, and God, in order to complete this systematic
unification. Kant refers to reason’s inescapable tendency to posit unexperienceable and hence
unknowable objects corresponding to these ideas as “transcendental illusion.”
Kant presents his analysis of transcendental illusion and his critique of transcendent metaphysics
in the series of chapters titled “Transcendental Dialectic,” which takes up the majority of the
second half of Critique of Pure Reason. This section summarizes Kant’s most important
arguments from the Dialectic.
Transcendental illusion in rational psychology arises when the mere thought of the I in the
proposition “I think” is mistaken for a cognition of the I as an object. (A cognition involves both
intuition and concept, while a mere thought involves only concept.) For instance, consider the
question whether we can cognize the I as a substance (that is, as a soul). On the one hand,
something is cognized as a substance when it is represented only as the subject of predication
and is never itself the predicate of some other subject. The I of “I think” is always represented as
subject (the I’s various thoughts are its predicates). On the other hand, something can only be
cognized as a substance when it is given as a persistent object in an intuition (see 2f above), and
there can be no intuition of the I itself. Hence although we cannot help but think of the I as a
substantial soul, we can never have cognition of the I as a substance, and hence knowledge of the
existence and nature of the soul is impossible.
In all four cases, Kant attempts to resolve these conflicts of reason with itself by appeal to
transcendental idealism. The claim that space and time are not features of things in themselves is
used to resolve the First and Second Antinomies. Since the empirical world in space and time is
identified with appearances, and since the world as a totality can never itself be given as a single
appearance, there is no determinate fact of the matter regarding the size of the universe: It is
neither determinately finite nor determinately infinite; rather, it is indefinitely large. Similarly,
matter has neither simplest atoms (or “monads”) nor is it infinitely divided; rather, it
is indefinitely divisible.
The distinction between appearances and things in themselves is used to resolve the Third and
Fourth Antinomies. Although every empirical event experienced within the realm of appearance
has a deterministic natural cause, it is at least logically possible that freedom can be a causally
efficacious power at the level of things in themselves. And although every empirical object
experienced within the realm of appearance is a contingently existing entity, it is logically
possible that there is a necessary being outside the realm of appearance which grounds the
existence of the contingent beings within the realm of appearance. It must be kept in mind that
Kant has not claimed to demonstrate the existence of a transcendent free will or a transcendent
necessary being: Kant denies the possibility of knowledge of things in themselves. Instead, Kant
only takes himself to have shown that the existence of such entities is logically possible. In his
moral theory, however, Kant will offer an argument for the actuality of freedom (see 5c below).
Kant identifies the idea of God with the idea of an ens realissimum, or “most real being.” This
most real being is also considered by reason to be a necessary being, that is, something which
exists necessarily instead of merely contingently. Reason is led to posit the idea of such a being
when it reflects on its conceptions of finite beings with limited reality and infers that the reality
of finite beings must derive from and depend on the reality of the most infinitely perfect being.
Of course, the fact that reason necessarily thinks of a most real, necessary being does not entail
that such a being exists. Kant argues that there are only three possible arguments for the
existence of such a being, and that none is successful.
Although Kant argues in the Transcendental Dialectic that we cannot have cognition of the soul,
of freedom of the will, nor of God, in his ethical writings he will complicate this story and argue
that we are justified in believing in these things (see 5c below).
3. Philosophy of Mathematics
The distinction between analytic and synthetic judgments (see 2b above) is necessary for
understanding Kant’s theory of mathematics. Recall that an analytic judgment is one where the
truth of the judgment depends only on the relation between the concepts used in the judgment.
The truth of a synthetic judgment, by contrast, requires that an object be “given” in sensibility
and that the concepts used in the judgment be combined in the object. In these terms, most of
Kant’s predecessors took mathematical truths to be analytic truths. Kant, by contrast argued that
mathematical knowledge is synthetic. It may seem surprising that one’s knowledge of
mathematical truths depends on an object being given in sensibility, for we surely don’t arrive at
mathematical knowledge by empirical means. Recall, however, that a judgment can be both
synthetic yet a priori. Like the judgments of the necessary structures of experience, mathematics
is also synthetic a priori according to Kant.
To make this point, Kant considers the proposition ‘7+5=12’. Surely, this proposition is a priori:
I can know its truth without doing empirical experiments to see what happens when I put seven
things next to five other things. More to the point, ‘7+5=12’ must be a priori because it is
a necessary truth, and empirical judgments are always merely contingent according to Kant. Yet
at the same time, the judgment is not analytic because, “The concept of twelve is by no means
already thought merely by my thinking of that unification of seven and five, and no matter how
long I analyze my concept of such a possible sum I will still not find twelve in it” (B15).
