Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                
Skip to main content
The book is available on line in open access at https://www.brepolsonline.net/doi/book/10.1484/M.ADARG-EB.5.117384
Research Interests:
Research Interests:
Research Interests:
This article enquires into the origins of the historiographical notion of double truth, a prominent and controversial category in the modern study of medieval philosophy. I believe that these origins are to be found in a short text by... more
This article enquires into the origins of the historiographical notion of double truth, a prominent and controversial category in the modern study of medieval philosophy. I believe that these origins are to be found in a short text by Jacob Thomasius from 1663, entitled De duplici & contradictoria veritate, which stands as a very early and highly original example of a history of double truth. I propose a detailed analysis of this document in order to shed light on the mechanisms that transformed duplex veritas from a keyword in Thomasius’s Protestant milieu into a historiographical category. As I show, the De duplici & contradictoria veritate provides a historical legitimation of Thomasius’s own brand of Lutheran Aristotelianism. It does so in a highly ambiguous fashion, namely by bringing together the Lutheran theologian and proponent of double truth Daniel Hofmann with anonymous medieval “Averroists”. I venture an explanation for Thomasius’s line of action by uncovering two of his implicit sources.
This article analyzes the entry on Andrea Cesalpino, an Italian thinker from the second half of the sixteenth century, in Pierre Bayle’s Dictionnaire historique et critique. I investigate how and why Bayle was able to portray Cesalpino as... more
This article analyzes the entry on Andrea Cesalpino, an Italian thinker from the second half of the sixteenth century, in Pierre Bayle’s Dictionnaire historique et critique. I investigate how and why Bayle was able to portray Cesalpino as both an authentic follower of Aristotle and a forerunner of Spinoza’s heterodox teachings. As I show, Bayle integrated two different and even conflicting threads of the reception Cesalpino enjoyed in the late sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries. The background which rendered Bayle’s synthesis possible turns out to be contemporary Cartesian polemics against both Spinoza and Aristotle.
Research Interests:
This article sheds new light on the complex relationship between Jacob Thomasius’s main occupation as a professor of Aristotelian philosophy at the Lutheran University of Leipzig and his works on the history of philosophy, which showed... more
This article sheds new light on the complex relationship between Jacob Thomasius’s main occupation as a professor of Aristotelian philosophy at the Lutheran University of Leipzig and his works on the history of philosophy, which showed the incompatibility of Aristotle with central Christian doctrines. I argue for a strong inner consistency between these two seemingly conflicting aspects of Thomasius’s intellectual activity. Far from paralyzing his way of doing ‘Christian Peripatetic philosophy,’ the history of philosophy was for Thomasius an indispensable analytical tool for reforming Aristotelianism. To illustrate my thesis, I investigate the way Thomasius used his historical reconstruction of Aristotle’s theory of intellect to intervene in a contemporary debate on the origin of the human soul, a debate which played a central role in the crystallization of a Lutheran confessional identity.
This article proposes an analysis of the notion of “genuine Aristotelianism” in Jacob Brucker’s influential Historia critica philosophiae (1742–1744). This category proves particularly interesting since genuine Aristotelians were for... more
This article proposes an analysis of the notion of “genuine Aristotelianism” in Jacob Brucker’s influential Historia critica philosophiae (1742–1744). This category proves particularly interesting since genuine Aristotelians were for Brucker not only an historiographical object but also a lens through which he examined his objects. Brucker applied the label to a number of early modern Italian and German thinkers who had allegedly restored the “genuine” Aristotle, disfigured by medieval scholastics. Yet, as I show, the fact that Brucker recognized the philological skill of early modern Aristotelians does not mean that he rated them very highly. On the contrary, this category helped him argue for the superiority of modern reason over the Aristotelian tradition as a whole. On the narrative level of the Historia critica, genuine Aristotelians were reduced to mere interpreters of Aristotle. They embodied the antithesis to Brucker’s ideal of the modern philosopher as an independent thinker. On the methodological level, genuine Aristotelians figured as excellent interpreters but only in as far as they vouched for Brucker’s own reconstruction of Aristotle’s “errors”.
The conference Inventing Europe in Modern History of Philosophy aims to study the strategies of demarcation implemented in the 18th and 19th centuries by historians of philosophy in order to create the allegedly philosophical culture of... more
The conference Inventing Europe in Modern History of Philosophy aims to study the strategies of demarcation implemented in the 18th and 19th centuries by historians of philosophy in order to create the allegedly philosophical culture of modern Europe, as well as national philosophies. From within the philosophical historiography, it investigates the cultural narratives that intended to establish the supremacy of Western culture above all others, as well as their effects on cultures that have been excluded from European rationality.
Research Interests:
The conference is organized in the context of the ERC-project MEMOPHI (Medieval Philosophy in Modern History of Philosophy). The focus of the conference is on the emergence and development of philosophical historiography as a university... more
The conference is organized in the context of the ERC-project MEMOPHI (Medieval Philosophy in Modern History of Philosophy). The focus of the conference is on the emergence and development of philosophical historiography as a university discipline, which took place in the 18th and 19th centuries. During that period, historians of philosophy sought to create a historical legitimation of modern reason by way of tracing its origins back to the Middle Ages. They evaluated medieval philosophical theories through the lenses of present-day leitmotifs and assigned to medieval thinkers positions within an imaginary map of cultural identities based on the juxtaposition between “Self” and “Other”. Categories such as “method”, “Geist” (“spirit”), “mysticism”, “atheism” and “pantheism” are examples of eighteenth- and nineteenth-century leitmotifs, which served as guidelines in the exploration and appropriation of the philosophical past. In the process of the historical elaboration of these categories, philosophical historiography saw medieval thinkers as prefigurations of modern reason. Some of them were regarded as “forerunners” that had constructively paved the way for modern rationality; whereas others, viewed as “outsiders”, had contributed to the same effect by way of their struggle against “the dominance of scholastic philosophy”. Participants are expected to explore the “fate” of a particular philosopher as portrayed in the writings on the history of philosophy from the 18th-19th century, and to evaluate her/his role in the narrative of the origins of modern reason in the Middle Ages.
Research Interests: