The Classical Quarterly 65.2 559–571 © The Classical Association (2015)
doi:10.1017/S0009838815000385
559
ARISTOTLE’S COMPARATIVE LOGIC: A MODEST PROPOSAL*
1. INTRODUCTION: THE PROBLEM
Both W.D. Ross’s and J. Brunschwig’s editions of Aristotle’s Topics contain the
following passage:
ἔτι εἰ τοῦ αὐτοῦ τινος τὸ μὲν μᾶλλον τὸ δὲ ἧττον τοιοῦτο· καὶ εἰ τὸ μὲν τοιούτου μᾶλλον
τοιοῦτο, τὸ δὲ μὴ τοιούτου, δῆλον ὅτι τὸ πϱῶτον μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο. (Γ 119 a20-2)
The passage is translated in the revised Oxford translation as follows: ‘Moreover, if in
any character one thing exceeds and another falls short of the same standard; also, if the
one exceeds something which possesses the character, while the other exceeds something which does not, then clearly the first thing exhibits that character in a greater
degree’.1
However, in most manuscripts the second, problematic, sentence of this passage runs
as follows:
καὶ εἰ τὸ μὲν τοιούτου μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο, τὸ δὲ μὴ τοιούτου τοιοῦτον, δῆλον ὅτι τὸ πϱῶτον
μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο.
This was clearly the text read by Boethius when he wrote his translation:
amplius si eodem aliquo hoc quidem magis illud autem minus tale; et si hoc quidem tali magis
tale, illud uero non tali tale, manifestum quoniam primum magis tale.2
As is already evident in Boethius’ literal translation, the Greek expression τὸ δὲ μὴ
τοιούτου τοιοῦτον is not straightforward. The deletion of τοιοῦτον after τὸ δὲ μὴ
τοιούτου, which was first proposed by H. Bonitz and is indirectly attested in a manuscript (P) of Alexander of Aphrodisias’ commentary on the Topics, seems beneficial
and is indeed accepted in both Ross’s and Brunschwig’s editions. This emendation certainly makes the expression less difficult, but does not help the reader to understand the
exact meaning of the passage, which remains problematic.
The aim of this short paper is to present a philosophical and philological discussion
of the above passage: we will show that (almost) all available translations are
* We thank Carlo Natali, Tobias Reinhardt, Carlos Steel and CQ’s anonymous referee(s) for their
comments on a previous draft of this paper. The authors are responsible for any remaining mistakes or
shortcomings.
1
The Complete Works of Aristotle. The Revised Oxford Translation, edited by J. Barnes (Princeton,
1984), 199.
2
Aristoteles Latinus. V 1–3. Topica. Translatio Boethii, fragmentum recensioni alterius, et translatio anonyma, ed. L. Minio-Paluello (Bruxelles-Paris, 1969), 59. Cf. also the Renaissance version of
Pacius: ‘si alterum sit tali re magis tale, alterum non sit tali re tale, manifestum est’, etc. (Aristotelis
Stagiritae Peripateticorum Principis Organum: hoc est, libri omnes ad Logicam pertinentes, Greaece
et Latine Jul. Pacius a Beriga recensuit [Hanau, 1623], 603).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The University of St Andrews, on 12 Sep 2017 at 15:38:23, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838815000385
560
L U CA G I L I A N D G I U S E P P E P E Z Z I N I
unsatisfactory and that most of them are unsound, and will propose our own translation
and interpretation.
Moreover, we will show that this passage was understood in the same way that we
understand it by some ancient commentators of Aristotle, such as Alexander of
Aphrodisias and the scholiast, whose gloss was incorporated in the text that was preserved by some medieval manuscripts.
Finally, on the basis of a linguistic analysis of elliptical contrasts in Aristotle, we will
claim that Aristotle’s text as printed by Ross and Brunschwig does indeed support our
interpretation, but at the same time we propose a simple emendation which would avoid
ambiguities.
2. MODERN TRANSLATIONS
The interpretation implied by the Oxford translation is widespread in modern versions of
Aristotle’s Topics.
For instance, Jacques Brunschwig translates as follows: ‘en outre, si une chose est
plus telle, une autre moins telle qu’un même terme de référence; ou encore (avec
deux termes de référence) si l’une est plus telle qu’un terme lui-même tel, l’autre
plus telle qu’un terme lui-même non tel, il est clair que c’est la première qui est plus
telle’.3
Similarly, Giorgio Colli has: ‘Inoltre, se un oggetto è più siffatto di un qualcosa e
l’altro oggetto è meno siffatto del medesimo qualcosa, come pure, se un oggetto è
più siffatto di un siffatto qualcosa e l’altro oggetto è più siffatto di un qualcosa non siffatto, sarà evidente che il primo oggetto è più siffatto del secondo’.4
Finally, in their recent edition Wagner and Rapp translate: ‘Ferner, wenn gegenueber
demselben das eine mehr und das andere weniger so beschaffen ist. Auch wenn das eine
mehr so und so beschaffen ist als ein so und so Beschaffenes, das andere aber (lediglich
mehr so und so beschaffen ist) als ein nicht so und so Beschaffenes, dann ist klar, dass
das erste mehr so und so beschaffen ist’.5
These translations, which all take μὴ as negating τοιούτου (‘something which does
not [possess the character]’, ‘non tel’, ‘un qualcosa non siffatto’, ‘als ein nicht so und so
Beschaffenes’), might seem linguistically correct, but they fail to understand Aristotle’s
point: they solve some of the obscurities of the Greek original text, but the resulting
argument is logically flawed.6 The flaw is implicitly observed by T. Waitz in his commentary on Aristotle’s Topics. In his note ad loc. he construes the passage in the same
3
Aristote Topiques Livres I-IV, texte établi et traduit par J. Brunschwig (Paris, 1967), 74. In his
notes on this passage, at 161 of his edition, Brunschwig acknowledges that all readings in the extant
manuscripts and Alexander’s lemma have the same meaning; however, Brunschwig fails to acknowledge that this meaning, as it has been rendered by his translation, contains a logical mistake of a certain magnitude.