4. Natural Science
In addition to his work in pure theoretical philosophy, Kant displayed an active interest in the
natural sciences throughout his career. Most of his important scientific contributions were in the
physical sciences (including not just physics proper, but also earth sciences and cosmology).
In Critique of the Power of Judgment (1790) he also presented a lengthy discussion of the
philosophical basis of the study of biological entities.
In general, Kant thought that a body of knowledge could only count as a science in the true sense
if it could admit of mathematical description and an a priori principle that could be “presented a
priori in intuition” (4:471). Hence, Kant was pessimistic about the possibility of empirical
psychology ever amounting to a true science. Kant even thought it might be the case that
“chemistry can be nothing more than a systematic art or experimental doctrine, but never a
proper science” (4:471).
This section focuses primarily on Kant’s physics (4a), but it also lists several of Kant’s other
scientific contributions (4b).
a. Physics
Kant’s interest in physical theory began early. His first published work, Thoughts on the True
Estimation of Living Forces (1749) was an inquiry into some foundational problems in physics,
and it entered into the “vis viva” (“living forces”) debate between Leibniz and the Cartesians
regarding how to quantify force in moving objects (for the most part, Kant sided with the
Leibnizians). A few years later, Kant wrote the Physical Monadology (1756), which dealt with
other foundational questions in physics (see 2a above.)
Kant’s mature physical theory is presented in its fullest form in Metaphysical Foundations of
Natural Science (1786). This theory can be understood as an outgrowth and consequence of the
transcendental theory of experience articulated in Critique of Pure Reason (see 2f above). Where
the Critique had shown the necessary conceptual forms to which all possible objects of
experience must conform, the Metaphysical Foundations specifies in greater detail what exactly
the physical constitution of these objects must be like. The continuity with the theory of
experience from the Critique is implicit in the very structure of the Metaphysical Foundations.
Just as Kant’s theory of experience was divided into four sections corresponding to the four
groups of categories (quantity, quality, relation, modality), the body of the Metaphysical
Foundations is also divided along the same lines.
At the end of his career, Kant worked on a project that was supposed to complete the connection
between the transcendental philosophy and physics. Among other things, Kant attempted to give
a transcendental, a priori demonstration of the existence of a ubiquitous “ether” that permeates
all of space. Although Kant never completed a manuscript for this project (due primarily to the
deterioration of his mental faculties at the end of his life), he did leave behind many notes and
partial drafts. Many of these notes and drafts have been edited and published under the title Opus
Postumum.
One of Kant’s most lasting scientific contributions came from his early work in cosmology. In
his Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens (1755), Kant gave a mechanical
explanation of the formation of the solar system and the galaxies in terms of the principles of
Newtonian physics. (A shorter version of the argument also appears in The Only Possible
Argument in Support of a Demonstration of the Existence of God from 1763.) Kant’s hypothesis
was that a single mechanical process could explain why we observe an orbital motion of smaller
bodies around larger ones at many different scales in the cosmos (moons around planets, planets
around stars, and stars around the center of the galaxy). He proposed that at the beginning of
creation, all matter was spread out more or less evenly and randomly in a kind of nebula. Since
the various bits of matter all attracted each other through gravitation, bodies would move
towards each other within local regions to form larger bodies. The largest of these became stars,
and the smaller ones became moons or planets. Because everything was already in motion (due
to the gravitational attraction of everything to everything), and because all objects would be
pulled towards the center of mass of their local region (for example, the sun at the center of the
solar system, or a planet at the center of its own smaller planetary system), the motion of objects
within that region would become orbital motions (as described by Newton’s theory of gravity).
Although the Universal Natural History was not widely read for most of Kant’s lifetime (due
primarily to Kant’s publisher going bankrupt while the printed books remained in a warehouse),
in 1796 Pierre-Simon Laplace (1749-1827) proposed a remarkably similar version of the same
theory, and this caused renewed interest in Kant’s book. Today the theory is referred to as the
“Kant-Laplace Nebular Hypothesis,” and a modified version of this theory is still held today.
Finally, in the second half of Critique of the Power of Judgment (1790), Kant discusses the
philosophical foundations of biology by way of an analysis of teleological judgments. While in
no way a fully worked out biological theory per se, Kant connects his account of biological
cognition in interesting ways to other important aspects of his philosophical system. First, natural
organisms are essentially teleological, or “purposive.” This purposiveness is manifested through
the organic structure of the organism: its many parts all work together to constitute the whole,
and any one part only makes sense in terms of its relation to the healthy functioning of the
whole. For instance, the teeth of an animal are designed to chew the kind of food that the animal
is equipped to hunt or forage and that it is suited to digest. In this respect, biological entities bear
a strong analogy to great works of art. Great works of art are also organic insofar as the parts
only make sense in the context of the whole, and art displays a purposiveness similar to that
found in nature (see section 7 below). Second, Kant discusses the importance of biology with
respect to theological cognition. While he denies that the apparent design behind the
purposiveness of organisms can be used as a proof for God’s existence (see 2g3 above), he does
think that the purposiveness found in nature provides a sort of hint that there is an intelligible
principle behind the observable, natural world, and hence that the ultimate purpose of all of
nature is a rational one. In connection with his moral theory and theory of human history (see
sections 5 and 6 below), Kant will argue that the teleology of nature can be understood as
ultimately directed towards a culmination in a fully rational nature, that is, humanity in its
(future) final form.
5. Moral Theory
Kant’s moral theory is organized around the idea that to act morally and to act in accordance
with reason are one and the same. In virtue of being a rational agent (that is, in virtue of
possessing practical reason, reason which is interested and goal-directed), one is obligated to
follow the moral law that practical reason prescribes. To do otherwise is to act irrationally.
Because Kant places his emphasis on the duty that comes with being a rational agent who is
cognizant of the moral law, Kant’s theory is considered a form of deontology (deon– comes from
the Greek for “duty” or “obligation”).
Like his theoretical philosophy, Kant’s practical philosophy is a priori, formal, and universal: the
moral law is derived non-empirically from the very structure of practical reason itself (its form),
and since all rational agents share the same practical reason, the moral law binds and obligates
everyone equally. So what is this moral law that obligates all rational agents universally and a
priori? The moral law is determined by what Kant refers to as the Categorical Imperative, which
is the general principle that demands that one respect the humanity in oneself and in others, that
one not make an exception for oneself when deliberating about how to act, and in general that
one only act in accordance with rules that everyone could and should obey.
Although Kant insists that the moral law is equally binding for all rational agents, he also insists
that the bindingness of the moral law is self-imposed: we autonomously prescribe the moral law
to ourselves. Because Kant thinks that the kind of autonomy in question here is only possible
under the presupposition of a transcendentally free basis of moral choice, the constraint that the
moral law places on an agent is not only consistent with freedom of the will, it requires it. Hence,
one of the most important aspects of Kant’s project is to show that we are justified in
presupposing that our morally significant choices are grounded in a transcendental freedom (the
very sort of freedom that Kant argued we could not prove through mere “theoretical” or
“speculative” reason; see 2gii above).
This section aims to explain the structure and content of Kant’s moral theory (5a-b), and also
Kant’s claims that belief in freedom, God, and the immortality of the soul are necessary
“postulates” of practical reason (5c). (On the relation between Kant’s moral theory and his
aesthetic theory, see 7c below.)
The point of Kant’s appeal to the universal law formulation of the categorical imperative is to
show that an action is morally permissible only if the maxim on which the action is based could
be affirmed as a universal law that everyone obeys without exception. The mark of immorality,
then, is that one makes an exception for oneself. That is, one acts in a way that they would not
want everyone else to. When someone chooses to lie about an adulterous liaison, one is
implicitly thinking, “in general people should tell the truth, but in this case I will be the
exception to the rule.”
Kant’s first formulation of the categorical imperative describes it in terms of the very form of
universal law itself. This formal account abstracts from any specific content that the moral law
might have for living, breathing human beings. Kant offers a second formulation to address the
material side of the moral law. Since the moral law has to do with actions, and all actions are by
definition teleological (that is, goal-directed), a material formulation of the categorical
imperative will require an appeal to the “ends” of human activity. Some ends are merely
instrumental, that is, they are sought only because they serve as “means” towards further ends.