4
Aristotele, Organon, a cura di G. Colli (Torino, 1955), 472.
5
Aristoteles, Topik, übersetzt und kommentiert von T. Wagner und C. Rapp (Stuttgart, 2004), 111.
6
Most translations are equivalent to Brunschwig’s and to Barnes’s revised Oxford translation: see
also Aristotle. Organon V. Les Topiques, édite par J. Tricot (Paris, 1950), 113 and Aristoteles. Topik.
Topik, neuntes Buch oder Über sophistischen Widerlegungsschlüsse, herausgegeben, übersetzt, mit
Einleitung und Anmerkungen versehen von H.G. Zekl (Darmstadt, 1997), 129; A. Zadro
(Aristotele. I Topici [Napoli, 1974]) and M. Zanatta (Aristotele. Analitici Secondi, Topici,
Confutazioni sofistiche [Torino, 1996]) did no better. Other translations are slightly better, in the
sense that they are not logically flawed; we will discuss them later.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The University of St Andrews, on 12 Sep 2017 at 15:38:23, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838815000385
A R I S TOT L E ’ S CO M P A R AT I V E LO G I C
561
way as modern translators do, adding that this is the first attestation of this problematic
rule: ‘ei loco quem habemus vs. 21 nullus est similis eorum qui praecesserunt: nam si
eum transferas ad τὸ αἱϱετόν, sic se habebit: εἰ τὸ μὲν αἱϱετοῦ αἱϱετώτεϱον, τὸ δὲ μὴ
αἱϱετοῦ αἱϱετώτεϱον, καὶ ἐκεῖνο τούτου ἔσται αἱϱετώτεϱον’.7
In order to better understand the problems of this interpretation, it is now useful to
recall what Aristotle is expounding in these chapters of the third book of the Topics.
3. THE CONTEXT
In the sections preceding our passage, Aristotle has been expanding his comparative
logic,8 and has already presented some of the properties of the relations ‘more than’,
‘less than’ and ‘equal to’ (cf. Top. B 114 b37 − 115 a26).
These properties are expanded further by the τόποι concerning comparative relations;
the τόποι should be understood as schemes of arguments, which can be used in a dialectical disputation.9 Even though Aristotle states at the beginning of the Topics that dialectic makes use of syllogisms, and syllogisms are defined as they were defined in the
Prior Analytics (A 24 b18-20), the τόποι do not have the structure of a syllogism, but
seem rather to be other forms of argument.10
7
Aristotelis Organon Graece, Pars Posterior. Analytica Posteriora, Topica, edidit T. Waitz
(Leipzig, 1846), 470. Waitz’s main concern seems to be that the τόπος at Γ 119 a20-2 is not paralleled
in the previous discussion on the ‘preferable’ (τὸ αἱϱετόν). Therefore, Waitz suggests to treat the
τόπος as if it were dealing with the ‘preferable’: his paraphrase, which echoes Alexander of
Aphrodisias’ commentary, makes explicit the logical flaw of the common reading of this passage.
It is difficult to establish whether Waitz intentionally stressed this inconsistency; we think, however,
that his reading is not completely accurate: Aristotle is not talking any longer about τὸ αἱϱετόν at Γ
119 a20-2, but he wants to make a claim on comparison in general (be it a comparison between two or
more αἱϱετά or not). We thank the journal’s referee for discussion on this point.
8
Comparative logics are presented in a formal way by E. Casari in his paper ‘Comparative logics’,
Synthese 73 (1987), 421–49. In this paper Casari underlines that Aristotle was the first to develop a
comparative logic. On Aristotle’s own comparative logic, see E. Casari, ‘Note sulla logica aristotelica
della comparazione’, Sileno 10 (1984), 131–46; J.M. Gambra Gutiérrez, ‘The topoi from the greater,
the lesser and the same degree: an essay on the σύγκϱισις in Aristotle’s Topics’, Argumentation 26
(2012), 413–37.
9
The only attempt at defining the status of the τόποι in Aristotle’s works has to be found in Rhet. B
26, 1403 a17-19. On the status of the τόποι see T. Reinhardt, Das Buch E der aristotelischen Topik.
Untersuchungen zur Echteitsfrage (Göttingen, 2000), 46. For a map of contemporary literature on the
controversial nature of the τόποι see M. Schramm, Die Prinzipien der aristotelischen Topik (Munich
and Leipzig, 2004), 89–107.
10
Oliver Primavesi defended the idea that the τόποι are forms of reasoning through which, given a
certain proposition which needs to be proved, we can built a dialectical syllogism. Primavesi developed his theory on the basis of the dialogical argumentation theory, which Aristotle expands in Topics
Θ; cf. O. Primavesi, Die aristotelische Topik. Ein Interpretationsmodell und seine Erprobung am
Beispiel von Topik B (Munich, 1996), 83–101. Even though the τόποι do not have the structure of
standard syllogism, we should not forget that Aristotle thought that all sound inferences may in principle be reduced to syllogistic (cf. Prior Analytics A 23 and A 32), but it is hard to see how this may
be true in the case of many τόποι. In particular, in Topics Γ Aristotle expands a series of τόποι whose
status is difficult to explain for two reasons:
(a) if we take this book as a treaty on comparative logic, all the rules that Aristotle introduces are theorems of a logic which is stronger than first-order logic (comparative logic,
as it has been presented by E. Casari [n. 8], is an extension of first-order logic); however,
since categorical syllogistic proves only a proper subset of the theorems of first-order
logic (cf. on this J. Łukasiewicz, Aristotle’s Syllogistic from the Standpoint of Modern
Formal Logic [Oxford, 19572], especially 77–99; A. Rini, Aristotle’s Modal Proofs.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The University of St Andrews, on 12 Sep 2017 at 15:38:23, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838815000385
562
L U CA G I L I A N D G I U S E P P E P E Z Z I N I
The relations ‘more than’ and ‘less than’ are intuitively transitive, and Aristotle clearly
maintains that these relations have this property of being transitive in Top. Γ 119 a20-2.