Kant argues that the moral law must be aimed at an end that is not merely instrumental, but is
rather an end in itself. Only rational agents, according to Kant, are ends in themselves. To act
morally is thus to respect rational agents as ends in themselves. Accordingly, the categorical
imperative can be reformulated as follows: “So act that you use humanity, whether in your own
person or in the person of any other, always at the same time as an end, never merely as a
means” (4:429). The basic idea here is that it is immoral to treat someone as a thing of merely
instrumental value; persons have an intrinsic (non-instrumental) value, and the moral law
demands that we respect this intrinsic value. To return to the example of the previous paragraphs,
it would be wrong to lie about an adulterous liaison because by withholding the truth one is
manipulating the other person to make things easier for oneself; this sort of manipulation,
however, amounts to treating the other as a thing (as a mere means to the comfort of not getting
in trouble), and not as a person deserving of respect and entitled to the truth.
The notion of a universal law provides the form of the categorical imperative and rational agents
as ends in themselves provide the matter. These two sides of the categorical imperative are
combined into yet a third formulation, which appeals to the notion of a “kingdom of ends.” A
kingdom of ends can be thought of as a sort of perfectly just utopian ideal in which all citizens of
this kingdom freely respect the intrinsic worth of the humanity in all others because of an
autonomously self-imposed recognition of the bindingness of the universal moral law for all
rational agents. The third formulation of the categorical imperative is simply the idea that one
should act in whatever way a member of this perfectly just society would act: “act in accordance
with the maxims of a member giving universal laws for a merely possible kingdom of ends”
(4:439). The idea of a kingdom of ends is an ideal (hence the “merely possible”). Although
humanity may never be able to achieve such a perfect state of utopian coexistence, we can at
least strive to approximate this state to an ever greater degree.
We will start with freedom. Kant argues that morality and the obligation that comes with it are
only possible if humans have free will. This is because the universal laws prescribed by the
categorical imperative presuppose autonomy (autos = self; nomos = law). To be autonomous is to
be the free ground of one’s own principles, or “laws” of action. Kant argues that if we
presuppose that humans are rational and have free will, then his entire moral theory follows
directly. The problem, however, lies in justifying the belief that we are free. Kant had argued in
the Second Analogy of Experience that every event in the natural world has a “determining
ground,” that is, a cause, and so all human actions, as natural events, themselves have
deterministic causes (see 2f above). The only room for freedom of the will would lie in the realm
of things in themselves, which contains the noumenal correlate of my phenomenal self. Since
things in themselves are unknowable, I can never look to them to get evidence that I possess
transcendental freedom. Kant gives at least two arguments to justify belief in freedom as a
precondition of his moral theory. (There is a great deal of controversy among commentators
regarding the exact form of his arguments, as well as their success. It will not be possible to
adjudicate those disputes in any detail here. See Section 10 (References and Further Readings)
for references to some of these commentaries.)
In the Groundwork, Kant suggests that the presupposition that we are free follows as a
consequence of the fact that we have practical reason and that we think of ourselves as practical
agents. Any time I face a choice that requires deliberation, I must consider the options before me
as really open. If I thought of my course of action as already determined ahead of time, then
there would not really be any choice to make. Furthermore, in taking my deliberation to be real, I
also think of the possible outcomes of my actions as caused by me. The notion of a causality that
originates in the self is the notion of a free will. So the very fact that I do deliberate about what
actions I will take means that I am presupposing that my choice is real and hence that I am free.
As Kant puts it, all practical agents act “under the idea of freedom” (4:448). It is not obvious that
this argument is strong enough for Kant’s purposes. The position seems to be that I must act as
though I am free, but acting as though I am free in no way entails that I really am free. At best, it
seems that since I act as though I am free, I thereby must act as though morality really does
obligate me. This does not establish that the moral law really does obligate me.
In the Second Critique, Kant offers a different argument for the reality of freedom. He argues
that it is a brute “fact of reason” (5:31) that the categorical imperative (and so morality generally)
obligates us as rational agents. In other words, all rational agents are at least implicitly conscious
of the bindingness of the moral law on us. Since morality requires freedom, it follows that if
morality is real, then freedom must be real too. Thus this “fact of reason” allows for an inference
to the reality of freedom. Although the conclusion of this argument is stronger than the earlier
argument, its premise is more controversial. For instance, it is far from obvious that all rational
agents are conscious of the moral law. If they were, how come no one discovered this exact
moral law before 1785 when Kant wrote the Groundwork? Equally problematic, it is not clear
why this “fact of reason” should count as knowledge of the bindingness of the moral law. It may
just be that we cannot help but believe that the moral law obligates us, in which case we once
again end up merely acting as though we are free and as though the moral law is real.
Again, there is much debate in the literature about the structure and success of Kant’s arguments.
It is clear, however, that the success of Kant’s moral project stands or falls with his arguments
for freedom of the will, and that the overall strength of this theory is determined to a high degree
by the epistemic status of our belief in our own freedom.
Kant’s arguments for immortality and God as postulates of practical reason presuppose that the
reality of the moral law and the freedom of the will have been established, and they also depend
on the principle that “‘ought’ implies ‘can’”: one cannot be obligated to do something unless the
thing in question is doable. For instance, there is no sense in which I am obligated to single-
handedly solve global poverty, because it is not within my power to do so. According to Kant,
the ultimate aim of a rational moral agent should be to become perfectly moral. We are obligated
to strive to become ever more moral. Given the “ought implies can” principle, if we ought to
work towards moral perfection, then moral perfection must be possible and we can become
perfect. However, Kant holds that moral perfection is something that finite rational agents such
as humans can only progress towards, but not actually attain in any finite amount of time, and
certainly not within any one human lifetime. Thus the moral law demands an “endless progress”
towards “complete conformity of the will with the moral law” (5:122). This endless progress
towards perfection can only be demanded of us if our own existence is endless. In short, one’s
belief that one should strive towards moral perfection presupposes the belief in the immortality
of the soul.
In addition to the “ought implies can” principle, Kant’s argument about belief in God also
involves an elaboration of the notion of the “highest good” at which all moral action aims (at
least indirectly). According to Kant, the highest good, that is, the most perfect possible state for a
community of rational agents, is not only one in which all agents act in complete conformity
with the moral law. It is also a state in which these agents are happy. Kant had argued that
although everyone naturally desires to be happy, happiness is only good when one deserves to be
happy. In the ideal scenario of a morally perfect community of rational agents, everyone deserves
to be happy. Since a deserved happiness is a good thing, the highest good will involve a situation
in which everyone acts in complete conformity with the moral law and everyone is completely
happy because they deserve to be. Now since we are obligated to work towards this highest
good, this complete, universal, morally justified happiness must be possible (again, because
“ought” implies “can”). This is where a puzzle arises. Although happiness is connected to
morality at the conceptual level when one deserves happiness, there is no natural connection
between morality and happiness. Our happiness depends on the natural world (for example,
whether we are healthy, whether natural disasters affect us), and the natural world operates
according to laws that are completely separate from the laws of morality. Accordingly, acting
morally is in general no guarantee that nature will make it possible for one to be happy. If
anything, behaving morally will often decrease one’s happiness (for doing the right thing often
involves doing the uncomfortable, difficult thing). And we all have plenty of empirical evidence
from the world we live in that often bad things happen to good people and good things happen to
bad people. Thus if the highest good (in which happiness is proportioned to virtue) is possible,
then somehow there must be a way for the laws of nature to eventually lead to a situation in
which happiness is proportioned to virtue. (Note that since at this point in the argument, Kant
takes himself to have established immortality as a postulate of practical reason, this “eventually”
may very well be far in the future). Since the laws of nature and the laws of morality are
completely separate on their own, the only way that the two could come together such that
happiness ends up proportioned to virtue would be if the ultimate cause and ground of nature set
up the world in such a way that the laws of nature would eventually lead to the perfect state in
question. Therefore, the possibility of the highest good requires the presupposition that the cause
of the world is intelligent and powerful enough to set nature up in the right way, and also that it
wills in accordance with justice that eventually the laws of nature will indeed lead to a state in
which the happiness of rational agents is proportioned to their virtue. This intelligent, powerful,
and just cause of the world is what traditionally goes by the name of “God.” Hence God is a
postulate of practical reason.
In his short essay “Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Purpose” (1784), Kant
outlines a speculative sketch of humanity’s history organized around his conception of the
teleology intrinsic to the species. The natural purpose of humanity is the development of reason.
This development is not something that can take place in one individual lifetime, but is instead
the ongoing project of humanity across the generations. Nature fosters this goal through both
human physiology and human psychology. Humans have no fur, claws, or sharp teeth, and so if
we are to be sheltered and fed, we must use our reason to create the tools necessary to satisfy our
needs. More importantly, at the cultural level, Kant argues that human society is characterized by
an “unsocial sociability”: on the one hand, humans need to live with other humans and we feel
incomplete in isolation; but on the other, we frequently disagree with each other and are
frustrated when others don’t agree with us on important matters. The frustration brought on by
disagreement serves as an incentive to develop our capacity to reason so that we can argue
persuasively and convince others to agree with us.