The logical argument introduced by the first sentence of our passage states that if A
is more ϕ than B, and C is less ϕ than B, then A is more ϕ than C (ἔτι εἰ τοῦ αὐτοῦ τινος
τὸ μὲν μᾶλλον τὸ δὲ ἧττον τοιοῦτο […] δῆλον ὅτι τὸ πϱῶτον μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο, Top. Γ
119 a20-2), a rule which is logically correct.
However, the second sentence (καὶ εἰ τὸ μὲν τοιούτου μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο, τὸ δὲ μὴ
τοιούτου, δῆλον ὅτι τὸ πϱῶτον μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο), as it has been understood by most
translators and commentators (see above), would state the following rule:
1) if A is more ϕ than B, and both A and B are ϕ, if there is a C which is more ϕ than D, and C is
ϕ, whilst D is not, then A is more ϕ than C.
This rule is plainly wrong. An example will make this clearer: the moon (A) is brighter
than this candle (B), and both of them are bright; on the other hand, the sun (C) is
brighter than a piece of coal (D), and whilst the sun is certainly bright, coal is not.
Now, from this it should follow by the above rule that the moon is brighter than the
Prior Analytics A8-22 in Predicate Logic [Dordrecht, 2011], 11–31), it is clear that the
rules that Aristotle expands in Topics Γ cannot be reduced to syllogistic;
(b) the doctrine of the praedicabilia, which plays a crucial role in the Topics (and, according to some scholars, in Aristotle’s Prior Analytics too: cf. on this M. Malink, ‘A reconstruction of Aristotle’s modal syllogistic’, History and Philosophy of Logic 27 [2006],
95–141), is absent in the section on comparatives in Topics Γ.
For these two reasons, it is difficult to establish whether Aristotle was committed to the
properties of the comparatives, which he expands in Topics Γ (this understanding seems
to be implied by Primavesi’s interpretation [this note]: if all τόποι are schemes for drawing
syllogisms, they should be understood as logical rules, whose validity Aristotle was taking
for granted), or whether he simply took these arguments to be dialectical arguments,
whose validity was not to be taken for granted, but which should have been able to persuade an opponent in a dialectical debate (this interpretation is suggested by Reinhardt in
his monograph [n. 9]). Both possibilities are compatible with the text: the τόποι are in both
readings the underlying argumentative forms of dialectical debates; as a consequence, even
if we think that Aristotle accepted these arguments as valid logical rules, this does not
necessarily mean that he was committed to the truth of the premises of these arguments.
Our impression is that Aristotle tried to expand the rules of comparison in a formal way;
later, when he tried to turn his (many) logics into a system, he thought that syllogistic
could have been the underlying logic of dialectic too (cf. An. Pr. A 24 a22-8). This is
why Aristotle introduced syllogisms as the standard inference for dialectic too in the
very first chapter of the Topics (cf. Top. A 100 a18-b23). However, this attempt at building
a system was not succesful, as we have noted above, when we underlined that comparative
logic cannot be reduced to syllogistic. Nevertheless, the τόποι expound properties that
Aristotle was presumably endorsing, if our reconstruction is correct. However things
might be, the properties of the comparative relations should make appeal to the common
understanding of these relations, so that the τόποι concerning comparative relations may
usefully result in a dialectical debate. In other words, even though Aristotle might have
been sceptical regarding their logical truth, as Reinhardt seems to suggest, these τόποι
should be accepted by most people. On the status of dialectic in the context of
Aristotle’s scientific research, see also W.A. de Pater, Les Topiques d’Aristote et la dialectique platonicienne (Fribourg, 1965); J.D.G. Evans, Aristotle’s Concept of Dialectic
(Cambridge, 1977); P. Slomkowski, Aristotle’s Topics (Leiden, New York and
Cologne, 1997); M. Wlodarczyk, ‘Aristotelian dialectic and the discovery of truth’,
OSAPh 18 (2000), 153–210.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The University of St Andrews, on 12 Sep 2017 at 15:38:23, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838815000385
A R I S TOT L E ’ S CO M P A R AT I V E LO G I C
563
sun—and this is clearly not the case. Therefore, the rule by means of which we have
inferred this conclusion must be wrong.
It is possible that Aristotle suggested a logically incorrect rule: his corpus is scattered
with notions that modern science has proved to be mistaken, and we should not be surprised if quandoque bonus dormitat Aristoteles. However, mistakes are not all of the
same sort, and if we accept this interpretation, we have to accept the idea that
Aristotle has endorsed a rule which is patently wrong: this seems to be at odds with
the careful descriptions of the other (correct) rules which govern the logic of comparatives, and which are found in the third book of the Topics.
4. SOME PROBLEMATIC SOLUTIONS
A first solution to the problems of rule 1 involves an interpretation of the passage as
shown by the following translation:
if the one exceeds something which possesses the character, while the other exceeds at best/only
something which does not, then clearly the first thing exhibits that character in a greater degree.
This translation interprets the text as stating the following rule:
2) if A is more ϕ than B, and both A and B are ϕ, if there is a C, which is ϕ, that is more ϕ at best
or only than D, where D is any not-ϕ, then A is more ϕ than C.
According to this ‘charitable’ interpretation, the not-ϕ term (D) compared to C is not just
any example of a not-ϕ, but the best case one can provide in which C is more ϕ than
something; in this way the counterexample of the sun, mentioned above, would be
ruled out, as the bright thing referred to in the second premise (C) would be more bright
only than a non-bright thing (D), thus never being more bright than another bright thing.
The main problem with this interpretation is that the logical component on which the
soundness of rule 2 relies upon, and which indeed distinguishes rule 2 from rule 1, is
expressed by a linguistic element (the adverb ‘at best’ or ‘only’) which the Greek
text does not display.