By means of our physiological deficiencies and our unsocial sociability, nature has nudged us,
generation by generation, to develop our capacity for reason and slowly to emerge from the hazy
fog of pre-history up to the present. This development is not yet complete. Kant takes stock of
where we were in his day, in late 18 th c. Prussia) in his short, popular essay: “An Answer to the
Question: What is Enlightenment?” (1784). To be enlightened, he argues, is to determine one’s
beliefs and actions in accordance with the free use of one’s reason. The process of enlightenment
is humanity’s “emergence from its self-incurred immaturity” (8:35), that is, the emergence from
an uncritical reliance on the authority of others (for example, parents, monarchs, or priests). This
is a slow, on-going process. Kant thought that his own age was an age of enlightenment, but not
yet a fully enlightened age.
The goal of humanity is to reach a point where all interpersonal interactions are conducted in
accordance with reason, and hence in accordance with the moral law (this is the idea of a
kingdom of ends described in 5b above). Kant thinks that there are two significant conditions
that must be in place before such an enlightened age can come to be. First, humans must live in a
perfectly just society under a perfectly just constitution. Second, the nations of the world must
coexist as an international federation in a state of “perpetual peace.” Some aspects of the first
condition are discussed in 6b, and of the second in 6c.
b. Political Theory
Kant fullest articulation of his political theory appears in the “Doctrine of Right,” which is the
first half of Metaphysics of Morals (1797). In line with his belief that a freedom grounded in
rationality is what bestows dignity upon human beings, Kant organizes his theory of justice
around the notion of freedom: “Any action is right if it can coexist with everyone’s freedom in
accordance with a universal law, or if on its maxim the freedom of choice of each can coexist
with everyone’s freedom in accordance with a universal law” (6:230). Implicit in this definition
is a theory of equality: everyone should be granted the same degree of freedom. Although a state,
through the passing and enforcing of laws, necessarily restricts freedom to some degree, Kant
argues that this is necessary for the preservation of equality of human freedom. This is because
when the freedoms of all are unchecked (for example, in the state of nature, which is also a
condition of anarchy), the strong will overpower the weak and infringe on their freedoms, in
which case freedoms will not be distributed equally, contrary to Kant’s basic principle of right.
Hence a fair and lawful coercion that restricts freedom is consistent with and required by
maximal and equal degrees of freedom for all.
Kant holds that republicanism is the ideal form of government. In a republic, voters elect
representatives and these representatives decide on particular laws on behalf of the people. (Kant
shows that he was not free of the prejudices of his day, and claims, with little argument, that
neither women nor the poor should be full citizens with voting rights.) Representatives are duty-
bound to choose these laws from the perspective of the “general will” (a term Kant borrows from
Rousseau), rather than from the perspective of the interests of any one individual or group within
society. Even though the entire population does not vote on each individual law, a law is said to
be just only in case an entire population of rational agents could and would consent to the law. In
this respect, Kant’s theory of just law is analogous to his universal law formulation of the
categorical imperative: both demand that it be possible in principle for everyone to affirm the
rule in question (see 5b above).
Among the freedoms that ought to be respected in a just society (republican or otherwise) are the
freedom to pursue happiness in any way one chooses (so long as this pursuit does not infringe
the rights of others, of course), freedom of religion, and freedom of speech. These last two are
especially important to Kant and he associated them with the ongoing enlightenment of humanity
in “What is Enlightenment?” He argues that it “would be a crime against human nature” (8:39) to
legislate religious doctrine because doing so would be to deny to humans the very free use of
reason that makes them human. Similarly, restrictions on what Kant calls the “public use of
one’s reason” are contrary to the most basic teleology of the human species, namely, the
development of reason. Kant himself had felt the sting of an infringement on these rights when
the government of Friedrich Wilhelm II (the successor to Frederick the Great) prohibited Kant
from publishing anything further on matters pertaining to religion.
c. Perpetual Peace
Kant elaborates the cosmopolitan theory first proposed in “Idea for a Universal History” in
his Towards Perpetual Peace (1795). The basic idea is that world peace can be achieved only
when international relations mirror, in certain respects, the relations between individuals in a just
society. Just as people cannot be traded as things, so too states cannot be traded as though they
were mere property. Just as individuals must respect others’ rights to free self-determination, so
too, “no state shall forcibly interfere in the constitution and government of another state” (8:346).