Another way to solve the problem, envisaged by some scholars, involves a simplification of the logic of the passage. An example of this is found in Rolfes’s translation:
‘Ferner, wenn das eine bestimmte Beschaffenheit in höherem, das andere in niederem
Grade hat als eine und dasselbe Dritte; und wenn das eine sie in höherem, das andere
nicht in höherem Grade hat als ein gleichbeschaffenes Dritte, so hat offenbar das
erste die betraffende Beschaffenheit in höherem Grade’.11
However, both this translation and the resulting interpretation are problematic. Apart
from the fact that Rolfes’s version hardly corresponds to the Greek, the rule which
Aristotle would have suggested, if these were his words, would be a truism:
11
Aristoteles. Topik, neu übersetzt und mit einer Einleitung und erklärenden Anmerkungen versehen von E. Rolfes (Leipzig, 1919), 60. W.A. Pickard-Cambridge’s translation had the same reading in
its original form, before the revision by J. Barnes (cf. The Work of Aristotle translated into English,
under the editorship of W.D. Ross, vol. 1 [Oxford, 1928], ad loc.). The Loeb translation by E.S.
Forster is more elliptical, but, as will be shown later (cf. n. 28), is probably the most accurate, as
regards both language and logic.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The University of St Andrews, on 12 Sep 2017 at 15:38:23, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838815000385
564
L U CA G I L I A N D G I U S E P P E P E Z Z I N I
3) if A is more ϕ than B, and C is less ϕ than B, then A is more ϕ than C
(first sentence);
if A is more ϕ than B, and C is not more ϕ than B, then A is more ϕ than C
(second sentence).
Rolfes’s reading would entail a repetition in the second sentence of what Aristotle has
just said in the first. As a consequence, one might be tempted to think that the second
sentence was simply a gloss. In other words, quite apart from its linguistic problems, this
alternative interpretation does not improve our understanding of the passage, although it
is logically correct.
5. ALEXANDER OF APHRODISIAS
There is yet another way to solve the problem, without stretching the Greek or simplifying the logic. This interpretation has been strangely neglected by modern scholars, but
was apparently clear to ancient commentators.
In his note commenting on the passage, Alexander of Aphrodisias quotes the rule of
Aristotle, in a form slightly different from those discussed above, and then presents an
exemplifying argument, which proves to be logically correct:
καὶ εἰ τὸ μὲν μᾶλλον τοιούτου τοιοῦτον, τὸ δὲ μὴ τοιοῦτον [sic AD Wallies : τοιούτου P :
τοιούτως τοιοῦτον B Ald.], δῆλον ὅτι τὸ πϱῶτον ῥηθὲν μᾶλλον τοιοῦτον. τοῦ τόπου τοῦ
λέγοντος ‘εἰ τὸ μὲν ἀγαθοῦ τινος μεῖζον εἴη ἀγαθόν, τὸ δὲ ἀγαθὸν μὲν εἴη μηδενὸς δὲ
ἀγαθοῦ μεῖζον, αἱϱετώτεϱον τὸ ἀγαθοῦ τινος μεῖζον’ (Alex. Aphr. in Top. 277, 17–20)
And if one thing is more of such sort than something of that sort, whereas τὸ δὲ μὴ τοιοῦτον, it
is clear that the first thing is more of that sort. As in this argument (τόπος): ‘if a certain good is
greater than another good, whereas a third good is greater than no other goods, it should be
preferred the good which is greater than something else’.
In his τόπος Alexander is clearly suggesting the following rule:
4) if A is more ϕ than B, and both A and B are ϕ, then if there is no D, which is ϕ, such that C is
more ϕ than D, then A is more ϕ than C.
This rule presupposes that the degrees according to which a property is shared by its subjects are ordered in a rigid way, namely that for every a, for every b, if a and b are different items and share the same property ϕ, either a is more ϕ than b, or b is more ϕ
than a.12 This is compatible with the common understanding of comparative relations.
What is worth noting is that, at first sight, Alexander’s interpretation does not seem
to be compatible with the wording of Aristotle’s lemma, and in particular with the problematic second premise, which is here given in yet another form (τὸ δὲ μὴ τοιοῦτον, i.e.
τὸ δὲ μὴ τοιοῦτο),13 which we have, for the moment, left in Greek as it is textually
problematic.
12
In other words, the relation ‘more than’ (as well as its reverse ‘less than’) appears to have the
property of trichotomy. This aspect is extremely interesting from the logical viewpoint, and if this
were what Aristotle had in mind, his remarks would no longer be trivial, or even unsound, but highly
relevant.
13
The forms τοιοῦτον and τοιοῦτο are mere variants, morphologically and semantically equivalent
(cf. LSJ ad loc.). Henceforth they will be referred to, without distinction, as τοιοῦτο(ν).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The University of St Andrews, on 12 Sep 2017 at 15:38:23, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838815000385
A R I S TOT L E ’ S CO M P A R AT I V E LO G I C
565
One might be tempted to emend Aristotle’s text by inserting into the second premise
the same μηδενός, which Alexander uses in his τόπος (μηδενὸς δὲ ἀγαθοῦ μεῖζον), and
which unequivocally introduces the property of trichotomy for comparative relations.
If we were to accept this tempting emendation, Aristotle’s passage would look something like this (following Ross’s and Brunschwig’s editions):
καὶ εἰ τὸ μὲν μᾶλλον τὸ δὲ ἧττον τοιοῦτο· καὶ εἰ τὸ μὲν τοιούτου μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο, τὸ δὲ
μη<δενὸς> τοιούτου [τοιούτου τοιοῦτον pler. codd. : τοιοῦτον Alex. (AD) : τοιούτου Alex.
(P) Bonitz : τοιούτως τοιοῦτον Alex. (B Ald.)], δῆλον ὅτι τὸ πϱῶτον μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο.
Moreover, if in any character one thing exceeds and another falls short of the same standard;
also, if the one, which possesses the character, exceeds something which possesses the
[same] character, while the other [exceeds] none which possesses the character, then clearly
the first thing possesses that character in a greater degree.’
This minor emendation, although it would explicitly state rule (4), is not palaeographically satisfactory, because it is difficult to admit that a copyist could have misread
μηδενός as μή. Moreover, Alexander did not read μηδενός, but he nevertheless understood the passage as referring to the trichotomy of comparative relations (cf. rule 4). The
only possibility is therefore to verify whether Aristotle’s text (in either of its variants)
may actually be interpreted in the same way as Alexander interpreted it, that is, as
expressing rule (4), which is most satisfactory from a logical point of view, although
it is widely neglected by modern translators and commentators.