And in general, just as individuals need to arrange themselves into just societies, states,
considered as individuals themselves, must arrange themselves into a global federation, a “league
of nations” (8:354). Of course, until a state of perpetual peace is reached, wars will be inevitable.
Even in times of wars, however, certain laws must be respected. For instance, it is never
permissible for hostilities to become so violent as to undermine the possibility of a future peace
treaty.
Kant argued that republicanism is especially conducive to peace, and he argued that perpetual
peace would require that all states be republics. This is because the people will only consent to a
war if they are willing to bear the economic burdens that war brings, and such a cost will only be
worthwhile when there is a truly dire threat. If only the will of the monarch is required to go to
war, since the monarch will not have to bear the full burden of the war (the cost will be
distributed among the subjects), there is much less disincentive against war.
Let us consider judgments of beauty (which Kant calls “judgments of taste”) first. Kant argues
that all judgments of taste involve four components, or “moments.” First, judgments of taste
involve a subjective yet disinterested enjoyment. We have an appreciation for the object without
desiring it. This contrasts judgments of taste from both cognitions, which represent objects as
they are rather than how they affect us, and desires, which represent objects in terms of what we
want. Second, judgments of taste involve universality. When we judge an object to be beautiful,
implicit in the judgment is the belief that everyone should judge the object in the same way.
Third, judgments of taste involve the form of purposiveness, or “purposeless purposiveness.”
Beautiful objects seem to be “for” something, even though there is nothing determinate that they
are for. Fourth, judgments of taste involve necessity. When presented with a beautiful object, I
take it that I ought to judge it as beautiful. Taken together, the theory is this: when I judge
something as beautiful, I enjoy the object without having any desires with respect to it, I believe
that everyone should judge the object to be beautiful, I represent some kind of purposiveness in
it, but without applying any concepts that would determine its specific purpose, and I also
represent myself as being obligated to judge it to be beautiful. Judgments of beauty are thus quite
peculiar. On the one hand, when we say an object is beautiful, it is not the same sort of
predication as when I say something is green, is a horse, or fits in a breadbox. Yet it is not for
that reason a purely subjective, personal judgment because of the necessity and intersubjective
universality involved in such judgments.
A further remark is in order regarding the “form of purposiveness” in judgments of taste. Kant
wants to emphasize that no determinate concepts are involved in judgments of taste, but that the
“reflective” power of judgment (that is, judgment’s ability to seek to find a suitable concept to fit
an object) is nevertheless very active during such judgments. When I encounter an unfamiliar
object, my reflective judgment is set in motion and seeks a concept until I figure out what sort of
thing the object is. When I encounter a beautiful object, the form of purposiveness in the object
also sets my reflecting judgment in motion, but no determinate concept is ever found for the
object. Although this might be expected to lead to frustration, Kant instead claims that it
provokes a “free play” (5:217) between the imagination and understanding. Kant does not say as
much about this “free play” as one would like, but the idea seems to be that since the experience
is not constrained by a determinate concept that must be applied to the object, the imagination
and understanding are free to give in to a lively interplay of thought and emotion in response to
the object. The experience of this free play of the faculties is the part of the aesthetic experience
that we take to be enjoyable.
Aside from judgments of taste, there is another important form of aesthetic experience: the
experience of the sublime. According to Kant, the experience of the sublime occurs when we
face things (whether natural or manmade) that dwarf the imagination and make us feel tiny and
insignificant in comparison. When we face something so large that we cannot come up with a
concept to adequately capture its magnitude, we experience a feeling akin to vertigo. A good
example of this is the “Deep Field” photographs from the Hubble Telescope. We already have
trouble comprehending the enormity of the Milky Way, but when we see an image containing
thousands of other galaxies of approximately the same size, the mind cannot even hope to
comprehend the immensity of what is depicted. Although this sort of experience can be
disconcerting, Kant also says that a disinterested pleasure (similar to the pleasure in the
beautiful) is experienced when the ideas of reason pertaining to the totality of the cosmos are
brought into play. Although the understanding can have no empirical concept of such an
indeterminable magnitude, reason has such an idea (in Kant’s technical sense of “idea”; see 2g
above), namely, the idea of the world as an indefinitely large totality. This feeling that reason can
subsume and capture even the totality of the immeasurable cosmos leads to the peculiar pleasure
of the sublime.
b. Theory of Art
Both natural objects and manmade art can be judged to be beautiful. Kant suggests that natural
beauties are purest, but works of art are especially interesting because they result from human
genius. The following briefly summarizes Kant’s theory of art and genius.