6. ELLIPTICAL NEGATIONS IN ARISTOTLE AND THE POSITION OF μή
A good starting point is to analyse what would be the most explicit and clear form of the
second premise of rule (4) without the emendation μηδενός. This would probably be
something like one of the following:
εἰ τὸ μὲν τοιούτου μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο(ν) (sc. ἐστι),
a. τὸ δὲ μή ἐστι μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο(ν) τοιούτου.
b. τὸ δὲ τοιούτου μὴ μᾶλλον τοιοῦτό(ν) ἐστι.
c. τὸ δὲ μή ἐστι τοιούτου μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο(ν).
d. τὸ δὲ τοιούτου μή ἐστι μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο(ν).
e. τὸ δὲ μὴ μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο(ν) τοιούτου ἐστι.
Also, if the one possesses the character in a greater degree than something which possesses the
[same] character, while the other does not possess the character in a greater degree than something which possesses the [same] character.
We do not try here to establish which of the above word orders, if any, would be
most idiomatic in Greek, nor which one would be most appropriate in the context,
given the parallelism with the first premise, but we simply note that most of them
seem to be paralleled in the corpus of Aristotle.14
14
For word order a. (verb, comparative, second term of comparison) cf. e.g. Met. M 1082 b19-21:
εἴτε δὲ μὴ ἔστι πλείων ἀϱιθμὸς ὁ τῆς τϱιάδος αὐτῆς ἢ ὁ τῆς δυάδος, θαυμαστόν. For word order b.
(second term of comparison, comparative, verb) cf. e.g. Pol. B 1265 b7: ὥστε ἀϱιθμοῦ τινὸς μὴ
πλείονα γεννᾶν. For word order d. (second term of comparison, verb, comparative) cf. e.g. Met. N
1088 b10-11: οἷον ἡ δεκὰς πολύ, [καὶ] εἰ ταύτης μή ἐστι πλεῖον. Finally, for word order e. (comparative, second term of comparison, verb) cf. e.g. [Oec.] B 1346 a16: τὸ τἀναλώματα μὴ μείζω
τῶν πϱοσόδων γίνεσθαι.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The University of St Andrews, on 12 Sep 2017 at 15:38:23, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838815000385
566
L U CA G I L I A N D G I U S E P P E P E Z Z I N I
However, none of the above clauses is likely to have been used by Aristotle; in contrastive comparisons of this kind, in which a sentence is followed by a second sentence
that is an exact negative copy of the first, the verb of the second sentence is normally
dropped. Cf. for example An. Post. A 73 b10-12: ἔτι δ’ ἄλλον τϱόπον τὸ μὲν δι’
αὑτὸ ὑπάϱχον ἑκάστῳ καθ’ αὑτό, τὸ δὲ μὴ δι’ αὑτὸ συμβεβηκός, οἷον εἰ
βαδίζοντος ἤστϱαψε, συμβεβηκός.15 In particular, the verb ἐστι is hardly ever found
in contrastive comparisons of this kind: cf. for instance An. Pr. A 30 a23-4: εἰ δὲ τὸ
μὲν Α Β μὴ ἔστιν ἀναγκαῖον, τὸ δὲ Β Γ ἀναγκαῖον.16
If we eliminate the verb ἐστι from the above sentences, we are left with only three options:
f. τὸ δὲ μὴ μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο(ν) τοιούτου. ( = a/e)
g. τὸ δὲ τοιούτου μὴ μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο(ν). ( = b/d)
h. τὸ δὲ μὴ τοιούτου μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο(ν). ( = c)
However, if options ( f ) and (g) are still straightforward and would state rule (4) in
clear terms, option (h) would be ambiguous. Indeed, the adverb μή could also be taken
as negating not the whole predicate phrase τοιούτου μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο(ν) or the implied
ἐστι (‘not possessing the character to a greater degree than another thing that possesses
the same character’) but only the (nominalized) adjective τοιούτου (‘[possessing the character to a greater degree than] another thing that does not possess the same character’).17
This construction of μή preceding a complex phrase and negating only the word
directly following it (in our case a noun phrase with τοιούτου as a head) can be easily
paralleled.18 Cf. for example Top. Θ 162 a3-5: εἴη δ’ ἄν ποτε λόγος καὶ
(μή
is
negating
συμπεπεϱασμένος
μὴ
συμπεπεϱασμένου
χείϱων19
συμπεπεϱασμένου, not συμπεπεϱασμένου χείϱων); Top. Γ 119 a16-17: τὸ ϕύσει
τοιοῦτο τοῦ μὴ ϕύσει τοιούτου μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο20 (μή is negating ϕύσει, not ϕύσει
τοιούτου).
In contrast to these types of cases, when the adverb μή is meant to negate the whole
phrase, it tends to be attached to the head: cf. for instance Eth. Nic. Ζ 1139 b34-5: εἰ γὰϱ
μὴ μᾶλλον τοῦ συμπεϱάσματος, κατὰ συμβεβηκὸς ἕξει τὴν ἐπιστήμην.21
15
‘Again in another sense that which happens to something else in virtue of the latter’s own nature
is said to happen to it per se; while that which does not so happen is called an accident.’
16
‘But if AB is not necessary, but BC is necessary.’
17
For the use of μή with noun, adjectives or participles (a use traditionally explained as being ‘generic’ as opposed to the ‘referential’ use of οὐ) see R. Kühner and B. Gerth, Ausführliche Grammatik
der griechischen Sprache: Zweiter Teil (Hannover and Leipzig 1904), 2.197-203, especially 201-2.
For a more recent and sophisticated account see E. Gerö, Negatives and Noun Phrases in Classical
Greek (Frankfurt am Main, 1997), with her supplementary article in Glotta 77 (2011), 38–55. Cf.
also J. Wackernagel, Lectures on Syntax, trans. D. Langslow (Oxford, 2009), 729–33, 752–4; A.G.
Laird, ‘When is generic μή particular?’, AJPh 43 (1922), 124–45; A.C. Moorhouse, Studies in the
Greek Negatives (Cardiff, 1959), 36–40. In our passage the conditional context (καὶ εἰ …) would
probably be enough to account for the use of μή (on this use see Wackernagel [this note], 750–1).
18
For the view that in Greek the negative particle is immediately placed before the word that is
negatived, cf. e.g. Kühner and Gerth (n. 17), 2.179; LSJ s.vv. οὐ D, μή D. For a criticism of this
view as ‘misleading oversimplification’, cf. Moorhouse (n. 17), 75–6, 89–120.
19
‘It is possible also that an argument, even though brought to a conclusion, may sometimes be
worse than one which is not so concluded.’
20
‘That which naturally has a certain quality has that quality in a greater degree than that which
possesses it not naturally.’ Cf. Alex. Aphr. ad loc. (p. 276.9): τὸ ϕύσει ἀγαθὸν τοῦ μὴ ϕύσει
αἱϱετώτεϱον.
21
‘If [the principles] are not better known to him than the conclusion, he will have his knowledge
only incidentally.’
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The University of St Andrews, on 12 Sep 2017 at 15:38:23, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838815000385
A R I S TOT L E ’ S CO M P A R AT I V E LO G I C
567
Consequently, the fact that in sentence (h) the adverb μή is detached from the head of
the phrase ([μᾶλλον] τοιοῦτο) might be taken as suggesting that it is negating the adverb
τοιούτου (‘[that possesses the character more than any other thing] that does not possess
the character’) and not the whole phrase τοιούτου μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο (or the implied ἐστι
or the whole clause)22 (‘not possessing the character to a greater degree than another
thing that possesses the same character’): consequently, sentence h might be construed
as expressing rule 1, which, as we have shown, is logically incorrect.
On the other hand, although it has significant syntactic plausibility, the interpretation
above (taking μή as negating τοιούτου) is not the only one possible: there are parallels
for the use of the adverb μή used to negate a complex noun phrase with the head in last
position. Cf. for example Arist. De An. Α 403 b9-15:
ἢ οὐκ ἔστιν εἷς ὁ πεϱὶ τὰ πάθη τῆς ὕλης τὰ μὴ χωϱιστὰ μηδ’ ᾗ χωϱιστά, ἀλλ’ ὁ ϕυσικὸς πεϱὶ
ἅπανθ’ ὅσα τοῦ τοιουδὶ σώματος καὶ τῆς τοιαύτης ὕλης ἔϱγα καὶ πάθη. (…) τῶν δὲ μὴ
χωϱιστῶν μέν, ᾗ δὲ μὴ τοιούτου σώματος πάθη καὶ ἐξ ἀϕαιϱέσεως, ὁ μαθηματικός.23
In the passage above, the adverb μή preceding the phrase τοιούτου σώματος πάθη is not
negating only the adjective τοιούτου (‘regarded as properties [that are] belonging to a
body not of a given sort’, i.e. ‘attributes [that are] belonging to a different body’) but
rather the whole phrase (‘regarded not as properties [that are] belonging to a body of
a given sort’). The phrase τοιούτου σώματος πάθη is a simplified form of the phrase
τοῦ τοιουδὶ σώματος καὶ τῆς τοιαύτης ὕλης ἔϱγα καὶ πάθη stated in the previous sentence, with which it is contrasted by means of the adverb μή. Indeed, the contrast
between the two phrases is the reason for the fact that in the second phrase μή is placed
in the first position detached from the head, and that no ambiguity is possible.24
Therefore, it is not syntactically inconceivable that in the clause (h) the adverb μή is
negating the whole phrase τοιούτου μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο(ν) (or the implied ἐστι or the
whole clause),25 and thus that the sentence could still be construed as expressing rule
22
From a semantic (and thus syntactic) point of view, the sentence with the negative particle negating only the predicate phrase (τοιούτου) μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο (‘is [not possessing the character to a
greater degree]’) is equivalent to both the one with the negative particle negating the (implied) copula
ἐστι (‘is not [possessing the character to a greater degree]’) and the one with the negative particle
negating the whole clause (‘not [is possessing the character to a greater degree]’).
23
‘Or shall we rather say that there is no one (who deals) with properties of the matter which are
not separable nor yet treated as separable, but the physicist deals with all the active properties or passive affections belonging to a body of a given sort and the corresponding matters? (…) When on the
other hand the qualities, though inseparable, are regarded not as properties belonging to a body of a
given sort and are treated abstractly, they fall within the province of the mathematician.’
24
The ‘detachment’ of the negative particle from the word expectedly negatived (the predicate in a
clause or the head in a phrase) is also to be related to a (primeval) tendency of the negative particle to
be placed in an initial position: in Herodotus, for instance, in negative conditional protases the particle
μή is normally found in first position (87%), often detached from the verb (57%); for these figures and
a discussion of the tendency and its development in the history of Greek, see Moorhouse (n. 17), 75–6,
82–120. On the syntax and position of the negative see also Wackernagel (n. 17), 725–34, 751–4.
25
It is perhaps worth mentioning that, according to the analysis of negation in the Peripatetics, in a
proposition the negative adverb always negates the copula (cf. Alex. Aphr. in An. Pr. 402.1–405.16).
In our case the copula would be the implied ἐστι (μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο), which, if negated by μή, would
indeed produce the meaning required by the interpretation we envisage (‘is not possessing the character to a higher degree …’; cf. above, n. 22). In other words, the explicit view of Aristotle’s school on
the syntactic role of negation might be compatible with our understanding of the syntactic role of μή in
the text under investigation. For the peripatetic analysis of negation see J. Barnes, ‘Peripatetic negations’, OSAPh 4 (1986), 201-14. For Aristotle’s analysis see W. Cavini, La negazione di frase nella
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The University of St Andrews, on 12 Sep 2017 at 15:38:23, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838815000385
568
L U CA G I L I A N D G I U S E P P E P E Z Z I N I
4 (‘not possessing the character to a greater degree than another thing that possesses the
same character’).