Although art must be manmade and not natural, Kant holds that art is beautiful insofar as it
imitates the beauty of nature. Specifically, a beautiful work of art must display the “form of
purposiveness” (described above, 7a) that can be encountered in the natural world. What makes
great art truly great, though, is that it is the result of genius in the artist. According to Kant,
genius is the innate talent possessed by the exceptional, gifted individual that allows that
individual to translate an intangible “aesthetic idea” into a tangible work of art. Aesthetic ideas
are the counterparts to the ideas of reason (see 2g above): where ideas of reason are concepts for
which no sensible intuition is adequate, aesthetic ideas are representations of the imagination for
which no concept is adequate (this is in line with Kant’s claim that beauty is not determinately
conceptualizable). When a genius is successful at exhibiting an aesthetic idea in a beautiful work
of art, the work will provoke the “free play” of the faculties described above (7a).
Kant divides the arts into three groups: the arts of speech (rhetoric and poetry), pictorial arts
(sculpture, architecture, and painting), and the art of the play of sensations (music and “the art of
colors”) (5:321ff.). These can, of course, be combined together. For instance opera combines
music and poetry into song, and combines this with theatre (which Kant considers a form of
painting). Kant deems poetry the greatest of the arts because of its ability to stimulate the
imagination and understanding and expand the mind through reflection. Music is the most
successful if judged in terms of “charm and movement of the mind” (5:328), because it evokes
the affect and feeling of human speech, but without being constrained by the determinate
concepts of actual words. However, if the question is which art advances culture the most, Kant
thinks that painting is better than music.
One consequence of Kant’s theory of art is that the contemporary notion of “conceptual art” is a
contradiction in terms: if there is a specific point or message (a determinate concept) that the
artist is trying to get across, then the work cannot provoke the indeterminate free play that is
necessary for the experience of the beautiful. At best, such works can be interesting or
provocative, but not truly beautiful and hence not truly art.
8. Pragmatic Anthropology
Together with a course on “physical geography” (a study of the world), Kant taught a class on
“pragmatic anthropology” almost every year of his career as a university teacher. Towards the
end of his career, Kant allowed his collected lecture notes for his anthropology course to be
edited and published as Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View (1789). Anthropology, for
Kant, is simply the study of human nature. Pragmatic anthropology is useful, practical
knowledge that students would need in order to successfully navigate the world and get through
life.
The Anthropology is interesting in two very different ways. First, Kant presents detailed
discussions of his views on issues related to empirical psychology, moral psychology, and
aesthetic taste that fill out and give substance to the highly abstract presentations of his writings
in pure theoretical philosophy. For instance, although in the theory of experience from Critique
of Pure Reason Kant argues that we need sensory intuitions in order to have empirical cognition
of the world, he does not explain in any detail how our specific senses—sight, hearing, touch,
taste, smell—contribute to this cognition. The Anthropology fills in a lot of this story. For
instance, we learn that sight and hearing are necessary for us to represent objects as public and
intersubjectively available. And we learn that touch is necessary for us to represent objects as
solid, and hence as substantial. With respect to his moral theory, many of Kant’s ethical writings
can give the impression that emotions and sentiments can only work against morality, and that
only pure reason can incline one towards the good. In the Anthropology Kant complicates this
story, informing us that nature has implanted sentiments of compassion to incline us towards the
good, even in the absence of a developed reason. Once reason has been developed, it can
promote an “enthusiasm of good resolution” (7:254) through attention to concrete instances of
virtuous action, in which case desire can work in cooperation with reason’s moral law, not
against it. Kant also supplements his moral theory through pedagogical advice about how to
cultivate an inclination towards moral behavior.
The other aspect of the Anthropology (and the student transcripts of his actual lectures) that
makes it so interesting is that the wealth and range of examples and discussions gives a much
fuller picture of Kant the person than we can get from his more technical writings. The many
examples present a picture of a man with wide-ranging opinions on all aspects of the human
experience. There are discussions of dreams, humor, boredom, personality-types, facial
expressions, pride and greed, gender and race issues, and more. We even get some fashion
advice: it is acceptable to wear yellow under a blue coat, but gaudy to wear blue under a yellow
coat. There has been a great deal of renewed interest in Kant’s anthropological writings and
many commentators have been appealing to these often neglected texts as a helpful resource that
provides contextualization of Kant’s more widely studied theoretical output.