Interestingly, option (h) is actually found in this form in two manuscripts of Aristotle
(Vaticanus Barberinianus 87 and Parisinus 1843) and is printed by Forster in his Loeb
edition (with an elliptical but correct translation; cf. n. 28): this reading is probably a
simplification of the original text, originating from the insertion of an explanatory
gloss of the scholiast in the text. Consequently, the reading could be considered as evidence for another ancient commentator interpreting the passage in the same way as
Alexander, an interpretation which, as we have seen, seems to be the correct one.
Going back to sentences ( f ), (g) and (h), it must be pointed out that it is still unlikely
that they represent the original text of Aristotle. Indeed, the readings of the majority of
the manuscripts and of Alexander suggest that the original text displayed a further
degree of ellipsis. In particular, it seems evident that the adverb μᾶλλον was not
repeated in the second sentence. The omission of μᾶλλον would produce the following
sentence:
i. τὸ δὲ μὴ τοιοῦτο(ν) τοιούτου. (< f )
j. τὸ δὲ μὴ τοιούτου τοιοῦτο(ν). (< g/h)
and, with a further degree of simplification,
k. τὸ δὲ μὴ τοιοῦτο(ν) (< f/g/h)
l. τὸ δὲ μὴ τοιούτου (< f/g/h)
Sentence ( j) is the text transmitted in most manuscripts of Aristotle and probably lying
behind the corrupt reading τοιούτως τοιοῦτον found in MS B of Alexander (also printed
in the Aldine edition); sentence (k) is transmitted in one branch of the tradition of
Alexander (MSS A and D) and printed by his editors; sentence (l ) is transmitted in
another of Alexander’s manuscripts (MS P) and printed by several editors of
Aristotle. Again, all these sentences would not be at variance with the usus scribendi
of Aristotle. Indeed, the simplification of the wording of the second member of a contrastive comparison is not limited to the omission of the verb.
It is difficult to determine which of these readings (i, j, k and l) was the original one,
since all present some problems and all could be explained palaeographically as corruptions of another reading (k and l as deriving from each other by confusion of final ν/υ, or
from i or j by haplography; i and j as deriving from insertion in the text of k, to be construed as a marginal or interlinear variant of l, or vice versa).
However, options (i) and ( j) are not satisfactory from a linguistic point of view: given
the fact that the adverb μᾶλλον functions as a syntactic bridge between τοιοῦτο(ν) and
τοιούτου, through its individual bond with each of them (μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο(ν) ‘the same
character to a greater degree’; μᾶλλον τοιούτου ‘to a greater degree than another thing
that possesses the same character’), its omission would be problematic in a context
where τοιοῦτο(ν) and τοιούτου would both be present.
Option (k) is linguistically more sound, but only if one takes τοιοῦτο(ν) as having not
the meaning it has in the previous sentence (‘of such sort’, ‘possessing the character/
quality’), but rather the anaphoric meaning of ‘such as this’, with reference to what
has just been said, i.e. τοιούτου μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο(ν); the resultant translation would be:
logica greca, in W. Cavini, M.C. Donnini Macciò, M.S. Funghi, D. Manetti (edd.), Studi su papiri
greci di logica e medicina (Florence, 1985), 7–126, especially 7–45.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The University of St Andrews, on 12 Sep 2017 at 15:38:23, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838815000385
A R I S TOT L E ’ S CO M P A R AT I V E LO G I C
569
If the one is possessing the character in a greater degree than something which possesses the
[same] character, while the other is not such as this [i.e. such as one possessing the character
in a greater degree than something which possesses the [same] character].
This option is advantageous in many respects, since the reading μὴ τοιοῦτο(ν) is well
attested in manuscripts and the text would express unambiguously rule 4. The only
problem with this reading is the fact that in the context the adjective τοιοῦτο(ν) is
being constantly used (more than fifteen times in section 119a alone) in the nonanaphoric indefinite sense of ‘possessing a certain quality’, ‘possessing such-and-such
a quality’ (or similar), and not in the anaphoric sense of ‘such as this [i.e. what has
just been said]’): such a sudden change of meaning within a sentence, from the nonanaphoric (εἰ τὸ μὲν τοιούτου μᾶλλον τοιοῦτον) to the anaphoric sense of τοιοῦτο
(τὸ δὲ μὴ τοιοῦτον) would be unexpected and difficult to defend.
We are thus left with option (l ), which is the reading printed by modern editors of
Aristotle and already found in one branch of the tradition of Alexander (MS P). As we
have seen above, this sentence (l ) is problematic since it displays some degree of ambiguity, as the adverb μή may seem to negate only the adjective.
Nevertheless, this sentence (l ) could still be construed as a simplified form of sentences (a)−(h), i.e. as expressing, in an elliptic form, rule 4. This would be possible
if one took the adverb μή as negating the implied copula or the predicate phrase
τοιούτου [μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο(ν)], whose omitted head (μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο) would be implied
by the contrast of the second premise with the preceding sentence. There are parallels of
a similar use of μή in elliptic sequences, attached to a complement but negating some
omitted material. Cf. for example An. Pr. A 29 a6-9:
οὐδ’ ἂν ἑκάτεϱος τινὶ τῷ μέσῳ ὑπάϱχῃ ἢ μὴ ὑπάϱχῃ, ἢ ὁ μὲν ὑπάϱχῃ ὁ δὲ μὴ ὑπάϱχῃ, ἢ ὁ
μὲν τινὶ ὁ δὲ μὴ παντί, ἢ ἀδιοϱίστως, οὐκ ἔσται συλλογισμὸς οὐδαμῶς.26
In the sentence above, the adverb μὴ (in bold) is not negating only the word παντί (‘it applies
to the not-whole’) but the whole verb phrase παντὶ ὑπάϱχῃ (‘it does not apply to the whole’),
whose omitted head (ὑπάϱχῃ) is implied, in a sequence of contrastive sentences.
Therefore, even reading (l ), found in most editions, could be construed as expressing, although in a very elliptic form, rule 4. Reading (l ) seems preferable to the
other options, and, if accepted in Aristotle’s text, should also be printed as such in
Alexander’s text, thus introducing the reading of manuscript P.27
There is however, a final degree of simplification, which would entail ellipsis of the
whole phrase:
[εἰ τὸ μὲν τοιούτου μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο (sc. ἐστι)],
m. τὸ δὲ μή
also, if the one possesses the character in a greater degree than something which possesses the
[same] character, while the other does not [possess the character to a greater degree than something which possesses the same character].28
26
‘Furthermore, if both terms apply or do not apply to some of the middle, or if one applies to some
and the other does not, or if one applies to some and the other does not apply to all, or if they are
related to the middle indefinitely, there will in no case be a syllogism’.
27
As pointed out by Wallies in the preface of his edition (p. xi), manuscript P (Parisinus 1874,
saec. xiii), although often corrupt, is occasionally carrier of good readings.
28
This translation is essentially the one provided by the Loeb edition, which thus seems to be one
of the most correct, although it does not explicitly discuss the issue.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The University of St Andrews, on 12 Sep 2017 at 15:38:23, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838815000385
570
L U CA G I L I A N D G I U S E P P E P E Z Z I N I
Editors have not yet suggested this reading, but it might be suitable from both a syntactic
and palaeographic point of view.
To begin with, complete simplification of the second member of a contrastive comparison to an elliptical phrase with τὸ δὲ μή (or similar) is very common in Aristotle. Cf.
for example:
Top. H 152 b6-7: ἔτι ἐκ τοῦ μᾶλλον, εἰ τὸ μὲν δέχεται τὸ μᾶλλον, τὸ δὲ μή.
Top. Δ 125 b38-9: καθάπεϱ οὐδὲ τὸ αὐτὸ ζῷον ὁτὲ μὲν ἄνθϱωπον εἶναι, ὁτὲ δὲ μή.
An. Pr. B 70 b29: καὶ ἐν οἷς μὴ ὅλοις ἑκάτεϱον, ὅταν τὸ μὲν ἔχῃ, τὸ δὲ μή.
An. Post. B 100 a2-3: ὥστε τοῖς μὲν γίνεσθαι λόγον ἐκ τῆς τῶν τοιούτων μονῆς, τοῖς δὲ μή.
De caelo A 280 b11-12: Ἕνα δ’ εἴ τι ὅλως ἀδύνατον γενέσθαι, ὥσθ’ ὁτὲ μὲν εἶναι, ὁτὲ δὲ μή.
Eth. Eud. B 1224 b7-8: ὅταν μὲν γάϱ τι τῶν ἔξωθεν παϱὰ τὴν ἐν αὐτῷ ὁϱμὴν κινῇ ἢ ἠϱεμίζῃ,
βίᾳ ϕαμέν, ὅταν δὲ μή, οὐ βίᾳ.
All these sentences display an ellipsis of one or more phrases in the second member of a
contrastive comparison introduced by μή, which would be the same construction which
we find in sentence (m).
However, it is easy to imagine how this elliptical construction could have created
some problems of interpretation for later readers of the text, who presumably opted
for inserting some of the material omitted, as testified to by the various readings
found in the manuscripts (τοιούτου τοιοῦτο, τοιούτου, τοιοῦτο(ν) or τοιούτου
μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο). These attempts at clarifying the Aristotelian obscuritas did not greatly
benefit Aristotle in so far as they created a dangerous ambiguity (μή negating τοιούτου),
which, if our reconstruction is correct, was not present in the original text, where the
adverb μή could only negate the whole of the omitted material (τοιούτου μᾶλλον
τοιοῦτο).
7. CONCLUSIONS
To sum up, we believe that Aristotle at Top. Γ 119 a20-2 has introduced the property of
trichotomy for the relations ‘more than’ and ‘less than’, as already understood by
Alexander of Aphrodisias (whose τόπος does not allow for any other interpretation of
Aristotle’s passage). This property can be expressed by the following rule:
4) if A is more ϕ than B, and both A and B are ϕ, then if there is no D, which is ϕ, such that C is
more ϕ than D, then A is more ϕ than C.
The translation we propose for the passage would be, after Barnes:
Moreover, if in any character one thing exceeds and another falls short of the same standard;
also, if the one exceeds something which possesses the character, while the other does not
exceed anything which possesses the character, then clearly the first thing exhibits that character in a greater degree.
This translation is faithful to the wording of the Greek text, in both the form printed in
most editions of Aristotle (τὸ δὲ μὴ τοιούτου), and in the form printed by Wallies in his
edition of the commentary ad loc. of Alexander of Aphrodisias (τὸ δὲ μὴ τοιοῦτον);
both of these forms might be correct, although the former is slightly preferable to the
second. Other readings (including the simplifying version found in Parisinus 1843 τὸ
δὲ μὴ τοιούτου μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο) are linguistically or paleographically unsound and
should be emended.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The University of St Andrews, on 12 Sep 2017 at 15:38:23, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838815000385
A R I S TOT L E ’ S CO M P A R AT I V E LO G I C
571
However, it is possible that Aristotle’s original text displayed a further degree of simplification, which involved omission of the whole phrase in the second premise
(τοιούτου μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο), with a pattern that is common in Aristotle’s contrastive
comparisons.
We therefore suggest, although cautiously, printing the following text, in both
Aristotle and Alexander:
ἔτι εἰ τοῦ αὐτοῦ τινος τὸ μὲν μᾶλλον τὸ δὲ ἧττον τοιοῦτο· καὶ εἰ τὸ μὲν τοιούτου μᾶλλον
τοιοῦτο, τὸ δὲ μή, δῆλον ὅτι τὸ πϱῶτον μᾶλλον τοιοῦτο.
All the other readings attested in manuscripts and editions might be construed as deriving from attempts at glossing the above text, by inserting the omitted material.
In conclusion, Top. Γ 119 a20-2 appears to be the only passage in which Aristotle
introduced the property of trichotomy; therefore, if correctly understood, it is important
for a better understanding of his comparative logic.
K.U. Leuven, Fonds Wetenschappelijk Onderzoek,
Vlaanderen
Magdalen College, Oxford
LUCA GILI
luca.gili@hiw.kuleuven.be
GIUSEPPE PEZZINI
giuseppe.pezzini@classics.ox.ac.uk
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. The University of St Andrews, on 12 Sep 2017 at 15:38:23, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838815000385